Title:   POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

Subject:  

Author:   by Aristotle

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Page No 46

Page No 47

Page No 48

Page No 49

Bookmarks





Page No 1


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

by Aristotle



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

POSTERIOR ANALYTICS..............................................................................................................................1

by Aristotle..............................................................................................................................................1

Book I ...................................................................................................................................................................2

1..............................................................................................................................................................2

2..............................................................................................................................................................3

3..............................................................................................................................................................4

4..............................................................................................................................................................5

5..............................................................................................................................................................6

6..............................................................................................................................................................7

7..............................................................................................................................................................9

8..............................................................................................................................................................9

9............................................................................................................................................................10

10..........................................................................................................................................................10

11..........................................................................................................................................................11

12..........................................................................................................................................................12

13..........................................................................................................................................................13

14..........................................................................................................................................................14

15..........................................................................................................................................................15

16..........................................................................................................................................................15

17..........................................................................................................................................................16

18..........................................................................................................................................................17

19..........................................................................................................................................................18

20..........................................................................................................................................................19

21..........................................................................................................................................................19

22..........................................................................................................................................................20

23..........................................................................................................................................................22

24..........................................................................................................................................................23

25..........................................................................................................................................................25

26..........................................................................................................................................................26

27..........................................................................................................................................................26

28..........................................................................................................................................................26

29..........................................................................................................................................................27

30..........................................................................................................................................................27

31..........................................................................................................................................................27

32..........................................................................................................................................................28

33..........................................................................................................................................................28

34..........................................................................................................................................................30

Book II...............................................................................................................................................................30

1............................................................................................................................................................30

2............................................................................................................................................................30

3............................................................................................................................................................31

4............................................................................................................................................................32

5............................................................................................................................................................33

6............................................................................................................................................................34

7............................................................................................................................................................34

8............................................................................................................................................................35

9............................................................................................................................................................36

10..........................................................................................................................................................36


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

i



Top




Page No 3


Table of Contents

11..........................................................................................................................................................37

12..........................................................................................................................................................38

13..........................................................................................................................................................40

14..........................................................................................................................................................42

15..........................................................................................................................................................42

16..........................................................................................................................................................43

17..........................................................................................................................................................43

18..........................................................................................................................................................44

19..........................................................................................................................................................45


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

ii



Top




Page No 4


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

by Aristotle

translated by G. R. G. Mure

Book I  

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

15 

16 

17 

18 

19 

20 

21 

22 

23 

24 

25 

26 

27 

28 

29 

30 

31 

32 

33 

34  

Book II  

1 

2 

3  

POSTERIOR ANALYTICS 1



Top




Page No 5


4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

15 

16 

17 

18 

19  

Book I

1

ALL instruction given or received by way of argument proceeds from  preexistent knowledge. This becomes

evident upon a survey of all  the  species of such instruction. The mathematical sciences and all  other

speculative disciplines are acquired in this way, and so are the  two  forms of dialectical reasoning, syllogistic

and inductive; for  each of  these latter make use of old knowledge to impart new, the  syllogism  assuming an

audience that accepts its premisses, induction  exhibiting  the universal as implicit in the clearly known

particular. Again, the  persuasion exerted by rhetorical arguments is  in principle the same,  since they use

either example, a kind of  induction, or enthymeme, a  form of syllogism. 

The preexistent knowledge required is of two kinds. In some cases  admission of the fact must be assumed,

in others comprehension of  the  meaning of the term used, and sometimes both assumptions are  essential.

Thus, we assume that every predicate can be either truly  affirmed or truly denied of any subject, and that

'triangle' means  so  and so; as regards 'unit' we have to make the double assumption  of the  meaning of the

word and the existence of the thing. The  reason is that  these several objects are not equally obvious to us.

Recognition of a  truth may in some cases contain as factors both  previous knowledge and  also knowledge

acquired simultaneously with  that  recognitionknowledge, this latter, of the particulars actually  falling under

the universal and therein already virtually known. For  example, the student knew beforehand that the angles

of every triangle  are equal to two right angles; but it was only at the actual moment at  which he was being led

on to recognize this as true in the instance  before him that he came to know 'this figure inscribed in the

semicircle' to be a triangle. For some things (viz. the singulars  finally reached which are not predicable of

anything else as  subject)  are only learnt in this way, i.e. there is here no  recognition through  a middle of a

minor term as subject to a major.  Before he was led on  to recognition or before he actually drew a  conclusion,

we should  perhaps say that in a manner he knew, in a  manner not. 

If he did not in an unqualified sense of the term know the  existence  of this triangle, how could he know

without qualification  that its  angles were equal to two right angles? No: clearly he knows  not  without

qualification but only in the sense that he knows  universally.  If this distinction is not drawn, we are faced

with the  dilemma in the  Meno: either a man will learn nothing or what he  already knows; for we  cannot

accept the solution which some people  offer. A man is asked,  'Do you, or do you not, know that every pair is


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

Book I 2



Top




Page No 6


even?' He says he does  know it. The questioner then produces a  particular pair, of the  existence, and so a

fortiori of the evenness,  of which he was unaware.  The solution which some people offer is to  assert that they

do not  know that every pair is even, but only that  everything which they know  to be a pair is even: yet what

they know to  be even is that of which  they have demonstrated evenness, i.e. what  they made the subject of

their premiss, viz. not merely every triangle  or number which they  know to be such, but any and every

number or  triangle without  reservation. For no premiss is ever couched in the  form 'every  number which you

know to be such', or 'every rectilinear  figure  which you know to be such': the predicate is always construed  as

applicable to any and every instance of the thing. On the other  hand, I imagine there is nothing to prevent a

man in one sense knowing  what he is learning, in another not knowing it. The strange thing  would be, not if

in some sense he knew what he was learning, but if he  were to know it in that precise sense and manner in

which he was  learning it. 

2

We suppose ourselves to possess unqualified scientific knowledge  of a thing, as opposed to knowing it in the

accidental way in which  the sophist knows, when we think that we know the cause on which the  fact depends,

as the cause of that fact and of no other, and, further,  that the fact could not be other than it is. Now that

scientific  knowing is something of this sort is evidentwitness both those who  falsely claim it and those who

actually possess it, since the former  merely imagine themselves to be, while the latter are also actually,  in the

condition described. Consequently the proper object of  unqualified scientific knowledge is something which

cannot be other  than it is. 

There may be another manner of knowing as wellthat will be  discussed later. What I now assert is that at all

events we do know by  demonstration. By demonstration I mean a syllogism productive of  scientific

knowledge, a syllogism, that is, the grasp of which is eo  ipso such knowledge. Assuming then that my thesis

as to the nature  of  scientific knowing is correct, the premisses of demonstrated  knowledge  must be true,

primary, immediate, better known than and  prior to the  conclusion, which is further related to them as effect

to  cause.  Unless these conditions are satisfied, the basic truths will  not be  'appropriate' to the conclusion.

Syllogism there may indeed  be without  these conditions, but such syllogism, not being  productive of

scientific knowledge, will not be demonstration. The  premisses must be  true: for that which is nonexistent

cannot be  knownwe cannot know,  e.g. that the diagonal of a square is  commensurate with its side. The

premisses must be primary and  indemonstrable; otherwise they will  require demonstration in order  to be

known, since to have knowledge,  if it be not accidental  knowledge, of things which are demonstrable,  means

precisely to have a  demonstration of them. The premisses must be  the causes of the  conclusion, better known

than it, and prior to it;  its causes, since  we possess scientific knowledge of a thing only when  we know its

cause; prior, in order to be causes; antecedently known,  this  antecedent knowledge being not our mere

understanding of the  meaning, but knowledge of the fact as well. Now 'prior' and 'better  known' are

ambiguous terms, for there is a difference between what  is  prior and better known in the order of being and

what is prior  and  better known to man. I mean that objects nearer to sense are prior  and  better known to man;

objects without qualification prior and  better  known are those further from sense. Now the most universal

causes are  furthest from sense and particular causes are nearest to  sense, and  they are thus exactly opposed to

one another. In saying  that the  premisses of demonstrated knowledge must be primary, I mean  that they  must

be the 'appropriate' basic truths, for I identify  primary premiss  and basic truth. A 'basic truth' in a

demonstration is  an immediate  proposition. An immediate proposition is one which has no  other  proposition

prior to it. A proposition is either part of an  enunciation, i.e. it predicates a single attribute of a single  subject.

If a proposition is dialectical, it assumes either part  indifferently; if it is demonstrative, it lays down one part

to the  definite exclusion of the other because that part is true. The term  'enunciation' denotes either part of a

contradiction indifferently.  A  contradiction is an opposition which of its own nature excludes a  middle. The

part of a contradiction which conjoins a predicate with  a  subject is an affirmation; the part disjoining them is

a negation. I  call an immediate basic truth of syllogism a 'thesis' when, though  it  is not susceptible of proof by


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

2 3



Top




Page No 7


the teacher, yet ignorance of it  does  not constitute a total bar to progress on the part of the  pupil: one  which

the pupil must know if he is to learn anything  whatever is an  axiom. I call it an axiom because there are such

truths  and we give  them the name of axioms par excellence. If a thesis  assumes one part  or the other of an

enunciation, i.e. asserts either  the existence or  the nonexistence of a subject, it is a hypothesis;  if it does not

so  assert, it is a definition. Definition is a 'thesis'  or a 'laying  something down', since the arithmetician lays it

down  that to be a  unit is to be quantitatively indivisible; but it is not a  hypothesis,  for to define what a unit is

is not the same as to  affirm its  existence. 

Now since the required ground of our knowledgei.e. of our  convictionof a fact is the possession of such a

syllogism as we  call  demonstration, and the ground of the syllogism is the facts  constituting its premisses, we

must not only know the primary  premissessome if not all of thembeforehand, but know them better  than

the conclusion: for the cause of an attribute's inherence in a  subject always itself inheres in the subject more

firmly than that  attribute; e.g. the cause of our loving anything is dearer to us  than  the object of our love. So

since the primary premisses are the  cause  of our knowledgei.e. of our convictionit follows that we  know

them  betterthat is, are more convinced of themthan their  consequences,  precisely because of our

knowledge of the latter is  the effect of our  knowledge of the premisses. Now a man cannot believe  in

anything more  than in the things he knows, unless he has either  actual knowledge of  it or something better

than actual knowledge.  But we are faced with  this paradox if a student whose belief rests  on demonstration

has not  prior knowledge; a man must believe in  some, if not in all, of the  basic truths more than in the

conclusion. Moreover, if a man sets out  to acquire the scientific  knowledge that comes through

demonstration,  he must not only have a  better knowledge of the basic truths and a  firmer conviction of them

than of the connexion which is being  demonstrated: more than this,  nothing must be more certain or better

known to him than these basic  truths in their character as  contradicting the fundamental premisses  which lead

to the opposed and  erroneous conclusion. For indeed the  conviction of pure science must  be unshakable. 

3

Some hold that, owing to the necessity of knowing the primary  premisses, there is no scientific knowledge.

Others think there is,  but that all truths are demonstrable. Neither doctrine is either  true  or a necessary

deduction from the premisses. The first school,  assuming that there is no way of knowing other than by

demonstration,  maintain that an infinite regress is involved, on the  ground that if  behind the prior stands no

primary, we could not know  the posterior  through the prior (wherein they are right, for one  cannot traverse an

infinite series): if on the other handthey saythe  series terminates  and there are primary premisses, yet these

are  unknowable because  incapable of demonstration, which according to them  is the only form  of knowledge.

And since thus one cannot know the  primary premisses,  knowledge of the conclusions which follow from

them  is not pure  scientific knowledge nor properly knowing at all, but  rests on the  mere supposition that the

premisses are true. The other  party agree  with them as regards knowing, holding that it is only  possible by

demonstration, but they see no difficulty in holding  that all truths  are demonstrated, on the ground that

demonstration may  be circular and  reciprocal. 

Our own doctrine is that not all knowledge is demonstrative: on  the contrary, knowledge of the immediate

premisses is independent of  demonstration. (The necessity of this is obvious; for since we must  know the

prior premisses from which the demonstration is drawn, and  since the regress must end in immediate truths,

those truths must be  indemonstrable.) Such, then, is our doctrine, and in addition we  maintain that besides

scientific knowledge there is its originative  source which enables us to recognize the definitions. 

Now demonstration must be based on premisses prior to and better  known than the conclusion; and the same

things cannot simultaneously  be both prior and posterior to one another: so circular  demonstration  is clearly

not possible in the unqualified sense of  'demonstration',  but only possible if 'demonstration' be extended to

include that other  method of argument which rests on a distinction  between truths prior  to us and truths


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

3 4



Top




Page No 8


without qualification prior,  i.e. the method by which  induction produces knowledge. But if we  accept this

extension of its  meaning, our definition of unqualified  knowledge will prove faulty;  for there seem to be two

kinds of it.  Perhaps, however, the second  form of demonstration, that which  proceeds from truths better

known to  us, is not demonstration in the  unqualified sense of the term. 

The advocates of circular demonstration are not only faced with  the difficulty we have just stated: in addition

their theory reduces  to the mere statement that if a thing exists, then it does existan  easy way of proving

anything. That this is so can be clearly shown  by  taking three terms, for to constitute the circle it makes no

difference whether many terms or few or even only two are taken.  Thus  by direct proof, if A is, B must be; if

B is, C must be;  therefore if  A is, C must be. Since thenby the circular proofif A  is, B must be,  and if B is,

A must be, A may be substituted for C  above. Then 'if B  is, A must be'='if B is, C must be', which above  gave

the conclusion  'if A is, C must be': but C and A have been  identified. Consequently  the upholders of circular

demonstration are  in the position of saying  that if A is, A must bea simple way of  proving anything.

Moreover,  even such circular demonstration is  impossible except in the case of  attributes that imply one

another,  viz. 'peculiar' properties. 

Now, it has been shown that the positing of one thingbe it one  term or one premissnever involves a

necessary consequent: two  premisses constitute the first and smallest foundation for drawing a  conclusion at

all and therefore a fortiori for the demonstrative  syllogism of science. If, then, A is implied in B and C, and B

and C  are reciprocally implied in one another and in A, it is possible, as  has been shown in my writings on

the syllogism, to prove all the  assumptions on which the original conclusion rested, by circular  demonstration

in the first figure. But it has also been shown that  in  the other figures either no conclusion is possible, or at

least  none  which proves both the original premisses. Propositions the  terms of  which are not convertible

cannot be circularly demonstrated  at all,  and since convertible terms occur rarely in actual  demonstrations, it

is clearly frivolous and impossible to say that  demonstration is  reciprocal and that therefore everything can be

demonstrated. 

4

Since the object of pure scientific knowledge cannot be other than  it is, the truth obtained by demonstrative

knowledge will be  necessary. And since demonstrative knowledge is only present when we  have a

demonstration, it follows that demonstration is an inference  from necessary premisses. So we must consider

what are the premisses  of demonstrationi.e. what is their character: and as a preliminary,  let us define what

we mean by an attribute 'true in every instance  of  its subject', an 'essential' attribute, and a 'commensurate and

universal' attribute. I call 'true in every instance' what is truly  predicable of all instancesnot of one to the

exclusion of  othersand  at all times, not at this or that time only; e.g. if animal  is truly  predicable of every

instance of man, then if it be true to  say 'this  is a man', 'this is an animal' is also true, and if the  one be true

now the other is true now. A corresponding account holds  if point is  in every instance predicable as contained

in line. There  is evidence  for this in the fact that the objection we raise against a  proposition  put to us as true

in every instance is either an  instance in which, or  an occasion on which, it is not true.  Essential attributes are

(1)  such as belong to their subject as  elements in its essential nature  (e.g. line thus belongs to  triangle, point

to line; for the very being  or 'substance' of triangle  and line is composed of these elements,  which are

contained in the  formulae defining triangle and line): (2)  such that, while they belong  to certain subjects, the

subjects to  which they belong are contained  in the attribute's own defining  formula. Thus straight and curved

belong to line, odd and even, prime  and compound, square and oblong,  to number; and also the formula

defining any one of these attributes  contains its subjecte.g. line or  number as the case may be. 

Extending this classification to all other attributes, I  distinguish  those that answer the above description as

belonging  essentially to  their respective subjects; whereas attributes related  in neither of  these two ways to

their subjects I call accidents or  'coincidents';  e.g. musical or white is a 'coincident' of animal. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

4 5



Top




Page No 9


Further (a) that is essential which is not predicated of a subject  other than itself: e.g. 'the walking [thing]'

walks and is white in  virtue of being something else besides; whereas substance, in the  sense of whatever

signifies a 'this somewhat', is not what it is in  virtue of being something else besides. Things, then, not

predicated  of a subject I call essential; things predicated of a subject I call  accidental or 'coincidental'. 

In another sense again (b) a thing consequentially connected with  anything is essential; one not so connected

is 'coincidental'. An  example of the latter is 'While he was walking it lightened': the  lightning was not due to

his walking; it was, we should say, a  coincidence. If, on the other hand, there is a consequential  connexion,

the predication is essential; e.g. if a beast dies when its  throat is being cut, then its death is also essentially

connected with  the cutting, because the cutting was the cause of death, not death a  'coincident' of the cutting. 

So far then as concerns the sphere of connexions scientifically  known in the unqualified sense of that term, all

attributes which  (within that sphere) are essential either in the sense that their  subjects are contained in them,

or in the sense that they are  contained in their subjects, are necessary as well as  consequentially  connected

with their subjects. For it is impossible  for them not to  inhere in their subjects either simply or in the  qualified

sense that  one or other of a pair of opposites must inhere  in the subject; e.g.  in line must be either straightness

or curvature,  in number either  oddness or evenness. For within a single identical  genus the contrary  of a given

attribute is either its privative or its  contradictory;  e.g. within number what is not odd is even, inasmuch as

within this  sphere even is a necessary consequent of notodd. So,  since any given  predicate must be either

affirmed or denied of any  subject, essential  attributes must inhere in their subjects of  necessity. 

Thus, then, we have established the distinction between the  attribute which is 'true in every instance' and the

'essential'  attribute. 

I term 'commensurately universal' an attribute which belongs to  every instance of its subject, and to every

instance essentially and  as such; from which it clearly follows that all commensurate  universals inhere

necessarily in their subjects. The essential  attribute, and the attribute that belongs to its subject as such,  are

identical. E.g. point and straight belong to line essentially, for  they belong to line as such; and triangle as

such has two right  angles, for it is essentially equal to two right angles. 

An attribute belongs commensurately and universally to a subject  when it can be shown to belong to any

random instance of that  subject  and when the subject is the first thing to which it can be  shown to  belong.

Thus, e.g. (1) the equality of its angles to two  right angles  is not a commensurately universal attribute of

figure.  For though it  is possible to show that a figure has its angles equal  to two right  angles, this attribute

cannot be demonstrated of any  figure selected  at haphazard, nor in demonstrating does one take a  figure at

randoma  square is a figure but its angles are not equal  to two right angles.  On the other hand, any isosceles

triangle has its  angles equal to two  right angles, yet isosceles triangle is not the  primary subject of  this

attribute but triangle is prior. So whatever  can be shown to have  its angles equal to two right angles, or to

possess any other  attribute, in any random instance of itself and  primarilythat is the  first subject to which the

predicate in question  belongs  commensurately and universally, and the demonstration, in  the  essential sense,

of any predicate is the proof of it as  belonging to  this first subject commensurately and universally:  while the

proof of  it as belonging to the other subjects to which it  attaches is  demonstration only in a secondary and

unessential sense.  Nor again (2)  is equality to two right angles a commensurately  universal attribute  of

isosceles; it is of wider application. 

