Title: ON INTERPRETATION
Subject:
Author: by Aristotle
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
ON INTERPRETATION
by Aristotle
Page No 2
Table of Contents
ON INTERPRETATION...................................................................................................................................1
by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1
1..............................................................................................................................................................1
2..............................................................................................................................................................1
3..............................................................................................................................................................2
4..............................................................................................................................................................2
5..............................................................................................................................................................3
6..............................................................................................................................................................3
7..............................................................................................................................................................4
8..............................................................................................................................................................5
9..............................................................................................................................................................5
10............................................................................................................................................................7
11............................................................................................................................................................9
12..........................................................................................................................................................11
13..........................................................................................................................................................12
14..........................................................................................................................................................14
ON INTERPRETATION
i
Page No 3
ON INTERPRETATION
by Aristotle
translated by E. M. Edghill
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
1
First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 'denial' and 'affirmation', then 'proposition' and
'sentence.'
Spoken words are the symbols of mental experience and written words are the symbols of spoken words. Just
as all men have not the same writing, so all men have not the same speech sounds, but the mental
experiences, which these directly symbolize, are the same for all, as also are those things of which our
experiences are the images. This matter has, however, been discussed in my treatise about the soul, for it
belongs to an investigation distinct from that which lies before us.
As there are in the mind thoughts which do not involve truth or falsity, and also those which must be either
true or false, so it is in speech. For truth and falsity imply combination and separation. Nouns and verbs,
provided nothing is added, are like thoughts without combination or separation; 'man' and 'white', as isolated
terms, are not yet either true or false. In proof of this, consider the word 'goatstag.' It has significance, but
there is no truth or falsity about it, unless 'is' or 'is not' is added, either in the present or in some other tense.
2
By a noun we mean a sound significant by convention, which has no reference to time, and of which no part
is significant apart from the rest. In the noun 'Fairsteed,' the part 'steed' has no significance in and by itself, as
ON INTERPRETATION 1
Page No 4
in the phrase 'fair steed.' Yet there is a difference between simple and composite nouns; for in the former the
part is in no way significant, in the latter it contributes to the meaning of the whole, although it has not an
independent meaning. Thus in the word 'pirateboat' the word 'boat' has no meaning except as part of the
whole word.
The limitation 'by convention' was introduced because nothing is by nature a noun or nameit is only so
when it becomes a symbol; inarticulate sounds, such as those which brutes produce, are significant, yet none
of these constitutes a noun.
The expression 'notman' is not a noun. There is indeed no recognized term by which we may denote such an
expression, for it is not a sentence or a denial. Let it then be called an indefinite noun.
The expressions 'of Philo', 'to Philo', and so on, constitute not nouns, but cases of a noun. The definition of
these cases of a noun is in other respects the same as that of the noun proper, but, when coupled with 'is',
'was', or will be', they do not, as they are, form a proposition either true or false, and this the noun proper
always does, under these conditions. Take the words 'of Philo is' or 'of or 'of Philo is not'; these words do not,
as they stand, form either a true or a false proposition.
3
A verb is that which, in addition to its proper meaning, carries with it the notion of time. No part of it has any
independent meaning, and it is a sign of something said of something else.
I will explain what I mean by saying that it carries with it the notion of time. 'Health' is a noun, but 'is healthy'
is a verb; for besides its proper meaning it indicates the present existence of the state in question.
Moreover, a verb is always a sign of something said of something else, i.e. of something either predicable of
or present in some other thing.
Such expressions as 'is nothealthy', 'is not, ill', I do not describe as verbs; for though they carry the
additional note of time, and always form a predicate, there is no specified name for this variety; but let them
be called indefinite verbs, since they apply equally well to that which exists and to that which does not.
Similarly 'he was healthy', 'he will be healthy', are not verbs, but tenses of a verb; the difference lies in the
fact that the verb indicates present time, while the tenses of the verb indicate those times which lie outside the
present.
Verbs in and by themselves are substantival and have significance, for he who uses such expressions arrests
the hearer's mind, and fixes his attention; but they do not, as they stand, express any judgement, either
positive or negative. For neither are 'to be' and 'not to be' the participle 'being' significant of any fact, unless
something is added; for they do not themselves indicate anything, but imply a copulation, of which we cannot
form a conception apart from the things coupled.
4
A sentence is a significant portion of speech, some parts of which have an independent meaning, that is to
say, as an utterance, though not as the expression of any positive judgement. Let me explain. The word
'human' has meaning, but does not constitute a proposition, either positive or negative. It is only when other
words are added that the whole will form an affirmation or denial. But if we separate one syllable of the word
'human' from the other, it has no meaning; similarly in the word 'mouse', the part 'ouse' has no meaning in
ON INTERPRETATION
3 2
Page No 5
itself, but is merely a sound. In composite words, indeed, the parts contribute to the meaning of the whole;
yet, as has been pointed out, they have not an independent meaning.
Every sentence has meaning, not as being the natural means by which a physical faculty is realized, but, as
we have said, by convention. Yet every sentence is not a proposition; only such are propositions as have in
them either truth or falsity. Thus a prayer is a sentence, but is neither true nor false.
Let us therefore dismiss all other types of sentence but the proposition, for this last concerns our present
inquiry, whereas the investigation of the others belongs rather to the study of rhetoric or of poetry.
5
The first class of simple propositions is the simple affirmation, the next, the simple denial; all others are only
one by conjunction.
