Title:   ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Bookmarks





Page No 1


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE..........................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

1..............................................................................................................................................................1

2..............................................................................................................................................................3


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

i



Top




Page No 3


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

by Aristotle

translated by J. I. Beare

1 

2  

1

WE have, in the next place, to treat of Memory and Remembering,  considering its nature, its cause, and the

part of the soul to which  this experience, as well as that of Recollecting, belongs. For the  persons who

possess a retentive memory are not identical with those  who excel in power of recollection; indeed, as a rule,

slow people  have a good memory, whereas those who are quickwitted and clever  are  better at recollecting. 

We must first form a true conception of these objects of memory, a  point on which mistakes are often made.

Now to remember the future  is  not possible, but this is an object of opinion or expectation  (and  indeed there

might be actually a science of expectation, like  that of  divination, in which some believe); nor is there

memory of the  present, but only senseperception. For by the latter we know not  the  future, nor the past, but

the present only. But memory relates  to the  past. No one would say that he remembers the present, when it  is

present, e.g. a given white object at the moment when he sees it;  nor  would one say that he remembers an

object of scientific  contemplation  at the moment when he is actually contemplating it,  and has it full  before

his mind;of the former he would say only  that he perceives it,  of the latter only that he knows it. But when

one has scientific  knowledge, or perception, apart from the  actualizations of the faculty  concerned, he thus

'remembers' (that the  angles of a triangle are  together equal to two right angles); as to  the former, that he

learned  it, or thought it out for himself, as to  the latter, that he heard, or  saw, it, or had some such sensible

experience of it. For whenever one  exercises the faculty of  remembering, he must say within himself, 'I

formerly heard (or  otherwise perceived) this,' or 'I formerly had this  thought'. 

Memory is, therefore, neither Perception nor Conception, but a  state  or affection of one of these, conditioned

by lapse of time. As  already  observed, there is no such thing as memory of the present  while  present, for the

present is object only of perception, and the  future,  of expectation, but the object of memory is the past. All

memory,  therefore, implies a time elapsed; consequently only those  animals  which perceive time remember,

and the organ whereby they  perceive time  is also that whereby they remember. 

The subject of 'presentation' has been already considered in our  work On the Soul. Without a presentation

intellectual activity is  impossible. For there is in such activity an incidental affection  identical with one also

incidental in geometrical demonstrations.  For  in the latter case, though we do not for the purpose of the  proof

make  any use of the fact that the quantity in the triangle  (for example,  which we have drawn) is determinate,

we nevertheless  draw it  determinate in quantity. So likewise when one exerts the  intellect  (e.g. on the subject

of first principles), although the  object may not  be quantitative, one envisages it as quantitative,  though he

ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE 1



Top




Page No 4


thinks it  in abstraction from quantity; while, on the  other hand, if the object  of the intellect is essentially of

the class  of things that are  quantitative, but indeterminate, one envisages it  as if it had  determinate quantity,

though subsequently, in thinking  it, he  abstracts from its determinateness. Why we cannot exercise  the

intellect on any object absolutely apart from the continuous, or  apply  it even to nontemporal things unless in

connexion with time, is  another question. Now, one must cognize magnitude and motion by  means  of the

same faculty by which one cognizes time (i.e. by that  which is  also the faculty of memory), and the

presentation (involved  in such  cognition) is an affection of the sensus communis; whence this  follows, viz.

that the cognition of these objects (magnitude, motion  time) is effected by the (said sensus communis, i.e.

the) primary  faculty of perception. Accordingly, memory (not merely of sensible,  but) even of intellectual

objects involves a presentation: hence we  may conclude that it belongs to the faculty of intelligence only

incidentally, while directly and essentially it belongs to the primary  faculty of senseperception. 