5

We must not fail to observe that we often fall into error because  our conclusion is not in fact primary and

commensurately universal  in  the sense in which we think we prove it so. We make this mistake  (1)  when the

subject is an individual or individuals above which there  is  no universal to be found: (2) when the subjects


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

5 6



Top




Page No 10


belong to different  species and there is a higher universal, but it has no name: (3)  when  the subject which the

demonstrator takes as a whole is really  only a  part of a larger whole; for then the demonstration will be true

of the  individual instances within the part and will hold in every  instance  of it, yet the demonstration will not

be true of this subject  primarily and commensurately and universally. When a demonstration  is  true of a

subject primarily and commensurately and universally,  that  is to be taken to mean that it is true of a given

subject  primarily  and as such. Case (3) may be thus exemplified. If a proof  were given  that perpendiculars to

the same line are parallel, it might  be  supposed that lines thus perpendicular were the proper subject of  the

demonstration because being parallel is true of every instance  of  them. But it is not so, for the parallelism

depends not on these  angles being equal to one another because each is a right angle, but  simply on their

being equal to one another. An example of (1) would be  as follows: if isosceles were the only triangle, it

would be thought  to have its angles equal to two right angles qua isosceles. An  instance of (2) would be the

law that proportionals alternate.  Alternation used to be demonstrated separately of numbers, lines,  solids, and

durations, though it could have been proved of them all by  a single demonstration. Because there was no

single name to denote  that in which numbers, lengths, durations, and solids are identical,  and because they

differed specifically from one another, this property  was proved of each of them separately. Today,

however, the proof is  commensurately universal, for they do not possess this attribute qua  lines or qua

numbers, but qua manifesting this generic character which  they are postulated as possessing universally.

Hence, even if one  prove of each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two  right  angles, whether by

means of the same or different proofs; still,  as  long as one treats separately equilateral, scalene, and  isosceles,

one  does not yet know, except sophistically, that  triangle has its angles  equal to two right angles, nor does

one yet  know that triangle has  this property commensurately and universally,  even if there is no  other species

of triangle but these. For one  does not know that  triangle as such has this property, nor even that  'all' triangles

have  itunless 'all' means 'each taken singly': if  'all' means 'as a whole  class', then, though there be none in

which  one does not recognize  this property, one does not know it of 'all  triangles'. 

When, then, does our knowledge fail of commensurate universality,  and when it is unqualified knowledge? If

triangle be identical in  essence with equilateral, i.e. with each or all equilaterals, then  clearly we have

unqualified knowledge: if on the other hand it be not,  and the attribute belongs to equilateral qua triangle;

then our  knowledge fails of commensurate universality. 'But', it will be asked,  'does this attribute belong to

the subject of which it has been  demonstrated qua triangle or qua isosceles? What is the point at which  the

subject. to which it belongs is primary? (i.e. to what subject can  it be demonstrated as belonging

commensurately and universally?)'  Clearly this point is the first term in which it is found to inhere as  the

elimination of inferior differentiae proceeds. Thus the angles  of  a brazen isosceles triangle are equal to two

right angles: but  eliminate brazen and isosceles and the attribute remains. 'But'you  may say'eliminate

figure or limit, and the attribute vanishes.' True,  but figure and limit are not the first differentiae whose

elimination  destroys the attribute. 'Then what is the first?' If it is  triangle,  it will be in virtue of triangle that

the attribute  belongs to all the  other subjects of which it is predicable, and  triangle is the subject  to which it

can be demonstrated as belonging  commensurately and  universally. 

6

Demonstrative knowledge must rest on necessary basic truths; for  the  object of scientific knowledge cannot

be other than it is. Now  attributes attaching essentially to their subjects attach  necessarily  to them: for

essential attributes are either elements in  the essential  nature of their subjects, or contain their subjects as

elements in  their own essential nature. (The pairs of opposites  which the latter  class includes are necessary

because one member or  the other  necessarily inheres.) It follows from this that premisses of  the

demonstrative syllogism must be connexions essential in the  sense  explained: for all attributes must inhere

essentially or else be  accidental, and accidental attributes are not necessary to their  subjects. 

We must either state the case thus, or else premise that the  conclusion of demonstration is necessary and that


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

6 7



Top




Page No 11


a demonstrated  conclusion cannot be other than it is, and then infer that the  conclusion must be developed

from necessary premisses. For though  you  may reason from true premisses without demonstrating, yet if  your

premisses are necessary you will assuredly demonstratein such  necessity you have at once a distinctive

character of demonstration.  That demonstration proceeds from necessary premisses is also indicated  by the

fact that the objection we raise against a professed  demonstration is that a premiss of it is not a necessary

truthwhether  we think it altogether devoid of necessity, or at any rate so far as  our opponent's previous

argument goes. This shows how naive it is to  suppose one's basic truths rightly chosen if one starts with a

proposition which is (1) popularly accepted and (2) true, such as  the  sophists' assumption that to know is the

same as to possess  knowledge.  For (1) popular acceptance or rejection is no criterion  of a basic  truth, which

can only be the primary law of the genus  constituting the  subject matter of the demonstration; and (2) not  all

truth is  'appropriate'. 

A further proof that the conclusion must be the development of  necessary premisses is as follows. Where

demonstration is possible,  one who can give no account which includes the cause has no scientific

knowledge. If, then, we suppose a syllogism in which, though A  necessarily inheres in C, yet B, the middle

term of the demonstration,  is not necessarily connected with A and C, then the man who argues  thus has no

reasoned knowledge of the conclusion, since this  conclusion does not owe its necessity to the middle term;

for though  the conclusion is necessary, the mediating link is a contingent  fact.  Or again, if a man is without

knowledge now, though he still  retains  the steps of the argument, though there is no change in  himself or in

the fact and no lapse of memory on his part; then  neither had he  knowledge previously. But the mediating

link, not being  necessary, may  have perished in the interval; and if so, though  there be no change in  him nor

in the fact, and though he will still  retain the steps of the  argument, yet he has not knowledge, and  therefore

had not knowledge  before. Even if the link has not  actually perished but is liable to  perish, this situation is

possible and might occur. But such a  condition cannot be knowledge. 

When the conclusion is necessary, the middle through which it was  proved may yet quite easily be

nonnecessary. You can in fact infer  the necessary even from a nonnecessary premiss, just as you can infer

the true from the not true. On the other hand, when the middle is  necessary the conclusion must be necessary;

just as true premisses  always give a true conclusion. Thus, if A is necessarily predicated of  B and B of C,

then A is necessarily predicated of C. But when the  conclusion is nonnecessary the middle cannot be

necessary either.  Thus: let A be predicated nonnecessarily of C but necessarily of B,  and let B be a

necessary predicate of C; then A too will be a  necessary predicate of C, which by hypothesis it is not. 

To sum up, then: demonstrative knowledge must be knowledge of a  necessary nexus, and therefore must

clearly be obtained through a  necessary middle term; otherwise its possessor will know neither the  cause nor

the fact that his conclusion is a necessary connexion.  Either he will mistake the nonnecessary for the

necessary and believe  the necessity of the conclusion without knowing it, or else he will  not even believe

itin which case he will be equally ignorant, whether  he actually infers the mere fact through middle terms or

the  reasoned  fact and from immediate premisses. 

Of accidents that are not essential according to our definition of  essential there is no demonstrative

knowledge; for since an  accident,  in the sense in which I here speak of it, may also not  inhere, it is  impossible

to prove its inherence as a necessary  conclusion. A  difficulty, however, might be raised as to why in  dialectic,

if the  conclusion is not a necessary connexion, such and  such determinate  premisses should be proposed in

order to deal with  such and such  determinate problems. Would not the result be the same  if one asked  any

questions whatever and then merely stated one's  conclusion? The  solution is that determinate questions have

to be put,  not because the  replies to them affirm facts which necessitate facts  affirmed by the  conclusion, but

because these answers are propositions  which if the  answerer affirm, he must affirm the conclusion and

affirm  it with  truth if they are true. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

6 8



Top




Page No 12


Since it is just those attributes within every genus which are  essential and possessed by their respective

subjects as such that  are  necessary it is clear that both the conclusions and the  premisses of  demonstrations

which produce scientific knowledge are  essential. For  accidents are not necessary: and, further, since

accidents are not  necessary one does not necessarily have reasoned  knowledge of a  conclusion drawn from

them (this is so even if the  accidental  premisses are invariable but not essential, as in proofs  through  signs;

for though the conclusion be actually essential, one  will not  know it as essential nor know its reason); but to

have  reasoned  knowledge of a conclusion is to know it through its cause. We  may  conclude that the middle

must be consequentially connected with  the  minor, and the major with the middle. 

7

It follows that we cannot in demonstrating pass from one genus to  another. We cannot, for instance, prove

geometrical truths by  arithmetic. For there are three elements in demonstration: (1) what is  proved, the

conclusionan attribute inhering essentially in a genus;  (2) the axioms, i.e. axioms which are premisses of

demonstration;  (3)  the subjectgenus whose attributes, i.e. essential properties, are  revealed by the

demonstration. The axioms which are premisses of  demonstration may be identical in two or more sciences:

but in the  case of two different genera such as arithmetic and geometry you  cannot apply arithmetical

demonstration to the properties of  magnitudes unless the magnitudes in question are numbers. How in  certain

cases transference is possible I will explain later. 

Arithmetical demonstration and the other sciences likewise  possess, each of them, their own genera; so that if

the  demonstration  is to pass from one sphere to another, the genus must be  either  absolutely or to some extent

the same. If this is not so,  transference  is clearly impossible, because the extreme and the middle  terms must

be drawn from the same genus: otherwise, as predicated,  they will not  be essential and will thus be accidents.

That is why  it cannot be  proved by geometry that opposites fall under one science,  nor even  that the product

of two cubes is a cube. Nor can the  theorem of any  one science be demonstrated by means of another  science,

unless these  theorems are related as subordinate to  superior (e.g. as optical  theorems to geometry or harmonic

theorems to  arithmetic). Geometry  again cannot prove of lines any property which  they do not possess qua

lines, i.e. in virtue of the fundamental  truths of their peculiar  genus: it cannot show, for example, that  the

straight line is the most  beautiful of lines or the contrary of  the circle; for these qualities  do not belong to

lines in virtue of  their peculiar genus, but through  some property which it shares with  other genera. 

8

It is also clear that if the premisses from which the syllogism  proceeds are commensurately universal, the

conclusion of such i.e.  in  the unqualified sensemust also be eternal. Therefore no  attribute can  be

demonstrated nor known by strictly scientific  knowledge to inhere  in perishable things. The proof can only be

accidental, because the  attribute's connexion with its perishable  subject is not  commensurately universal but

temporary and special.  If such a  demonstration is made, one premiss must be perishable and  not

commensurately universal (perishable because only if it is  perishable  will the conclusion be perishable; not

commensurately  universal,  because the predicate will be predicable of some  instances of the  subject and not

of others); so that the conclusion  can only be that a  fact is true at the momentnot commensurately and

universally. The  same is true of definitions, since a definition is  either a primary  premiss or a conclusion of a

demonstration, or else  only differs from  a demonstration in the order of its terms.  Demonstration and science

of merely frequent occurrencese.g. of  eclipse as happening to the  moonare, as such, clearly eternal:

whereas so far as they are not  eternal they are not fully  commensurate. Other subjects too have  properties

attaching to them  in the same way as eclipse attaches to  the moon. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

7 9



Top




Page No 13


9

It is clear that if the conclusion is to show an attribute  inhering as such, nothing can be demonstrated except

from its  'appropriate' basic truths. Consequently a proof even from true,  indemonstrable, and immediate

premisses does not constitute knowledge.  Such proofs are like Bryson's method of squaring the circle; for

they  operate by taking as their middle a common charactera character,  therefore, which the subject may

share with anotherand consequently  they apply equally to subjects different in kind. They therefore  afford

knowledge of an attribute only as inhering accidentally, not as  belonging to its subject as such: otherwise they

would not have been  applicable to another genus. 

Our knowledge of any attribute's connexion with a subject is  accidental unless we know that connexion

through the middle term in  virtue of which it inheres, and as an inference from basic premisses  essential and

'appropriate' to the subjectunless we know, e.g. the  property of possessing angles equal to two right angles

as belonging  to that subject in which it inheres essentially, and as inferred  from  basic premisses essential and

'appropriate' to that subject: so  that  if that middle term also belongs essentially to the minor, the  middle  must

belong to the same kind as the major and minor terms.  The only  exceptions to this rule are such cases as

theorems in  harmonics which  are demonstrable by arithmetic. Such theorems are  proved by the same  middle

terms as arithmetical properties, but with a  qualificationthe  fact falls under a separate science (for the

subject  genus is  separate), but the reasoned fact concerns the superior  science, to  which the attributes

essentially belong. Thus, even  these apparent  exceptions show that no attribute is strictly  demonstrable except

from  its 'appropriate' basic truths, which,  however, in the case of these  sciences have the requisite identity  of

character. 

It is no less evident that the peculiar basic truths of each  inhering attribute are indemonstrable; for basic truths

from which  they might be deduced would be basic truths of all that is, and the  science to which they belonged

would possess universal sovereignty.  This is so because he knows better whose knowledge is deduced from

higher causes, for his knowledge is from prior premisses when it  derives from causes themselves uncaused:

hence, if he knows better  than others or best of all, his knowledge would be science in a higher  or the highest

degree. But, as things are, demonstration is not  transferable to another genus, with such exceptions as we

have  mentioned of the application of geometrical demonstrations to theorems  in mechanics or optics, or of

arithmetical demonstrations to those  of  harmonics. 

It is hard to be sure whether one knows or not; for it is hard to  be  sure whether one's knowledge is based on

the basic truths  appropriate to each attributethe differentia of true knowledge. We  think we have scientific

knowledge if we have reasoned from true and  primary premisses. But that is not so: the conclusion must be

homogeneous with the basic facts of the science. 

10

I call the basic truths of every genus those clements in it the  existence of which cannot be proved. As regards

both these primary  truths and the attributes dependent on them the meaning of the name is  assumed. The fact

of their existence as regards the primary truths  must be assumed; but it has to be proved of the remainder, the

attributes. Thus we assume the meaning alike of unity, straight, and  triangular; but while as regards unity and

magnitude we assume also  the fact of their existence, in the case of the remainder proof is  required. 

Of the basic truths used in the demonstrative sciences some are  peculiar to each science, and some are

common, but common only in  the  sense of analogous, being of use only in so far as they fall  within  the genus

constituting the province of the science in question. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

9 10



Top




Page No 14


Peculiar truths are, e.g. the definitions of line and straight;  common truths are such as 'take equals from

equals and equals remain'.  Only so much of these common truths is required as falls within the  genus in

question: for a truth of this kind will have the same force  even if not used generally but applied by the

geometer only to  magnitudes, or by the arithmetician only to numbers. Also peculiar  to  a science are the

subjects the existence as well as the meaning  of  which it assumes, and the essential attributes of which it

investigates, e.g. in arithmetic units, in geometry points and  lines.  Both the existence and the meaning of the

subjects are  assumed by  these sciences; but of their essential attributes only  the meaning is  assumed. For

example arithmetic assumes the meaning  of odd and even,  square and cube, geometry that of

incommensurable, or  of deflection or  verging of lines, whereas the existence of these  attributes is

demonstrated by means of the axioms and from previous  conclusions as  premisses. Astronomy too proceeds

in the same way.  For indeed every  demonstrative science has three elements: (1) that  which it posits,  the

subject genus whose essential attributes it  examines; (2) the  socalled axioms, which are primary premisses

of its  demonstration;  (3) the attributes, the meaning of which it assumes.  Yet some sciences  may very well

pass over some of these elements; e.g.  we might not  expressly posit the existence of the genus if its  existence

were  obvious (for instance, the existence of hot and cold is  more evident  than that of number); or we might

omit to assume  expressly the meaning  of the attributes if it were well understood. In  the way the meaning  of

axioms, such as 'Take equals from equals and  equals remain', is  well known and so not expressly assumed.

Nevertheless in the nature of  the case the essential elements of  demonstration are three: the  subject, the

attributes, and the basic  premisses. 

That which expresses necessary selfgrounded fact, and which we  must  necessarily believe, is distinct both

from the hypotheses of a  science  and from illegitimate postulateI say 'must believe', because  all  syllogism,

and therefore a fortiori demonstration, is addressed  not to  the spoken word, but to the discourse within the

soul, and  though we  can always raise objections to the spoken word, to the  inward  discourse we cannot

always object. That which is capable of  proof  but assumed by the teacher without proof is, if the pupil

believes and  accepts it, hypothesis, though only in a limited sense  hypothesisthat  is, relatively to the pupil; if

the pupil has no  opinion or a contrary  opinion on the matter, the same assumption is an  illegitimate  postulate.

Therein lies the distinction between  hypothesis and  illegitimate postulate: the latter is the contrary of  the

pupil's  opinion, demonstrable, but assumed and used without  demonstration. 

The definitionviz. those which are not expressed as statements  that  anything is or is notare not hypotheses:

but it is in the  premisses  of a science that its hypotheses are contained. Definitions  require  only to be

understood, and this is not hypothesisunless it be  contended that the pupil's hearing is also an hypothesis

required by  the teacher. Hypotheses, on the contrary, postulate facts on the being  of which depends the being

of the fact inferred. Nor are the  geometer's hypotheses false, as some have held, urging that one must  not

employ falsehood and that the geometer is uttering falsehood in  stating that the line which he draws is a foot

long or straight,  when  it is actually neither. The truth is that the geometer does not  draw  any conclusion from

the being of the particular line of which  he  speaks, but from what his diagrams symbolize. A further

distinction  is  that all hypotheses and illegitimate postulates are either  universal  or particular, whereas a

definition is neither. 

11

So demonstration does not necessarily imply the being of Forms nor  a  One beside a Many, but it does

necessarily imply the possibility of  truly predicating one of many; since without this possibility we  cannot

save the universal, and if the universal goes, the middle  term  goes witb. it, and so demonstration becomes

impossible. We  conclude,  then, that there must be a single identical term  unequivocally  predicable of a

number of individuals. 

The law that it is impossible to affirm and deny simultaneously  the same predicate of the same subject is not


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

11 11



Top




Page No 15


expressly posited by any  demonstration except when the conclusion also has to be expressed in  that form; in

which case the proof lays down as its major premiss that  the major is truly affirmed of the middle but falsely

denied. It makes  no difference, however, if we add to the middle, or again to the minor  term, the

corresponding negative. For grant a minor term of which it  is true to predicate maneven if it be also true to

predicate  notman  of itstill grant simply that man is animal and not  notanimal, and  the conclusion

follows: for it will still be true to  say that  Calliaseven if it be also true to say that  notCalliasis animal

and not notanimal. The reason is that the  major term is predicable  not only of the middle, but of something

other than the middle as  well, being of wider application; so that the  conclusion is not  affected even if the

middle is extended to cover the  original middle  term and also what is not the original middle term. 

The law that every predicate can be either truly affirmed or truly  denied of every subject is posited by such

demonstration as uses  reductio ad impossibile, and then not always universally, but so far  as it is requisite;

within the limits, that is, of the genusthe  genus, I mean (as I have already explained), to which the man of

science applies his demonstrations. In virtue of the common elements  of demonstrationI mean the common

axioms which are used as  premisses  of demonstration, not the subjects nor the attributes  demonstrated as

belonging to themall the sciences have communion with  one another,  and in communion with them all is

dialectic and any  science which  might attempt a universal proof of axioms such as the  law of excluded

middle, the law that the subtraction of equals from  equals leaves  equal remainders, or other axioms of the

same kind.  Dialectic has no  definite sphere of this kind, not being confined to a  single genus.  Otherwise its

method would not be interrogative; for the  interrogative  method is barred to the demonstrator, who cannot

use the  opposite  facts to prove the same nexus. This was shown in my work on  the  syllogism. 