Every proposition must contain a verb or the tense of a verb. The phrase which defines the species 'man', if no
verb in present, past, or future time be added, is not a proposition. It may be asked how the expression 'a
footed animal with two feet' can be called single; for it is not the circumstance that the words follow in
unbroken succession that effects the unity. This inquiry, however, finds its place in an investigation foreign to
that before us.
We call those propositions single which indicate a single fact, or the conjunction of the parts of which results
in unity: those propositions, on the other hand, are separate and many in number, which indicate many facts,
or whose parts have no conjunction.
Let us, moreover, consent to call a noun or a verb an expression only, and not a proposition, since it is not
possible for a man to speak in this way when he is expressing something, in such a way as to make a
statement, whether his utterance is an answer to a question or an act of his own initiation.
To return: of propositions one kind is simple, i.e. that which asserts or denies something of something, the
other composite, i.e. that which is compounded of simple propositions. A simple proposition is a statement,
with meaning, as to the presence of something in a subject or its absence, in the present, past, or future,
according to the divisions of time.
6
An affirmation is a positive assertion of something about something, a denial a negative assertion.
Now it is possible both to affirm and to deny the presence of something which is present or of something
which is not, and since these same affirmations and denials are possible with reference to those times which
lie outside the present, it would be possible to contradict any affirmation or denial. Thus it is plain that every
affirmation has an opposite denial, and similarly every denial an opposite affirmation.
We will call such a pair of propositions a pair of contradictories. Those positive and negative propositions are
said to be contradictory which have the same subject and predicate. The identity of subject and of predicate
must not be 'equivocal'. Indeed there are definitive qualifications besides this, which we make to meet the
casuistries of sophists.
ON INTERPRETATION
5 3
Page No 6
7
Some things are universal, others individual. By the term 'universal' I mean that which is of such a nature as
to be predicated of many subjects, by 'individual' that which is not thus predicated. Thus 'man' is a universal,
'Callias' an individual.
Our propositions necessarily sometimes concern a universal subject, sometimes an individual.
If, then, a man states a positive and a negative proposition of universal character with regard to a universal,
these two propositions are 'contrary'. By the expression 'a proposition of universal character with regard to a
universal', such propositions as 'every man is white', 'no man is white' are meant. When, on the other hand,
the positive and negative propositions, though they have regard to a universal, are yet not of universal
character, they will not be contrary, albeit the meaning intended is sometimes contrary. As instances of
propositions made with regard to a universal, but not of universal character, we may take the 'propositions
'man is white', 'man is not white'. 'Man' is a universal, but the proposition is not made as of universal
character; for the word 'every' does not make the subject a universal, but rather gives the proposition a
universal character. If, however, both predicate and subject are distributed, the proposition thus constituted is
contrary to truth; no affirmation will, under such circumstances, be true. The proposition 'every man is every
animal' is an example of this type.
An affirmation is opposed to a denial in the sense which I denote by the term 'contradictory', when, while the
subject remains the same, the affirmation is of universal character and the denial is not. The affirmation
'every man is white' is the contradictory of the denial 'not every man is white', or again, the proposition 'no
man is white' is the contradictory of the proposition 'some men are white'. But propositions are opposed as
contraries when both the affirmation and the denial are universal, as in the sentences 'every man is white', 'no
man is white', 'every man is just', 'no man is just'.
We see that in a pair of this sort both propositions cannot be true, but the contradictories of a pair of
contraries can sometimes both be true with reference to the same subject; for instance 'not every man is white'
and some men are white' are both true. Of such corresponding positive and negative propositions as refer to
universals and have a universal character, one must be true and the other false. This is the case also when the
reference is to individuals, as in the propositions 'Socrates is white', 'Socrates is not white'.
When, on the other hand, the reference is to universals, but the propositions are not universal, it is not always
the case that one is true and the other false, for it is possible to state truly that man is white and that man is
not white and that man is beautiful and that man is not beautiful; for if a man is deformed he is the reverse of
beautiful, also if he is progressing towards beauty he is not yet beautiful.
This statement might seem at first sight to carry with it a contradiction, owing to the fact that the proposition
'man is not white' appears to be equivalent to the proposition 'no man is white'. This, however, is not the case,
nor are they necessarily at the same time true or false.
It is evident also that the denial corresponding to a single affirmation is itself single; for the denial must deny
just that which the affirmation affirms concerning the same subject, and must correspond with the affirmation
both in the universal or particular character of the subject and in the distributed or undistributed sense in
which it is understood.
For instance, the affirmation 'Socrates is white' has its proper denial in the proposition 'Socrates is not white'.
If anything else be negatively predicated of the subject or if anything else be the subject though the predicate
remain the same, the denial will not be the denial proper to that affirmation, but on that is distinct.
ON INTERPRETATION
7 4
Page No 7
The denial proper to the affirmation 'every man is white' is 'not every man is white'; that proper to the
affirmation 'some men are white' is 'no man is white', while that proper to the affirmation 'man is white' is
'man is not white'.
We have shown further that a single denial is contradictorily opposite to a single affirmation and we have
explained which these are; we have also stated that contrary are distinct from contradictory propositions and
which the contrary are; also that with regard to a pair of opposite propositions it is not always the case that
one is true and the other false. We have pointed out, moreover, what the reason of this is and under what
circumstances the truth of the one involves the falsity of the other.
