Title:   The Categories

Subject:  

Author:   Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Bookmarks





Page No 1


The Categories

Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

The Categories .....................................................................................................................................................1

Aristotle...................................................................................................................................................1

Section 1  ...............................................................................................................................................................1

Part 1........................................................................................................................................................1

Part 2........................................................................................................................................................2

Part 3........................................................................................................................................................2

Part 4........................................................................................................................................................2

Part 5........................................................................................................................................................3

Part 6........................................................................................................................................................6

Section 2  ...............................................................................................................................................................8

Part 7........................................................................................................................................................8

Part 8......................................................................................................................................................11

Section 3  .............................................................................................................................................................15

Part 9......................................................................................................................................................15

Part 10....................................................................................................................................................15

Part 11....................................................................................................................................................18

Part 12....................................................................................................................................................18

Part 13....................................................................................................................................................19

Part 14....................................................................................................................................................20

Part 15....................................................................................................................................................20


The Categories

i



Top




Page No 3


The Categories

Aristotle

Translated by E. M. Edghill

Section 1   

Part 1 

Part 2 

Part 3 

Part 4 

Part 5 

Part 6  

Section 2   

Part 7 

Part 8  

Section 3   

Part 9 

Part 10 

Part 11 

Part 12 

Part 13 

Part 14 

Part 15  

Section 1 

Part 1

Things are said to be named 'equivocally' when, though they have  a  common name, the definition

corresponding with the name differs  for  each. Thus, a real man and a figure in a picture can both lay  claim to

the name 'animal'; yet these are equivocally so named,  for, though  they have a common name, the definition

corresponding  with the name  differs for each. For should any one define in what  sense each is an  animal, his

definition in the one case will be  appropriate to that  case only. 

On the other hand, things are said to be named 'univocally' which  have both the name and the definition

answering to the name in  common. A man and an ox are both 'animal', and these are  univocally  so named,

inasmuch as not only the name, but also the  definition, is  the same in both cases: for if a man should state  in

what sense each  is an animal, the statement in the one case  would be identical with  that in the other. 

Things are said to be named 'derivatively', which derive their  name from some other name, but differ from it

in termination.  Thus  the grammarian derives his name from the word 'grammar', and  the  courageous man

from the word 'courage'. 

The Categories 1



Top




Page No 4


Part 2

Forms of speech are either simple or composite. Examples of the  latter are such expressions as 'the man runs',

'the man wins'; of  the  former 'man', 'ox', 'runs', 'wins'. 

Of things themselves some are predicable of a subject, and are  never present in a subject. Thus 'man' is

predicable of the  individual man, and is never present in a subject. 

By being 'present in a subject' I do not mean present as parts  are  present in a whole, but being incapable of

existence apart  from the  said subject. 

Some things, again, are present in a subject, but are never  predicable of a subject. For instance, a certain point

of  grammatical  knowledge is present in the mind, but is not  predicable of any  subject; or again, a certain

whiteness may be  present in the body (for  colour requires a material basis), yet  it is never predicable of

anything. 

Other things, again, are both predicable of a subject and present  in a subject. Thus while knowledge is present

in the human mind,  it  is predicable of grammar. 

There is, lastly, a class of things which are neither present in  a  subject nor predicable of a subject, such as the

individual man  or the  individual horse. But, to speak more generally, that which  is  individual and has the

character of a unit is never predicable  of a  subject. Yet in some cases there is nothing to prevent such  being

present in a subject. Thus a certain point of grammatical  knowledge is  present in a subject. 

Part 3

When one thing is predicated of another, all that which is  predicable of the predicate will be predicable also

of the  subject.  Thus, 'man' is predicated of the individual man; but  'animal' is  predicated of 'man'; it will,

therefore, be  predicable of the  individual man also: for the individual man is  both 'man' and  'animal'. 

If genera are different and coordinate, their differentiae are  themselves different in kind. Take as an instance

the genus  'animal'  and the genus 'knowledge'. 'With feet', 'twofooted',  'winged',  'aquatic', are differentiae of

'animal'; the species of  knowledge are  not distinguished by the same differentiae. One  species of knowledge

does not differ from another in being  'twofooted'. 

But where one genus is subordinate to another, there is nothing  to  prevent their having the same differentiae:

for the greater  class is  predicated of the lesser, so that all the differentiae  of the  predicate will be differentiae

also of the subject. 

Part 4

Expressions which are in no way composite signify substance,  quantity, quality, relation, place, time,

position, state,  action, or  affection. To sketch my meaning roughly, examples of  substance are  'man' or 'the

horse', of quantity, such terms as  'two cubits long' or  'three cubits long', of quality, such  attributes as 'white',

'grammatical'. 'Double', 'half',  'greater', fall under the category of  relation; 'in a the market  place', 'in the

Lyceum', under that of  place; 'yesterday', 'last  year', under that of time. 'Lying',  'sitting', are terms  indicating

position, 'shod', 'armed', state; 'to  lance', 'to  cauterize', action; 'to be lanced', 'to be cauterized',  affection. 

No one of these terms, in and by itself, involves an affirmation;  it is by the combination of such terms that

positive or negative  statements arise. For every assertion must, as is admitted, be  either  true or false, whereas


The Categories

Part 2 2



Top




Page No 5


expressions which are not in any  way composite  such as 'man', 'white', 'runs', 'wins', cannot be  either true or

false. 

Part 5

Substance, in the truest and primary and most definite sense of  the word, is that which is neither predicable of

a subject nor  present in a subject; for instance, the individual man or horse.  But  in a secondary sense those

things are called substances  within which,  as species, the primary substances are included;  also those which,

as  genera, include the species. For instance,  the individual man is  included in the species 'man', and the  genus

to which the species  belongs is 'animal'; these,  thereforethat is to say, the species  'man' and the genus

'animal,are termed secondary substances. 

It is plain from what has been said that both the name and the  definition of the predicate must be predicable

of the subject.  For  instance, 'man' is predicted of the individual man. Now in  this case  the name of the species

man' is applied to the  individual, for we use  the term 'man' in describing the  individual; and the definition of

'man' will also be predicated  of the individual man, for the  individual man is both man and  animal. Thus, both

the name and the  definition of the species are  predicable of the individual. 

With regard, on the other hand, to those things which are present  in a subject, it is generally the case that

neither their name  nor  their definition is predicable of that in which they are  present.  Though, however, the

definition is never predicable,  there is nothing  in certain cases to prevent the name being used.  For instance,

'white'  being present in a body is predicated of  that in which it is present,  for a body is called white: the

definition, however, of the colour  white' is never predicable of  the body. 

Everything except primary substances is either predicable of a  primary substance or present in a primary

substance. This becomes  evident by reference to particular instances which occur.  'Animal' is  predicated of

the species 'man', therefore of the  individual man, for  if there were no individual man of whom it  could be

predicated, it  could not be predicated of the species  'man' at all. Again, colour is  present in body, therefore in

individual bodies, for if there were no  individual body in which  it was present, it could not be present in  body

at all. Thus  everything except primary substances is either  predicated of  primary substances, or is present in

them, and if these  last did  not exist, it would be impossible for anything else to exist. 

Of secondary substances, the species is more truly substance than  the genus, being more nearly related to

primary substance. For if  any  one should render an account of what a primary substance is,  he would  render a

more instructive account, and one more proper  to the subject,  by stating the species than by stating the genus.

Thus, he would give  a more instructive account of an individual  man by stating that he was  man than by

stating that he was  animal, for the former description is  peculiar to the individual  in a greater degree, while

the latter is  too general. Again, the  man who gives an account of the nature of an  individual tree will  give a

more instructive account by mentioning the  species 'tree'  than by mentioning the genus 'plant'. 

Moreover, primary substances are most properly called substances  in virtue of the fact that they are the

entities which underlie  every. else, and that everything else is either predicated of  them or  present in them.

Now the same relation which subsists  between primary  substance and everything else subsists also  between

the species and  the genus: for the species is to the  genus as subject is to predicate,  since the genus is

predicated  of the species, whereas the species  cannot be predicated of the  genus. Thus we have a second

ground for  asserting that the  species is more truly substance than the genus. 

Of species themselves, except in the case of such as are genera,  no one is more truly substance than another.

We should not give a  more appropriate account of the individual man by stating the  species  to which he

belonged, than we should of an individual  horse by  adopting the same method of definition. In the same way,


The Categories

Part 5 3



Top




Page No 6


of primary  substances, no one is more truly substance than  another; an individual  man is not more truly

substance than an  individual ox. 

It is, then, with good reason that of all that remains, when we  exclude primary substances, we concede to

species and genera  alone  the name 'secondary substance', for these alone of all the  predicates  convey a

knowledge of primary substance. For it is by  stating the  species or the genus that we appropriately define any

individual man;  and we shall make our definition more exact by  stating the former than  by stating the latter.