Hence not only human beings and the beings which possess opinion  or intelligence, but also certain other

animals, possess memory. If  memory were a function of (pure) intellect, it would not have been  as  it is an

attribute of many of the lower animals, but probably, in  that  case, no mortal beings would have had memory;

since, even as  the case  stands, it is not an attribute of them all, just because  all have not  the faculty of

perceiving time. Whenever one actually  remembers having  seen or heard, or learned, something, he includes

in this act (as we  have already observed) the consciousness of  'formerly'; and the  distinction of 'former' and

'latter' is a  distinction in time. 

Accordingly if asked, of which among the parts of the soul memory  is  a function, we reply: manifestly of that

part to which  'presentation' appertains; and all objects capable of being  presented  (viz. aistheta) are

immediately and properly objects of  memory, while  those (viz. noeta) which necessarily involve (but only

involve)  presentation are objects of memory incidentally. 

One might ask how it is possible that though the affection (the  presentation) alone is present, and the (related)

fact absent, the  latterthat which is not presentis remembered. (The question arises),  because it is clear that

we must conceive that which is generated  through senseperception in the sentient soul, and in the part of  the

body which is its seatviz. that affection the state whereof we  call  memoryto be some such thing as a

picture. The process of  movement  (sensory stimulation) involved the act of perception stamps  in, as it  were, a

sort of impression of the percept, just as persons  do who make  an impression with a seal. This explains why,

in those who  are  strongly moved owing to passion, or time of life, no mnemonic  impression is formed; just as

no impression would be formed if the  movement of the seal were to impinge on running water; while there

are  others in whom, owing to the receiving surface being frayed, as  happens to (the stucco on) old (chamber)

walls, or owing to the  hardness of the receiving surface, the requisite impression is not  implanted at all.

Hence both very young and very old persons are  defective in memory; they are in a state of flux, the former

because  of their growth, the latter, owing to their decay. In like manner,  also, both those who are too quick

and those who are too slow have bad  memories. The former are too soft, the latter too hard (in the texture  of

their receiving organs), so that in the case of the former the  presented image (though imprinted) does not

remain in the soul,  while  on the latter it is not imprinted at all. 

But then, if this truly describes what happens in the genesis of  memory, (the question stated above arises:)

when one remembers, is  it  this impressed affection that he remembers, or is it the  objective  thing from which

this was derived? If the former, it would  follow that  we remember nothing which is absent; if the latter, how

is  it possible  that, though perceiving directly only the impression, we  remember that  absent thing which we

do not perceive? Granted that  there is in us  something like an impression or picture, why should the

perception of  the mere impression be memory of something else, instead  of being  related to this impression

alone? For when one actually  remembers,  this impression is what he contemplates, and this is what  he

perceives. How then does he remember what is not present? One might  as  well suppose it possible also to see

or hear that which is not  present. In reply, we suggest that this very thing is quite  conceivable, nay, actually

occurs in experience. A picture painted  on  a panel is at once a picture and a likeness: that is, while one and


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE 2



Top




Page No 5


the same, it is both of these, although the 'being' of both is not the  same, and one may contemplate it either as

a picture, or as a  likeness. Just in the same way we have to conceive that the mnemonic  presentation within us

is something which by itself is merely an  object of contemplation, while, inrelation to something else, it is

also a presentation of that other thing. In so far as it is regarded  in itself, it is only an object of contemplation,

or a presentation;  but when considered as relative to something else, e.g. as its  likeness, it is also a mnemonic

token. Hence, whenever the residual  sensory process implied by it is actualized in consciousness, if the  soul

perceives this in so far as it is something absolute, it  appears  to occur as a mere thought or presentation; but if

the soul  perceives  it qua related to something else, then,just as when one  contemplates  the painting in the

picture as being a likeness, and  without having  (at the moment) seen the actual Koriskos,  contemplates it as a

likeness of Koriskos, and in that case the  experience involved in this  contemplation of it (as relative) is

different from what one has when  he contemplates it simply as a  painted figure(so in the case of  memory we

have the analogous  difference for), of the objects in the  soul, the one (the unrelated  object) presents itself

simply as a  thought, but the other (the  related object) just because, as in the  painting, it is a likeness,  presents

itself as a mnemonic token. 