8
An affirmation or denial is single, if it indicates some one fact about some one subject; it matters not whether
the subject is universal and whether the statement has a universal character, or whether this is not so. Such
single propositions are: 'every man is white', 'not every man is white';'man is white','man is not white'; 'no
man is white', 'some men are white'; provided the word 'white' has one meaning. If, on the other hand, one
word has two meanings which do not combine to form one, the affirmation is not single. For instance, if a
man should establish the symbol 'garment' as significant both of a horse and of a man, the proposition
'garment is white' would not be a single affirmation, nor its opposite a single denial. For it is equivalent to the
proposition 'horse and man are white', which, again, is equivalent to the two propositions 'horse is white',
'man is white'. If, then, these two propositions have more than a single significance, and do not form a single
proposition, it is plain that the first proposition either has more than one significance or else has none; for a
particular man is not a horse.
This, then, is another instance of those propositions of which both the positive and the negative forms may be
true or false simultaneously.
9
In the case of that which is or which has taken place, propositions, whether positive or negative, must be true
or false. Again, in the case of a pair of contradictories, either when the subject is universal and the
propositions are of a universal character, or when it is individual, as has been said,' one of the two must be
true and the other false; whereas when the subject is universal, but the propositions are not of a universal
character, there is no such necessity. We have discussed this type also in a previous chapter.
When the subject, however, is individual, and that which is predicated of it relates to the future, the case is
altered. For if all propositions whether positive or negative are either true or false, then any given predicate
must either belong to the subject or not, so that if one man affirms that an event of a given character will take
place and another denies it, it is plain that the statement of the one will correspond with reality and that of the
other will not. For the predicate cannot both belong and not belong to the subject at one and the same time
with regard to the future.
Thus, if it is true to say that a thing is white, it must necessarily be white; if the reverse proposition is true, it
will of necessity not be white. Again, if it is white, the proposition stating that it is white was true; if it is not
white, the proposition to the opposite effect was true. And if it is not white, the man who states that it is
making a false statement; and if the man who states that it is white is making a false statement, it follows that
it is not white. It may therefore be argued that it is necessary that affirmations or denials must be either true
or false.
ON INTERPRETATION
8 5
Page No 8
Now if this be so, nothing is or takes place fortuitously, either in the present or in the future, and there are no
real alternatives; everything takes place of necessity and is fixed. For either he that affirms that it will take
place or he that denies this is in correspondence with fact, whereas if things did not take place of necessity, an
event might just as easily not happen as happen; for the meaning of the word 'fortuitous' with regard to
present or future events is that reality is so constituted that it may issue in either of two opposite directions.
Again, if a thing is white now, it was true before to say that it would be white, so that of anything that has
taken place it was always true to say 'it is' or 'it will be'. But if it was always true to say that a thing is or will
be, it is not possible that it should not be or not be about to be, and when a thing cannot not come to be, it is
impossible that it should not come to be, and when it is impossible that it should not come to be, it must come
to be. All, then, that is about to be must of necessity take place. It results from this that nothing is uncertain or
fortuitous, for if it were fortuitous it would not be necessary.
Again, to say that neither the affirmation nor the denial is true, maintaining, let us say, that an event neither
will take place nor will not take place, is to take up a position impossible to defend. In the first place, though
facts should prove the one proposition false, the opposite would still be untrue. Secondly, if it was true to say
that a thing was both white and large, both these qualities must necessarily belong to it; and if they will
belong to it the next day, they must necessarily belong to it the next day. But if an event is neither to take
place nor not to take place the next day, the element of chance will be eliminated. For example, it would be
necessary that a seafight should neither take place nor fail to take place on the next day.
These awkward results and others of the same kind follow, if it is an irrefragable law that of every pair of
contradictory propositions, whether they have regard to universals and are stated as universally applicable, or
whether they have regard to individuals, one must be true and the other false, and that there are no real
alternatives, but that all that is or takes place is the outcome of necessity. There would be no need to
deliberate or to take trouble, on the supposition that if we should adopt a certain course, a certain result would
follow, while, if we did not, the result would not follow. For a man may predict an event ten thousand years
beforehand, and another may predict the reverse; that which was truly predicted at the moment in the past
will of necessity take place in the fullness of time.
Further, it makes no difference whether people have or have not actually made the contradictory statements.
For it is manifest that the circumstances are not influenced by the fact of an affirmation or denial on the part
of anyone. For events will not take place or fail to take place because it was stated that they would or would
not take place, nor is this any more the case if the prediction dates back ten thousand years or any other space
of time. Wherefore, if through all time the nature of things was so constituted that a prediction about an event
was true, then through all time it was necessary that that should find fulfillment; and with regard to all events,
circumstances have always been such that their occurrence is a matter of necessity. For that of which
someone has said truly that it will be, cannot fail to take place; and of that which takes place, it was always
true to say that it would be.
Yet this view leads to an impossible conclusion; for we see that both deliberation and action are causative
with regard to the future, and that, to speak more generally, in those things which are not continuously actual
there is potentiality in either direction. Such things may either be or not be; events also therefore may either
take place or not take place. There are many obvious instances of this. It is possible that this coat may be cut
in half, and yet it may not be cut in half, but wear out first. In the same way, it is possible that it should not be
cut in half; unless this were so, it would not be possible that it should wear out first. So it is therefore with all
other events which possess this kind of potentiality. It is therefore plain that it is not of necessity that
everything is or takes place; but in some instances there are real alternatives, in which case the affirmation is
no more true and no more false than the denial; while some exhibit a predisposition and general tendency in
one direction or the other, and yet can issue in the opposite direction by exception.