12

If a syllogistic question is equivalent to a proposition embodying  one of the two sides of a contradiction, and

if each science has its  peculiar propositions from which its peculiar conclusion is developed,  then there is

such a thing as a distinctively scientific question, and  it is the interrogative form of the premisses from which

the  'appropriate' conclusion of each science is developed. Hence it is  clear that not every question will be

relevant to geometry, nor to  medicine, nor to any other science: only those questions will be  geometrical

which form premisses for the proof of the theorems of  geometry or of any other science, such as optics,

which uses the  same  basic truths as geometry. Of the other sciences the like is true.  Of  these questions the

geometer is bound to give his account, using  the  basic truths of geometry in conjunction with his previous

conclusions;  of the basic truths the geometer, as such, is not bound  to give any  account. The like is true of the

other sciences. There  is a limit,  then, to the questions which we may put to each man of  science; nor is  each

man of science bound to answer all inquiries on  each several  subject, but only such as fall within the defined

field  of his own  science. If, then, in controversy with a geometer qua  geometer the  disputant confines himself

to geometry and proves  anything from  geometrical premisses, he is clearly to be applauded; if  he goes  outside

these he will be at fault, and obviously cannot even  refute  the geometer except accidentally. One should

therefore not  discuss  geometry among those who are not geometers, for in such a  company an  unsound

argument will pass unnoticed. This is  correspondingly true in  the other sciences. 

Since there are 'geometrical' questions, does it follow that there  are also distinctively 'ungeometrical'

questions? Further, in each  special sciencegeometry for instancewhat kind of error is it that  may vitiate

questions, and yet not exclude them from that science?  Again, is the erroneous conclusion one constructed

from premisses  opposite to the true premisses, or is it formal fallacy though drawn  from geometrical

premisses? Or, perhaps, the erroneous conclusion is  due to the drawing of premisses from another science;

e.g. in a  geometrical controversy a musical question is distinctively  ungeometrical, whereas the notion that

parallels meet is in one  sense  geometrical, being ungeometrical in a different fashion: the  reason  being that

'ungeometrical', like 'unrhythmical', is  equivocal, meaning  in the one case not geometry at all, in the other  bad

geometry? It is  this error, i.e. error based on premisses of  this kind'of' the  science but falsethat is the


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

12 12



Top




Page No 16


contrary of  science. In mathematics the  formal fallacy is not so common, because  it is the middle term in

which the ambiguity lies, since the major  is predicated of the whole  of the middle and the middle of the

whole  of the minor (the predicate  of course never has the prefix 'all'); and  in mathematics one can, so  to

speak, see these middle terms with an  intellectual vision, while in  dialectic the ambiguity may escape

detection. E.g. 'Is every circle a  figure?' A diagram shows that  this is so, but the minor premiss 'Are  epics

circles?' is shown by the  diagram to be false. 

If a proof has an inductive minor premiss, one should not bring an  'objection' against it. For since every

premiss must be applicable  to  a number of cases (otherwise it will not be true in every instance,  which, since

the syllogism proceeds from universals, it must be), then  assuredly the same is true of an 'objection'; since

premisses and  'objections' are so far the same that anything which can be validly  advanced as an 'objection'

must be such that it could take the form of  a premiss, either demonstrative or dialectical. On the other hand,

arguments formally illogical do sometimes occur through taking as  middles mere attributes of the major and

minor terms. An instance of  this is Caeneus' proof that fire increases in geometrical  proportion:  'Fire', he

argues, 'increases rapidly, and so does  geometrical  proportion'. There is no syllogism so, but there is a

syllogism if the  most rapidly increasing proportion is geometrical and  the most rapidly  increasing proportion

is attributable to fire in  its motion.  Sometimes, no doubt, it is impossible to reason from  premisses  predicating

mere attributes: but sometimes it is possible,  though the  possibility is overlooked. If false premisses could

never  give true  conclusions 'resolution' would be easy, for premisses and  conclusion  would in that case

inevitably reciprocate. I might then  argue thus:  let A be an existing fact; let the existence of A imply  such and

such  facts actually known to me to exist, which we may call  B. I can now,  since they reciprocate, infer A

from B. 

Reciprocation of premisses and conclusion is more frequent in  mathematics, because mathematics takes

definitions, but never an  accident, for its premissesa second characteristic distinguishing  mathematical

reasoning from dialectical disputations. 

A science expands not by the interposition of fresh middle terms,  but by the apposition of fresh extreme

terms. E.g. A is predicated  of  B, B of C, C of D, and so indefinitely. Or the expansion may be  lateral: e.g. one

major A, may be proved of two minors, C and E.  Thus  let A represent numbera number or number taken

indeterminately; B  determinate odd number; C any particular odd  number. We can then  predicate A of C.

Next let D represent determinate  even number, and E  even number. Then A is predicable of E. 

13

Knowledge of the fact differs from knowledge of the reasoned fact.  To begin with, they differ within the

same science and in two ways:  (1) when the premisses of the syllogism are not immediate (for then  the

proximate cause is not contained in thema necessary condition  of  knowledge of the reasoned fact): (2) when

the premisses are  immediate,  but instead of the cause the better known of the two  reciprocals is  taken as the

middle; for of two reciprocally predicable  terms the one  which is not the cause may quite easily be the better

known and so  become the middle term of the demonstration. Thus (2) (a)  you might  prove as follows that the

planets are near because they do  not  twinkle: let C be the planets, B not twinkling, A proximity.  Then B is

predicable of C; for the planets do not twinkle. But A is  also  predicable of B, since that which does not

twinkle is nearwe  must  take this truth as having been reached by induction or  senseperception. Therefore

A is a necessary predicate of C; so that  we have demonstrated that the planets are near. This syllogism,  then,

proves not the reasoned fact but only the fact; since they are  not  near because they do not twinkle, but,

because they are near, do  not  twinkle. The major and middle of the proof, however, may be  reversed,  and

then the demonstration will be of the reasoned fact.  Thus: let C  be the planets, B proximity, A not twinkling.

Then B is an  attribute  of C, and Anot twinklingof B. Consequently A is predicable  of C, and  the syllogism

proves the reasoned fact, since its middle  term is the  proximate cause. Another example is the inference that


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

13 13



Top




Page No 17


the  moon is  spherical from its manner of waxing. Thus: since that which so  waxes  is spherical, and since the

moon so waxes, clearly the moon is  spherical. Put in this form, the syllogism turns out to be proof of  the fact,

but if the middle and major be reversed it is proof of the  reasoned fact; since the moon is not spherical

because it waxes in a  certain manner, but waxes in such a manner because it is spherical.  (Let C be the moon,

B spherical, and A waxing.) Again (b), in cases  where the cause and the effect are not reciprocal and the

effect is  the better known, the fact is demonstrated but not the reasoned  fact.  This also occurs (1) when the

middle falls outside the major and  minor, for here too the strict cause is not given, and so the  demonstration is

of the fact, not of the reasoned fact. For example,  the question 'Why does not a wall breathe?' might be

answered,  'Because it is not an animal'; but that answer would not give the  strict cause, because if not being

an animal causes the absence of  respiration, then being an animal should be the cause of  respiration,

according to the rule that if the negation of causes  the noninherence  of y, the affirmation of x causes the

inherence of  y; e.g. if the  disproportion of the hot and cold elements is the cause  of ill health,  their proportion

is the cause of health; and  conversely, if the  assertion of x causes the inherence of y, the  negation of x must

cause  y's noninherence. But in the case given this  consequence does not  result; for not every animal

breathes. A  syllogism with this kind of  cause takes place in the second figure.  Thus: let A be animal, B

respiration, C wall. Then A is predicable  of all B (for all that  breathes is animal), but of no C; and

consequently B is predicable of  no C; that is, the wall does not  breathe. Such causes are like  farfetched

explanations, which  precisely consist in making the cause  too remote, as in Anacharsis'  account of why the

Scythians have no  fluteplayers; namely because  they have no vines. 

Thus, then, do the syllogism of the fact and the syllogism of the  reasoned fact differ within one science and

according to the  position  of the middle terms. But there is another way too in which  the fact  and the reasoned

fact differ, and that is when they are  investigated  respectively by different sciences. This occurs in the  case of

problems related to one another as subordinate and superior,  as when  optical problems are subordinated to

geometry, mechanical  problems to  stereometry, harmonic problems to arithmetic, the data  of observation  to

astronomy. (Some of these sciences bear almost the  same name; e.g.  mathematical and nautical astronomy,

mathematical  and acoustical  harmonics.) Here it is the business of the empirical  observers to know  the fact,

of the mathematicians to know the reasoned  fact; for the  latter are in possession of the demonstrations giving

the causes, and  are often ignorant of the fact: just as we have  often a clear insight  into a universal, but through

lack of  observation are ignorant of some  of its particular instances. These  connexions have a perceptible

existence though they are manifestations  of forms. For the  mathematical sciences concern forms: they do not

demonstrate  properties of a substratum, since, even though the  geometrical  subjects are predicable as

properties of a perceptible  substratum, it  is not as thus predicable that the mathematician  demonstrates

properties of them. As optics is related to geometry,  so another  science is related to optics, namely the theory

of the  rainbow. Here  knowledge of the fact is within the province of the  natural  philosopher, knowledge of

the reasoned fact within that of the  optician, either qua optician or qua mathematical optician. Many  sciences

not standing in this mutual relation enter into it at points;  e.g. medicine and geometry: it is the physician's

business to know  that circular wounds heal more slowly, the geometer's to know the  reason why. 

14

Of all the figures the most scientific is the first. Thus, it is  the  vehicle of the demonstrations of all the

mathematical sciences,  such  as arithmetic, geometry, and optics, and practically all of all  sciences that

investigate causes: for the syllogism of the reasoned  fact is either exclusively or generally speaking and in

most cases  in  this figurea second proof that this figure is the most scientific;  for grasp of a reasoned

conclusion is the primary condition of  knowledge. Thirdly, the first is the only figure which enables us to

pursue knowledge of the essence of a thing. In the second figure no  affirmative conclusion is possible, and

knowledge of a thing's essence  must be affirmative; while in the third figure the conclusion can be

affirmative, but cannot be universal, and essence must have a  universal character: e.g. man is not twofooted

animal in any  qualified sense, but universally. Finally, the first figure has no  need of the others, while it is by


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

14 14



Top




Page No 18


means of the first that the other  two figures are developed, and have their intervals closepacked  until

immediate premisses are reached. 

Clearly, therefore, the first figure is the primary condition of  knowledge. 

15

Just as an attribute A may (as we saw) be atomically connected  with a subject B, so its disconnexion may be

atomic. I call 'atomic'  connexions or disconnexions which involve no intermediate term;  since  in that case the

connexion or disconnexion will not be  mediated by  something other than the terms themselves. It follows that

if either A  or B, or both A and B, have a genus, their disconnexion  cannot be  primary. Thus: let C be the

genus of A. Then, if C is not  the genus of  Bfor A may well have a genus which is not the genus of  Bthere

will  be a syllogism proving A's disconnexion from B thus: 

        all A is C,

        no B is C,

        therefore no B is A.

Or if it is B which has a genus D, we have 

        all B is D,

        no D is A,

        therefore no B is A, by syllogism;

and the proof will be similar if both A and B have a genus. That the  genus of A need not be the genus of B

and vice versa, is shown by  the  existence of mutually exclusive coordinate series of  predication. If  no term in

the series ACD...is predicable of any  term in the series  BEF...,and if Ga term in the former seriesis  the

genus of A, clearly  G will not be the genus of B; since, if it  were, the series would not  be mutually exclusive.

So also if B has a  genus, it will not be the  genus of A. If, on the other hand, neither A  nor B has a genus and

A  does not inhere in B, this disconnexion must  be atomic. If there be a  middle term, one or other of them is

bound to  have a genus, for the  syllogism will be either in the first or the  second figure. If it is  in the first, B

will have a genusfor the  premiss containing it must  be affirmative: if in the second, either  A or B

indifferently, since  syllogism is possible if either is  contained in a negative premiss,  but not if both premisses

are  negative. 

Hence it is clear that one thing may be atomically disconnected  from  another, and we have stated when and

how this is possible. 

16

Ignorancedefined not as the negation of knowledge but as a  positive  state of mindis error produced by

inference. 

(1) Let us first consider propositions asserting a predicate's  immediate connexion with or disconnexion from

a subject. Here, it is  true, positive error may befall one in alternative ways; for it may  arise where one directly

believes a connexion or disconnexion as  well  as where one's belief is acquired by inference. The error,

however,  that consists in a direct belief is without complication; but  the  error resulting from inferencewhich

here concerns ustakes many  forms. Thus, let A be atomically disconnected from all B: then the  conclusion

inferred through a middle term C, that all B is A, will  be  a case of error produced by syllogism. Now, two

cases are possible.  Either (a) both premisses, or (b) one premiss only, may be false.  (a)  If neither A is an

attribute of any C nor C of any B, whereas  the  contrary was posited in both cases, both premisses will be

false. (C  may quite well be so related to A and B that C is neither  subordinate  to A nor a universal attribute of


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

15 15



Top




Page No 19


B: for B, since A was  said to be  primarily disconnected from B, cannot have a genus, and A  need not

necessarily be a universal attribute of all things.  Consequently both  premisses may be false.) On the other

hand, (b)  one of the premisses  may be true, though not either indifferently  but only the major AC  since, B

having no genus, the premiss CB  will always be false, while  AC may be true. This is the case if,  for

example, A is related  atomically to both C and B; because when the  same term is related  atomically to more

terms than one, neither of  those terms will belong  to the other. It is, of course, equally the  case if AC is not

atomic. 

Error of attribution, then, occurs through these causes and in  this form onlyfor we found that no syllogism

of universal attribution  was possible in any figure but the first. On the other hand, an  error  of nonattribution

may occur either in the first or in the  second  figure. Let us therefore first explain the various forms it  takes in

the first figure and the character of the premisses in each  case. 

(c) It may occur when both premisses are false; e.g. supposing A  atomically connected with both C and B, if

it be then assumed that  no  C is and all B is C, both premisses are false. 

(d) It is also possible when one is false. This may be either  premiss indifferently. AC may be true, CB

falseAC true because A  is not an attribute of all things, CB false because C, which never  has the attribute

A, cannot be an attribute of B; for if CB were  true, the premiss AC would no longer be true, and besides if

both  premisses were true, the conclusion would be true. Or again, CB may  be true and AC false; e.g. if

both C and A contain B as genera, one  of them must be subordinate to the other, so that if the premiss takes

the form No C is A, it will be false. This makes it clear that whether  either or both premisses are false, the

conclusion will equally be  false. 

In the second figure the premisses cannot both be wholly false;  for if all B is A, no middle term can be with

truth universally  affirmed of one extreme and universally denied of the other: but  premisses in which the

middle is affirmed of one extreme and denied of  the other are the necessary condition if one is to get a valid

inference at all. Therefore if, taken in this way, they are wholly  false, their contraries conversely should be

wholly true. But this  is  impossible. On the other hand, there is nothing to prevent both  premisses being

partially false; e.g. if actually some A is C and some  B is C, then if it is premised that all A is C and no B is

C, both  premisses are false, yet partially, not wholly, false. The same is  true if the major is made negative

instead of the minor. Or one  premiss may be wholly false, and it may be either of them. Thus,  supposing that

actually an attribute of all A must also be an  attribute of all B, then if C is yet taken to be a universal attribute

of all but universally nonattributable to B, CA will be true but CB  false. Again, actually that which is an

attribute of no B will not  be  an attribute of all A either; for if it be an attribute of all A,  it  will also be an

attribute of all B, which is contrary to  supposition;  but if C be nevertheless assumed to be a universal  attribute

of A, but  an attribute of no B, then the premiss CB is true  but the major is  false. The case is similar if the

major is made the  negative premiss.  For in fact what is an attribute of no A will not be  an attribute of  any B

either; and if it be yet assumed that C is  universally  nonattributable to A, but a universal attribute of B, the

premiss CA  is true but the minor wholly false. Again, in fact it is  false to  assume that that which is an

attribute of all B is an  attribute of no  A, for if it be an attribute of all B, it must be an  attribute of some  A. If

then C is nevertheless assumed to be an  attribute of all B but  of no A, CB will be true but CA false. 

It is thus clear that in the case of atomic propositions erroneous  inference will be possible not only when both

premisses are false  but  also when only one is false. 

17

In the case of attributes not atomically connected with or  disconnected from their subjects, (a) (i) as long as

the false  conclusion is inferred through the 'appropriate' middle, only the  major and not both premisses can be


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

17 16



Top




Page No 20


false. By 'appropriate middle' I  mean the middle term through which the contradictoryi.e. the

trueconclusion is inferrible. Thus, let A be attributable to B  through a middle term C: then, since to produce

a conclusion the  premiss CB must be taken affirmatively, it is clear that this premiss  must always be true,

for its quality is not changed. But the major AC  is false, for it is by a change in the quality of AC that the

conclusion becomes its contradictoryi.e. true. Similarly (ii) if  the  middle is taken from another series of

predication; e.g. suppose D  to  be not only contained within A as a part within its whole but  also  predicable of

all B. Then the premiss DB must remain  unchanged, but  the quality of AD must be changed; so that DB

is  always true, AD  always false. Such error is practically identical  with that which is  inferred through the

'appropriate' middle. On the  other hand, (b) if  the conclusion is not inferred through the  'appropriate'

middle(i)  when the middle is subordinate to A but is  predicable of no B, both  premisses must be false,

because if there  is to be a conclusion both  must be posited as asserting the contrary  of what is actually the

fact, and so posited both become false: e.g.  suppose that actually all  D is A but no B is D; then if these

premisses are changed in quality,  a conclusion will follow and both of  the new premisses will be false.  When,

however, (ii) the middle D is  not subordinate to A, AD will be  true, DB falseAD true because A  was not

subordinate to D, DB false  because if it had been true, the  conclusion too would have been true;  but it is ex

hypothesi false. 

When the erroneous inference is in the second figure, both  premisses  cannot be entirely false; since if B is

subordinate to A,  there can be  no middle predicable of all of one extreme and of none of  the other,  as was

stated before. One premiss, however, may be false,  and it may  be either of them. Thus, if C is actually an

attribute of  both A and  B, but is assumed to be an attribute of A only and not of  B, CA  will be true, CB

false: or again if C be assumed to be  attributable  to B but to no A, CB will be true, CA false. 

We have stated when and through what kinds of premisses error will  result in cases where the erroneous

conclusion is negative. If the  conclusion is affirmative, (a) (i) it may be inferred through the  'appropriate'

middle term. In this case both premisses cannot be false  since, as we said before, CB must remain

unchanged if there is to  be  a conclusion, and consequently AC, the quality of which is  changed,  will always

be false. This is equally true if (ii) the middle  is taken  from another series of predication, as was stated to be

the  case also  with regard to negative error; for DB must remain  unchanged, while  the quality of AD must

be converted, and the type of  error is the  same as before. 

(b) The middle may be inappropriate. Then (i) if D is subordinate  to  A, AD will be true, but DB false;

since A may quite well be  predicable of several terms no one of which can be subordinated to  another. If,

however, (ii) D is not subordinate to A, obviously AD,  since it is affirmed, will always be false, while DB

may be either  true or false; for A may very well be an attribute of no D, whereas  all B is D, e.g. no science is

animal, all music is science. Equally  well A may be an attribute of no D, and D of no B. It emerges, then,  that

if the middle term is not subordinate to the major, not only both  premisses but either singly may be false. 

Thus we have made it clear how many varieties of erroneous  inference  are liable to happen and through what

kinds of premisses  they occur,  in the case both of immediate and of demonstrable truths. 

18

It is also clear that the loss of any one of the senses entails  the loss of a corresponding portion of knowledge,

and that, since we  learn either by induction or by demonstration, this knowledge cannot  be acquired. Thus

demonstration develops from universals, induction  from particulars; but since it is possible to familiarize the

pupil  with even the socalled mathematical abstractions only through  inductioni.e. only because each

subject genus possesses, in virtue of  a determinate mathematical character, certain properties which can  be

treated as separate even though they do not exist in isolationit  is  consequently impossible to come to grasp

universals except  through  induction. But induction is impossible for those who have  not  senseperception.


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

18 17



Top




Page No 21


For it is senseperception alone which is  adequate  for grasping the particulars: they cannot be objects of

scientific  knowledge, because neither can universals give us knowledge  of them  without induction, nor can

we get it through induction without  senseperception. 