We can now understand why it is that sometimes, when we have such  processes, based on some former act of

perception, occurring in the  soul, we do not know whether this really implies our having had  perceptions

corresponding to them, and we doubt whether the case is or  is not one of memory. But occasionally it

happens that (while thus  doubting) we get a sudden idea and recollect that we heard or saw  something

formerly. This (occurrence of the 'sudden idea') happens  whenever, from contemplating a mental object as

absolute, one  changes  his point of view, and regards it as relative to something  else. 

The opposite (sc. to the case of those who at first do not  recognize  their phantasms as mnemonic) also occurs,

as happened in the  cases  of Antipheron of Oreus and others suffering from mental  derangement;  for they

were accustomed to speak of their mere phantasms  as facts  of their past experience, and as if remembering

them. This  takes place  whenever one contemplates what is not a likeness as if it  were a  likeness. 

Mnemonic exercises aim at preserving one's memory of something by  repeatedly reminding him of it; which

implies nothing else (on the  learner's part) than the frequent contemplation of something (viz. the  'mnemonic',

whatever it may be) as a likeness, and not as out of  relation. 

As regards the question, therefore, what memory or remembering is,  it has now been shown that it is the state

of a presentation,  related  as a likeness to that of which it is a presentation; and as to  the  question of which of

the faculties within us memory is a function,  (it  has been shown) that it is a function of the primary faculty of

senseperception, i.e. of that faculty whereby we perceive time. 

2

Next comes the subject of Recollection, in dealing with which we  must assume as fundamental the truths

elicited above in our  introductory discussions. For recollection is not the 'recovery' or  'acquisition' of

memory; since at the instant when one at first learns  (a fact of science) or experiences (a particular fact of

sense), he  does not thereby 'recover' a memory, inasmuch as none has preceded,  nor does he acquire one ab

initio. It is only at the instant when  the  aforesaid state or affection (of the aisthesis or upolepsis) is  implanted

in the soul that memory exists, and therefore memory is  not  itself implanted concurrently with the continuous

implantation  of the  (original) sensory experience. 

Further: at the very individual and concluding instant when first  (the sensory experience or scientific

knowledge) has been completely  implanted, there is then already established in the person affected  the

(sensory) affection, or the scientific knowledge (if one ought  to  apply the term 'scientific knowledge' to the

(mnemonic) state or  affection; and indeed one may well remember, in the 'incidental'  sense, some of the


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

2 3



Top




Page No 6


things (i.e. ta katholou) which are properly  objects of scientific knowledge); but to remember, strictly and

properly speaking, is an activity which will not be immanent until the  original experience has undergone

lapse of time. For one remembers now  what one saw or otherwise experienced formerly; the moment of the

original experience and the moment of the memory of it are never  identical. 

Again, (even when time has elapsed, and one can be said really to  have acquired memory, this is not

necessarily recollection, for  firstly) it is obviously possible, without any present act of  recollection, to

remember as a continued consequence of the original  perception or other experience; whereas when (after an

interval of  obliviscence) one recovers some scientific knowledge which he had  before, or some perception, or

some other experience, the state of  which we above declared to be memory, it is then, and then only,  that  this

recovery may amount to a recollection of any of the things  aforesaid. But, (though as observed above,

remembering does not  necessarily imply recollecting), recollecting always implies  remembering, and

actualized memory follows (upon the successful act of  recollecting). 

But secondly, even the assertion that recollection is the  reinstatement in consciousness of something which

was there before but  had disappeared requires qualification. This assertion may be true,  but it may also be

false; for the same person may twice learn (from  some teacher), or twice discover (i.e. excogitate), the same

fact.  Accordingly, the act of recollecting ought (in its definition) to be  distinguished from these acts; i.e.

recollecting must imply in those  who recollect the presence of some spring over and above that from  which

they originally learn. 