All other things  that we state, such as that he  is white, that he runs, and so on,  are irrelevant to the definition.

Thus it is just that these  alone, apart from primary substances,  should be called  substances. 

Further, primary substances are most properly so called, because  they underlie and are the subjects of

everything else. Now the  same  relation that subsists between primary substance and  everything else  subsists

also between the species and the genus  to which the primary  substance belongs, on the one hand, and  every

attribute which is not  included within these, on the other.  For these are the subjects of all  such. If we call an

individual  man 'skilled in grammar', the predicate  is applicable also to the  species and to the genus to which

he  belongs. This law holds good  in all cases. 

It is a common characteristic of all sub. stance that it is never  present in a subject. For primary substance is

neither present in  a  subject nor predicated of a subject; while, with regard to  secondary  substances, it is clear

from the following arguments  (apart from  others) that they are not present in a subject. For  'man' is  predicated

of the individual man, but is not present in  any subject:  for manhood is not present in the individual man. In

the same way,  'animal' is also predicated of the individual man,  but is not present  in him. Again, when a thing

is present in a  subject, though the name  may quite well be applied to that in  which it is present, the  definition

cannot be applied. Yet of  secondary substances, not only  the name, but also the definition,  applies to the

subject: we should  use both the definition of the  species and that of the genus with  reference to the individual

man. Thus substance cannot be present in a  subject. 

Yet this is not peculiar to substance, for it is also the case  that differentiae cannot be present in subjects. The

characteristics  'terrestrial' and 'twofooted' are predicated of  the species 'man',  but not present in it. For they

are not in  man. Moreover, the  definition of the differentia may be  predicated of that of which the  differentia

itself is predicated.  For instance, if the characteristic  'terrestrial' is predicated  of the species 'man', the

definition also  of that characteristic  may be used to form the predicate of the  species 'man': for 'man'  is

terrestrial. 

The fact that the parts of substances appear to be present in the  whole, as in a subject, should not make us

apprehensive lest we  should have to admit that such parts are not substances: for in  explaining the phrase

'being present in a subject', we stated'  that  we meant 'otherwise than as parts in a whole'. 

It is the mark of substances and of differentiae that, in all  propositions of which they form the predicate, they

are  predicated  univocally. For all such propositions have for their  subject either  the individual or the species.

It is true that,  inasmuch as primary  substance is not predicable of anything, it  can never form the  predicate of

any proposition. But of secondary  substances, the species  is predicated of the individual, the  genus both of

the species and of  the individual. Similarly the  differentiae are predicated of the  species and of the

individuals. Moreover, the definition of the  species and that of  the genus are applicable to the primary

substance,  and that of  the genus to the species. For all that is predicated of  the  predicate will be predicated

also of the subject. Similarly, the  definition of the differentiae will be applicable to the species  and  to the

individuals. But it was stated above that the word  'univocal'  was applied to those things which had both name

and  definition in  common. It is, therefore, established that in every  proposition, of  which either substance or a

differentia forms the  predicate, these are  predicated univocally. 


The Categories

Part 5 4



Top




Page No 7


All substance appears to signify that which is individual. In the  case of primary substance this is indisputably

true, for the  thing is  a unit. In the case of secondary substances, when we  speak, for  instance, of 'man' or

'animal', our form of speech  gives the  impression that we are here also indicating that which  is individual,  but

the impression is not strictly true; for a  secondary substance is  not an individual, but a class with a  certain

qualification; for it is  not one and single as a primary  substance is; the words 'man',  'animal', are predicable of

more  than one subject. 

Yet species and genus do not merely indicate quality, like the  term 'white'; 'white' indicates quality and

nothing further, but  species and genus determine the quality with reference to a  substance: they signify

substance qualitatively differentiated.  The  determinate qualification covers a larger field in the case  of the

genus that in that of the species: he who uses the word  'animal' is  herein using a word of wider extension than

he who  uses the word  'man'. 

Another mark of substance is that it has no contrary. What could  be the contrary of any primary substance,

such as the individual  man  or animal? It has none. Nor can the species or the genus have  a  contrary. Yet this

characteristic is not peculiar to substance,  but is  true of many other things, such as quantity. There is  nothing

that  forms the contrary of 'two cubits long' or of 'three  cubits long', or  of 'ten', or of any such term. A man

may contend  that 'much' is the  contrary of 'little', or 'great' of 'small',  but of definite  quantitative terms no

contrary exists. 

Substance, again, does not appear to admit of variation of  degree.  I do not mean by this that one substance

cannot be more  or less truly  substance than another, for it has already been  stated' that this is  the case; but that

no single substance  admits of varying degrees  within itself. For instance, one  particular substance, 'man',

cannot  be more or less man either  than himself at some other time or than  some other man. One man  cannot

be more man than another, as that which  is white may be  more or less white than some other white object, or

as  that which  is beautiful may be more or less beautiful than some other  beautiful object. The same quality,

moreover, is said to subsist  in a  thing in varying degrees at different times. A body, being  white, is  said to be

whiter at one time than it was before, or,  being warm, is  said to be warmer or less warm than at some other

time. But substance  is not said to be more or less that which it  is: a man is not more  truly a man at one time

than he was before,  nor is anything, if it is  substance, more or less what it is.  Substance, then, does not admit

of  variation of degree. 

The most distinctive mark of substance appears to be that, while  remaining numerically one and the same, it

is capable of  admitting  contrary qualities. From among things other than  substance, we should  find ourselves

unable to bring forward any  which possessed this mark.  Thus, one and the same colour cannot  be white and

black. Nor can the  same one action be good and bad:  this law holds good with everything  that is not

substance. But  one and the selfsame substance, while  retaining its identity, is  yet capable of admitting

contrary  qualities. The same individual  person is at one time white, at another  black, at one time warm,  at

another cold, at one time good, at another  bad. This capacity  is found nowhere else, though it might be

maintained that a  statement or opinion was an exception to the rule.  The same  statement, it is agreed, can be

both true and false. For if  the  statement 'he is sitting' is true, yet, when the person in  question has risen, the

same statement will be false. The same  applies to opinions. For if any one thinks truly that a person is  sitting,

yet, when that person has risen, this same opinion, if  still  held, will be false. Yet although this exception may

be  allowed, there  is, nevertheless, a difference in the manner in  which the thing takes  place. It is by

themselves changing that  substances admit contrary  qualities. It is thus that that which  was hot becomes cold,

for it has  entered into a different state.  Similarly that which was white becomes  black, and that which was  bad

good, by a process of change; and in the  same way in all  other cases it is by changing that substances are

capable of  admitting contrary qualities. But statements and opinions  themselves remain unaltered in all

respects: it is by the  alteration  in the facts of the case that the contrary quality  comes to be theirs.  The

statement 'he is sitting' remains  unaltered, but it is at one time  true, at another false,  according to

circumstances. What has been said  of statements  applies also to opinions. Thus, in respect of the manner  in


The Categories

Part 5 5



Top




Page No 8


which  the thing takes place, it is the peculiar mark of substance  that  it should be capable of admitting

contrary qualities; for it is  by itself changing that it does so. 

If, then, a man should make this exception and contend that  statements and opinions are capable of admitting

contrary  qualities,  his contention is unsound. For statements and opinions  are said to  have this capacity, not

because they themselves  undergo modification,  but because this modification occurs in the  case of something

else.  The truth or falsity of a statement  depends on facts, and not on any  power on the part of the  statement

itself of admitting contrary  qualities. In short, there  is nothing which can alter the nature of  statements and

opinions.  As, then, no change takes place in  themselves, these cannot be  said to be capable of admitting

contrary  qualities. 

But it is by reason of the modification which takes place within  the substance itself that a substance is said to

be capable of  admitting contrary qualities; for a substance admits within  itself  either disease or health,

whiteness or blackness. It is in  this sense  that it is said to be capable of admitting contrary  qualities. 

To sum up, it is a distinctive mark of substance, that, while  remaining numerically one and the same, it is

capable of  admitting  contrary qualities, the modification taking place  through a change in  the substance itself. 

Let these remarks suffice on the subject of substance. 

Part 6

Quantity is either discrete or continuous. Moreover, some  quantities are such that each part of the whole has a

relative  position to the other parts: others have within them no such  relation  of part to part. 

Instances of discrete quantities are number and speech; of  continuous, lines, surfaces, solids, and, besides

these, time and  place. 

In the case of the parts of a number, there is no common boundary  at which they join. For example: two fives

make ten, but the two  fives have no common boundary, but are separate; the parts three  and  seven also do not

join at any boundary. Nor, to generalize,  would it  ever be possible in the case of number that there should  be

a common  boundary among the parts; they are always separate.  Number, therefore,  is a discrete quantity. 