19

Every syllogism is effected by means of three terms. One kind of  syllogism serves to prove that A inheres in

C by showing that A  inheres in B and B in C; the other is negative and one of its  premisses asserts one term

of another, while the other denies one term  of another. It is clear, then, that these are the fundamentals and

socalled hypotheses of syllogism. Assume them as they have been  stated, and proof is bound to

followproof that A inheres in C through  B, and again that A inheres in B through some other middle term,

and  similarly that B inheres in C. If our reasoning aims at gaining  credence and so is merely dialectical, it is

obvious that we have only  to see that our inference is based on premisses as credible as  possible: so that if a

middle term between A and B is credible  though  not real, one can reason through it and complete a  dialectical

syllogism. If, however, one is aiming at truth, one must  be guided by  the real connexions of subjects and

attributes. Thus:  since there are  attributes which are predicated of a subject  essentially or naturally  and not

coincidentallynot, that is, in the  sense in which we say  'That white (thing) is a man', which is not  the same

mode of  predication as when we say 'The man is white': the  man is white not  because he is something else but

because he is man,  but the white is  man because 'being white' coincides with 'humanity'  within one

substratumtherefore there are terms such as are  naturally subjects of  predicates. Suppose, then, C such a

term not  itself attributable to  anything else as to a subject, but the  proximate subject of the  attribute Bi.e.

so that BC is immediate;  suppose further E related  immediately to F, and F to B. The first  question is, must

this series  terminate, or can it proceed to  infinity? The second question is as  follows: Suppose nothing is

essentially predicated of A, but A is  predicated primarily of H and of  no intermediate prior term, and  suppose

H similarly related to G and G  to B; then must this series  also terminate, or can it too proceed to  infinity?

There is this much  difference between the questions: the  first is, is it possible to  start from that which is not

itself  attributable to anything else but  is the subject of attributes, and  ascend to infinity? The second is  the

problem whether one can start  from that which is a predicate but  not itself a subject of predicates,  and

descend to infinity? A third  question is, if the extreme terms are  fixed, can there be an infinity  of middles? I

mean this: suppose for  example that A inheres in C and B  is intermediate between them, but  between B and A

there are other  middles, and between these again fresh  middles; can these proceed to  infinity or can they not?

This is the  equivalent of inquiring, do  demonstrations proceed to infinity, i.e.  is everything demonstrable?  Or

do ultimate subject and primary  attribute limit one another? 

I hold that the same questions arise with regard to negative  conclusions and premisses: viz. if A is attributable

to no B, then  either this predication will be primary, or there will be an  intermediate term prior to B to which

a is not attributableG, let  us  say, which is attributable to all Band there may still be  another  term H prior to

G, which is attributable to all G. The same  questions  arise, I say, because in these cases too either the series

of prior  terms to which a is not attributable is infinite or it  terminates. 

One cannot ask the same questions in the case of reciprocating  terms, since when subject and predicate are

convertible there is  neither primary nor ultimate subject, seeing that all the  reciprocals  qua subjects stand in

the same relation to one another,  whether we say  that the subject has an infinity of attributes or  that both

subjects  and attributesand we raised the question in both  casesare infinite  in number. These questions then

cannot be  askedunless, indeed, the  terms can reciprocate by two different  modes, by accidental  predication

in one relation and natural  predication in the other. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

19 18



Top




Page No 22


20

Now, it is clear that if the predications terminate in both the  upward and the downward direction (by 'upward'

I mean the ascent to  the more universal, by 'downward' the descent to the more particular),  the middle terms

cannot be infinite in number. For suppose that A is  predicated of F, and that the intermediatescall them

BB'B"...are  infinite, then clearly you might descend from and find one term  predicated of another ad

infinitum, since you have an infinity of  terms between you and F; and equally, if you ascend from F, there  are

infinite terms between you and A. It follows that if these  processes  are impossible there cannot be an infinity

of  intermediates between A  and F. Nor is it of any effect to urge that  some terms of the series  AB...F are

contiguous so as to exclude  intermediates, while others  cannot be taken into the argument at  all: whichever

terms of the  series B...I take, the number of  intermediates in the direction either  of A or of F must be finite or

infinite: where the infinite series  starts, whether from the first  term or from a later one, is of no  moment, for

the succeeding terms in  any case are infinite in number. 

21

Further, if in affirmative demonstration the series terminates in  both directions, clearly it will terminate too in

negative  demonstration. Let us assume that we cannot proceed to infinity either  by ascending from the

ultimate term (by 'ultimate term' I mean a  term  such as was, not itself attributable to a subject but itself  the

subject of attributes), or by descending towards an ultimate  from the  primary term (by 'primary term' I mean a

term predicable of a  subject  but not itself a subject). If this assumption is justified,  the series  will also

terminate in the case of negation. For a negative  conclusion  can be proved in all three figures. In the first

figure  it is proved  thus: no B is A, all C is B. In packing the interval  BC we must reach  immediate

propositionsas is always the case with  the minor  premisssince BC is affirmative. As regards the other

premiss it is  plain that if the major term is denied of a term D prior  to B, D will  have to be predicable of all B,

and if the major is  denied of yet  another term prior to D, this term must be predicable of  all D.  Consequently,

since the ascending series is finite, the descent  will  also terminate and there will be a subject of which A is

primarily  nonpredicable. In the second figure the syllogism is, all A  is B, no  C is B,..no C is A. If proof of

this is required, plainly  it may be  shown either in the first figure as above, in the second  as here, or  in the

third. The first figure has been discussed, and  we will proceed  to display the second, proof by which will be

as  follows: all B is D,  no C is D..., since it is required that B  should be a subject of which  a predicate is

affirmed. Next, since D is  to be proved not to belong  to C, then D has a further predicate  which is denied of

C. Therefore,  since the succession of predicates  affirmed of an ever higher  universal terminates, the

succession of  predicates denied terminates  too. 

The third figure shows it as follows: all B is A, some B is not C.  Therefore some A is not C. This premiss, i.e.

CB, will be proved  either in the same figure or in one of the two figures discussed  above. In the first and

second figures the series terminates. If we  use the third figure, we shall take as premisses, all E is B, some E

is not C, and this premiss again will be proved by a similar  prosyllogism. But since it is assumed that the

series of descending  subjects also terminates, plainly the series of more universal  nonpredicables will

terminate also. Even supposing that the proof  is  not confined to one method, but employs them all and is now

in  the  first figure, now in the second or thirdeven so the regress  will  terminate, for the methods are finite in

number, and if finite  things  are combined in a finite number of ways, the result must be  finite. 

Thus it is plain that the regress of middles terminates in the  case of negative demonstration, if it does so also

in the case of  affirmative demonstration. That in fact the regress terminates in both  these cases may be made

clear by the following dialectical  considerations. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

20 19



Top




Page No 23


22

In the case of predicates constituting the essential nature of a  thing, it clearly terminates, seeing that if

definition is possible,  or in other words, if essential form is knowable, and an infinite  series cannot be

traversed, predicates constituting a thing's  essential nature must be finite in number. But as regards predicates

generally we have the following prefatory remarks to make. (1) We  can  affirm without falsehood 'the white

(thing) is walking', and  that big  (thing) is a log'; or again, 'the log is big', and 'the man  walks'.  But the

affirmation differs in the two cases. When I affirm  'the white  is a log', I mean that something which happens

to be  white is a  lognot that white is the substratum in which log  inheres, for it was  not qua white or qua a

species of white that the  white (thing) came to  be a log, and the white (thing) is  consequently not a log except

incidentally. On the other hand, when  I affirm 'the log is white', I  do not mean that something else,  which

happens also to be a log, is  white (as I should if I said 'the  musician is white,' which would mean  'the man

who happens also to be a  musician is white'); on the  contrary, log is here the substratumthe  substratum

which actually  came to be white, and did so qua wood or qua  a species of wood and qua  nothing else. 

If we must lay down a rule, let us entitle the latter kind of  statement predication, and the former not

predication at all, or not  strict but accidental predication. 'White' and 'log' will thus serve  as types respectively

of predicate and subject. 

We shall assume, then, that the predicate is invariably predicated  strictly and not accidentally of the subject,

for on such  predication  demonstrations depend for their force. It follows from  this that when  a single attribute

is predicated of a single subject,  the predicate  must affirm of the subject either some element  constituting its

essential nature, or that it is in some way  qualified, quantified,  essentially related, active, passive, placed,  or

dated. 

(2) Predicates which signify substance signify that the subject is  identical with the predicate or with a species

of the predicate.  Predicates not signifying substance which are predicated of a  subject  not identical with

themselves or with a species of  themselves are  accidental or coincidental; e.g. white is a  coincident of man,

seeing  that man is not identical with white or a  species of white, but rather  with animal, since man is identical

with a species of animal. These  predicates which do not signify  substance must be predicates of some  other

subject, and nothing can be  white which is not also other than  white. The Forms we can dispense  with, for

they are mere sound without  sense; and even if there are  such things, they are not relevant to our  discussion,

since  demonstrations are concerned with predicates such as  we have defined. 

(3) If A is a quality of B, B cannot be a quality of Aa quality  of a quality. Therefore A and B cannot be

predicated reciprocally of  one another in strict predication: they can be affirmed without  falsehood of one

another, but not genuinely predicated of each  other.  For one alternative is that they should be substantially

predicated of  one another, i.e. B would become the genus or  differentia of Athe  predicate now become

subject. But it has been  shown that in these  substantial predications neither the ascending  predicates nor the

descending subjects form an infinite series; e.g.  neither the series,  man is biped, biped is animal, nor the

series  predicating animal of  man, man of Callias, Callias of a further.  subject as an element of  its essential

nature, is infinite. For all  such substance is  definable, and an infinite series cannot be  traversed in thought:

consequently neither the ascent nor the  descent is infinite, since a  substance whose predicates were  infinite

would not be definable. Hence  they will not be predicated  each as the genus of the other; for this  would

equate a genus with one  of its own species. Nor (the other  alternative) can a quale be  reciprocally predicated

of a quale, nor  any term belonging to an  adjectival category of another such term,  except by accidental

predication; for all such predicates are  coincidents and are  predicated of substances. On the other handin

proof of the  impossibility of an infinite ascending seriesevery  predication  displays the subject as somehow

qualified or quantified or  as  characterized under one of the other adjectival categories, or else  is  an element in

its substantial nature: these latter are limited in  number, and the number of the widest kinds under which


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

22 20



Top




Page No 24


predications  fall is also limited, for every predication must exhibit its subject  as somehow qualified,

quantified, essentially related, acting or  suffering, or in some place or at some time. 

I assume first that predication implies a single subject and a  single attribute, and secondly that predicates

which are not  substantial are not predicated of one another. We assume this  because  such predicates are all

coincidents, and though some are  essential  coincidents, others of a different type, yet we maintain  that all of

them alike are predicated of some substratum and that a  coincident is  never a substratumsince we do not

class as a coincident  anything  which does not owe its designation to its being something  other than  itself, but

always hold that any coincident is predicated  of some  substratum other than itself, and that another group of

coincidents  may have a different substratum. Subject to these  assumptions then,  neither the ascending nor the

descending series of  predication in  which a single attribute is predicated of a single  subject is  infinite. For the

subjects of which coincidents are  predicated are as  many as the constitutive elements of each individual

substance, and  these we have seen are not infinite in number, while in  the ascending  series are contained

those constitutive elements with  their  coincidentsboth of which are finite. We conclude that there  is a  given

subject (D) of which some attribute (C) is primarily  predicable;  that there must be an attribute (B) primarily

predicable  of the first  attribute, and that the series must end with a term (A)  not predicable  of any term prior

to the last subject of which it was  predicated (B),  and of which no term prior to it is predicable. 

The argument we have given is one of the socalled proofs; an  alternative proof follows. Predicates so related

to their subjects  that there are other predicates prior to them predicable of those  subjects are demonstrable;

but of demonstrable propositions one cannot  have something better than knowledge, nor can one know them

without  demonstration. Secondly, if a consequent is only known through an  antecedent (viz. premisses prior

to it) and we neither know this  antecedent nor have something better than knowledge of it, then we  shall not

have scientific knowledge of the consequent. Therefore, if  it is possible through demonstration to know

anything without  qualification and not merely as dependent on the acceptance of certain  premissesi.e.

hypotheticallythe series of intermediate  predications  must terminate. If it does not terminate, and beyond

any predicate  taken as higher than another there remains another still  higher, then  every predicate is

demonstrable. Consequently, since  these  demonstrable predicates are infinite in number and therefore  cannot

be  traversed, we shall not know them by demonstration. If,  therefore, we  have not something better than

knowledge of them, we  cannot through  demonstration have unqualified but only hypothetical  science of

anything. 

As dialectical proofs of our contention these may carry  conviction, but an analytic process will show more

briefly that  neither the ascent nor the descent of predication can be infinite in  the demonstrative sciences

which are the object of our  investigation.  Demonstration proves the inherence of essential  attributes in things.

Now attributes may be essential for two reasons:  either because they  are elements in the essential nature of

their  subjects, or because  their subjects are elements in their essential  nature. An example of  the latter is odd

as an attribute of  numberthough it is number's  attribute, yet number itself is an  element in the definition of

odd;  of the former, multiplicity or the  indivisible, which are elements in  the definition of number. In  neither

kind of attribution can the terms  be infinite. They are not  infinite where each is related to the term  below it as

odd is to  number, for this would mean the inherence in odd  of another  attribute of odd in whose nature odd

was an essential  element: but  then number will be an ultimate subject of the whole  infinite chain of  attributes,

and be an element in the definition of  each of them.  Hence, since an infinity of attributes such as contain  their

subject  in their definition cannot inhere in a single thing, the  ascending  series is equally finite. Note,

moreover, that all such  attributes  must so inhere in the ultimate subjecte.g. its attributes  in number  and

number in themas to be commensurate with the subject  and not of  wider extent. Attributes which are

essential elements in  the nature of  their subjects are equally finite: otherwise definition  would be  impossible.

Hence, if all the attributes predicated are  essential  and these cannot be infinite, the ascending series will

terminate, and  consequently the descending series too. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

22 21



Top




Page No 25


If this is so, it follows that the intermediates between any two  terms are also always limited in number. An

immediately obvious  consequence of this is that demonstrations necessarily involve basic  truths, and that the

contention of somereferred to at the outsetthat  all truths are demonstrable is mistaken. For if there are basic

truths, (a) not all truths are demonstrable, and (b) an infinite  regress is impossible; since if either (a) or (b)

were not a fact,  it  would mean that no interval was immediate and indivisible, but that  all intervals were

divisible. This is true because a conclusion is  demonstrated by the interposition, not the apposition, of a fresh

term. If such interposition could continue to infinity there might  be  an infinite number of terms between any

two terms; but this is  impossible if both the ascending and descending series of  predication  terminate; and of

this fact, which before was shown  dialectically,  analytic proof has now been given. 

23

It is an evident corollary of these conclusions that if the same  attribute A inheres in two terms C and D

predicable either not at all,  or not of all instances, of one another, it does not always belong  to  them in virtue

of a common middle term. Isosceles and scalene  possess  the attribute of having their angles equal to two right

angles  in  virtue of a common middle; for they possess it in so far as they  are  both a certain kind of figure, and

not in so far as they differ  from  one another. But this is not always the case: for, were it so, if  we  take B as the

common middle in virtue of which A inheres in C and  D,  clearly B would inhere in C and D through a second

common middle,  and  this in turn would inhere in C and D through a third, so that  between  two terms an

infinity of intermediates would fallan  impossibility.  Thus it need not always be in virtue of a common

middle  term that a  single attribute inheres in several subjects, since  there must be  immediate intervals. Yet if

the attribute to be proved  common to two  subjects is to be one of their essential attributes, the  middle terms

involved must be within one subject genus and be  derived from the same  group of immediate premisses; for

we have seen  that processes of proof  cannot pass from one genus to another. 

It is also clear that when A inheres in B, this can be  demonstrated if there is a middle term. Further, the

'elements' of  such a conclusion are the premisses containing the middle in question,  and they are identical in

number with the middle terms, seeing that  the immediate propositionsor at least such immediate

propositions  as  are universalare the 'elements'. If, on the other hand, there is  no  middle term, demonstration

ceases to be possible: we are on the way  to  the basic truths. Similarly if A does not inhere in B, this can  be

demonstrated if there is a middle term or a term prior to B in  which A  does not inhere: otherwise there is no

demonstration and a  basic truth  is reached. There are, moreover, as many 'elements' of the  demonstrated

conclusion as there are middle terms, since it is  propositions containing these middle terms that are the basic

premisses on which the demonstration rests; and as there are some  indemonstrable basic truths asserting that

'this is that' or that  'this inheres in that', so there are others denying that 'this is  that' or that 'this inheres in

that'in fact some basic truths will  affirm and some will deny being. 

When we are to prove a conclusion, we must take a primary  essential predicatesuppose it Cof the subject

B, and then suppose  A  similarly predicable of C. If we proceed in this manner, no  proposition or attribute

which falls beyond A is admitted in the  proof: the interval is constantly condensed until subject and  predicate

become indivisible, i.e. one. We have our unit when the  premiss becomes immediate, since the immediate

premiss alone is a  single premiss in the unqualified sense of 'single'. And as in other  spheres the basic element

is simple but not identical in allin a  system of weight it is the mina, in music the quartertone, and so

onso in syllogism the unit is an immediate premiss, and in the  knowledge that demonstration gives it is an

intuition. In  syllogisms,  then, which prove the inherence of an attribute, nothing  falls outside  the major term.

In the case of negative syllogisms on  the other hand,  (1) in the first figure nothing falls outside the  major term

whose  inherence is in question; e.g. to prove through a  middle C that A does  not inhere in B the premisses

required are, all B  is C, no C is A.  Then if it has to be proved that no C is A, a  middle must be found  between

and C; and this procedure will never  vary. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

23 22



Top




Page No 26


(2) If we have to show that E is not D by means of the premisses,  all D is C; no E, or not all E, is C; then the

middle will never  fall  beyond E, and E is the subject of which D is to be denied in  the  conclusion. 

(3) In the third figure the middle will never fall beyond the  limits  of the subject and the attribute denied of it. 

24

Since demonstrations may be either commensurately universal or  particular, and either affirmative or

negative; the question arises,  which form is the better? And the same question may be put in regard  to

socalled 'direct' demonstration and reductio ad impossibile. Let  us first examine the commensurately

universal and the particular  forms, and when we have cleared up this problem proceed to discuss  'direct'

demonstration and reductio ad impossibile. 

The following considerations might lead some minds to prefer  particular demonstration. 

(1) The superior demonstration is the demonstration which gives us  greater knowledge (for this is the ideal of

demonstration), and we  have greater knowledge of a particular individual when we know it in  itself than

when we know it through something else; e.g. we know  Coriscus the musician better when we know that

Coriscus is musical  than when we know only that man is musical, and a like argument  holds  in all other

cases. But commensurately universal  demonstration,  instead of proving that the subject itself actually  is x,

proves only  that something else is x e.g. in attempting to  prove that isosceles  is x, it proves not that isosceles

but only that  triangle is x  whereas particular demonstration proves that the  subject itself is x.  The

demonstration, then, that a subject, as such,  possesses an  attribute is superior. If this is so, and if the  particular

rather  than the commensurately universal forms  demonstrates, particular  demonstration is superior. 

(2) The universal has not a separate being over against groups of  singulars. Demonstration nevertheless

creates the opinion that its  function is conditioned by something like thissome separate entity  belonging to

the real world; that, for instance, of triangle or of  figure or number, over against particular triangles, figures,

and  numbers. But demonstration which touches the real and will not mislead  is superior to that which moves

among unrealities and is delusory. Now  commensurately universal demonstration is of the latter kind: if we

engage in it we find ourselves reasoning after a fashion well  illustrated by the argument that the proportionate

is what answers  to  the definition of some entity which is neither line, number, solid,  nor plane, but a

proportionate apart from all these. Since, then, such  a proof is characteristically commensurate and universal,

and less  touches reality than does particular demonstration, and creates a  false opinion, it will follow that

commensurate and universal is  inferior to particular demonstration. 