Acts of recollection, as they occur in experience, are due to the  fact that one movement has by nature another

that succeeds it in  regular order. 

If this order be necessary, whenever a subject experiences the  former of two movements thus connected, it

will (invariably)  experience the latter; if, however, the order be not necessary, but  customary, only in the

majority of cases will the subject experience  the latter of the two movements. But it is a fact that there are

some  movements, by a single experience of which persons take the  impress of  custom more deeply than they

do by experiencing others many  times;  hence upon seeing some things but once we remember them  better

than  others which we may have been frequently. 

Whenever therefore, we are recollecting, we are experiencing  certain  of the antecedent movements until

finally we experience the  one  after which customarily comes that which we seek. This explains  why we  hunt

up the series (of kineseis) having started in thought  either from  a present intuition or some other, and from

something  either  similar, or contrary, to what we seek, or else from that which  is  contiguous with it. Such is

the empirical ground of the process of  recollection; for the mnemonic movements involved in these

startingpoints are in some cases identical, in others, again,  simultaneous, with those of the idea we seek,

while in others they  comprise a portion of them, so that the remnant which one  experienced  after that portion

(and which still requires to be excited  in memory)  is comparatively small. 

Thus, then, it is that persons seek to recollect, and thus, too,  it is that they recollect even without the effort of

seeking to do so,  viz. when the movement implied in recollection has supervened on  some  other which is its

condition. For, as a rule, it is when  antecedent  movements of the classes here described have first been

excited, that  the particular movement implied in recollection follows.  We need not  examine a series of which

the beginning and end lie far  apart, in  order to see how (by recollection) we remember; one in which  they lie

near one another will serve equally well. For it is clear  that the  method is in each case the same, that is, one

hunts up the  objective  series, without any previous search or previous  recollection. For  (there is, besides the

natural order, viz. the order  of the pralmata,  or events of the primary experience, also a customary  order, and)

by  the effect of custom the mnemonic movements tend to  succeed one  another in a certain order.

Accordingly, therefore, when  one wishes to  recollect, this is what he will do: he will try to  obtain a beginning

of movement whose sequel shall be the movement  which he desires to  reawaken. This explains why attempts


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

2 4



Top




Page No 7


at  recollection succeed soonest  and best when they start from a beginning  (of some objective series).  For, in

order of succession, the  mnemonic movements are to one another  as the objective facts (from  which they are

derived). Accordingly,  things arranged in a fixed  order, like the successive demonstrations  in geometry, are

easy to  remember (or recollect) while badly arranged  subjects are remembered  with difficulty. 

Recollecting differs also in this respect from relearning, that  one who recollects will be able, somehow, to

move, solely by his own  effort, to the term next after the startingpoint. When one cannot  do  this of himself,

but only by external assistance, he no longer  remembers (i.e. he has totally forgotten, and therefore of course

cannot recollect). It often happens that, though a person cannot  recollect at the moment, yet by seeking he can

do so, and discovers  what he seeks. This he succeeds in doing by setting up many movements,  until finally he

excites one of a kind which will have for its  sequel  the fact he wishes to recollect. For remembering (which is

the  condicio sine qua non of recollecting) is the existence,  potentially,  in the mind of a movement capable of

stimulating it to  the desired  movement, and this, as has been said, in such a way that  the person  should be

moved (prompted to recollection) from within  himself, i.e.  in consequence of movements wholly contained

within  himself. 

But one must get hold of a startingpoint. This explains why it is  that persons are supposed to recollect

sometimes by starting from  mnemonic loci. The cause is that they pass swiftly in thought from one  point to

another, e.g. from milk to white, from white to mist, and  thence to moist, from which one remembers Autumn

(the 'season of  mists'), if this be the season he is trying to recollect. 