ON INTERPRETATION
8 6
Page No 9
Now that which is must needs be when it is, and that which is not must needs not be when it is not. Yet it
cannot be said without qualification that all existence and nonexistence is the outcome of necessity. For
there is a difference between saying that that which is, when it is, must needs be, and simply saying that all
that is must needs be, and similarly in the case of that which is not. In the case, also, of two contradictory
propositions this holds good. Everything must either be or not be, whether in the present or in the future, but
it is not always possible to distinguish and state determinately which of these alternatives must necessarily
come about.
Let me illustrate. A seafight must either take place tomorrow or not, but it is not necessary that it should
take place tomorrow, neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet it is necessary that it either
should or should not take place tomorrow. Since propositions correspond with facts, it is evident that when
in future events there is a real alternative, and a potentiality in contrary directions, the corresponding
affirmation and denial have the same character.
This is the case with regard to that which is not always existent or not always nonexistent. One of the two
propositions in such instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say determinately that this or
that is false, but must leave the alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than the
other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of
an affirmation and a denial one should be true and the other false. For in the case of that which exists
potentially, but not actually, the rule which applies to that which exists actually does not hold good. The case
is rather as we have indicated.
10
An affirmation is the statement of a fact with regard to a subject, and this subject is either a noun or that
which has no name; the subject and predicate in an affirmation must each denote a single thing. I have
already explained' what is meant by a noun and by that which has no name; for I stated that the expression
'notman' was not a noun, in the proper sense of the word, but an indefinite noun, denoting as it does in a
certain sense a single thing. Similarly the expression 'does not enjoy health' is not a verb proper, but an
indefinite verb. Every affirmation, then, and every denial, will consist of a noun and a verb, either definite or
indefinite.
There can be no affirmation or denial without a verb; for the expressions 'is', 'will be', 'was', 'is coming to be',
and the like are verbs according to our definition, since besides their specific meaning they convey the notion
of time. Thus the primary affirmation and denial are 'as follows: 'man is', 'man is not'. Next to these, there are
the propositions: 'notman is', 'notman is not'. Again we have the propositions: 'every man is, 'every man is
not', 'all that is notman is', 'all that is notman is not'. The same classification holds good with regard to such
periods of time as lie outside the present.
When the verb 'is' is used as a third element in the sentence, there can be positive and negative propositions
of two sorts. Thus in the sentence 'man is just' the verb 'is' is used as a third element, call it verb or noun,
which you will. Four propositions, therefore, instead of two can be formed with these materials. Two of the
four, as regards their affirmation and denial, correspond in their logical sequence with the propositions which
deal with a condition of privation; the other two do not correspond with these.
I mean that the verb 'is' is added either to the term 'just' or to the term 'notjust', and two negative
propositions are formed in the same way. Thus we have the four propositions. Reference to the subjoined
table will make matters clear:
A. Affirmation B. Denial
ON INTERPRETATION
10 7
Page No 10
Man is just Man is not just
\ /
X
/ \
D. Denial C. Affirmation
Man is not notjust Man is notjust
Here 'is' and 'is not' are added either to 'just' or to 'notjust'. This then is the proper scheme for these
propositions, as has been said in the Analytics. The same rule holds good, if the subject is distributed. Thus
we have the table:
A'. Affirmation B'. Denial
Every man is just Not every man is just
\ /
X
D'. Denial / \ C'. Affirmation
Not every man is notjust Every man is notjust Yet here it is not possible, in the same way as in the former
case, that the propositions joined in the table by a diagonal line should both be true; though under certain
circumstances this is the case.
We have thus set out two pairs of opposite propositions; there are moreover two other pairs, if a term be
conjoined with 'notman', the latter forming a kind of subject. Thus:
A." B."
Notman is just Notman is not just
\ /
X
D." / \ C."
Notman is not notjust Notman is notjust
This is an exhaustive enumeration of all the pairs of opposite propositions that can possibly be framed. This
last group should remain distinct from those which preceded it, since it employs as its subject the expression
'notman'.
When the verb 'is' does not fit the structure of the sentence (for instance, when the verbs 'walks', 'enjoys
health' are used), that scheme applies, which applied when the word 'is' was added.
Thus we have the propositions: 'every man enjoys health', 'every man doesnotenjoyhealth', 'all that is
notman enjoys health', 'all that is notman doesnotenjoyhealth'. We must not in these propositions use
the expression 'not every man'. The negative must be attached to the word 'man', for the word 'every' does not
give to the subject a universal significance, but implies that, as a subject, it is distributed. This is plain from
the following pairs: 'man enjoys health', 'man does not enjoy health'; 'notman enjoys health', 'not man does
not enjoy health'. These propositions differ from the former in being indefinite and not universal in character.
Thus the adjectives 'every' and no additional significance except that the subject, whether in a positive or in a
negative sentence, is distributed. The rest of the sentence, therefore, will in each case be the same.
Since the contrary of the proposition 'every animal is just' is 'no animal is just', it is plain that these two
propositions will never both be true at the same time or with reference to the same subject. Sometimes,
however, the contradictories of these contraries will both be true, as in the instance before us: the propositions
'not every animal is just' and 'some animals are just' are both true.
ON INTERPRETATION
10 8
Page No 11
Further, the proposition 'no man is just' follows from the proposition 'every man is not just' and the
proposition 'not every man is not just', which is the opposite of 'every man is notjust', follows from the
proposition 'some men are just'; for if this be true, there must be some just men.