We may retort thus. (1) The first argument applies no more to  commensurate and universal than to particular

demonstration. If  equality to two right angles is attributable to its subject not qua  isosceles but qua triangle,

he who knows that isosceles possesses that  attribute knows the subject as qua itself possessing the attribute,

to  a less degree than he who knows that triangle has that attribute. To  sum up the whole matter: if a subject is

proved to possess qua  triangle an attribute which it does not in fact possess qua  triangle,  that is not

demonstration: but if it does possess it qua  triangle the  rule applies that the greater knowledge is his who

knows the subject  as possessing its attribute qua that in virtue of  which it actually  does possess it. Since, then,

triangle is the  wider term, and there is  one identical definition of trianglei.e. the  term is not  equivocaland

since equality to two right angles belongs  to all  triangles, it is isosceles qua triangle and not triangle qua

isosceles  which has its angles so related. It follows that he who  knows a  connexion universally has greater

knowledge of it as it in  fact is  than he who knows the particular; and the inference is that  commensurate and

universal is superior to particular demonstration. 

(2) If there is a single identical definition i.e. if the  commensurate universal is unequivocalthen the universal


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

24 23



Top




Page No 27


will  possess  being not less but more than some of the particulars, inasmuch  as it  is universals which comprise

the imperishable, particulars  that tend  to perish. 

(3) Because the universal has a single meaning, we are not  therefore  compelled to suppose that in these

examples it has being as  a  substance apart from its particularsany more than we need make a  similar

supposition in the other cases of unequivocal universal  predication, viz. where the predicate signifies not

substance but  quality, essential relatedness, or action. If such a supposition is  entertained, the blame rests not

with the demonstration but with the  hearer. 

(4) Demonstration is syllogism that proves the cause, i.e. the  reasoned fact, and it is rather the commensurate

universal than the  particular which is causative (as may be shown thus: that which  possesses an attribute

through its own essential nature is itself  the  cause of the inherence, and the commensurate universal is

primary;  hence the commensurate universal is the cause). Consequently  commensurately universal

demonstration is superior as more  especially  proving the cause, that is the reasoned fact. 

(5) Our search for the reason ceases, and we think that we know,  when the coming to be or existence of the

fact before us is not due to  the coming to be or existence of some other fact, for the last step of  a search thus

conducted is eo ipso the end and limit of the problem.  Thus: 'Why did he come?' 'To get the

moneywherewith to pay a  debtthat he might thereby do what was right.' When in this regress we  can no

longer find an efficient or final cause, we regard the last  step of it as the end of the comingor being or

coming to beand we  regard ourselves as then only having full knowledge of the reason  why  he came. 

If, then, all causes and reasons are alike in this respect, and if  this is the means to full knowledge in the case

of final causes such  as we have exemplified, it follows that in the case of the other  causes also full knowledge

is attained when an attribute no longer  inheres because of something else. Thus, when we learn that exterior

angles are equal to four right angles because they are the exterior  angles of an isosceles, there still remains

the question 'Why has  isosceles this attribute?' and its answer 'Because it is a triangle,  and a triangle has it

because a triangle is a rectilinear figure.'  If  rectilinear figure possesses the property for no further reason, at

this point we have full knowledgebut at this point our knowledge  has  become commensurately universal,

and so we conclude that  commensurately universal demonstration is superior. 

(6) The more demonstration becomes particular the more it sinks  into  an indeterminate manifold, while

universal demonstration tends to  the simple and determinate. But objects so far as they are an  indeterminate

manifold are unintelligible, so far as they are  determinate, intelligible: they are therefore intelligible rather in

so far as they are universal than in so far as they are particular.  From this it follows that universals are more

demonstrable: but  since  relative and correlative increase concomitantly, of the more  demonstrable there will

be fuller demonstration. Hence the  commensurate and universal form, being more truly demonstration, is  the

superior. 

(7) Demonstration which teaches two things is preferable to  demonstration which teaches only one. He who

possesses  commensurately  universal demonstration knows the particular as well,  but he who  possesses

particular demonstration does not know the  universal. So  that this is an additional reason for preferring

commensurately  universal demonstration. And there is yet this  further argument: 

(8) Proof becomes more and more proof of the commensurate  universal as its middle term approaches nearer

to the basic truth, and  nothing is so near as the immediate premiss which is itself the  basic  truth. If, then,

proof from the basic truth is more accurate  than  proof not so derived, demonstration which depends more

closely on  it  is more accurate than demonstration which is less closely  dependent.  But commensurately

universal demonstration is characterized  by this  closer dependence, and is therefore superior. Thus, if A had

to be  proved to inhere in D, and the middles were B and C, B being the  higher term would render the

demonstration which it mediated the  more  universal. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

24 24



Top




Page No 28


Some of these arguments, however, are dialectical. The clearest  indication of the precedence of

commensurately universal demonstration  is as follows: if of two propositions, a prior and a posterior, we

have a grasp of the prior, we have a kind of knowledgea potential  graspof the posterior as well. For

example, if one knows that the  angles of all triangles are equal to two right angles, one knows in  a

sensepotentiallythat the isosceles' angles also are equal to two  right angles, even if one does not know that

the isosceles is a  triangle; but to grasp this posterior proposition is by no means to  know the commensurate

universal either potentially or actually.  Moreover, commensurately universal demonstration is through and

through intelligible; particular demonstration issues in  senseperception. 

25

The preceding arguments constitute our defence of the superiority  of  commensurately universal to particular

demonstration. That  affirmative  demonstration excels negative may be shown as follows. 

(1) We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus of the  demonstration which derives from fewer postulates

or hypothesesin  short from fewer premisses; for, given that all these are equally well  known, where they are

fewer knowledge will be more speedily  acquired,  and that is a desideratum. The argument implied in our

contention that  demonstration from fewer assumptions is superior may  be set out in  universal form as

follows. Assuming that in both cases  alike the  middle terms are known, and that middles which are prior are

better  known than such as are posterior, we may suppose two  demonstrations of  the inherence of A in E, the

one proving it  through the middles B, C  and D, the other through F and G. Then AD is  known to the same

degree  as AE (in the second proof), but AD is  better known than and prior  to AE (in the first proof); since

AE  is proved through AD, and the  ground is more certain than the  conclusion. 

Hence demonstration by fewer premisses is ceteris paribus  superior. Now both affirmative and negative

demonstration operate  through three terms and two premisses, but whereas the former  assumes  only that

something is, the latter assumes both that something  is and  that something else is not, and thus operating

through more  kinds of  premiss is inferior. 

(2) It has been proved that no conclusion follows if both  premisses are negative, but that one must be

negative, the other  affirmative. So we are compelled to lay down the following  additional  rule: as the

demonstration expands, the affirmative  premisses must  increase in number, but there cannot be more than one

negative premiss  in each complete proof. Thus, suppose no B is A,  and all C is B. Then  if both the premisses

are to be again expanded, a  middle must be  interposed. Let us interpose D between A and B, and E  between

B and C.  Then clearly E is affirmatively related to B and C,  while D is  affirmatively related to B but

negatively to A; for all B  is D, but  there must be no D which is A. Thus there proves to be a  single  negative

premiss, AD. In the further prosyllogisms too it is  the  same, because in the terms of an affirmative

syllogism the  middle is  always related affirmatively to both extremes; in a negative  syllogism  it must be

negatively related only to one of them, and so  this  negation comes to be a single negative premiss, the other

premisses  being affirmative. If, then, that through which a truth is  proved is a  better known and more certain

truth, and if the negative  proposition  is proved through the affirmative and not vice versa,  affirmative

demonstration, being prior and better known and more  certain, will be  superior. 

(3) The basic truth of demonstrative syllogism is the universal  immediate premiss, and the universal premiss

asserts in affirmative  demonstration and in negative denies: and the affirmative  proposition  is prior to and

better known than the negative (since  affirmation  explains denial and is prior to denial, just as being is  prior

to  notbeing). It follows that the basic premiss of  affirmative  demonstration is superior to that of negative

demonstration, and the  demonstration which uses superior basic  premisses is superior. 

(4) Affirmative demonstration is more of the nature of a basic  form of proof, because it is a sine qua non of


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

25 25



Top




Page No 29


negative demonstration. 

26

Since affirmative demonstration is superior to negative, it is  clearly superior also to reductio ad impossibile.

We must first make  certain what is the difference between negative demonstration and  reductio ad

impossibile. Let us suppose that no B is A, and that all C  is B: the conclusion necessarily follows that no C is

A. If these  premisses are assumed, therefore, the negative demonstration that no C  is A is direct. Reductio ad

impossibile, on the other hand, proceeds  as follows. Supposing we are to prove that does not inhere in B, we

have to assume that it does inhere, and further that B inheres in C,  with the resulting inference that A inheres

in C. This we have to  suppose a known and admitted impossibility; and we then infer that A  cannot inhere in

B. Thus if the inherence of B in C is not questioned,  A's inherence in B is impossible. 

The order of the terms is the same in both proofs: they differ  according to which of the negative propositions

is the better known,  the one denying A of B or the one denying A of C. When the falsity  of  the conclusion is

the better known, we use reductio ad  impossible;  when the major premiss of the syllogism is the more

obvious, we use  direct demonstration. All the same the proposition  denying A of B is,  in the order of being,

prior to that denying A of  C; for premisses are  prior to the conclusion which follows from  them, and 'no C is

A' is  the conclusion, 'no B is A' one of its  premisses. For the destructive  result of reductio ad impossibile is

not a proper conclusion, nor are  its antecedents proper premisses.  On the contrary: the constituents of

syllogism are premisses related  to one another as whole to part or  part to whole, whereas the  premisses AC

and AB are not thus related  to one another. Now the  superior demonstration is that which proceeds  from

better known and  prior premisses, and while both these forms  depend for credence on the  notbeing of

something, yet the source of  the one is prior to that  of the other. Therefore negative  demonstration will have

an  unqualified superiority to reductio ad  impossibile, and affirmative  demonstration, being superior to

negative, will consequently be  superior also to reductio ad  impossibile. 

27

The science which is knowledge at once of the fact and of the  reasoned fact, not of the fact by itself without

the reasoned fact, is  the more exact and the prior science. 

A science such as arithmetic, which is not a science of properties  qua inhering in a substratum, is more exact

than and prior to a  science like harmonics, which is a science of pr,operties inhering  in  a substratum; and

similarly a science like arithmetic, which is  constituted of fewer basic elements, is more exact than and prior

to  geometry, which requires additional elements. What I mean by  'additional elements' is this: a unit is

substance without position,  while a point is substance with position; the latter contains an  additional element. 

28

A single science is one whose domain is a single genus, viz. all  the  subjects constituted out of the primary

entities of the genusi.e.  the  parts of this total subjectand their essential properties. 

One science differs from another when their basic truths have  neither a common source nor are derived those

of the one science  from  those the other. This is verified when we reach the  indemonstrable  premisses of a

science, for they must be within one  genus with its  conclusions: and this again is verified if the  conclusions

proved by  means of them fall within one genusi.e. are  homogeneous. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

26 26



Top




Page No 30


29

One can have several demonstrations of the same connexion not only  by taking from the same series of

predication middles which are  other  than the immediately cohering term e.g. by taking C, D, and F  severally

to prove ABbut also by taking a middle from another  series. Thus let A be change, D alteration of a

property, B feeling  pleasure, and G relaxation. We can then without falsehood predicate  D  of B and A of D,

for he who is pleased suffers alteration of a  property, and that which alters a property changes. Again, we can

predicate A of G without falsehood, and G of B; for to feel pleasure  is to relax, and to relax is to change. So

the conclusion can be drawn  through middles which are different, i.e. not in the same seriesyet  not so that

neither of these middles is predicable of the other, for  they must both be attributable to some one subject. 

A further point worth investigating is how many ways of proving  the same conclusion can be obtained by

varying the figure, 

30

There is no knowledge by demonstration of chance conjunctions; for  chance conjunctions exist neither by

necessity nor as general  connexions but comprise what comes to be as something distinct from  these. Now

demonstration is concerned only with one or other of  these  two; for all reasoning proceeds from necessary or

general  premisses,  the conclusion being necessary if the premisses are  necessary and  general if the premisses

are general. Consequently, if  chance  conjunctions are neither general nor necessary, they are not

demonstrable. 

31

Scientific knowledge is not possible through the act of  perception. Even if perception as a faculty is of 'the

such' and not  merely of a 'this somewhat', yet one must at any rate actually  perceive a 'this somewhat', and at

a definite present place and  time:  but that which is commensurately universal and true in all cases  one  cannot

perceive, since it is not 'this' and it is not 'now'; if it  were, it would not be commensurately universalthe term

we apply to  what is always and everywhere. Seeing, therefore, that  demonstrations  are commensurately

universal and universals  imperceptible, we clearly  cannot obtain scientific knowledge by the  act of

perception: nay, it  is obvious that even if it were possible to  perceive that a triangle  has its angles equal to

two right angles,  we should still be looking  for a demonstrationwe should not (as  some say) possess

knowledge of  it; for perception must be of a  particular, whereas scientific  knowledge involves the recognition

of  the commensurate universal. So  if we were on the moon, and saw the  earth shutting out the sun's  light, we

should not know the cause of  the eclipse: we should perceive  the present fact of the eclipse, but  not the

reasoned fact at all,  since the act of perception is not of  the commensurate universal. I do  not, of course, deny

that by watching  the frequent recurrence of this  event we might, after tracking the  commensurate universal,

possess a  demonstration, for the  commensurate universal is elicited from the  several groups of  singulars. 

The commensurate universal is precious because it makes clear the  cause; so that in the case of facts like

these which have a cause  other than themselves universal knowledge is more precious than  senseperceptions

and than intuition. (As regards primary truths there  is of course a different account to be given.) Hence it is

clear  that  knowledge of things demonstrable cannot be acquired by  perception,  unless the term perception is

applied to the possession of  scientific  knowledge through demonstration. Nevertheless certain  points do arise

with regard to connexions to be proved which are  referred for their  explanation to a failure in

senseperception: there  are cases when an  act of vision would terminate our inquiry, not  because in seeing

we  should be knowing, but because we should have  elicited the universal  from seeing; if, for example, we

saw the  pores in the glass and the  light passing through, the reason of the  kindling would be clear to us

because we should at the same time see  it in each instance and intuit  that it must be so in all instances. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

29 27



Top




Page No 31


32

All syllogisms cannot have the same basic truths. This may be  shown first of all by the following dialectical

considerations. (1)  Some syllogisms are true and some false: for though a true inference  is possible from false

premisses, yet this occurs once onlyI mean  if  A for instance, is truly predicable of C, but B, the middle, is

false,  both AB and BC being false; nevertheless, if middles are  taken to  prove these premisses, they will be

false because every  conclusion  which is a falsehood has false premisses, while true  conclusions have  true

premisses, and false and true differ in kind.  Then again, (2)  falsehoods are not all derived from a single

identical  set of  principles: there are falsehoods which are the contraries of  one  another and cannot coexist,

e.g. 'justice is injustice', and  'justice  is cowardice'; 'man is horse', and 'man is ox'; 'the equal is  greater', and

'the equal is less.' From established principles we  may  argue the case as follows, confiningourselves

therefore to true  conclusions. Not even all these are inferred from the same basic  truths; many of them in fact

have basic truths which differ  generically and are not transferable; units, for instance, which are  without

position, cannot take the place of points, which have  position. The transferred terms could only fit in as

middle terms or  as major or minor terms, or else have some of the other terms  between  them, others outside

them. 

Nor can any of the common axiomssuch, I mean, as the law of  excluded middleserve as premisses for the

proof of all conclusions.  For the kinds of being are different, and some attributes attach to  quanta and some to

qualia only; and proof is achieved by means of  the  common axioms taken in conjunction with these several

kinds and  their  attributes. 

Again, it is not true that the basic truths are much fewer than  the conclusions, for the basic truths are the

premisses, and the  premisses are formed by the apposition of a fresh extreme term or  the  interposition of a

fresh middle. Moreover, the number of  conclusions  is indefinite, though the number of middle terms is  finite;

and lastly  some of the basic truths are necessary, others  variable. 

Looking at it in this way we see that, since the number of  conclusions is indefinite, the basic truths cannot be

identical or  limited in number. If, on the other hand, identity is used in  another  sense, and it is said, e.g. 'these

and no other are the  fundamental  truths of geometry, these the fundamentals of calculation,  these again  of

medicine'; would the statement mean anything except  that the  sciences have basic truths? To call them

identical because  they are  selfidentical is absurd, since everything can be  identified with  everything in that

sense of identity. Nor again can  the contention  that all conclusions have the same basic truths mean  that from

the  mass of all possible premisses any conclusion may be  drawn. That would  be exceedingly naive, for it is

not the case in  the clearly evident  mathematical sciences, nor is it possible in  analysis, since it is the

immediate premisses which are the basic  truths, and a fresh conclusion  is only formed by the addition of a

new  immediate premiss: but if it  be admitted that it is these primary  immediate premisses which are  basic

truths, each subjectgenus will  provide one basic truth. If,  however, it is not argued that from the  mass of all

possible premisses  any conclusion may be proved, nor yet  admitted that basic truths  differ so as to be

generically different  for each science, it remains  to consider the possibility that, while  the basic truths of all

knowledge are within one genus, special  premisses are required to  prove special conclusions. But that this

cannot be the case has been  shown by our proof that the basic truths  of things generically  different

themselves differ generically. For  fundamental truths are of  two kinds, those which are premisses of

demonstration and the  subjectgenus; and though the former are common,  the latternumber,  for instance,

and magnitudeare peculiar. 

33

Scientific knowledge and its object differ from opinion and the  object of opinion in that scientific knowledge

is commensurately  universal and proceeds by necessary connexions, and that which is  necessary cannot be


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

32 28



Top




Page No 32


otherwise. So though there are things which are  true and real and yet can be otherwise, scientific knowledge

clearly  does not concern them: if it did, things which can be otherwise  would  be incapable of being

otherwise. Nor are they any concern of  rational  intuitionby rational intuition I mean an originative  source of

scientific knowledgenor of indemonstrable knowledge,  which is the  grasping of the immediate premiss.

Since then rational  intuition,  science, and opinion, and what is revealed by these  terms, are the  only things

that can be 'true', it follows that it is  opinion that is  concerned with that which may be true or false, and  can

be otherwise:  opinion in fact is the grasp of a premiss which is  immediate but not  necessary. This view also

fits the observed facts,  for opinion is  unstable, and so is the kind of being we have described  as its object.

Besides, when a man thinks a truth incapable of being  otherwise he  always thinks that he knows it, never that

he opines  it. He thinks  that he opines when he thinks that a connexion, though  actually so,  may quite easily

be otherwise; for he believes that  such is the proper  object of opinion, while the necessary is the  object of

knowledge. 

In what sense, then, can the same thing be the object of both  opinion and knowledge? And if any one chooses

to maintain that all  that he knows he can also opine, why should not opinion be  knowledge?  For he that

knows and he that opines will follow the same  train of  thought through the same middle terms until the

immediate  premisses  are reached; because it is possible to opine not only the  fact but  also the reasoned fact,

and the reason is the middle term; so  that,  since the former knows, he that opines also has knowledge. 

The truth perhaps is that if a man grasp truths that cannot be  other  than they are, in the way in which he

grasps the definitions  through  which demonstrations take place, he will have not opinion but  knowledge: if

on the other hand he apprehends these attributes as  inhering in their subjects, but not in virtue of the subjects'

substance and essential nature possesses opinion and not genuine  knowledge; and his opinion, if obtained

through immediate premisses,  will be both of the fact and of the reasoned fact; if not so obtained,  of the fact

alone. The object of opinion and knowledge is not quite  identical; it is only in a sense identical, just as the

object of true  and false opinion is in a sense identical. The sense in which some  maintain that true and false

opinion can have the same object leads  them to embrace many strange doctrines, particularly the doctrine that

what a man opines falsely he does not opine at all. There are really  many senses of 'identical', and in one

sense the object of true and  false opinion can be the same, in another it cannot. Thus, to have a  true opinion

that the diagonal is commensurate with the side would  be  absurd: but because the diagonal with which they

are both concerned  is  the same, the two opinions have objects so far the same: on the  other  hand, as regards

their essential definable nature these  objects  differ. The identity of the objects of knowledge and opinion  is

similar. Knowledge is the apprehension of, e.g. the attribute  'animal'  as incapable of being otherwise, opinion

the apprehension  of 'animal'  as capable of being otherwisee.g. the apprehension that  animal is an  element in

the essential nature of man is knowledge;  the apprehension  of animal as predicable of man but not as an

element in man's  essential nature is opinion: man is the subject in  both judgements,  but the mode of inherence

differs. 