The same is true of speech. That speech is a quantity is evident:  for it is measured in long and short syllables.

I mean here that  speech which is vocal. Moreover, it is a discrete quantity for  its  parts have no common

boundary. There is no common boundary at  which  the syllables join, but each is separate and distinct from

the rest. 

A line, on the other hand, is a continuous quantity, for it is  possible to find a common boundary at which its

parts join. In  the  case of the line, this common boundary is the point; in the  case of  the plane, it is the line: for

the parts of the plane  have also a  common boundary. Similarly you can find a common  boundary in the case

of the parts of a solid, namely either a  line or a plane. 

Space and time also belong to this class of quantities. Time,  past, present, and future, forms a continuous

whole. Space,  likewise,  is a continuous quantity; for the parts of a solid  occupy a certain  space, and these

have a common boundary; it  follows that the parts of  space also, which are occupied by the  parts of the solid,

have the  same common boundary as the parts of  the solid. Thus, not only time,  but space also, is a continuous

quantity, for its parts have a common  boundary. 

Quantities consist either of parts which bear a relative position  each to each, or of parts which do not. The


The Categories

Part 6 6



Top




Page No 9


parts of a line bear  a  relative position to each other, for each lies somewhere, and  it would  be possible to

distinguish each, and to state the  position of each on  the plane and to explain to what sort of part  among the

rest each was  contiguous. Similarly the parts of a  plane have position, for it could  similarly be stated what

was  the position of each and what sort of  parts were contiguous. The  same is true with regard to the solid and

to space. But it would  be impossible to show that the arts of a number  had a relative  position each to each, or

a particular position, or to  state what  parts were contiguous. Nor could this be done in the case  of  time, for

none of the parts of time has an abiding existence, and  that which does not abide can hardly have position. It

would be  better to say that such parts had a relative order, in virtue of  one  being prior to another. Similarly

with number: in counting,  'one' is  prior to 'two', and 'two' to 'three', and thus the parts  of number may  be said

to possess a relative order, though it  would be impossible to  discover any distinct position for each.  This

holds good also in the  case of speech. None of its parts has  an abiding existence: when once  a syllable is

pronounced, it is  not possible to retain it, so that,  naturally, as the parts do  not abide, they cannot have

position. Thus,  some quantities  consist of parts which have position, and some of  those which  have not. 

Strictly speaking, only the things which I have mentioned belong  to the category of quantity: everything else

that is called  quantitative is a quantity in a secondary sense. It is because we  have in mind some one of these

quantities, properly so called,  that  we apply quantitative terms to other things. We speak of  what is white  as

large, because the surface over which the white  extends is large;  we speak of an action or a process as

lengthy,  because the time  covered is long; these things cannot in their  own right claim the  quantitative

epithet. For instance, should  any one explain how long an  action was, his statement would be  made in terms

of the time taken, to  the effect that it lasted a  year, or something of that sort. In the  same way, he would

explain the size of a white object in terms of  surface, for he  would state the area which it covered. Thus the

things  already  mentioned, and these alone, are in their intrinsic nature  quantities; nothing else can claim the

name in its own right,  but, if  at all, only in a secondary sense. 

Quantities have no contraries. In the case of definite quantities  this is obvious; thus, there is nothing that is

the contrary of  'two  cubits long' or of 'three cubits long', or of a surface, or  of any  such quantities. A man

might, indeed, argue that 'much'  was the  contrary of 'little', and 'great' of 'small'. But these  are not

quantitative, but relative; things are not great or small  absolutely,  they are so called rather as the result of an

act of  comparison. For  instance, a mountain is called small, a grain  large, in virtue of the  fact that the latter is

greater than  others of its kind, the former  less. Thus there is a reference  here to an external standard, for if  the

terms 'great' and  'small' were used absolutely, a mountain would  never be called  small or a grain large. Again,

we say that there are  many people  in a village, and few in Athens, although those in the  city are  many times

as numerous as those in the village: or we say  that a  house has many in it, and a theatre few, though those in

the  theatre far outnumber those in the house. The terms 'two cubits  long,  "three cubits long,' and so on

indicate quantity, the terms  'great'  and 'small' indicate relation, for they have reference to  an external  standard.

It is, therefore, plain that these are to  be classed as  relative. 

Again, whether we define them as quantitative or not, they have  no  contraries: for how can there be a

contrary of an attribute  which is  not to be apprehended in or by itself, but only by  reference to  something

external? Again, if 'great' and 'small'  are contraries, it  will come about that the same subject can  admit

contrary qualities at  one and the same time, and that  things will themselves be contrary to  themselves. For it

happens  at times that the same thing is both small  and great. For the  same thing may be small in comparison

with one  thing, and great  in comparison with another, so that the same thing  comes to be  both small and great

at one and the same time, and is of  such a  nature as to admit contrary qualities at one and the same  moment.

Yet it was agreed, when substance was being discussed, that  nothing admits contrary qualities at one and the

same moment. For  though substance is capable of admitting contrary qualities, yet  no  one is at the same time

both sick and healthy, nothing is at  the same  time both white and black. Nor is there anything which  is

qualified in  contrary ways at one and the same time. 


The Categories

Part 6 7



Top




Page No 10


Moreover, if these were contraries, they would themselves be  contrary to themselves. For if 'great' is the

contrary of  'small',  and the same thing is both great and small at the same  time, then  'small' or 'great' is the

contrary of itself. But this  is impossible.  The term 'great', therefore, is not the contrary  of the term 'small',  nor

'much' of 'little'. And even though a  man should call these terms  not relative but quantitative, they  would not

have contraries. 

It is in the case of space that quantity most plausibly appears  to  admit of a contrary. For men define the term

'above' as the  contrary  of 'below', when it is the region at the centre they  mean by 'below';  and this is so,

because nothing is farther from  the extremities of the  universe than the region at the centre.  Indeed, it seems

that in  defining contraries of every kind men  have recourse to a spatial  metaphor, for they say that those

things are contraries which, within  the same class, are separated  by the greatest possible distance. 

Quantity does not, it appears, admit of variation of degree. One  thing cannot be two cubits long in a greater

degree than another.  Similarly with regard to number: what is 'three' is not more  truly  three than what is 'five'

is five; nor is one set of three  more truly  three than another set. Again, one period of time is  not said to be

more truly time than another. Nor is there any  other kind of quantity,  of all that have been mentioned, with

regard to which variation of  degree can be predicated. The  category of quantity, therefore, does  not admit of

variation of  degree. 

The most distinctive mark of quantity is that equality and  inequality are predicated of it. Each of the aforesaid

quantities  is  said to be equal or unequal. For instance, one solid is said  to be  equal or unequal to another;

number, too, and time can have  these  terms applied to them, indeed can all those kinds of  quantity that  have

been mentioned. 

That which is not a quantity can by no means, it would seem, be  termed equal or unequal to anything else.

One particular  disposition  or one particular quality, such as whiteness, is by  no means compared  with another

in terms of equality and  inequality but rather in terms  of similarity. Thus it is the  distinctive mark of quantity

that it can  be called equal and  unequal. 

Section 2 

Part 7

Those things are called relative, which, being either said to be  of something else or related to something else,

are explained by  reference to that other thing. For instance, the word 'superior'  is  explained by reference to

something else, for it is  superiority over  something else that is meant. Similarly, the  expression 'double' has

this external reference, for it is the  double of something else that  is meant. So it is with everything  else of this

kind. There are,  moreover, other relatives, e.g.  habit, disposition, perception,  knowledge, and attitude. The

significance of all these is explained by  a reference to  something else and in no other way. Thus, a habit is a

habit of  something, knowledge is knowledge of something, attitude is  the  attitude of something. So it is with

all other relatives that  have been mentioned. Those terms, then, are called relative, the  nature of which is

explained by reference to something else, the  preposition 'of' or some other preposition being used to indicate

the  relation. Thus, one mountain is called great in comparison  with son  with another; for the mountain claims

this attribute by  comparison  with something. Again, that which is called similar  must be similar to  something

else, and all other such attributes  have this external  reference. It is to be noted that lying and  standing and

sitting are  particular attitudes, but attitude is  itself a relative term. To lie,  to stand, to be seated, are not

themselves attitudes, but take their  name from the aforesaid  attitudes. 

It is possible for relatives to have contraries. Thus virtue has  a  contrary, vice, these both being relatives;

knowledge, too, has  a  contrary, ignorance. But this is not the mark of all relatives;  'double' and 'triple' have no


The Categories

Section 2  8



Top




Page No 11


contrary, nor indeed has any such  term. 