It is evident, also, that when the subject is individual, if a question is asked and the negative answer is the true
one, a certain positive proposition is also true. Thus, if the question were asked Socrates wise?' and the
negative answer were the true one, the positive inference 'Then Socrates is unwise' is correct. But no such
inference is correct in the case of universals, but rather a negative proposition. For instance, if to the question
'Is every man wise?' the answer is 'no', the inference 'Then every man is unwise' is false. But under these
circumstances the inference 'Not every man is wise' is correct. This last is the contradictory, the former the
contrary. Negative expressions, which consist of an indefinite noun or predicate, such as 'notman' or
'notjust', may seem to be denials containing neither noun nor verb in the proper sense of the words. But they
are not. For a denial must always be either true or false, and he that uses the expression 'not man', if nothing
more be added, is not nearer but rather further from making a true or a false statement than he who uses the
expression 'man'.
The propositions 'everything that is not man is just', and the contradictory of this, are not equivalent to any of
the other propositions; on the other hand, the proposition 'everything that is not man is not just' is equivalent
to the proposition 'nothing that is not man is just'.
The conversion of the position of subject and predicate in a sentence involves no difference in its meaning.
Thus we say 'man is white' and 'white is man'. If these were not equivalent, there would be more than one
contradictory to the same proposition, whereas it has been demonstrated' that each proposition has one proper
contradictory and one only. For of the proposition 'man is white' the appropriate contradictory is 'man is not
white', and of the proposition 'white is man', if its meaning be different, the contradictory will either be 'white
is not notman' or 'white is not man'. Now the former of these is the contradictory of the proposition 'white is
notman', and the latter of these is the contradictory of the proposition 'man is white'; thus there will be two
contradictories to one proposition.
It is evident, therefore, that the inversion of the relative position of subject and predicate does not affect the
sense of affirmations and denials.
11
There is no unity about an affirmation or denial which, either positively or negatively, predicates one thing of
many subjects, or many things of the same subject, unless that which is indicated by the many is really some
one thing. do not apply this word 'one' to those things which, though they have a single recognized name, yet
do not combine to form a unity. Thus, man may be an animal, and biped, and domesticated, but these three
predicates combine to form a unity. On the other hand, the predicates 'white', 'man', and 'walking' do not thus
combine. Neither, therefore, if these three form the subject of an affirmation, nor if they form its predicate, is
there any unity about that affirmation. In both cases the unity is linguistic, but not real.
If therefore the dialectical question is a request for an answer, i.e. either for the admission of a premiss or for
the admission of one of two contradictoriesand the premiss is itself always one of two contradictoriesthe
answer to such a question as contains the above predicates cannot be a single proposition. For as I have
explained in the Topics, question is not a single one, even if the answer asked for is true.
At the same time it is plain that a question of the form 'what is it?' is not a dialectical question, for a
dialectical questioner must by the form of his question give his opponent the chance of announcing one of
two alternatives, whichever he wishes. He must therefore put the question into a more definite form, and
ON INTERPRETATION
11 9
Page No 12
inquire, e.g.. whether man has such and such a characteristic or not.
Some combinations of predicates are such that the separate predicates unite to form a single predicate. Let us
consider under what conditions this is and is not possible. We may either state in two separate propositions
that man is an animal and that man is a biped, or we may combine the two, and state that man is an animal
with two feet. Similarly we may use 'man' and 'white' as separate predicates, or unite them into one. Yet if a
man is a shoemaker and is also good, we cannot construct a composite proposition and say that he is a good
shoemaker. For if, whenever two separate predicates truly belong to a subject, it follows that the predicate
resulting from their combination also truly belongs to the subject, many absurd results ensue. For instance, a
man is man and white. Therefore, if predicates may always be combined, he is a white man. Again, if the
predicate 'white' belongs to him, then the combination of that predicate with the former composite predicate
will be permissible. Thus it will be right to say that he is a white man so on indefinitely. Or, again, we may
combine the predicates 'musical', 'white', and 'walking', and these may be combined many times. Similarly we
may say that Socrates is Socrates and a man, and that therefore he is the man Socrates, or that Socrates is a
man and a biped, and that therefore he is a twofooted man. Thus it is manifest that if man states
unconditionally that predicates can always be combined, many absurd consequences ensue.
We will now explain what ought to be laid down.
Those predicates, and terms forming the subject of predication, which are accidental either to the same
subject or to one another, do not combine to form a unity. Take the proposition 'man is white of complexion
and musical'. Whiteness and being musical do not coalesce to form a unity, for they belong only accidentally
to the same subject. Nor yet, if it were true to say that that which is white is musical, would the terms
'musical' and 'white' form a unity, for it is only incidentally that that which is musical is white; the
combination of the two will, therefore, not form a unity.
Thus, again, whereas, if a man is both good and a shoemaker, we cannot combine the two propositions and
say simply that he is a good shoemaker, we are, at the same time, able to combine the predicates 'animal' and
'biped' and say that a man is an animal with two feet, for these predicates are not accidental.
Those predicates, again, cannot form a unity, of which the one is implicit in the other: thus we cannot
combine the predicate 'white' again and again with that which already contains the notion 'white', nor is it
right to call a man an animalman or a twofooted man; for the notions 'animal' and 'biped' are implicit in the
word 'man'. On the other hand, it is possible to predicate a term simply of any one instance, and to say that
some one particular man is a man or that some one white man is a white man.
Yet this is not always possible: indeed, when in the adjunct there is some opposite which involves a
contradiction, the predication of the simple term is impossible. Thus it is not right to call a dead man a man.
When, however, this is not the case, it is not impossible.
Yet the facts of the case might rather be stated thus: when some such opposite elements are present,
resolution is never possible, but when they are not present, resolution is nevertheless not always possible.