This also shows that one cannot opine and know the same thing  simultaneously; for then one would

apprehend the same thing as both  capable and incapable of being otherwisean impossibility. Knowledge  and

opinion of the same thing can coexist in two different people  in  the sense we have explained, but not

simultaneously in the same  person. That would involve a man's simultaneously apprehending, e.g.  (1) that

man is essentially animali.e. cannot be other than  animaland (2) that man is not essentially animal, that is,

we may  assume, may be other than animal. 

Further consideration of modes of thinking and their distribution  under the heads of discursive thought,

intuition, science, art,  practical wisdom, and metaphysical thinking, belongs rather partly  to  natural science,

partly to moral philosophy. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

32 29



Top




Page No 33


34

Quick wit is a faculty of hitting upon the middle term  instantaneously. It would be exemplified by a man who

saw that the  moon has her bright side always turned towards the sun, and quickly  grasped the cause of this,

namely that she borrows her light from him;  or observed somebody in conversation with a man of wealth and

divined  that he was borrowing money, or that the friendship of these  people  sprang from a common enmity.

In all these instances he has seen  the  major and minor terms and then grasped the causes, the middle  terms. 

Let A represent 'bright side turned sunward', B 'lighted from the  sun', C the moon. Then B, 'lighted from the

sun' is predicable of C,  the moon, and A, 'having her bright side towards the source of her  light', is predicable

of B. So A is predicable of C through B. 

Book II

1

THE kinds of question we ask are as many as the kinds of things  which we know. They are in fact four:(1)

whether the connexion of  an  attribute with a thing is a fact, (2) what is the reason of the  connexion, (3)

whether a thing exists, (4) What is the nature of the  thing. Thus, when our question concerns a complex of

thing and  attribute and we ask whether the thing is thus or otherwise  qualifiedwhether, e.g. the sun suffers

eclipse or notthen we are  asking as to the fact of a connexion. That our inquiry ceases with the  discovery

that the sun does suffer eclipse is an indication of this;  and if we know from the start that the sun suffers

eclipse, we do  not  inquire whether it does so or not. On the other hand, when we know  the  fact we ask the

reason; as, for example, when we know that the sun  is  being eclipsed and that an earthquake is in progress, it

is the  reason  of eclipse or earthquake into which we inquire. 

Where a complex is concerned, then, those are the two questions we  ask; but for some objects of inquiry we

have a different kind of  question to ask, such as whether there is or is not a centaur or a  God. (By 'is or is not'

I mean 'is or is not, without further  qualification'; as opposed to 'is or is not [e.g.] white'.) On the  other hand,

when we have ascertained the thing's existence, we inquire  as to its nature, asking, for instance, 'what, then, is

God?' or 'what  is man?'. 

2

These, then, are the four kinds of question we ask, and it is in  the  answers to these questions that our

knowledge consists. 

Now when we ask whether a connexion is a fact, or whether a thing  without qualification is, we are really

asking whether the connexion  or the thing has a 'middle'; and when we have ascertained either  that  the

connexion is a fact or that the thing isi.e. ascertained  either  the partial or the unqualified being of the

thingand are  proceeding  to ask the reason of the connexion or the nature of the  thing, then we  are asking

what the 'middle' is. 

(By distinguishing the fact of the connexion and the existence of  the thing as respectively the partial and the

unqualified being of the  thing, I mean that if we ask 'does the moon suffer eclipse?', or 'does  the moon wax?',

the question concerns a part of the thing's being; for  what we are asking in such questions is whether a thing

is this or  that, i.e. has or has not this or that attribute: whereas, if we ask  whether the moon or night exists, the

question concerns the  unqualified being of a thing.) 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

34 30



Top




Page No 34


We conclude that in all our inquiries we are asking either whether  there is a 'middle' or what the 'middle' is:

for the 'middle' here  is  precisely the cause, and it is the cause that we seek in all our  inquiries. Thus, 'Does the

moon suffer eclipse?' means 'Is there or is  there not a cause producing eclipse of the moon?', and when we

have  learnt that there is, our next question is, 'What, then, is this  cause? for the cause through which a thing

isnot is this or that,  i.e. has this or that attribute, but without qualification isand  the  cause through which it

isnot is without qualification, but is  this or  that as having some essential attribute or some accidentare  both

alike the middle'. By that which is without qualification I  mean the  subject, e.g. moon or earth or sun or

triangle; by that which  a  subject is (in the partial sense) I mean a property, e.g. eclipse,  equality or inequality,

interposition or noninterposition. For in all  these examples it is clear that the nature of the thing and the

reason  of the fact are identical: the question 'What is eclipse?' and its  answer 'The privation of the moon's

light by the interposition of  the  earth' are identical with the question 'What is the reason of  eclipse?' or 'Why

does the moon suffer eclipse?' and the reply  'Because of the failure of light through the earth's shutting it out'.

Again, for 'What is a concord? A commensurate numerical ratio of a  high and a low note', we may substitute

'What ratio makes a high and a  low note concordant? Their relation according to a commensurate  numerical

ratio.' 'Are the high and the low note concordant?' is  equivalent to 'Is their ratio commensurate?'; and when

we find that it  is commensurate, we ask 'What, then, is their ratio?'. 

Cases in which the 'middle' is sensible show that the object of  our inquiry is always the 'middle': we inquire,

because we have not  perceived it, whether there is or is not a 'middle' causing, e.g. an  eclipse. On the other

hand, if we were on the moon we should not be  inquiring either as to the fact or the reason, but both fact and

reason would be obvious simultaneously. For the act of perception  would have enabled us to know the

universal too; since, the present  fact of an eclipse being evident, perception would then at the same  time give

us the present fact of the earth's screening the sun's  light, and from this would arise the universal. 

Thus, as we maintain, to know a thing's nature is to know the  reason  why it is; and this is equally true of

things in so far as they  are  said without qualification to he as opposed to being possessed of  some  attribute,

and in so far as they are said to be possessed of some  attribute such as equal to right angles, or greater or less. 

3

It is clear, then, that all questions are a search for a 'middle'.  Let us now state how essential nature is revealed

and in what way it  can be reduced to demonstration; what definition is, and what things  are definable. And let

us first discuss certain difficulties which  these questions raise, beginning what we have to say with a point

most  intimately connected with our immediately preceding remarks, namely  the doubt that might be felt as to

whether or not it is possible to  know the same thing in the same relation, both by definition and by

demonstration. It might, I mean, be urged that definition is held to  concern essential nature and is in every

case universal and  affirmative; whereas, on the other hand, some conclusions are negative  and some are not

universal; e.g. all in the second figure are  negative, none in the third are universal. And again, not even all

affirmative conclusions in the first figure are definable, e.g. 'every  triangle has its angles equal to two right

angles'. An argument  proving this difference between demonstration and definition is that  to have scientific

knowledge of the demonstrable is identical with  possessing a demonstration of it: hence if demonstration of

such  conclusions as these is possible, there clearly cannot also be  definition of them. If there could, one might

know such a conclusion  also in virtue of its definition without possessing the  demonstration  of it; for there is

nothing to stop our having the one  without the  other. 

Induction too will sufficiently convince us of this difference;  for never yet by defining anythingessential

attribute or accidentdid  we get knowledge of it. Again, if to define is to acquire knowledge of  a substance, at

any rate such attributes are not substances. 

It is evident, then, that not everything demonstrable can be  defined. What then? Can everything definable be


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

3 31



Top




Page No 35


demonstrated, or  not?  There is one of our previous arguments which covers this too.  Of a  single thing qua

single there is a single scientific knowledge.  Hence,  since to know the demonstrable scientifically is to

possess the  demonstration of it, an impossible consequence will follow:possession  of its definition without

its demonstration will give knowledge of the  demonstrable. 

Moreover, the basic premisses of demonstrations are definitions,  and  it has already been shown that these will

be found indemonstrable;  either the basic premisses will be demonstrable and will depend on  prior premisses,

and the regress will be endless; or the primary  truths will be indemonstrable definitions. 

But if the definable and the demonstrable are not wholly the same,  may they yet be partially the same? Or is

that impossible, because  there can be no demonstration of the definable? There can be none,  because

definition is of the essential nature or being of something,  and all demonstrations evidently posit and assume

the essential  naturemathematical demonstrations, for example, the nature of unity  and the odd, and all the

other sciences likewise. Moreover, every  demonstration proves a predicate of a subject as attaching or as not

attaching to it, but in definition one thing is not predicated of  another; we do not, e.g. predicate animal of

biped nor biped of  animal, nor yet figure of planeplane not being figure nor figure  plane. Again, to prove

essential nature is not the same as to prove  the fact of a connexion. Now definition reveals essential nature,

demonstration reveals that a given attribute attaches or does not  attach to a given subject; but different things

require different  demonstrationsunless the one demonstration is related to the other as  part to whole. I add

this because if all triangles have been proved to  possess angles equal to two right angles, then this attribute

has been  proved to attach to isosceles; for isosceles is a part of which all  triangles constitute the whole. But in

the case before us the fact and  the essential nature are not so related to one another, since the  one  is not a part

of the other. 

So it emerges that not all the definable is demonstrable nor all  the  demonstrable definable; and we may draw

the general conclusion  that  there is no identical object of which it is possible to possess  both a  definition and

a demonstration. It follows obviously that  definition  and demonstration are neither identical nor contained

either within  the other: if they were, their objects would be related  either as  identical or as whole and part. 

4

So much, then, for the first stage of our problem. The next step  is to raise the question whether syllogismi.e.

demonstrationof the  definable nature is possible or, as our recent argument assumed,  impossible. 

We might argue it impossible on the following grounds:(a)  syllogism  proves an attribute of a subject

through the middle term; on  the other  hand (b) its definable nature is both 'peculiar' to a  subject and

predicated of it as belonging to its essence. But in that  case (1) the  subject, its definition, and the middle term

connecting  them must be  reciprocally predicable of one another; for if A is to C,  obviously  A is 'peculiar' to B

and B to Cin fact all three terms are  'peculiar'  to one another: and further (2) if A inheres in the essence  of

all B  and B is predicated universally of all C as belonging to C's  essence, A also must be predicated of C as

belonging to its essence. 

If one does not take this relation as thus duplicatedif, that is,  A  is predicated as being of the essence of B,

but B is not of the  essence of the subjects of which it is predicatedA will not  necessarily be predicated of C

as belonging to its essence. So both  premisses will predicate essence, and consequently B also will be

predicated of C as its essence. Since, therefore, both premisses do  predicate essencei.e. definable formC's

definable form will appear  in the middle term before the conclusion is drawn. 

We may generalize by supposing that it is possible to prove the  essential nature of man. Let C be man, A

man's essential  naturetwofooted animal, or aught else it may be. Then, if we are to  syllogize, A must be


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

4 32



Top




Page No 36


predicated of all B. But this premiss will be  mediated by a fresh definition, which consequently will also be

the  essential nature of man. Therefore the argument assumes what it has to  prove, since B too is the essential

nature of man. It is, however, the  case in which there are only the two premissesi.e. in which the  premisses

are primary and immediatewhich we ought to investigate,  because it best illustrates the point under

discussion. 

Thus they who prove the essential nature of soul or man or  anything else through reciprocating terms beg the

question. It would  be begging the question, for example, to contend that the soul is that  which causes its own

life, and that what causes its own life is a  selfmoving number; for one would have to postulate that the soul

is a  selfmoving number in the sense of being identical with it. For if A  is predicable as a mere consequent of

B and B of C, A will not on that  account be the definable form of C: A will merely be what it was  true  to say

of C. Even if A is predicated of all B inasmuch as B is  identical with a species of A, still it will not follow:

being an  animal is predicated of being a mansince it is true that in all  instances to be human is to be animal,

just as it is also true that  every man is an animalbut not as identical with being man. 

We conclude, then, that unless one takes both the premisses as  predicating essence, one cannot infer that A is

the definable form and  essence of C: but if one does so take them, in assuming B one will  have assumed,

before drawing the conclusion, what the definable form  of C is; so that there has been no inference, for one

has begged the  question. 

5

Nor, as was said in my formal logic, is the method of division a  process of inference at all, since at no point

does the  characterization of the subject follow necessarily from the  premising  of certain other facts: division

demonstrates as little as  does  induction. For in a genuine demonstration the conclusion must not  be  put as a

question nor depend on a concession, but must follow  necessarily from its premisses, even if the respondent

deny it. The  definer asks 'Is man animal or inanimate?' and then assumeshe has not  inferredthat man is

animal. Next, when presented with an exhaustive  division of animal into terrestrial and aquatic, he assumes

that man  is terrestrial. Moreover, that man is the complete formula,  terrestrialanimal, does not follow

necessarily from the premisses:  this too is an assumption, and equally an assumption whether the  division

comprises many differentiae or few. (Indeed as this method of  division is used by those who proceed by it,

even truths that can be  inferred actually fail to appear as such.) For why should not the  whole of this formula

be true of man, and yet not exhibit his  essential nature or definable form? Again, what guarantee is there

against an unessential addition, or against the omission of the  final  or of an intermediate determinant of the

substantial being? 

The champion of division might here urge that though these lapses  do  occur, yet we can solve that difficulty

if all the attributes we  assume are constituents of the definable form, and if, postulating the  genus, we

produce by division the requisite uninterrupted sequence  of  terms, and omit nothing; and that indeed we

cannot fail to fulfil  these conditions if what is to be divided falls whole into the  division at each stage, and

none of it is omitted; and that thisthe  dividendummust without further question be (ultimately) incapable

of  fresh specific division. Nevertheless, we reply, division does  not  involve inference; if it gives knowledge,

it gives it in another  way.  Nor is there any absurdity in this: induction, perhaps, is not  demonstration any

more than is division, et it does make evident  some  truth. Yet to state a definition reached by division is not

to  state a  conclusion: as, when conclusions are drawn without their  appropriate  middles, the alleged necessity

by which the inference  follows from the  premisses is open to a question as to the reason  for it, so  definitions

reached by division invite the same question. 

Thus to the question 'What is the essential nature of man?' the  divider replies 'Animal, mortal, footed, biped,

wingless'; and when at  each step he is asked 'Why?', he will say, and, as he thinks, proves  by division, that all


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

5 33



Top




Page No 37


animal is mortal or immortal: but such a formula  taken in its entirety is not definition; so that even if division

does  demonstrate its formula, definition at any rate does not turn out to  be a conclusion of inference. 

6

Can we nevertheless actually demonstrate what a thing essentially  and substantially is, but hypothetically, i.e.

by premising (1) that  its definable form is constituted by the 'peculiar' attributes of  its  essential nature; (2) that

such and such are the only attributes  of  its essential nature, and that the complete synthesis of them is  peculiar

to the thing; and thussince in this synthesis consists the  being of the thingobtaining our conclusion? Or is

the truth that,  since proof must be through the middle term, the definable form is  once more assumed in this

minor premiss too? 

Further, just as in syllogizing we do not premise what syllogistic  inference is (since the premisses from which

we conclude must be  related as whole and part), so the definable form must not fall within  the syllogism but

remain outside the premisses posited. It is only  against a doubt as to its having been a syllogistic inference at

all  that we have to defend our argument as conforming to the definition of  syllogism. It is only when some

one doubts whether the conclusion  proved is the definable form that we have to defend it as conforming  to

the definition of definable form which we assumed. Hence  syllogistic inference must be possible even

without the express  statement of what syllogism is or what definable form is. 

The following type of hypothetical proof also begs the question.  If evil is definable as the divisible, and the

definition of a thing's  contraryif it has one the contrary of the thing's definition; then,  if good is the contrary

of evil and the indivisible of the  divisible,  we conclude that to be good is essentially to be  indivisible. The

question is begged because definable form is  assumed as a premiss, and  as a premiss which is to prove

definable  form. 'But not the same  definable form', you may object. That I admit,  for in demonstrations  also

we premise that 'this' is predicable of  'that'; but in this  premiss the term we assert of the minor is neither  the

major itself  nor a term identical in definition, or convertible,  with the major. 

Again, both proof by division and the syllogism just described are  open to the question why man should be

animalbipedterrestrial and  not merely animal and terrestrial, since what they premise does not  ensure that

the predicates shall constitute a genuine unity and not  merely belong to a single subject as do musical and

grammatical when  predicated of the same man. 

7

How then by definition shall we prove substance or essential  nature?  We cannot show it as a fresh fact

necessarily following from  the  assumption of premisses admitted to be factsthe method of  demonstration:

we may not proceed as by induction to establish a  universal on the evidence of groups of particulars which

offer no  exception, because induction proves not what the essential nature of a  thing is but that it has or has

not some attribute. Therefore, since  presumably one cannot prove essential nature by an appeal to sense

perception or by pointing with the finger, what other method remains? 

To put it another way: how shall we by definition prove essential  nature? He who knows what humanor any

othernature is, must know also  that man exists; for no one knows the nature of what does not  existone can

know the meaning of the phrase or name 'goatstag' but  not what the essential nature of a goatstag is. But

further, if  definition can prove what is the essential nature of a thing, can it  also prove that it exists? And how

will it prove them both by the same  process, since definition exhibits one single thing and  demonstration

another single thing, and what human nature is and the  fact that man  exists are not the same thing? Then too

we hold that  it is by  demonstration that the being of everything must be  provedunless  indeed to be were its

essence; and, since being is not a  genus, it is  not the essence of anything. Hence the being of  anything as fact


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

6 34



Top




Page No 38


is  matter for demonstration; and this is the actual  procedure of the  sciences, for the geometer assumes the

meaning of the  word triangle,  but that it is possessed of some attribute he proves.  What is it,  then, that we

shall prove in defining essential nature?  Triangle? In  that case a man will know by definition what a thing's

nature is  without knowing whether it exists. But that is impossible. 

Moreover it is clear, if we consider the methods of defining  actually in use, that definition does not prove that

the thing defined  exists: since even if there does actually exist something which is  equidistant from a centre,

yet why should the thing named in the  definition exist? Why, in other words, should this be the formula

defining circle? One might equally well call it the definition of  mountain copper. For definitions do not carry

a further guarantee that  the thing defined can exist or that it is what they claim to define:  one can always ask

why. 

Since, therefore, to define is to prove either a thing's essential  nature or the meaning of its name, we may

conclude that definition, if  it in no sense proves essential nature, is a set of words signifying  precisely what a

name signifies. But that were a strange  consequence;  for (1) both what is not substance and what does not

exist at all  would be definable, since even nonexistents can be  signified by a  name: (2) all sets of words or

sentences would be  definitions, since  any kind of sentence could be given a name; so that  we should all be

talking in definitions, and even the Iliad would be a  definition: (3)  no demonstration can prove that any

particular name  means any  particular thing: neither, therefore, do definitions, in  addition to  revealing the

meaning of a name, also reveal that the name  has this  meaning. It appears then from these considerations that

neither  definition and syllogism nor their objects are identical,  and further  that definition neither demonstrates

nor proves  anything, and that  knowledge of essential nature is not to be obtained  either by  definition or by

demonstration. 

8

We must now start afresh and consider which of these conclusions  are  sound and which are not, and what is

the nature of definition, and  whether essential nature is in any sense demonstrable and definable or  in none. 