It also appears that relatives can admit of variation of degree.  For 'like' and 'unlike', 'equal' and 'unequal', have

the  modifications 'more' and 'less' applied to them, and each of  these is  relative in character: for the terms

'like' and  'unequal' bear  'unequal' bear a reference to something external.  Yet, again, it is  not every relative

term that admits of  variation of degree. No term  such as 'double' admits of this  modification. All relatives

have  correlatives: by the term  'slave' we mean the slave of a master, by  the term 'master', the  master of a

slave; by 'double', the double of  its hall; by  'half', the half of its double; by 'greater', greater  than that  which is

less; by 'less,' less than that which is greater. 

So it is with every other relative term; but the case we use to  express the correlation differs in some instances.

Thus, by  knowledge  we mean knowledge the knowable; by the knowable, that  which is to be  apprehended by

knowledge; by perception,  perception of the  perceptible; by the perceptible, that which is  apprehended by

perception. 

Sometimes, however, reciprocity of correlation does not appear to  exist. This comes about when a blunder is

made, and that to which  the  relative is related is not accurately stated. If a man states  that a  wing is

necessarily relative to a bird, the connexion  between these  two will not be reciprocal, for it will not be

possible to say that a  bird is a bird by reason of its wings. The  reason is that the original  statement was

inaccurate, for the  wing is not said to be relative to  the bird qua bird, since many  creatures besides birds have

wings, but  qua winged creature. If,  then, the statement is made accurate, the  connexion will be  reciprocal, for

we can speak of a wing, having  reference  necessarily to a winged creature, and of a winged creature  as  being

such because of its wings. 

Occasionally, perhaps, it is necessary to coin words, if no word  exists by which a correlation can adequately

be explained. If we  define a rudder as necessarily having reference to a boat, our  definition will not be

appropriate, for the rudder does not have  this  reference to a boat qua boat, as there are boats which have  no

rudders. Thus we cannot use the terms reciprocally, for the  word  'boat' cannot be said to find its explanation

in the word  'rudder'. As  there is no existing word, our definition would  perhaps be more  accurate if we coined

some word like 'ruddered'  as the correlative of  'rudder'. If we express ourselves thus  accurately, at any rate the

terms are reciprocally connected, for  the 'ruddered' thing is  'ruddered' in virtue of its rudder. So it  is in all

other cases. A  head will be more accurately defined as  the correlative of that which  is 'headed', than as that of

an  animal, for the animal does not have a  head qua animal, since  many animals have no head. 

Thus we may perhaps most easily comprehend that to which a thing  is related, when a name does not exist, if,

from that which has a  name, we derive a new name, and apply it to that with which the  first  is reciprocally

connected, as in the aforesaid instances,  when we  derived the word 'winged' from 'wing' and from 'rudder'. 

All relatives, then, if properly defined, have a correlative. I  add this condition because, if that to which they

are related is  stated as haphazard and not accurately, the two are not found to  be  interdependent. Let me state

what I mean more clearly. Even in  the  case of acknowledged correlatives, and where names exist for  each,

there will be no interdependence if one of the two is  denoted, not by  that name which expresses the

correlative notion,  but by one of  irrelevant significance. The term 'slave,' if  defined as related, not  to a master,

but to a man, or a biped, or  anything of that sort, is  not reciprocally connected with that in  relation to which it

is  defined, for the statement is not exact.  Further, if one thing is said  to be correlative with another, and  the

terminology used is correct,  then, though all irrelevant  attributes should be removed, and only  that one

attribute left in  virtue of which it was correctly stated to  be correlative with  that other, the stated correlation

will still  exist. If the  correlative of 'the slave' is said to be 'the master',  then,  though all irrelevant attributes of

the said 'master', such as  'biped', 'receptive of knowledge', 'human', should be removed,  and  the attribute

'master' alone left, the stated correlation  existing  between him and the slave will remain the same, for it  is of a

master  that a slave is said to be the slave. On the other  hand, if, of two  correlatives, one is not correctly


The Categories

Section 2  9



Top




Page No 12


termed, then,  when all other  attributes are removed and that alone is left in  virtue of which it  was stated to be

correlative, the stated  correlation will be found to  have disappeared. 

For suppose the correlative of 'the slave' should be said to be  'the man', or the correlative of 'the wing"the

bird'; if the  attribute 'master' be withdrawn from' the man', the correlation  between 'the man' and 'the slave'

will cease to exist, for if the  man  is not a master, the slave is not a slave. Similarly, if the  attribute  'winged' be

withdrawn from 'the bird', 'the wing' will  no longer be  relative; for if the socalled correlative is not  winged,

it follows  that 'the wing' has no correlative. 

Thus it is essential that the correlated terms should be exactly  designated; if there is a name existing, the

statement will be  easy;  if not, it is doubtless our duty to construct names. When  the  terminology is thus

correct, it is evident that all  correlatives are  interdependent. 

Correlatives are thought to come into existence simultaneously.  This is for the most part true, as in the case of

the double and  the  half. The existence of the half necessitates the existence of  that of  which it is a half.

Similarly the existence of a master  necessitates  the existence of a slave, and that of a slave  implies that of a

master; these are merely instances of a general  rule. Moreover, they  cancel one another; for if there is no

double it follows that there is  no half, and vice versa; this  rule also applies to all such  correlatives. Yet it does

not  appear to be true in all cases that  correlatives come into  existence simultaneously. The object of

knowledge would appear to  exist before knowledge itself, for it is  usually the case that we  acquire knowledge

of objects already  existing; it would be  difficult, if not impossible, to find a branch  of knowledge the

beginning of the existence of which was  contemporaneous with that  of its object. 

Again, while the object of knowledge, if it ceases to exist,  cancels at the same time the knowledge which was

its correlative,  the  converse of this is not true. It is true that if the object  of  knowledge does not exist there can

be no knowledge: for there  will no  longer be anything to know. Yet it is equally true that,  if knowledge  of a

certain object does not exist, the object may  nevertheless quite  well exist. Thus, in the case of the squaring  of

the circle, if indeed  that process is an object of knowledge,  though it itself exists as an  object of knowledge,

yet the  knowledge of it has not yet come into  existence. Again, if all  animals ceased to exist, there would be

no  knowledge, but there  might yet be many objects of knowledge. 

This is likewise the case with regard to perception: for the  object of perception is, it appears, prior to the act

of  perception.  If the perceptible is annihilated, perception also  will cease to  exist; but the annihilation of

perception does not  cancel the  existence of the perceptible. For perception implies a  body perceived  and a

body in which perception takes place. Now if  that which is  perceptible is annihilated, it follows that the  body

is annihilated,  for the body is a perceptible thing; and if  the body does not exist,  it follows that perception

also ceases  to exist. Thus the annihilation  of the perceptible involves that  of perception. 

But the annihilation of perception does not involve that of the  perceptible. For if the animal is annihilated, it

follows that  perception also is annihilated, but perceptibles such as body,  heat,  sweetness, bitterness, and so

on, will remain. 

Again, perception is generated at the same time as the perceiving  subject, for it comes into existence at the

same time as the  animal.  But the perceptible surely exists before perception; for  fire and  water and such

elements, out of which the animal is  itself composed,  exist before the animal is an animal at all, and  before

perception.  Thus it would seem that the perceptible exists  before perception. 

It may be questioned whether it is true that no substance is  relative, as seems to be the case, or whether

exception is to be  made  in the case of certain secondary substances. With regard to  primary  substances, it is

quite true that there is no such  possibility, for  neither wholes nor parts of primary substances  are relative. The

individual man or ox is not defined with  reference to something  external. Similarly with the parts: a  particular


The Categories

Section 2  10



Top




Page No 13


hand or head is not  defined as a particular hand or  head of a particular person, but as  the hand or head of a

particular person. It is true also, for the most  part at least,  in the case of secondary substances; the species

'man'  and the  species 'ox' are not defined with reference to anything  outside  themselves. Wood, again, is only

relative in so far as it is  some  one's property, not in so far as it is wood. It is plain, then,  that in the cases

mentioned substance is not relative. But with  regard to some secondary substances there is a difference of

opinion;  thus, such terms as 'head' and 'hand' are defined with  reference to  that of which the things indicated

are a part, and  so it comes about  that these appear to have a relative character.  Indeed, if our  definition of that

which is relative was complete,  it is very  difficult, if not impossible, to prove that no  substance is relative.  If,

however, our definition was not  complete, if those things only are  properly called relative in  the case of

which relation to an external  object is a necessary  condition of existence, perhaps some explanation  of the

dilemma  may be found. 

The former definition does indeed apply to all relatives, but the  fact that a thing is explained with reference to

something else  does  not make it essentially relative. 