Take the proposition 'Homer is soandso', say 'a poet'; does it follow that Homer is, or does it not? The verb
'is' is here used of Homer only incidentally, the proposition being that Homer is a poet, not that he is, in the
independent sense of the word.
Thus, in the case of those predications which have within them no contradiction when the nouns are
expanded into definitions, and wherein the predicates belong to the subject in their own proper sense and not
in any indirect way, the individual may be the subject of the simple propositions as well as of the composite.
But in the case of that which is not, it is not true to say that because it is the object of opinion, it is; for the
opinion held about it is that it is not, not that it is.
ON INTERPRETATION
11 10
Page No 13
12
As these distinctions have been made, we must consider the mutual relation of those affirmations and denials
which assert or deny possibility or contingency, impossibility or necessity: for the subject is not without
difficulty.
We admit that of composite expressions those are contradictory each to each which have the verb 'to be' its
positive and negative form respectively. Thus the contradictory of the proposition 'man is' is 'man is not', not
'notman is', and the contradictory of 'man is white' is 'man is not white', not 'man is notwhite'. For
otherwise, since either the positive or the negative proposition is true of any subject, it will turn out true to
say that a piece of wood is a man that is not white.
Now if this is the case, in those propositions which do not contain the verb 'to be' the verb which takes its
place will exercise the same function. Thus the contradictory of 'man walks' is 'man does not walk', not
'notman walks'; for to say 'man walks' merely equivalent to saying 'man is walking'.
If then this rule is universal, the contradictory of 'it may be' is may not be', not 'it cannot be'.
Now it appears that the same thing both may and may not be; for instance, everything that may be cut or may
walk may also escape cutting and refrain from walking; and the reason is that those things that have
potentiality in this sense are not always actual. In such cases, both the positive and the negative propositions
will be true; for that which is capable of walking or of being seen has also a potentiality in the opposite
direction.
But since it is impossible that contradictory propositions should both be true of the same subject, it follows
that' it may not be' is not the contradictory of 'it may be'. For it is a logical consequence of what we have said,
either that the same predicate can be both applicable and inapplicable to one and the same subject at the same
time, or that it is not by the addition of the verbs 'be' and 'not be', respectively, that positive and negative
propositions are formed. If the former of these alternatives must be rejected, we must choose the latter.
The contradictory, then, of 'it may be' is 'it cannot be'. The same rule applies to the proposition 'it is
contingent that it should be'; the contradictory of this is 'it is not contingent that it should be'. The similar
propositions, such as 'it is necessary' and 'it is impossible', may be dealt with in the same manner. For it
comes about that just as in the former instances the verbs 'is' and 'is not' were added to the subjectmatter of
the sentence 'white' and 'man', so here 'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' are the subjectmatter and
'is possible', 'is contingent', are added. These indicate that a certain thing is or is not possible, just as in the
former instances 'is' and 'is not' indicated that certain things were or were not the case.
The contradictory, then, of 'it may not be' is not 'it cannot be', but 'it cannot not be', and the contradictory of 'it
may be' is not 'it may not be', but cannot be'. Thus the propositions 'it may be' and 'it may not be' appear each
to imply the other: for, since these two propositions are not contradictory, the same thing both may and may
not be. But the propositions 'it may be' and 'it cannot be' can never be true of the same subject at the same
time, for they are contradictory. Nor can the propositions 'it may not be' and 'it cannot not be' be at once true
of the same subject.
The propositions which have to do with necessity are governed by the same principle. The contradictory of 'it
is necessary that it should be', is not 'it is necessary that it should not be,' but 'it is not necessary that it should
be', and the contradictory of 'it is necessary that it should not be' is 'it is not necessary that it should not be'.
Again, the contradictory of 'it is impossible that it should be' is not 'it is impossible that it should not be' but 'it
ON INTERPRETATION
12 11
Page No 14
is not impossible that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is impossible that it should not be' is 'it is not
impossible that it should not be'.
To generalize, we must, as has been stated, define the clauses 'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' as
the subjectmatter of the propositions, and in making these terms into affirmations and denials we must
combine them with 'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' respectively.
We must consider the following pairs as contradictory propositions:
It may be. It cannot be.
It is contingent. It is not contingent.
It is impossible. It is not impossible.
It is necessary. It is not necessary.
It is true. It is not true.
13
Logical sequences follow in due course when we have arranged the propositions thus. From the proposition
'it may be' it follows that it is contingent, and the relation is reciprocal. It follows also that it is not impossible
and not necessary.
From the proposition 'it may not be' or 'it is contingent that it should not be' it follows that it is not necessary
that it should not be and that it is not impossible that it should not be. From the proposition 'it cannot be' or 'it
is not contingent' it follows that it is necessary that it should not be and that it is impossible that it should be.
From the proposition 'it cannot not be' or 'it is not contingent that it should not be' it follows that it is
necessary that it should be and that it is impossible that it should not be.
Let us consider these statements by the help of a table:
A. B. It may be. It cannot be. It is contingent. It is not contingent. It is not impossible It is impossible that it
that it should be. should be. It is not necessary It is necessary that it that it should be. should not be.
C. D. It may not be. It cannot not be. It is contingent that it It is not contingent that should not be. it should
not be. It is not impossible It is impossible thatit that it should not be. should not be. It is not necessary that It
is necessary that it it should not be. should be.