Now to know its essential nature is, as we said, the same as to  know  the cause of a thing's existence, and the

proof of this depends  on the  fact that a thing must have a cause. Moreover, this cause is  either  identical with

the essential nature of the thing or distinct  from  it; and if its cause is distinct from it, the essential nature of

the thing is either demonstrable or indemonstrable. Consequently, if  the cause is distinct from the thing's

essential nature and  demonstration is possible, the cause must be the middle term, and, the  conclusion proved

being universal and affirmative, the proof is in the  first figure. So the method just examined of proving it

through  another essential nature would be one way of proving essential nature,  because a conclusion

containing essential nature must be inferred  through a middle which is an essential nature just as a 'peculiar'

property must be inferred through a middle which is a 'peculiar'  property; so that of the two definable natures

of a single thing  this  method will prove one and not the other. 

Now it was said before that this method could not amount to  demonstration of essential natureit is actually a

dialectical proof  of itso let us begin again and explain by what method it can be  demonstrated. When we are

aware of a fact we seek its reason, and  though sometimes the fact and the reason dawn on us simultaneously,

yet we cannot apprehend the reason a moment sooner than the fact;  and  clearly in just the same way we

cannot apprehend a thing's  definable  form without apprehending that it exists, since while we are  ignorant

whether it exists we cannot know its essential nature.  Moreover we are  aware whether a thing exists or not

sometimes  through apprehending an  element in its character, and sometimes  accidentally, as, for example,

when we are aware of thunder as a noise  in the clouds, of eclipse as a  privation of light, or of man as some

species of animal, or of the  soul as a selfmoving thing. As often  as we have accidental knowledge  that the

thing exists, we must be in a  wholly negative state as  regards awareness of its essential nature;  for we have


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

8 35



Top




Page No 39


not got genuine  knowledge even of its existence, and to  search for a thing's essential  nature when we are

unaware that it  exists is to search for nothing. On  the other hand, whenever we  apprehend an element in the

thing's  character there is less  difficulty. Thus it follows that the degree of  our knowledge of a  thing's essential

nature is determined by the sense  in which we are  aware that it exists. Let us then take the following  as our

first  instance of being aware of an element in the essential  nature. Let A  be eclipse, C the moon, B the earth's

acting as a  screen. Now to ask  whether the moon is eclipsed or not is to ask  whether or not B has  occurred.

But that is precisely the same as  asking whether A has a  defining condition; and if this condition  actually

exists, we assert  that A also actually exists. Or again we  may ask which side of a  contradiction the defining

condition  necessitates: does it make the  angles of a triangle equal or not equal  to two right angles? When we

have found the answer, if the premisses  are immediate, we know fact  and reason together; if they are not

immediate, we know the fact  without the reason, as in the following  example: let C be the moon,  A eclipse, B

the fact that the moon fails  to produce shadows though  she is full and though no visible body  intervenes

between us and  her. Then if B, failure to produce shadows  in spite of the absence  of an intervening body, is

attributable A to  C, and eclipse, is  attributable to B, it is clear that the moon is  eclipsed, but the  reason why is

not yet clear, and we know that  eclipse exists, but we  do not know what its essential nature is. But  when it is

clear that  A is attributable to C and we proceed to ask the  reason of this  fact, we are inquiring what is the

nature of B: is it  the earth's  acting as a screen, or the moon's rotation or her  extinction? But B is  the definition

of the other term, viz. in these  examples, of the major  term A; for eclipse is constituted by the earth  acting as

a screen.  Thus, (1) 'What is thunder?' 'The quenching of  fire in cloud', and (2)  'Why does it thunder?' 'Because

fire is  quenched in the cloud', are  equivalent. Let C be cloud, A thunder, B  the quenching of fire. Then B  is

attributable to C, cloud, since fire  is quenched in it; and A,  noise, is attributable to B; and B is  assuredly the

definition of  the major term A. If there be a further  mediating cause of B, it  will be one of the remaining

partial  definitions of A. 

We have stated then how essential nature is discovered and becomes  known, and we see that, while there is

no syllogismi.e. no  demonstrative syllogismof essential nature, yet it is through  syllogism, viz.

demonstrative syllogism, that essential nature is  exhibited. So we conclude that neither can the essential

nature of  anything which has a cause distinct from itself be known without  demonstration, nor can it be

demonstrated; and this is what we  contended in our preliminary discussions. 

9

Now while some things have a cause distinct from themselves,  others have not. Hence it is evident that there

are essential  natures  which are immediate, that is are basic premisses; and of these  not  only that they are but

also what they are must be assumed or  revealed  in some other way. This too is the actual procedure of the

arithmetician, who assumes both the nature and the existence of  unit.  On the other hand, it is possible (in the

manner explained) to  exhibit  through demonstration the essential nature of things which  have a  'middle', i.e. a

cause of their substantial being other than  that  being itself; but we do not thereby demonstrate it. 

10

Since definition is said to be the statement of a thing's nature,  obviously one kind of definition will be a

statement of the meaning of  the name, or of an equivalent nominal formula. A definition in this  sense tells

you, e.g. the meaning of the phrase 'triangular  character'. When we are aware that triangle exists, we inquire

the  reason why it exists. But it is difficult thus to learn the definition  of things the existence of which we do

not genuinely knowthe cause of  this difficulty being, as we said before, that we only know  accidentally

whether or not the thing exists. Moreover, a statement  may be a unity in either of two ways, by conjunction,

like the  Iliad,  or because it exhibits a single predicate as inhering not  accidentally  in a single subject. 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

9 36



Top




Page No 40


That then is one way of defining definition. Another kind of  definition is a formula exhibiting the cause of a

thing's existence.  Thus the former signifies without proving, but the latter will clearly  be a

quasidemonstration of essential nature, differing from  demonstration in the arrangement of its terms. For

there is a  difference between stating why it thunders, and stating what is the  essential nature of thunder; since

the first statement will be  'Because fire is quenched in the clouds', while the statement of  what  the nature of

thunder is will be 'The noise of fire being  quenched in  the clouds'. Thus the same statement takes a different

form: in one  form it is continuous demonstration, in the other  definition. Again,  thunder can be defined as

noise in the clouds,  which is the conclusion  of the demonstration embodying essential  nature. On the other

hand the  definition of immediates is an  indemonstrable positing of essential  nature. 

We conclude then that definition is (a) an indemonstrable  statement of essential nature, or (b) a syllogism of

essential  nature  differing from demonstration in grammatical form, or (c) the  conclusion of a demonstration

giving essential nature. 

Our discussion has therefore made plain (1) in what sense and of  what things the essential nature is

demonstrable, and in what sense  and of what things it is not; (2) what are the various meanings of the  term

definition, and in what sense and of what things it proves the  essential nature, and in what sense and of what

things it does not;  (3) what is the relation of definition to demonstration, and how far  the same thing is both

definable and demonstrable and how far it is  not. 

11

We think we have scientific knowledge when we know the cause, and  there are four causes: (1) the definable

form, (2) an antecedent which  necessitates a consequent, (3) the efficient cause, (4) the final  cause. Hence

each of these can be the middle term of a proof, for  (a)  though the inference from antecedent to necessary

consequent  does not  hold if only one premiss is assumedtwo is the  minimumstill when  there are two it

holds on condition that they  have a single common  middle term. So it is from the assumption of this  single

middle term  that the conclusion follows necessarily. The  following example will  also show this. Why is the

angle in a  semicircle a right angle?or  from what assumption does it follow  that it is a right angle? Thus,  let

A be right angle, B the half of  two right angles, C the angle in a  semicircle. Then B is the cause  in virtue of

which A, right angle, is  attributable to C, the angle  in a semicircle, since B=A and the other,  viz. C,=B, for C

is half  of two right angles. Therefore it is the  assumption of B, the half  of two right angles, from which it

follows  that A is attributable to  C, i.e. that the angle in a semicircle is a  right angle. Moreover, B  is identical

with (b) the defining form of A,  since it is what A's  definition signifies. Moreover, the formal cause  has

already been  shown to be the middle. (c) 'Why did the Athenians  become involved  in the Persian war?' means

'What cause originated the  waging of war  against the Athenians?' and the answer is, 'Because they  raided

Sardis  with the Eretrians', since this originated the war. Let  A be war, B  unprovoked raiding, C the

Athenians. Then B, unprovoked  raiding, is  true of C, the Athenians, and A is true of B, since men  make war

on  the unjust aggressor. So A, having war waged upon them, is  true of  B, the initial aggressors, and B is true

of C, the Athenians,  who were  the aggressors. Hence here too the causein this case the  efficient  causeis the

middle term. (d) This is no less true where the  cause  is the final cause. E.g. why does one take a walk after

supper?  For  the sake of one's health. Why does a house exist? For the  preservation  of one's goods. The end in

view is in the one case  health, in the  other preservation. To ask the reason why one must walk  after supper  is

precisely to ask to what end one must do it. Let C be  walking after  supper, B the nonregurgitation of food, A

health. Then  let walking  after supper possess the property of preventing food from  rising to  the orifice of the

stomach, and let this condition be  healthy; since  it seems that B, the nonregurgitation of food, is  attributable

to  C, taking a walk, and that A, health, is attributable  to B. What,  then, is the cause through which A, the final

cause,  inheres in C?  It is B, the nonregurgitation of food; but B is a kind  of  definition of A, for A will be

explained by it. Why is B the cause  of A's belonging to C? Because to be in a condition such as B is to be  in

health. The definitions must be transposed, and then the detail  will become clearer. Incidentally, here the


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

11 37



Top




Page No 41


order of coming to be is  the reverse of what it is in proof through the efficient cause: in the  efficient order the

middle term must come to be first, whereas in  the  teleological order the minor, C, must first take place, and

the  end in  view comes last in time. 

The same thing may exist for an end and be necessitated as well.  For  example, light shines through a lantern

(1) because that which  consists  of relatively small particles necessarily passes through  pores larger  than those

particlesassuming that light does issue by  penetration  and (2) for an end, namely to save us from

stumbling. If  then, a  thing can exist through two causes, can it come to be through  two  causesas for instance

if thunder be a hiss and a roar necessarily  produced by the quenching of fire, and also designed, as the

Pythagoreans say, for a threat to terrify those that lie in Tartarus?  Indeed, there are very many such cases,

mostly among the processes  and products of the natural world; for nature, in different senses  of  the term

'nature', produces now for an end, now by necessity. 

Necessity too is of two kinds. It may work in accordance with a  thing's natural tendency, or by constraint and

in opposition to it;  as, for instance, by necessity a stone is borne both upwards and  downwards, but not by the

same necessity. 

Of the products of man's intelligence some are never due to chance  or necessity but always to an end, as for

example a house or a statue;  others, such as health or safety, may result from chance as well. 

It is mostly in cases where the issue is indeterminate (though  only where the production does not originate in

chance, and the end is  consequently good), that a result is due to an end, and this is true  alike in nature or in

art. By chance, on the other hand, nothing comes  to be for an end. 

12

The effect may be still coming to be, or its occurrence may be past  or future, yet the cause will be the same as

when it is actually  existentfor it is the middle which is the causeexcept that if the  effect actually exists the

cause is actually existent, if it is coming  to be so is the cause, if its occurrence is past the cause is past, if

future the cause is future. For example, the moon was eclipsed because  the earth intervened, is becoming

eclipsed because the earth is in  process of intervening, will be eclipsed because the earth will  intervene, is

eclipsed because the earth intervenes. 

To take a second example: assuming that the definition of ice is  solidified water, let C be water, A solidified,

B the middle, which is  the cause, namely total failure of heat. Then B is attributed to C,  and A, solidification,

to B: ice when B is occurring, has formed  when  B has occurred, and will form when B shall occur. 

This sort of cause, then, and its effect come to be simultaneously  when they are in process of becoming, and

exist simultaneously when  they actually exist; and the same holds good when they are past and  when they are

future. But what of cases where they are not  simultaneous? Can causes and effects different from one another

form,  as they seem to us to form, a continuous succession, a past  effect  resulting from a past cause different

from itself, a future  effect  from a future cause different from it, and an effect which is  comingtobe from a

cause different from and prior to it? Now on  this  theory it is from the posterior event that we reason (and this

though  these later events actually have their source of origin in  previous  eventsa fact which shows that

also when the effect is  comingtobe  we still reason from the posterior event), and from the  event we  cannot

reason (we cannot argue that because an event A has  occurred,  therefore an event B has occurred

subsequently to A but  still in the  pastand the same holds good if the occurrence is  future)cannot  reason

because, be the time interval definite or  indefinite, it will  never be possible to infer that because it is true  to

say that A  occurred, therefore it is true to say that B, the  subsequent event,  occurred; for in the interval

between the events,  though A has already  occurred, the latter statement will be false. And  the same argument


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

12 38



Top




Page No 42


applies also to future events; i.e. one cannot infer  from an event  which occurred in the past that a future event

will  occur. The reason  of this is that the middle must be homogeneous, past  when the extremes  are past,

future when they are future, coming to  be when they are  comingtobe, actually existent when they are

actually existent; and  there cannot be a middle term homogeneous  with extremes respectively  past and future.

And it is a further  difficulty in this theory that  the time interval can be neither  indefinite nor definite, since

during  it the inference will be  false. We have also to inquire what it is  that holds events together  so that the

comingtobe now occurring in  actual things follows upon a  past event. It is evident, we may  suggest, that a

past event and a  present process cannot be  'contiguous', for not even two past events  can be 'contiguous'. For

past events are limits and atomic; so just as  points are not  'contiguous' neither are past events, since both are

indivisible. For  the same reason a past event and a present process  cannot be  'contiguous', for the process is

divisible, the event  indivisible.  Thus the relation of present process to past event is  analogous to  that of line to

point, since a process contains an  infinity of past  events. These questions, however, must receive a more

explicit  treatment in our general theory of change. 

The following must suffice as an account of the manner in which  the middle would be identical with the

cause on the supposition that  comingtobe is a series of consecutive events: for in the terms of  such a series

too the middle and major terms must form an immediate  premiss; e.g. we argue that, since C has occurred,

therefore A  occurred: and C's occurrence was posterior, A's prior; but C is the  source of the inference because

it is nearer to the present moment,  and the startingpoint of time is the present. We next argue that,  since D

has occurred, therefore C occurred. Then we conclude that,  since D has occurred, therefore A must have

occurred; and the cause is  C, for since D has occurred C must have occurred, and since C has  occurred A

must previously have occurred. 

If we get our middle term in this way, will the series terminate  in an immediate premiss, or since, as we said,

no two events are  'contiguous', will a fresh middle term always intervene because  there  is an infinity of

middles? No: though no two events are  'contiguous',  yet we must start from a premiss consisting of a  middle

and the  present event as major. The like is true of future  events too, since  if it is true to say that D will exist, it

must be a  prior truth to  say that A will exist, and the cause of this conclusion  is C; for if D  will exist, C will

exist prior to D, and if C will  exist, A will exist  prior to it. And here too the same infinite  divisibility might be

urged, since future events are not 'contiguous'.  But here too an  immediate basic premiss must be assumed.

And in the  world of fact this  is so: if a house has been built, then blocks  must have been quarried  and shaped.

The reason is that a house  having been built necessitates  a foundation having been laid, and if a  foundation

has been laid  blocks must have been shaped beforehand.  Again, if a house will be  built, blocks will similarly

be shaped  beforehand; and proof is  through the middle in the same way, for the  foundation will exist  before

the house. 

Now we observe in Nature a certain kind of circular process of  comingtobe; and this is possible only if the

middle and extreme  terms are reciprocal, since conversion is conditioned by reciprocity  in the terms of the

proof. Thisthe convertibility of conclusions  and  premisseshas been proved in our early chapters, and the

circular  process is an instance of this. In actual fact it is  exemplified thus:  when the earth had been moistened

an exhalation  was bound to rise, and  when an exhalation had risen cloud was bound to  form, and from the

formation of cloud rain necessarily resulted and by  the fall of rain  the earth was necessarily moistened: but

this was the  startingpoint,  so that a circle is completed; for posit any one of  the terms and  another follows

from it, and from that another, and from  that again  the first. 

Some occurrences are universal (for they are, or cometobe what  they are, always and in ever case); others

again are not always what  they are but only as a general rule: for instance, not every man can  grow a beard,

but it is the general rule. In the case of such  connexions the middle term too must be a general rule. For if A

is  predicated universally of B and B of C, A too must be predicated  always and in every instance of C, since

to hold in every instance and  always is of the nature of the universal. But we have assumed a  connexion

which is a general rule; consequently the middle term B must  also be a general rule. So connexions which


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

12 39



Top




Page No 43


embody a general rulei.e.  which exist or come to be as a general rulewill also derive from  immediate basic

premisses. 

13

We have already explained how essential nature is set out in the  terms of a demonstration, and the sense in

which it is or is not  demonstrable or definable; so let us now discuss the method to be  adopted in tracing the

elements predicated as constituting the  definable form. 

Now of the attributes which inhere always in each several thing  there are some which are wider in extent than

it but not wider than  its genus (by attributes of wider extent mean all such as are  universal attributes of each

several subject, but in their application  are not confined to that subject). while an attribute may inhere in

every triad, yet also in a subject not a triadas being inheres in  triad but also in subjects not numbers at

allodd on the other hand is  an attribute inhering in every triad and of wider application  (inhering as it does

also in pentad), but which does not extend beyond  the genus of triad; for pentad is a number, but nothing

outside number  is odd. It is such attributes which we have to select, up to the exact  point at which they are

severally of wider extent than the subject but  collectively coextensive with it; for this synthesis must be the

substance of the thing. For example every triad possesses the  attributes number, odd, and prime in both

senses, i.e. not only as  possessing no divisors, but also as not being a sum of numbers.  This,  then, is precisely

what triad is, viz. a number, odd, and  prime in the  former and also the latter sense of the term: for these

attributes  taken severally apply, the first two to all odd numbers,  the last to  the dyad also as well as to the

triad, but, taken  collectively, to no  other subject. Now since we have shown above' that  attributes  predicated

as belonging to the essential nature are  necessary and that  universals are necessary, and since the  attributes

which we select as  inhering in triad, or in any other  subject whose attributes we select  in this way, are

predicated as  belonging to its essential nature,  triad will thus possess these  attributes necessarily. Further, that

the synthesis of them  constitutes the substance of triad is shown by  the following argument.  If it is not

identical with the being of  triad, it must be related  to triad as a genus named or nameless. It  will then be of

wider extent  than triadassuming that wider potential  extent is the character of  a genus. If on the other hand

this  synthesis is applicable to no  subject other than the individual  triads, it will be identical with  the being of

triad, because we make  the further assumption that the  substance of each subject is the  predication of

elements in its  essential nature down to the last  differentia characterizing the  individuals. It follows that any

other  synthesis thus exhibited will  likewise be identical with the being of  the subject. 

The author of a handbook on a subject that is a generic whole  should divide the genus into its first infimae

speciesnumber e.g.  into triad and dyadand then endeavour to seize their definitions by  the method we have

describedthe definition, for example, of  straight  line or circle or right angle. After that, having established

what the  category is to which the subaltern genus belongsquantity  or quality,  for instancehe should

examine the properties 'peculiar'  to the  species, working through the proximate common differentiae.  He

should  proceed thus because the attributes of the genera compounded  of the  infimae species will be clearly

given by the definitions of the  species; since the basic element of them all is the definition, i.e.  the simple

infirma species, and the attributes inhere essentially in  the simple infimae species, in the genera only in virtue

of these. 

Divisions according to differentiae are a useful accessory to this  method. What force they have as proofs we

did, indeed, explain  above,  but that merely towards collecting the essential nature they  may be of  use we will

proceed to show. They might, indeed, seem to  be of no use  at all, but rather to assume everything at the start

and to be no  better than an initial assumption made without  division. But, in fact,  the order in which the

attributes are  predicated does make a  differenceit matters whether we say  animaltamebiped, or

bipedanimaltame. For if every definable  thing consists of two  elements and 'animaltame' forms a unity,

and  again out of this and  the further differentia man (or whatever else is  the unity under  construction) is


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

13 40



Top




Page No 44


constituted, then the elements we  assume have  necessarily been reached by division. Again, division is  the

only  possible method of avoiding the omission of any element of  the  essential nature. Thus, if the primary

genus is assumed and we  then  take one of the lower divisions, the dividendum will not fall  whole  into this

division: e.g. it is not all animal which is either  wholewinged or splitwinged but all winged animal, for it is

winged  animal to which this differentiation belongs. The primary  differentiation of animal is that within

which all animal falls. The  like is true of every other genus, whether outside animal or a  subaltern genus of

animal; e.g. the primary differentiation of bird is  that within which falls every bird, of fish that within which

falls  every fish. So, if we proceed in this way, we can be sure that nothing  has been omitted: by any other

method one is bound to omit something  without knowing it. 