>From this it is plain that, if a man definitely apprehends a  relative thing, he will also definitely apprehend

that to which  it is  relative. Indeed this is selfevident: for if a man knows  that some  particular thing is

relative, assuming that we call  that a relative in  the case of which relation to something is a  necessary

condition of  existence, he knows that also to which it  is related. For if he does  not know at all that to which it

is  related, he will not know whether  or not it is relative. This is  clear, moreover, in particular  instances. If a

man knows  definitely that such and such a thing is  'double', he will also  forthwith know definitely that of

which it is  the double. For if  there is nothing definite of which he knows it to  be the double,  he does not know

at all that it is double. Again, if he  knows  that a thing is more beautiful, it follows necessarily that he  will

forthwith definitely know that also than which it is more  beautiful. He will not merely know indefinitely that

it is more  beautiful than something which is less beautiful, for this would  be  supposition, not knowledge. For

if he does not know definitely  that  than which it is more beautiful, he can no longer claim to  know  definitely

that it is more beautiful than something else  which is less  beautiful: for it might be that nothing was less

beautiful. It is,  therefore, evident that if a man apprehends  some relative thing  definitely, he necessarily

knows that also  definitely to which it is  related. 

Now the head, the hand, and such things are substances, and it is  possible to know their essential character

definitely, but it  does  not necessarily follow that we should know that to which  they are  related. It is not

possible to know forthwith whose head  or hand is  meant. Thus these are not relatives, and, this being  the

case, it  would be true to say that no substance is relative  in character. It is  perhaps a difficult matter, in such

cases, to  make a positive  statement without more exhaustive examination,  but to have raised  questions with

regard to details is not  without advantage. 

Part 8

By 'quality' I mean that in virtue of which people are said to be  such and such. 

Quality is a term that is used in many senses. One sort of  quality  let us call 'habit' or 'disposition'. Habit

differs from  disposition  in being more lasting and more firmly established.  The various kinds  of knowledge

and of virtue are habits, for  knowledge, even when  acquired only in a moderate degree, is, it  is agreed,

abiding in its  character and difficult to displace,  unless some great mental upheaval  takes place, through

disease or  any such cause. The virtues, also,  such as justice,  selfrestraint, and so on, are not easily dislodged

or dismissed,  so as to give place to vice. 

By a disposition, on the other hand, we mean a condition that is  easily changed and quickly gives place to its

opposite. Thus,  heat,  cold, disease, health, and so on are dispositions. For a  man is  disposed in one way or


The Categories

Part 8 11



Top




Page No 14


another with reference to these,  but quickly  changes, becoming cold instead of warm, ill instead  of well. So it

is  with all other dispositions also, unless  through lapse of time a  disposition has itself become inveterate  and

almost impossible to  dislodge: in which case we should  perhaps go so far as to call it a  habit. 

It is evident that men incline to call those conditions habits  which are of a more or less permanent type and

difficult to  displace;  for those who are not retentive of knowledge, but  volatile, are not  said to have such and

such a 'habit' as regards  knowledge, yet they  are disposed, we may say, either better or  worse, towards

knowledge.  Thus habit differs from disposition in  this, that while the latter in  ephemeral, the former is

permanent  and difficult to alter. 

Habits are at the same time dispositions, but dispositions are  not  necessarily habits. For those who have some

specific habit  may be said  also, in virtue of that habit, to be thus or thus  disposed; but those  who are disposed

in some specific way have  not in all cases the  corresponding habit. 

Another sort of quality is that in virtue of which, for example,  we call men good boxers or runners, or healthy

or sickly: in fact  it  includes all those terms which refer to inborn capacity or  incapacity.  Such things are not

predicated of a person in virtue  of his  disposition, but in virtue of his inborn capacity or  incapacity to do

something with ease or to avoid defeat of any  kind. Persons are called  good boxers or good runners, not in

virtue of such and such a  disposition, but in virtue of an inborn  capacity to accomplish  something with ease.

Men are called  healthy in virtue of the inborn  capacity of easy resistance to  those unhealthy influences that

may  ordinarily arise; unhealthy,  in virtue of the lack of this capacity.  Similarly with regard to  softness and

hardness. Hardness is predicated  of a thing because  it has that capacity of resistance which enables it  to

withstand  disintegration; softness, again, is predicated of a thing  by  reason of the lack of that capacity. 

A third class within this category is that of affective qualities  and affections. Sweetness, bitterness, sourness,

are examples of  this  sort of quality, together with all that is akin to these;  heat,  moreover, and cold,

whiteness, and blackness are affective  qualities.  It is evident that these are qualities, for those  things that

possess  them are themselves said to be such and such  by reason of their  presence. Honey is called sweet

because it  contains sweetness; the  body is called white because it contains  whiteness; and so in all  other

cases. 

The term 'affective quality' is not used as indicating that those  things which admit these qualities are affected

in any way. Honey  is  not called sweet because it is affected in a specific way, nor  is this  what is meant in any

other instance. Similarly heat and  cold are  called affective qualities, not because those things  which admit

them  are affected. What is meant is that these said  qualities are capable  of producing an 'affection' in the way

of  perception. For sweetness  has the power of affecting the sense of  taste; heat, that of touch;  and so it is with

the rest of these  qualities. 

Whiteness and blackness, however, and the other colours, are not  said to be affective qualities in this sense,

but because they  themselves are the results of an affection. It is plain that many  changes of colour take place

because of affections. When a man is  ashamed, he blushes; when he is afraid, he becomes pale, and so  on.  So

true is this, that when a man is by nature liable to such  affections, arising from some concomitance of

elements in his  constitution, it is a probable inference that he has the  corresponding complexion of skin. For

the same disposition of  bodily  elements, which in the former instance was momentarily  present in the  case of

an access of shame, might be a result of a  man's natural  temperament, so as to produce the corresponding

colouring also as a  natural characteristic. All conditions,  therefore, of this kind, if  caused by certain

permanent and  lasting affections, are called  affective qualities. For pallor  and duskiness of complexion are

called  qualities, inasmuch as we  are said to be such and such in virtue of  them, not only if they  originate in

natural constitution, but also if  they come about  through long disease or sunburn, and are difficult to  remove,

or  indeed remain throughout life. For in the same way we are  said to  be such and such because of these. 


The Categories

Part 8 12



Top




Page No 15


Those conditions, however, which arise from causes which may  easily be rendered ineffective or speedily

removed, are called,  not  qualities, but affections: for we are not said to be such  virtue of  them. The man who

blushes through shame is not said to  be a  constitutional blusher, nor is the man who becomes pale  through

fear  said to be constitutionally pale. He is said rather  to have been  affected. 

Thus such conditions are called affections, not qualities.  In like  manner there are affective qualities and

affections of  the soul. That  temper with which a man is born and which has its  origin in certain  deepseated

affections is called a quality. I  mean such conditions as  insanity, irascibility, and so on: for  people are said to

be mad or  irascible in virtue of these.  Similarly those abnormal psychic states  which are not inborn, but  arise

from the concomitance of certain other  elements, and are  difficult to remove, or altogether permanent, are

called  qualities, for in virtue of them men are said to be such and  such. 

Those, however, which arise from causes easily rendered  ineffective are called affections, not qualities.

Suppose that a  man  is irritable when vexed: he is not even spoken of as a  badtempered  man, when in such

circumstances he loses his temper  somewhat, but  rather is said to be affected. Such conditions are  therefore

termed,  not qualities, but affections. 

The fourth sort of quality is figure and the shape that belongs  to  a thing; and besides this, straightness and

curvedness and any  other  qualities of this type; each of these defines a thing as  being such  and such. Because

it is triangular or quadrangular a  thing is said to  have a specific character, or again because it  is straight or

curved;  in fact a thing's shape in every case  gives rise to a qualification of  it. 

Rarity and density, roughness and smoothness, seem to be terms  indicating quality: yet these, it would

appear, really belong to  a  class different from that of quality. For it is rather a  certain  relative position of the

parts composing the thing thus  qualified  which, it appears, is indicated by each of these terms.  A thing is

dense, owing to the fact that its parts are closely  combined with one  another; rare, because there are

interstices  between the parts;  smooth, because its parts lie, so to speak,  evenly; rough, because  some parts

project beyond others. 

There may be other sorts of quality, but those that are most  properly so called have, we may safely say, been

enumerated. 

These, then, are qualities, and the things that take their name  from them as derivatives, or are in some other

way dependent on  them,  are said to be qualified in some specific way. In most,  indeed in  almost all cases, the

name of that which is qualified  is derived from  that of the quality. Thus the terms 'whiteness',  'grammar',

'justice',  give us the adjectives 'white',  'grammatical', 'just', and so on. 