Now the propositions 'it is impossible that it should be' and 'it is not impossible that it should be' are
consequent upon the propositions 'it may be', 'it is contingent', and 'it cannot be', 'it is not contingent', the
contradictories upon the contradictories. But there is inversion. The negative of the proposition 'it is
impossible' is consequent upon the proposition 'it may be' and the corresponding positive in the first case
upon the negative in the second. For 'it is impossible' is a positive proposition and 'it is not impossible' is
negative.
We must investigate the relation subsisting between these propositions and those which predicate necessity.
That there is a distinction is clear. In this case, contrary propositions follow respectively from contradictory
propositions, and the contradictory propositions belong to separate sequences. For the proposition 'it is not
necessary that it should be' is not the negative of 'it is necessary that it should not be', for both these
propositions may be true of the same subject; for when it is necessary that a thing should not be, it is not
necessary that it should be. The reason why the propositions predicating necessity do not follow in the same
kind of sequence as the rest, lies in the fact that the proposition 'it is impossible' is equivalent, when used with
ON INTERPRETATION
13 12
Page No 15
a contrary subject, to the proposition 'it is necessary'. For when it is impossible that a thing should be, it is
necessary, not that it should be, but that it should not be, and when it is impossible that a thing should not be,
it is necessary that it should be. Thus, if the propositions predicating impossibility or nonimpossibility
follow without change of subject from those predicating possibility or nonpossibility, those predicating
necessity must follow with the contrary subject; for the propositions 'it is impossible' and 'it is necessary' are
not equivalent, but, as has been said, inversely connected.
Yet perhaps it is impossible that the contradictory propositions predicating necessity should be thus arranged.
For when it is necessary that a thing should be, it is possible that it should be. (For if not, the opposite
follows, since one or the other must follow; so, if it is not possible, it is impossible, and it is thus impossible
that a thing should be, which must necessarily be; which is absurd.)
Yet from the proposition 'it may be' it follows that it is not impossible, and from that it follows that it is not
necessary; it comes about therefore that the thing which must necessarily be need not be; which is absurd. But
again, the proposition 'it is necessary that it should be' does not follow from the proposition 'it may be', nor
does the proposition 'it is necessary that it should not be'. For the proposition 'it may be' implies a twofold
possibility, while, if either of the two former propositions is true, the twofold possibility vanishes. For if a
thing may be, it may also not be, but if it is necessary that it should be or that it should not be, one of the two
alternatives will be excluded. It remains, therefore, that the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not
be' follows from the proposition 'it may be'. For this is true also of that which must necessarily be.
Moreover the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not be' is the contradictory of that which follows
from the proposition 'it cannot be'; for 'it cannot be' is followed by 'it is impossible that it should be' and by 'it
is necessary that it should not be', and the contradictory of this is the proposition 'it is not necessary that it
should not be'. Thus in this case also contradictory propositions follow contradictory in the way indicated,
and no logical impossibilities occur when they are thus arranged.
It may be questioned whether the proposition 'it may be' follows from the proposition 'it is necessary that it
should be'. If not, the contradictory must follow, namely that it cannot be, or, if a man should maintain that
this is not the contradictory, then the proposition 'it may not be'.
Now both of these are false of that which necessarily is. At the same time, it is thought that if a thing may be
cut it may also not be cut, if a thing may be it may also not be, and thus it would follow that a thing which
must necessarily be may possibly not be; which is false. It is evident, then, that it is not always the case that
that which may be or may walk possesses also a potentiality in the other direction. There are exceptions. In
the first place we must except those things which possess a potentiality not in accordance with a rational
principle, as fire possesses the potentiality of giving out heat, that is, an irrational capacity. Those
potentialities which involve a rational principle are potentialities of more than one result, that is, of contrary
results; those that are irrational are not always thus constituted. As I have said, fire cannot both heat and not
heat, neither has anything that is always actual any twofold potentiality. Yet some even of those potentialities
which are irrational admit of opposite results. However, thus much has been said to emphasize the truth that it
is not every potentiality which admits of opposite results, even where the word is used always in the same
sense.
But in some cases the word is used equivocally. For the term 'possible' is ambiguous, being used in the one
case with reference to facts, to that which is actualized, as when a man is said to find walking possible
because he is actually walking, and generally when a capacity is predicated because it is actually realized; in
the other case, with reference to a state in which realization is conditionally practicable, as when a man is said
to find walking possible because under certain conditions he would walk. This last sort of potentiality
belongs only to that which can be in motion, the former can exist also in the case of that which has not this
power. Both of that which is walking and is actual, and of that which has the capacity though not necessarily
ON INTERPRETATION
13 13
Page No 16
realized, it is true to say that it is not impossible that it should walk (or, in the other case, that it should be),
but while we cannot predicate this latter kind of potentiality of that which is necessary in the unqualified
sense of the word, we can predicate the former.
Our conclusion, then, is this: that since the universal is consequent upon the particular, that which is
necessary is also possible, though not in every sense in which the word may be used.
We may perhaps state that necessity and its absence are the initial principles of existence and nonexistence,
and that all else must be regarded as posterior to these.
It is plain from what has been said that that which is of necessity is actual. Thus, if that which is eternal is
prior, actuality also is prior to potentiality. Some things are actualities without potentiality, namely, the
primary substances; a second class consists of those things which are actual but also potential, whose
actuality is in nature prior to their potentiality, though posterior in time; a third class comprises those things
which are never actualized, but are pure potentialities.
14
The question arises whether an affirmation finds its contrary in a denial or in another affirmation; whether the
proposition 'every man is just' finds its contrary in the proposition 'no man is just', or in the proposition 'every
man is unjust'. Take the propositions 'Callias is just', 'Callias is not just', 'Callias is unjust'; we have to
discover which of these form contraries.