To define and divide one need not know the whole of existence. Yet  some hold it impossible to know the

differentiae distinguishing each  thing from every single other thing without knowing every single other  thing;

and one cannot, they say, know each thing without knowing its  differentiae, since everything is identical with

that from which it  does not differ, and other than that from which it differs. Now  first  of all this is a fallacy:

not every differentia precludes  identity,  since many differentiae inhere in things specifically  identical,  though

not in the substance of these nor essentially.  Secondly, when  one has taken one's differing pair of opposites

and  assumed that the  two sides exhaust the genus, and that the subject one  seeks to define  is present in one or

other of them, and one has  further verified its  presence in one of them; then it does not  matter whether or not

one  knows all the other subjects of which the  differentiae are also  predicated. For it is obvious that when by

this process one reaches  subjects incapable of further differentiation  one will possess the  formula defining the

substance. Moreover, to  postulate that the  division exhausts the genus is not illegitimate  if the opposites

exclude a middle; since if it is the differentia of  that genus,  anything contained in the genus must lie on one of

the two  sides. 

In establishing a definition by division one should keep three  objects in view: (1) the admission only of

elements in the definable  form, (2) the arrangement of these in the right order, (3) the  omission of no such

elements. The first is feasible because one can  establish genus and differentia through the topic of the genus,

just  as one can conclude the inherence of an accident through the topic  of  the accident. The right order will be

achieved if the right term is  assumed as primary, and this will be ensured if the term selected is  predicable of

all the others but not all they of it; since there  must  be one such term. Having assumed this we at once

proceed in the  same  way with the lower terms; for our second term will be the first  of the  remainder, our third

the first of those which follow the second  in a  'contiguous' series, since when the higher term is excluded, that

term  of the remainder which is 'contiguous' to it will be primary, and  so  on. Our procedure makes it clear that

no elements in the  definable  form have been omitted: we have taken the differentia that  comes first  in the

order of division, pointing out that animal, e.g.  is divisible  exhaustively into A and B, and that the subject

accepts  one of the two  as its predicate. Next we have taken the differentia of  the whole thus  reached, and

shown that the whole we finally reach is  not further  divisiblei.e. that as soon as we have taken the last

differentia to  form the concrete totality, this totality admits of  no division into  species. For it is clear that

there is no superfluous  addition, since  all these terms we have selected are elements in the  definable form;

and nothing lacking, since any omission would have  to be a genus or a  differentia. Now the primary term is a

genus, and  this term taken in  conjunction with its differentiae is a genus:  moreover the  differentiae are all

included, because there is now no  further  differentia; if there were, the final concrete would admit  of division

into species, which, we said, is not the case. 

To resume our account of the right method of investigation: We  must start by observing a set of similari.e.

specifically  identicalindividuals, and consider what element they have in  common.  We must then apply the

same process to another set of  individuals  which belong to one species and are generically but not  specifically

identical with the former set. When we have established  what the  common element is in all members of this

second species,  and likewise  in members of further species, we should again consider  whether the  results

established possess any identity, and persevere  until we reach  a single formula, since this will be the

definition  of the thing. But  if we reach not one formula but two or more,  evidently the definiendum  cannot be


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

13 41



Top




Page No 45


one thing but must be more than  one. I may illustrate my  meaning as follows. If we were inquiring what  the

essential nature of  pride is, we should examine instances of proud  men we know of to see  what, as such, they

have in common; e.g. if  Alcibiades was proud, or  Achilles and Ajax were proud, we should  find on inquiring

what they  all had in common, that it was intolerance  of insult; it was this  which drove Alcibiades to war,

Achilles  wrath, and Ajax to suicide. We  should next examine other cases,  Lysander, for example, or Socrates,

and then if these have in common  indifference alike to good and ill  fortune, I take these two results  and

inquire what common element have  equanimity amid the  vicissitudes of life and impatience of dishonour.  If

they have none,  there will be two genera of pride. Besides, every  definition is always  universal and

commensurate: the physician does  not prescribe what is  healthy for a single eye, but for all eyes or  for a

determinate  species of eye. It is also easier by this method to  define the  single species than the universal, and

that is why our  procedure  should be from the several species to the universal  generathis for  the further

reason too that equivocation is less  readily detected in  genera than in infimae species. Indeed,  perspicuity is

essential in  definitions, just as inferential movement  is the minimum required in  demonstrations; and we shall

attain  perspicuity if we can collect  separately the definition of each  species through the group of  singulars

which we have established e.g.  the definition of  similarity not unqualified but restricted to colours  and to

figures;  the definition of acuteness, but only of soundand so  proceed to the  common universal with a careful

avoidance of  equivocation. We may  add that if dialectical disputation must not  employ metaphors, clearly

metaphors and metaphorical expressions are  precluded in definition:  otherwise dialectic would involve

metaphors. 

14

In order to formulate the connexions we wish to prove we have to  select our analyses and divisions. The

method of selection consists in  laying down the common genus of all our subjects of investigationif  e.g.

they are animals, we lay down what the properties are which  inhere in every animal. These established, we

next lay down the  properties essentially connected with the first of the remaining  classese.g. if this first

subgenus is bird, the essential  properties  of every birdand so on, always characterizing the  proximate

subgenus.  This will clearly at once enable us to say in  virtue of what character  the subgeneraman, e.g. or

horsepossess  their properties. Let A be  animal, B the properties of every animal, C  D E various species of

animal. Then it is clear in virtue of what  character B inheres in  Dnamely Aand that it inheres in C and E

for  the same reason: and  throughout the remaining subgenera always the  same rule applies. 

We are now taking our examples from the traditional classnames,  but  we must not confine ourselves to

considering these. We must  collect  any other common character which we observe, and then consider  with

what species it is connected and what.properties belong to it.  For  example, as the common properties of

horned animals we collect the  possession of a third stomach and only one row of teeth. Then since it  is clear

in virtue of what character they possess these  attributesnamely their horned characterthe next question is,

to what  species does the possession of horns attach? 

Yet a further method of selection is by analogy: for we cannot  find a single identical name to give to a squid's

pounce, a fish's  spine, and an animal's bone, although these too possess common  properties as if there were a

single osseous nature. 

15

Some connexions that require proof are identical in that they  possess an identical 'middle' e.g. a whole group

might be proved  through 'reciprocal replacement'and of these one class are  identical  in genus, namely all

those whose difference consists in  their  concerning different subjects or in their mode of manifestation.  This

latter class may be exemplified by the questions as to the causes  respectively of echo, of reflection, and of the

rainbow: the  connexions to be proved which these questions embody are identical  generically, because all


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

14 42



Top




Page No 46


three are forms of repercussion; but  specifically they are different. 

Other connexions that require proof only differ in that the  'middle'  of the one is subordinate to the 'middle' of

the other. For  example:  Why does the Nile rise towards the end of the month? Because  towards  its close the

month is more stormy. Why is the month more  stormy  towards its close? Because the moon is waning. Here

the one  cause is  subordinate to the other. 

16

The question might be raised with regard to cause and effect  whether  when the effect is present the cause also

is present; whether,  for  instance, if a plant sheds its leaves or the moon is eclipsed,  there  is present also the

cause of the eclipse or of the fall of the  leavesthe possession of broad leaves, let us say, in the latter case,  in

the former the earth's interposition. For, one might argue, if this  cause is not present, these phenomena will

have some other cause: if  it is present, its effect will be at once implied by itthe eclipse by  the earth's

interposition, the fall of the leaves by the possession of  broad leaves; but if so, they will be logically

coincident and each  capable of proof through the other. Let me illustrate: Let A be  deciduous character, B the

possession of broad leaves, C vine. Now  if  A inheres in B (for every broadleaved plant is deciduous), and B

in C  (every vine possessing broad leaves); then A inheres in C  (every vine  is deciduous), and the middle term

B is the cause. But  we can also  demonstrate that the vine has broad leaves because it is  deciduous.  Thus, let D

be broadleaved, E deciduous, F vine. Then E  inheres in F  (since every vine is deciduous), and D in E (for

every  deciduous plant  has broad leaves): therefore every vine has broad  leaves, and the  cause is its deciduous

character. If, however, they  cannot each be the  cause of the other (for cause is prior to effect,  and the earth's

interposition is the cause of the moon's eclipse and  not the eclipse  of the interposition)if, then,

demonstration  through the cause is of  the reasoned fact and demonstration not  through the cause is of the  bare

fact, one who knows it through the  eclipse knows the fact of the  earth's interposition but not the  reasoned

fact. Moreover, that the  eclipse is not the cause of the  interposition, but the interposition  of the eclipse, is

obvious  because the interposition is an element in  the definition of  eclipse, which shows that the eclipse is

known  through the  interposition and not vice versa. 

On the other hand, can a single effect have more than one cause?  One  might argue as follows: if the same

attribute is predicable of  more  than one thing as its primary subject, let B be a primary subject  in  which A

inheres, and C another primary subject of A, and D and E  primary subjects of B and C respectively. A will

then inhere in D  and  E, and B will be the cause of A's inherence in D, C of A's  inherence  in E. The presence

of the cause thus necessitates that of  the effect,  but the presence of the effect necessitates the presence  not of

all  that may cause it but only of a cause which yet need not be  the whole  cause. We may, however, suggest

that if the connexion to  be proved is  always universal and commensurate, not only will the  cause be a whole

but also the effect will be universal and  commensurate. For instance,  deciduous character will belong

exclusively to a subject which is a  whole, and, if this whole has  species, universally and commensurately  to

those speciesi.e. either  to all species of plant or to a single  species. So in these  universal and commensurate

connexions the  'middle' and its effect must  reciprocate, i.e. be convertible.  Supposing, for example, that the

reason why trees are deciduous is the  coagulation of sap, then if a  tree is deciduous, coagulation must be

present, and if coagulation  is presentnot in any subject but in a  treethen that tree must be  deciduous. 

17

Can the cause of an identical effect be not identical in every  instance of the effect but different? Or is that

impossible? Perhaps  it is impossible if the effect is demonstrated as essential and not as  inhering in virtue of a

symptom or an accidentbecause the middle is  then the definition of the major termthough possible if the

demonstration is not essential. Now it is possible to consider the  effect and its subject as an accidental

conjunction, though such  conjunctions would not be regarded as connexions demanding  scientific  proof. But


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

16 43



Top




Page No 47


if they are accepted as such, the middle will  correspond to  the extremes, and be equivocal if they are

equivocal,  generically one  if they are generically one. Take the question why  proportionals  alternate. The

cause when they are lines, and when  they are numbers,  is both different and identical; different in so far  as

lines are  lines and not numbers, identical as involving a given  determinate  increment. In all proportionals this

is so. Again, the  cause of  likeness between colour and colour is other than that between  figure  and figure; for

likeness here is equivocal, meaning perhaps  in the  latter case equality of the ratios of the sides and equality of

the  angles, in the case of colours identity of the act of perceiving  them,  or something else of the sort. Again,

connexions requiring proof  which  are identical by analogy middles also analogous. 

The truth is that cause, effect, and subject are reciprocally  predicable in the following way. If the species are

taken severally,  the effect is wider than the subject (e.g. the possession of  external  angles equal to four right

angles is an attribute wider  than triangle  or are), but it is coextensive with the species taken  collectively (in

this instance with all figures whose external  angles are equal to four  right angles). And the middle likewise

reciprocates, for the middle is  a definition of the major; which is  incidentally the reason why all  the sciences

are built up through  definition. 

We may illustrate as follows. Deciduous is a universal attribute  of vine, and is at the same time of wider

extent than vine; and of  fig, and is of wider extent than fig: but it is not wider than but  coextensive with the

totality of the species. Then if you take the  middle which is proximate, it is a definition of deciduous. I say

that, because you will first reach a middle next the subject, and a  premiss asserting it of the whole subject,

and after that a middlethe  coagulation of sap or something of the sortproving the connexion of  the first

middle with the major: but it is the coagulation of sap at  the junction of leafstalk and stem which defines

deciduous. 

If an explanation in formal terms of the interrelation of cause  and  effect is demanded, we shall offer the

following. Let A be an  attribute of all B, and B of every species of D, but so that both A  and B are wider than

their respective subjects. Then B will be a  universal attribute of each species of D (since I call such an

attribute universal even if it is not commensurate, and I call an  attribute primary universal if it is

commensurate, not with each  species severally but with their totality), and it extends beyond each  of them

taken separately. 

Thus, B is the cause of A's inherence in the species of D:  consequently A must be of wider extent than B;

otherwise why should  B  be the cause of A's inherence in D any more than A the cause of  B's  inherence in D?

Now if A is an attribute of all the species of  E, all  the species of E will be united by possessing some

common cause  other  than B: otherwise how shall we be able to say that A is  predicable of  all of which E is

predicable, while E is not  predicable of all of  which A can be predicated? I mean how can there  fail to be

some  special cause of A's inherence in E, as there was of  A's inherence in  all the species of D? Then are the

species of E, too,  united by  possessing some common cause? This cause we must look for.  Let us call  it C. 

We conclude, then, that the same effect may have more than one  cause, but not in subjects specifically

identical. For instance, the  cause of longevity in quadrupeds is lack of bile, in birds a dry  constitutionor

certainly something different. 

18

If immediate premisses are not reached at once, and there is not  merely one middle but several middles, i.e.

several causes; is the  cause of the property's inherence in the several species the middle  which is proximate to

the primary universal, or the middle which is  proximate to the species? Clearly the cause is that nearest to

each  species severally in which it is manifested, for that is the cause  of  the subject's falling under the

universal. To illustrate  formally: C  is the cause of B's inherence in D; hence C is the cause  of A's  inherence in


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

18 44



Top




Page No 48


D, B of A's inherence in C, while the cause of A's  inherence in B is B itself. 

19

As regards syllogism and demonstration, the definition of, and the  conditions required to produce each of

them, are now clear, and with  that also the definition of, and the conditions required to produce,

demonstrative knowledge, since it is the same as demonstration. As  to  the basic premisses, how they become

known and what is the  developed  state of knowledge of them is made clear by raising some  preliminary

problems. 

We have already said that scientific knowledge through  demonstration  is impossible unless a man knows the

primary immediate  premisses.  But there are questions which might be raised in respect of  the  apprehension of

these immediate premisses: one might not only ask  whether it is of the same kind as the apprehension of the

conclusions,  but also whether there is or is not scientific knowledge of both; or  scientific knowledge of the

latter, and of the former a different kind  of knowledge; and, further, whether the developed states of

knowledge  are not innate but come to be in us, or are innate but at  first  unnoticed. Now it is strange if we

possess them from birth;  for it  means that we possess apprehensions more accurate than  demonstration  and

fail to notice them. If on the other hand we acquire  them and do  not previously possess them, how could we

apprehend and  learn without  a basis of preexistent knowledge? For that is  impossible, as we used  to find in

the case of demonstration. So it  emerges that neither can  we possess them from birth, nor can they come  to be

in us if we are  without knowledge of them to the extent of  having no such developed  state at all. Therefore

we must possess a  capacity of some sort, but  not such as to rank higher in accuracy than  these developed

states.  And this at least is an obvious characteristic  of all animals, for  they possess a congenital discriminative

capacity which is called  senseperception. But though senseperception  is innate in all  animals, in some the

senseimpression comes to  persist, in others it  does not. So animals in which this persistence  does not come

to be  have either no knowledge at all outside the act of  perceiving, or no  knowledge of objects of which no

impression  persists; animals in which  it does come into being have perception and  can continue to retain the

senseimpression in the soul: and when such  persistence is frequently  repeated a further distinction at once

arises between those which out  of the persistence of such  senseimpressions develop a power of

systematizing them and those  which do not. So out of senseperception  comes to be what we call  memory,

and out of frequently repeated  memories of the same thing  develops experience; for a number of  memories

constitute a single  experience. From experience againi.e.  from the universal now  stabilized in its entirety

within the soul, the  one beside the many  which is a single identity within them  alloriginate the skill of  the

craftsman and the knowledge of the man  of science, skill in the  sphere of coming to be and science in the

sphere of being. 

We conclude that these states of knowledge are neither innate in a  determinate form, nor developed from

other higher states of knowledge,  but from senseperception. It is like a rout in battle stopped by  first one

man making a stand and then another, until the original  formation has been restored. The soul is so

constituted as to be  capable of this process. 

Let us now restate the account given already, though with  insufficient clearness. When one of a number of

logically  indiscriminable particulars has made a stand, the earliest universal  is present in the soul: for though

the act of senseperception is of  the particular, its content is universalis man, for example, not  the  man

Callias. A fresh stand is made among these rudimentary  universals,  and the process does not cease until the

indivisible  concepts, the  true universals, are established: e.g. such and such a  species of  animal is a step

towards the genus animal, which by the  same process  is a step towards a further generalization. 

Thus it is clear that we must get to know the primary premisses by  induction; for the method by which even

senseperception implants  the  universal is inductive. Now of the thinking states by which we  grasp  truth,


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

19 45



Top




Page No 49


some are unfailingly true, others admit of erroropinion,  for  instance, and calculation, whereas scientific

knowing and  intuition  are always true: further, no other kind of thought except  intuition is  more accurate than

scientific knowledge, whereas  primary premisses are  more knowable than demonstrations, and all  scientific

knowledge is  discursive. From these considerations it  follows that there will be no  scientific knowledge of

the primary  premisses, and since except  intuition nothing can be truer than  scientific knowledge, it will be

intuition that apprehends the primary  premissesa result which also  follows from the fact that demonstration

cannot be the originative  source of demonstration, nor,  consequently, scientific knowledge of  scientific

knowledge.If,  therefore, it is the only other kind of true  thinking except  scientific knowing, intuition will be

the originative  source of  scientific knowledge. And the originative source of science  grasps the  original basic

premiss, while science as a whole is  similarly  related as originative source to the whole body of fact. 

THE END 


POSTERIOR ANALYTICS

19 46



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. POSTERIOR ANALYTICS, page = 5

   3. by Aristotle, page = 5

4.  Book I, page = 6

   5.  1, page = 6

   6.  2, page = 7

   7.  3, page = 8

   8.  4, page = 9

   9.  5, page = 10

   10.  6, page = 11

   11.  7, page = 13

   12.  8, page = 13

   13.  9, page = 14

   14.  10, page = 14

   15.  11, page = 15

   16.  12, page = 16

   17.  13, page = 17

   18.  14, page = 18

   19.  15, page = 19

   20.  16, page = 19

   21.  17, page = 20

   22.  18, page = 21

   23.  19, page = 22

   24.  20, page = 23

   25.  21, page = 23

   26.  22, page = 24

   27.  23, page = 26

   28.  24, page = 27

   29.  25, page = 29

   30.  26, page = 30

   31.  27, page = 30

   32.  28, page = 30

   33.  29, page = 31

   34.  30, page = 31

   35.  31, page = 31

   36.  32, page = 32

   37.  33, page = 32

   38.  34, page = 34

39.  Book II, page = 34

   40.  1, page = 34

   41.  2, page = 34

   42.  3, page = 35

   43.  4, page = 36

   44.  5, page = 37

   45.  6, page = 38

   46.  7, page = 38

   47.  8, page = 39

   48.  9, page = 40

   49.  10, page = 40

   50.  11, page = 41

   51.  12, page = 42

   52.  13, page = 44

   53.  14, page = 46

   54.  15, page = 46

   55.  16, page = 47

   56.  17, page = 47

   57.  18, page = 48

   58.  19, page = 49