There are some cases, however, in which, as the quality under  consideration has no name, it is impossible that

those possessed  of  it should have a name that is derivative. For instance, the  name given  to the runner or

boxer, who is so called in virtue of  an inborn  capacity, is not derived from that of any quality; for  lob those

capacities have no name assigned to them. In this, the  inborn capacity  is distinct from the science, with

reference to  which men are called,  e.g. boxers or wrestlers. Such a science is  classed as a disposition;  it has a

name, and is called 'boxing'  or 'wrestling' as the case may  be, and the name given to those  disposed in this

way is derived from  that of the science.  Sometimes, even though a name exists for the  quality, that which

takes its character from the quality has a name  that is not a  derivative. For instance, the upright man takes his

character  from the possession of the quality of integrity, but the  name  given him is not derived from the word

'integrity'. Yet this does  not occur often. 

We may therefore state that those things are said to be possessed  of some specific quality which have a name

derived from that of  the  aforesaid quality, or which are in some other way dependent  on it. 


The Categories

Part 8 13



Top




Page No 16


One quality may be the contrary of another; thus justice is the  contrary of injustice, whiteness of blackness,

and so on. The  things,  also, which are said to be such and such in virtue of  these qualities,  may be contrary

the one to the other; for that  which is unjust is  contrary to that which is just, that which is  white to that which

is  black. This, however, is not always the  case. Red, yellow, and such  colours, though qualities, have no

contraries. 

If one of two contraries is a quality, the other will also be a  quality. This will be evident from particular

instances, if we  apply  the names used to denote the other categories; for  instance, granted  that justice is the

contrary of injustice and  justice is a quality,  injustice will also be a quality: neither  quantity, nor relation, nor

place, nor indeed any other category  but that of quality, will be  applicable properly to injustice. So  it is with

all other contraries  falling under the category of  quality. 

Qualities admit of variation of degree. Whiteness is predicated  of  one thing in a greater or less degree than of

another. This is  also  the case with reference to justice. Moreover, one and the  same thing  may exhibit a

quality in a greater degree than it did  before: if a  thing is white, it may become whiter. 

Though this is generally the case, there are exceptions. For if  we  should say that justice admitted of variation

of degree,  difficulties  might ensue, and this is true with regard to all  those qualities which  are dispositions.

There are some, indeed,  who dispute the possibility  of variation here. They maintain that  justice and health

cannot very  well admit of variation of degree  themselves, but that people vary in  the degree in which they

possess these qualities, and that this is the  case with  grammatical learning and all those qualities which are

classed as  dispositions. However that may be, it is an  incontrovertible fact  that the things which in virtue of

these  qualities are said to be  what they are vary in the degree in which  they possess them; for  one man is said

to be better versed in grammar,  or more healthy  or just, than another, and so on. 

The qualities expressed by the terms 'triangular' and  'quadrangular' do not appear to admit of variation of

degree, nor  indeed do any that have to do with figure. For those things to  which  the definition of the triangle

or circle is applicable are  all equally  triangular or circular. Those, on the other hand, to  which the same

definition is not applicable, cannot be said to  differ from one  another in degree; the square is no more a circle

than the rectangle,  for to neither is the definition of the  circle appropriate. In short,  if the definition of the

term  proposed is not applicable to both  objects, they cannot be  compared. Thus it is not all qualities which

admit of variation  of degree. 

Whereas none of the characteristics I have mentioned are peculiar  to quality, the fact that likeness and

unlikeness can be  predicated  with reference to quality only, gives to that category  its distinctive  feature. One

thing is like another only with  reference to that in  virtue of which it is such and such; thus  this forms the

peculiar mark  of quality. 

We must not be disturbed because it may be argued that, though  proposing to discuss the category of quality,

we have included in  it  many relative terms. We did say that habits and dispositions  were  relative. In

practically all such cases the genus is  relative, the  individual not. Thus knowledge, as a genus, is  explained by

reference  to something else, for we mean a knowledge  of something. But  particular branches of knowledge

are not thus  explained. The knowledge  of grammar is not relative to anything  external, nor is the knowledge

of music, but these, if relative  at all, are relative only in virtue  of their genera; thus grammar  is said be the

knowledge of something,  not the grammar of  something; similarly music is the knowledge of  something, not

the  music of something. 

Thus individual branches of knowledge are not relative. And it is  because we possess these individual

branches of knowledge that we  are  said to be such and such. It is these that we actually  possess: we are  called

experts because we possess knowledge in  some particular branch.  Those particular branches, therefore, of

knowledge, in virtue of which  we are sometimes said to be such  and such, are themselves qualities,  and are


The Categories

Part 8 14



Top




Page No 17


not relative.  Further, if anything should happen to fall  within both the  category of quality and that of relation,

there would  be nothing  extraordinary in classing it under both these heads. 

Section 3 

Part 9

Action and affection both admit of contraries and also of  variation of degree. Heating is the contrary of

cooling, being  heated  of being cooled, being glad of being vexed. Thus they  admit of  contraries. They also

admit of variation of degree: for  it is possible  to heat in a greater or less degree; also to be  heated in a greater

or  less degree. Thus action and affection  also admit of variation of  degree. So much, then, is stated with

regard to these categories. 

We spoke, moreover, of the category of position when we were  dealing with that of relation, and stated that

such terms derived  their names from those of the corresponding attitudes. 

As for the rest, time, place, state, since they are easily  intelligible, I say no more about them than was said at

the  beginning, that in the category of state are included such states  as  'shod', 'armed', in that of place 'in the

Lyceum' and so on,  as was  explained before. 

Part 10

The proposed categories have, then, been adequately dealt with.  We  must next explain the various senses in

which the term  'opposite' is  used. Things are said to be opposed in four senses:  (i) as  correlatives to one

another, (ii) as contraries to one  another, (iii)  as privatives to positives, (iv) as affirmatives  to negatives. 

Let me sketch my meaning in outline. An instance of the use of  the  word 'opposite' with reference to

correlatives is afforded by  the  expressions 'double' and 'half'; with reference to contraries  by 'bad'  and 'good'.

Opposites in the sense of 'privatives' and  'positives'  are' blindness' and 'sight'; in the sense of  affirmatives and

negatives, the propositions 'he sits', 'he does  not sit'. 

(i) Pairs of opposites which fall under the category of relation  are explained by a reference of the one to the

other, the  reference  being indicated by the preposition 'of' or by some  other preposition.  Thus, double is a

relative term, for that  which is double is explained  as the double of something.  Knowledge, again, is the

opposite of the  thing known, in the same  sense; and the thing known also is explained  by its relation to  its

opposite, knowledge. For the thing known is  explained as that  which is known by something, that is, by

knowledge.  Such things,  then, as are opposite the one to the other in the sense  of being  correlatives are

explained by a reference of the one to the  other. 

(ii) Pairs of opposites which are contraries are not in any way  interdependent, but are contrary the one to the

other. The good  is  not spoken of as the good of the had, but as the contrary of  the bad,  nor is white spoken of

as the white of the black, but as  the contrary  of the black. These two types of opposition are  therefore distinct.

Those contraries which are such that the  subjects in which they are  naturally present, or of which they  are

predicated, must necessarily  contain either the one or the  other of them, have no intermediate, but  those in the

case of  which no such necessity obtains, always have an  intermediate.  Thus disease and health are naturally

present in the  body of an  animal, and it is necessary that either the one or the  other  should be present in the

body of an animal. Odd and even, again,  are predicated of number, and it is necessary that the one or the

other should be present in numbers. Now there is no intermediate  between the terms of either of these two

pairs. On the other  hand, in  those contraries with regard to which no such necessity  obtains, we  find an

intermediate. Blackness and whiteness are  naturally present in  the body, but it is not necessary that  either the


The Categories

Section 3  15



Top




Page No 18


one or the other  should be present in the body,  inasmuch as it is not true to say that  everybody must be white

or  black. Badness and goodness, again, are  predicated of man, and of  many other things, but it is not

necessary  that either the one  quality or the other should be present in that of  which they are  predicated: it is

not true to say that everything that  may be  good or bad must be either good or bad. These pairs of  contraries

have intermediates: the intermediates between white and  black are  grey, sallow, and all the other colours that

come between;  the  intermediate between good and bad is that which is neither the  one nor the other. 

Some intermediate qualities have names, such as grey and sallow  and all the other colours that come between

white and black; in  other  cases, however, it is not easy to name the intermediate,  but we must  define it as that

which is not either extreme, as in  the case of that  which is neither good nor bad, neither just nor  unjust. 