It seems true in general that the middle point also among all  things  is a good mnemonic startingpoint from

which to reach any of  them. For  if one does not recollect before, he will do so when he has  come to  this, or, if

not, nothing can help him; as, e.g. if one were  to have  in mind the numerical series denoted by the symbols A,

B, G,  D, E,  Z, I, H, O. For, if he does not remember what he wants at E,  then at E  he remembers O; because

from E movement in either direction  is  possible, to D or to Z. But, if it is not for one of these that he  is

searching, he will remember (what he is searching for) when he  has  come to G if he is searching for H or I.

But if (it is) not (for H  or  I that he is searching, but for one of the terms that remain), he  will  remember by

going to A, and so in all cases (in which one  starts from  a middle point). The cause of one's sometimes

recollecting  and  sometimes not, though starting from the same point, is, that  from the  same startingpoint a

movement can be made in several  directions, as,  for instance, from G to I or to D. If, then, the  mind has not

(when  starting from E) moved in an old path (i.e. one  in which it moved  first having the objective experience,

and that,  therefore, in which  un'ethized' phusis would have it again move),  it tends to move to the  more

customary; for (the mind having, by  chance or otherwise, missed  moving in the 'old' way) Custom now

assumes the role of Nature. Hence  the rapidity with which we recollect  what we frequently think about.  For

as regular sequence of events is  in accordance with nature, so,  too, regular sequence is observed in  the

actualization of kinesis (in  consciousness), and here frequency  tends to produce (the regularity  of) nature.

And since in the realm of  nature occurrences take place  which are even contrary to nature, or  fortuitous, the

same happens a  fortiori in the sphere swayed by  custom, since in this sphere natural  law is not similarly

established.  Hence it is that (from the same  startingpoint) the mind receives an  impulse to move sometimes

in the  required direction, and at other  times otherwise, (doing the latter)  particularly when something else

somehow deflects the mind from the  right direction and attracts it  to itself. This last consideration  explains

too how it happens that,  when we want to remember a name, we  remember one somewhat like it,  indeed, but

blunder in reference to  (i.e. in pronouncing) the one we  intended. 

Thus, then, recollection takes place. 

But the point of capital importance is that (for the purpose of  recollection) one should cognize, determinately

or indeterminately,  the timerelation (of that which he wishes to recollect). There  is,let it be taken as a

fact,something by which one distinguishes  a  greater and a smaller time; and it is reasonable to think that one

does this in a way analogous to that in which one discerns (spacial)  magnitudes. For it is not by the mind's


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

2 5



Top




Page No 8


reaching out towards them,  as  some say a visual ray from the eye does (in seeing), that one  thinks  of large

things at a distance in space (for even if they are  not  there, one may similarly think them); but one does so by

a  proportionate mental movement. For there are in the mind the like  figures and movements (i.e. 'like' to

those of objects and events).  Therefore, when one thinks the greater objects, in what will his  thinking those

differ from his thinking the smaller? (In nothing,)  because all the internal though smaller are as it were

proportional to  the external. Now, as we may assume within a person something  proportional to the forms (of

distant magnitudes), so, too, we may  doubtless assume also something else proportional to their  distances.

As, therefore, if one has (psychically) the movement in AB,  BE, he  constructs in thought (i.e. knows

objectively) GD, since AG and  GD  bear equal ratios respectively (to AB and BE), (so he who  recollects  also

proceeds). Why then does he construct GD rather than  ZH? Is it  not because as AG is to AB, so is O to I?

These movements  therefore  (sc. in AB, BE, and in O:I) he has simultaneously. But if he  wishes to  construct

to thought ZH, he has in mind BE in like manner as  before  (when constructing GD), but now, instead of (the

movements of  the  ratio) O:I, he has in mind (those of the ratio K:L; for  K:L::ZA:BA.  (See diagram.) 

When, therefore, the 'movement' corresponding to the object and  that  corresponding to its time concur, then

one actually remembers. If  one supposes (himself to move in these different but concurrent  ways)  without

really doing so, he supposes himself to remember. 