Now if the spoken word corresponds with the judgement of the mind, and if, in thought, that judgement is the
contrary of another, which pronounces a contrary fact, in the way, for instance, in which the judgement 'every
man is just' pronounces a contrary to that pronounced by the judgement 'every man is unjust', the same must
needs hold good with regard to spoken affirmations.
But if, in thought, it is not the judgement which pronounces a contrary fact that is the contrary of another,
then one affirmation will not find its contrary in another, but rather in the corresponding denial. We must
therefore consider which true judgement is the contrary of the false, that which forms the denial of the false
judgement or that which affirms the contrary fact.
Let me illustrate. There is a true judgement concerning that which is good, that it is good; another, a false
judgement, that it is not good; and a third, which is distinct, that it is bad. Which of these two is contrary to
the true? And if they are one and the same, which mode of expression forms the contrary?
It is an error to suppose that judgements are to be defined as contrary in virtue of the fact that they have
contrary subjects; for the judgement concerning a good thing, that it is good, and that concerning a bad thing,
that it is bad, may be one and the same, and whether they are so or not, they both represent the truth. Yet the
subjects here are contrary. But judgements are not contrary because they have contrary subjects, but because
they are to the contrary effect.
Now if we take the judgement that that which is good is good, and another that it is not good, and if there are
at the same time other attributes, which do not and cannot belong to the good, we must nevertheless refuse to
treat as the contraries of the true judgement those which opine that some other attribute subsists which does
not subsist, as also those that opine that some other attribute does not subsist which does subsist, for both
these classes of judgement are of unlimited content.
Those judgements must rather be termed contrary to the true judgements, in which error is present. Now these
ON INTERPRETATION
14 14
Page No 17
judgements are those which are concerned with the starting points of generation, and generation is the passing
from one extreme to its opposite; therefore error is a like transition.
Now that which is good is both good and not bad. The first quality is part of its essence, the second
accidental; for it is by accident that it is not bad. But if that true judgement is most really true, which
concerns the subject's intrinsic nature, then that false judgement likewise is most really false, which concerns
its intrinsic nature. Now the judgement that that is good is not good is a false judgement concerning its
intrinsic nature, the judgement that it is bad is one concerning that which is accidental. Thus the judgement
which denies the true judgement is more really false than that which positively asserts the presence of the
contrary quality. But it is the man who forms that judgement which is contrary to the true who is most
thoroughly deceived, for contraries are among the things which differ most widely within the same class. If
then of the two judgements one is contrary to the true judgement, but that which is contradictory is the more
truly contrary, then the latter, it seems, is the real contrary. The judgement that that which is good is bad is
composite. For presumably the man who forms that judgement must at the same time understand that that
which is good is not good.
Further, the contradictory is either always the contrary or never; therefore, if it must necessarily be so in all
other cases, our conclusion in the case just dealt with would seem to be correct. Now where terms have no
contrary, that judgement is false, which forms the negative of the true; for instance, he who thinks a man is
not a man forms a false judgement. If then in these cases the negative is the contrary, then the principle is
universal in its application.
Again, the judgement that that which is not good is not good is parallel with the judgement that that which is
good is good. Besides these there is the judgement that that which is good is not good, parallel with the
judgement that that that is not good is good. Let us consider, therefore, what would form the contrary of the
true judgement that that which is not good is not good. The judgement that it is bad would, of course, fail to
meet the case, since two true judgements are never contrary and this judgement might be true at the same
time as that with which it is connected. For since some things which are not good are bad, both judgements
may be true. Nor is the judgement that it is not bad the contrary, for this too might be true, since both
qualities might be predicated of the same subject. It remains, therefore, that of the judgement concerning that
which is not good, that it is not good, the contrary judgement is that it is good; for this is false. In the same
way, moreover, the judgement concerning that which is good, that it is not good, is the contrary of the
judgement that it is good.
It is evident that it will make no difference if we universalize the positive judgement, for the universal
negative judgement will form the contrary. For instance, the contrary of the judgement that everything that is
good is good is that nothing that is good is good. For the judgement that that which is good is good, if the
subject be understood in a universal sense, is equivalent to the judgement that whatever is good is good, and
this is identical with the judgement that everything that is good is good. We may deal similarly with
judgements concerning that which is not good.
If therefore this is the rule with judgements, and if spoken affirmations and denials are judgements expressed
in words, it is plain that the universal denial is the contrary of the affirmation about the same subject. Thus
the propositions 'everything good is good', 'every man is good', have for their contraries the propositions
'nothing good is good', 'no man is good'. The contradictory propositions, on the other hand, are 'not
everything good is good', 'not every man is good'.
It is evident, also, that neither true judgements nor true propositions can be contrary the one to the other. For
whereas, when two propositions are true, a man may state both at the same time without inconsistency,
contrary propositions are those which state contrary conditions, and contrary conditions cannot subsist at one
and the same time in the same subject.
ON INTERPRETATION
14 15
Page No 18
THE END
ON INTERPRETATION
14 16
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. ON INTERPRETATION, page = 4
3. by Aristotle, page = 4
4. 1, page = 4
5. 2, page = 4
6. 3, page = 5
7. 4, page = 5
8. 5, page = 6
9. 6, page = 6
10. 7, page = 7
11. 8, page = 8
12. 9, page = 8
13. 10, page = 10
14. 11, page = 12
15. 12, page = 14
16. 13, page = 15
17. 14, page = 17