(iii) 'privatives' and 'Positives' have reference to the same  subject. Thus, sight and blindness have reference to

the eye. It  is a  universal rule that each of a pair of opposites of this type  has  reference to that to which the

particular 'positive' is  natural. We  say that that is capable of some particular faculty  or possession has  suffered

privation when the faculty or  possession in question is in no  way present in that in which, and  at the time at

which, it should  naturally be present. We do not  call that toothless which has not  teeth, or that blind which

has  not sight, but rather that which has  not teeth or sight at the  time when by nature it should. For there are

some creatures which  from birth are without sight, or without teeth,  but these are not  called toothless or blind. 

To be without some faculty or to possess it is not the same as  the  corresponding 'privative' or 'positive'. 'Sight'

is a  'positive',  'blindness' a 'privative', but 'to possess sight' is  not equivalent to  'sight', 'to be blind' is not

equivalent to  'blindness'. Blindness is  a 'privative', to be blind is to be in  a state of privation, but is  not a

'privative'. Moreover, if  'blindness' were equivalent to 'being  blind', both would be  predicated of the same

subject; but though a man  is said to be  blind, he is by no means said to be blindness. 

To be in a state of 'possession' is, it appears, the opposite of  being in a state of 'privation', just as 'positives'

and  'privatives'  themselves are opposite. There is the same type of  antithesis in both  cases; for just as

blindness is opposed to  sight, so is being blind  opposed to having sight. 

That which is affirmed or denied is not itself affirmation or  denial. By 'affirmation' we mean an affirmative

proposition, by  'denial' a negative. Now, those facts which form the matter of  the  affirmation or denial are not

propositions; yet these two are  said to  be opposed in the same sense as the affirmation and  denial, for in  this

case also the type of antithesis is the same.  For as the  affirmation is opposed to the denial, as in the two

propositions 'he  sits', 'he does not sit', so also the fact which  constitutes the  matter of the proposition in one

case is opposed  to that in the other,  his sitting, that is to say, to his not  sitting. 

It is evident that 'positives' and 'privatives' are not opposed  each to each in the same sense as relatives. The

one is not  explained  by reference to the other; sight is not sight of  blindness, nor is any  other preposition used

to indicate the  relation. Similarly blindness  is not said to be blindness of  sight, but rather, privation of sight.

Relatives, moreover,  reciprocate; if blindness, therefore, were a  relative, there  would be a reciprocity of

relation between it and that  with which  it was correlative. But this is not the case. Sight is not  called  the sight

of blindness. 

That those terms which fall under the heads of 'positives' and  'privatives' are not opposed each to each as

contraries, either,  is  plain from the following facts: Of a pair of contraries such  that they  have no

intermediate, one or the other must needs be  present in the  subject in which they naturally subsist, or of  which

they are  predicated; for it is those, as we proved,' in the  case of which this  necessity obtains, that have no

intermediate.  Moreover, we cited  health and disease, odd and even, as  instances. But those contraries  which

have an intermediate are  not subject to any such necessity. It  is not necessary that every  substance, receptive

of such qualities,  should be either black or  white, cold or hot, for something  intermediate between these

contraries may very well be present in the  subject. We proved,  moreover, that those contraries have an


The Categories

Section 3  16



Top




Page No 19


intermediate in the case  of which the said necessity does not obtain.  Yet when one of the  two contraries is a

constitutive property of the  subject, as it  is a constitutive property of fire to be hot, of snow  to be  white, it is

necessary determinately that one of the two  contraries, not one or the other, should be present in the  subject;

for fire cannot be cold, or snow black. Thus, it is not  the case here  that one of the two must needs be present

in every  subject receptive  of these qualities, but only in that subject of  which the one forms a  constitutive

property. Moreover, in such  cases it is one member of the  pair determinately, and not either  the one or the

other, which must be  present. 

In the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', on the other hand,  neither of the aforesaid statements holds good. For

it is not  necessary that a subject receptive of the qualities should always  have either the one or the other; that

which has not yet advanced  to  the state when sight is natural is not said either to be blind  or to  see. Thus

'positives' and 'privatives' do not belong to  that class of  contraries which consists of those which have no

intermediate. On the  other hand, they do not belong either to  that class which consists of  contraries which

have an  intermediate. For under certain conditions it  is necessary that  either the one or the other should form

part of the  constitution  of every appropriate subject. For when a thing has  reached the  stage when it is by

nature capable of sight, it will be  said  either to see or to be blind, and that in an indeterminate sense,

signifying that the capacity may be either present or absent; for  it  is not necessary either that it should see or

that it should  be blind,  but that it should be either in the one state or in the  other. Yet in  the case of those

contraries which have an  intermediate we found that  it was never necessary that either the  one or the other

should be  present in every appropriate subject,  but only that in certain  subjects one of the pair should be

present, and that in a determinate  sense. It is, therefore, plain  that 'positives' and 'privatives' are  not opposed

each to each in  either of the senses in which contraries  are opposed. 

Again, in the case of contraries, it is possible that there  should  be changes from either into the other, while the

subject  retains its  identity, unless indeed one of the contraries is a  constitutive  property of that subject, as heat

is of fire. For it  is possible that  that that which is healthy should become  diseased, that which is  white, black,

that which is cold, hot,  that which is good, bad, that  which is bad, good. The bad man, if  he is being brought

into a better  way of life and thought, may  make some advance, however slight, and if  he should once

improve,  even ever so little, it is plain that he might  change completely,  or at any rate make very great

progress; for a man  becomes more  and more easily moved to virtue, however small the  improvement  was at

first. It is, therefore, natural to suppose that he  will  make yet greater progress than he has made in the past;

and as  this process goes on, it will change him completely and establish  him  in the contrary state, provided he

is not hindered by lack of  time. In  the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', however,  change in both  directions is

impossible. There may be a change  from possession to  privation, but not from privation to  possession. The

man who has  become blind does not regain his  sight; the man who has become bald  does not regain his hair;

the  man who has lost his teeth does not grow  his grow a new set. (iv)  Statements opposed as affirmation and

negation belong manifestly  to a class which is distinct, for in this  case, and in this case  only, it is necessary

for the one opposite to  be true and the  other false. 

Neither in the case of contraries, nor in the case of  correlatives, nor in the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', is

it  necessary for one to be true and the other false. Health and  disease  are contraries: neither of them is true or

false.  'Double' and 'half'  are opposed to each other as correlatives:  neither of them is true or  false. The case is

the same, of  course, with regard to 'positives' and  'privatives' such as  'sight' and 'blindness'. In short, where

there is  no sort of  combination of words, truth and falsity have no place, and  all  the opposites we have

mentioned so far consist of simple words. 

At the same time, when the words which enter into opposed  statements are contraries, these, more than any

other set of  opposites, would seem to claim this characteristic. 'Socrates is  ill'  is the contrary of 'Socrates is

well', but not even of such  composite  expressions is it true to say that one of the pair must  always be true  and

the other false. For if Socrates exists, one  will be true and the  other false, but if he does not exist, both  will be

false; for neither  'Socrates is ill' nor 'Socrates is  well' is true, if Socrates does not  exist at all. 


The Categories

Section 3  17



Top




Page No 20


In the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', if the subject does  not exist at all, neither proposition is true, but

even if the  subject exists, it is not always the fact that one is true and  the  other false. For 'Socrates has sight' is

the opposite of  'Socrates is  blind' in the sense of the word 'opposite' which  applies to possession  and

privation. Now if Socrates exists, it  is not necessary that one  should be true and the other false, for  when he is

not yet able to  acquire the power of vision, both are  false, as also if Socrates is  altogether nonexistent. 

But in the case of affirmation and negation, whether the subject  exists or not, one is always false and the

other true. For  manifestly, if Socrates exists, one of the two propositions  'Socrates  is ill', 'Socrates is not ill', is

true, and the other  false. This is  likewise the case if he does not exist; for if he  does not exist, to  say that he is

ill is false, to say that he is  not ill is true. Thus  it is in the case of those opposites only,  which are opposite in

the  sense in which the term is used with  reference to affirmation and  negation, that the rule holds good,  that

one of the pair must be true  and the other false. 

Part 11

That the contrary of a good is an evil is shown by induction: the  contrary of health is disease, of courage,

cowardice, and so on.  But  the contrary of an evil is sometimes a good, sometimes an  evil. For  defect, which is

an evil, has excess for its contrary,  this also being  an evil, and the mean. which is a good, is  equally the

contrary of the  one and of the other. It is only in a  few cases, however, that we see  instances of this: in most,

the  contrary of an evil is a good. 

In the case of contraries, it is not always necessary that if one  exists the other should also exist: for if all

become healthy  there  will be health and no disease, and again, if everything  turns white,  there will be white,

but no black. Again, since the  fact that Socrates  is ill is the contrary of the fact that  Socrates is well, and two

contrary conditions cannot both obtain  in one and the same individual  at the same time, both these  contraries

could not exist at once: for  if that Socrates was well  was a fact, then that Socrates was ill could  not possibly

be one. 