For one may be mistaken, and think that he remembers when he  really does not. But it is not possible,

conversely, that when one  actually remembers he should not suppose himself to remember, but  should

remember unconsciously. For remembering, as we have conceived  it, essentially implies consciousness of

itself. If, however, the  movement corresponding to the objective fact takes place without  that  corresponding

to the time, or, if the latter takes place  without the  former, one does not remember. 

The movement answering to the time is of two kinds. Sometimes in  remembering a fact one has no

determinate timenotion of it, no such  notion as that e.g. he did something or other on the day before

yesterday; while in other cases he has a determinate notionof the  time. Still, even though one does not

remember with actual  determination of the time, he genuinely remembers, none the less.  Persons are wont to

say that they remember (something), but yet do not  know when (it occurred, as happens) whenever they do

not know  determinately the exact length of time implied in the 'when'. 

It has been already stated that those who have a good memory are  not  identical with those who are quick at

recollecting. But the act of  recollecting differs from that of remembering, not only  chronologically, but also

in this, that many also of the other animals  (as well as man) have memory, but, of all that we are acquainted

with,  none, we venture to say, except man, shares in the faculty of  recollection. The cause of this is that

recollection is, as it were  a  mode of inference. For he who endeavours to recollect infers that he  formerly

saw, or heard, or had some such experience, and the process  (by which he succeeds in recollecting) is, as it

were, a sort of  investigation. But to investigate in this way belongs naturally to  those animals alone which are

also endowed with the faculty of  deliberation; (which proves what was said above), for deliberation  is  a form

of inference. 

That the affection is corporeal, i.e. that recollection is a  searching for an 'image' in a corporeal substrate, is

proved by the  fact that in some persons, when, despite the most strenuous  application of thought, they have

been unable to recollect, it (viz.  the anamnesis = the effort at recollection) excites a feeling of  discomfort,

which, even though they abandon the effort at  recollection, persists in them none the less; and especially in

persons of melancholic temperament. For these are most powerfully  moved by presentations. The reason why

the effort of recollection is  not under the control of their will is that, as those who throw a  stone cannot stop it

at their will when thrown, so he who tries to  recollect and 'hunts' (after an idea) sets up a process in a  material

part, (that) in which resides the affection. Those who have  moisture  around that part which is the centre of

senseperception  suffer most  discomfort of this kind. For when once the moisture has  been set in  motion it is

not easily brought to rest, until the idea  which was  sought for has again presented itself, and thus the


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

2 6



Top




Page No 9


movement  has found  a straight course. For a similar reason bursts of anger or  fits of  terror, when once they

have excited such motions, are not at  once  allayed, even though the angry or terrified persons (by efforts  of

will) set up counter motions, but the passions continue to move  them  on, in the same direction as at first, in

opposition to such  counter  motions. The affection resembles also that in the case of  words,  tunes, or sayings,

whenever one of them has become inveterate  on the  lips. People give them up and resolve to avoid them; yet

again they  find themselves humming the forbidden air, or using the  prohibited  word. Those whose upper

parts are abnormally large, as.  is the case  with dwarfs, have abnormally weak memory, as compared with

their  opposites, because of the great weight which they have resting  upon  the organ of perception, and

because their mnemonic movements  are,  from the very first, not able to keep true to a course, but are

dispersed, and because, in the effort at recollection, these movements  do not easily find a direct onward path.

Infants and very old  persons  have bad memories, owing to the amount of movement going on  within  them;

for the latter are in process of rapid decay, the  former in  process of vigorous growth; and we may add that

children,  until  considerably advanced in years, are dwarflike in their bodily  structure. Such then is our

theory as regards memory and remembering  their nature, and the particular organ of the soul by which

animals  remember; also as regards recollection, its formal definition, and the  manner and causesof its

performance. 

THE END 


ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE

2 7



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE, page = 4

   3. by Aristotle, page = 4

   4.  1, page = 4

   5.  2, page = 6