It is plain that contrary attributes must needs be present in  subjects which belong to the same species or

genus. Disease and  health require as their subject the body of an animal; white and  black require a body,

without further qualification; justice and  injustice require as their subject the human soul. 

Moreover, it is necessary that pairs of contraries should in all  cases either belong to the same genus or belong

to contrary  genera or  be themselves genera. White and black belong to the  same genus,  colour; justice and

injustice, to contrary genera,  virtue and vice;  while good and evil do not belong to genera, but  are themselves

actual  genera, with terms under them. 

Part 12

There are four senses in which one thing can be said to be  'prior'  to another. Primarily and most properly the

term has  reference to  time: in this sense the word is used to indicate  that one thing is  older or more ancient

than another, for the  expressions 'older' and  'more ancient' imply greater length of  time. 

Secondly, one thing is said to be 'prior' to another when the  sequence of their being cannot be reversed. In this

sense 'one'  is  'prior' to 'two'. For if 'two' exists, it follows directly  that 'one'  must exist, but if 'one' exists, it

does not follow  necessarily that  'two' exists: thus the sequence subsisting  cannot be reversed. It is  agreed,

then, that when the sequence of  two things cannot be reversed,  then that one on which the other  depends is

called 'prior' to that  other. 


The Categories

Part 11 18



Top




Page No 21


In the third place, the term 'prior' is used with reference to  any  order, as in the case of science and of oratory.

For in  sciences which  use demonstration there is that which is prior and  that which is  posterior in order; in

geometry, the elements are  prior to the  propositions; in reading and writing, the letters of  the alphabet are

prior to the syllables. Similarly, in the case  of speeches, the  exordium is prior in order to the narrative. 

Besides these senses of the word, there is a fourth. That which  is  better and more honourable is said to have a

natural priority.  In  common parlance men speak of those whom they honour and love  as  'coming first' with

them. This sense of the word is perhaps  the most  farfetched. 

Such, then, are the different senses in which the term 'prior' is  used. 

Yet it would seem that besides those mentioned there is yet  another. For in those things, the being of each of

which implies  that  of the other, that which is in any way the cause may  reasonably be  said to be by nature

'prior' to the effect. It is  plain that there are  instances of this. The fact of the being of  a man carries with it the

truth of the proposition that he is,  and the implication is  reciprocal: for if a man is, the  proposition wherein

we allege that he  is true, and conversely, if  the proposition wherein we allege that he  is true, then he is.  The

true proposition, however, is in no way the  cause of the  being of the man, but the fact of the man's being does

seem  somehow to be the cause of the truth of the proposition, for the  truth or falsity of the proposition

depends on the fact of the  man's  being or not being. 

Thus the word 'prior' may be used in five senses. 

Part 13

The term 'simultaneous' is primarily and most appropriately  applied to those things the genesis of the one of

which is  simultaneous with that of the other; for in such cases neither is  prior or posterior to the other. Such

things are said to be  simultaneous in point of time. Those things, again, are  'simultaneous' in point of nature,

the being of each of which  involves that of the other, while at the same time neither is the  cause of the other's

being. This is the case with regard to the  double and the half, for these are reciprocally dependent, since,  if

there is a double, there is also a half, and if there is a  half, there  is also a double, while at the same time

neither is  the cause of the  being of the other. 

Again, those species which are distinguished one from another and  opposed one to another within the same

genus are said to be  'simultaneous' in nature. I mean those species which are  distinguished each from each by

one and the same method of  division.  Thus the 'winged' species is simultaneous with the  'terrestrial' and  the

'water' species. These are distinguished  within the same genus,  and are opposed each to each, for the  genus

'animal' has the 'winged',  the 'terrestrial', and the  'water' species, and no one of these is  prior or posterior to

another; on the contrary, all such things appear  to be  'simultaneous' in nature. Each of these also, the

terrestrial,  the winged, and the water species, can be divided again into  subspecies. Those species, then, also

will be 'simultaneous'  point of  nature, which, belonging to the same genus, are  distinguished each  from each

by one and the same method of  differentiation. 

But genera are prior to species, for the sequence of their being  cannot be reversed. If there is the species

'wateranimal', there  will be the genus 'animal', but granted the being of the genus  'animal', it does not follow

necessarily that there will be the  species 'wateranimal'. 

Those things, therefore, are said to be 'simultaneous' in nature,  the being of each of which involves that of the

other, while at  the  same time neither is in any way the cause of the other's  being; those  species, also, which

are distinguished each from  each and opposed  within the same genus. Those things, moreover,  are

'simultaneous' in  the unqualified sense of the word which  come into being at the same  time. 


The Categories

Part 13 19



Top




Page No 22


Part 14

There are six sorts of movement: generation, destruction,  increase, diminution, alteration, and change of

place. 

It is evident in all but one case that all these sorts of  movement  are distinct each from each. Generation is

distinct from  destruction,  increase and change of place from diminution, and so  on. But in the  case of

alteration it may be argued that the  process necessarily  implies one or other of the other five sorts  of motion.

This is not  true, for we may say that all affections,  or nearly all, produce in us  an alteration which is distinct

from  all other sorts of motion, for  that which is affected need not  suffer either increase or diminution  or any

of the other sorts of  motion. Thus alteration is a distinct  sort of motion; for, if it  were not, the thing altered

would not only  be altered, but would  forthwith necessarily suffer increase or  diminution or some one  of the

other sorts of motion in addition; which  as a matter of  fact is not the case. Similarly that which was

undergoing the  process of increase or was subject to some other sort  of motion  would, if alteration were not a

distinct form of motion,  necessarily be subject to alteration also. But there are some  things  which undergo

increase but yet not alteration. The square,  for  instance, if a gnomon is applied to it, undergoes increase  but

not  alteration, and so it is with all other figures of this  sort.  Alteration and increase, therefore, are distinct. 

Speaking generally, rest is the contrary of motion. But the  different forms of motion have their own contraries

in other  forms;  thus destruction is the contrary of generation, diminution  of  increase, rest in a place, of change

of place. As for this  last,  change in the reverse direction would seem to be most truly  its  contrary; thus motion

upwards is the contrary of motion  downwards and  vice versa. 

In the case of that sort of motion which yet remains, of those  that have been enumerated, it is not easy to state

what is its  contrary. It appears to have no contrary, unless one should  define  the contrary here also either as

'rest in its quality' or  as 'change  in the direction of the contrary quality', just as we  defined the  contrary of

change of place either as rest in a place  or as change in  the reverse direction. For a thing is altered  when

change of quality  takes place; therefore either rest in its  quality or change in the  direction of the contrary may

be called  the contrary of this  qualitative form of motion. In this way  becoming white is the contrary  of

becoming black; there is  alteration in the contrary direction,  since a change of a  qualitative nature takes place. 

Part 15

The term 'to have' is used in various senses. In the first place  it is used with reference to habit or disposition

or any other  quality, for we are said to 'have' a piece of knowledge or a  virtue.  Then, again, it has reference to

quantity, as, for  instance, in the  case of a man's height; for he is said to 'have'  a height of three or  four cubits.

It is used, moreover, with  regard to apparel, a man being  said to 'have' a coat or tunic; or  in respect of

something which we  have on a part of ourselves, as  a ring on the hand: or in respect of  something which is a

part of  us, as hand or foot. The term refers also  to content, as in the  case of a vessel and wheat, or of a jar and

wine; a jar is said  to 'have' wine, and a cornmeasure wheat. The  expression in such  cases has reference to

content. Or it refers to  that which has  been acquired; we are said to 'have' a house or a  field. A man is  also

said to 'have' a wife, and a wife a husband, and  this  appears to be the most remote meaning of the term, for by

the use  of it we mean simply that the husband lives with the wife. 

Other senses of the word might perhaps be found, but the most  ordinary ones have all been enumerated. 


The Categories

Part 14 20



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. The Categories, page = 4

   3. Aristotle, page = 4

4. Section 1 , page = 4

   5. Part 1, page = 4

   6. Part 2, page = 5

   7. Part 3, page = 5

   8. Part 4, page = 5

   9. Part 5, page = 6

   10. Part 6, page = 9

11. Section 2 , page = 11

   12. Part 7, page = 11

   13. Part 8, page = 14

14. Section 3 , page = 18

   15. Part 9, page = 18

   16. Part 10, page = 18

   17. Part 11, page = 21

   18. Part 12, page = 21

   19. Part 13, page = 22

   20. Part 14, page = 23

   21. Part 15, page = 23