Title:   A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

Subject:  

Author:   by Georg Simmel

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Bookmarks





Page No 1


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

by Georg Simmel



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value ...............................................................................................................1

by Georg Simmel.....................................................................................................................................1


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

i



Top




Page No 3


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

by Georg Simmel

The fact of economic exchange confers upon the value of  things something superindividual. It detaches

them from  dissolution in the mere subjectivity of the agents, and causes  them to determine each other

reciprocally, since each exerts its  economic function in the other. The practically effective value  is conferred

upon the object, not merely by its own desirability,  but by the desirability of another object. Not merely the

relationship to the receptive subjects characterizes this value,  but also the fact that it arrives at this

relationship only at  the price of a sacrifice; while from the opposite point of view  this sacrifice appears as a

good to be enjoyed, and the object in  question, on the contrary, as a sacrifice. Hence the objects  acquire a

reciprocity of counterweight, which makes value appear  in a quite special manner as an objective quality

indwelling in  themselves. While the object itself is the thing in controversy   which means that the sacrifice

which it represents is being  determined  its significance for both contracting parties  appears much more as

something outside of these latter and  selfexistent than if the individual thought of it only in its  relation to

himself. We shall see later how also isolated  industry, by placing the workman over against the demands of

nature, imposes upon him the like necessity of sacrifice for  gaining of the object, so that in this case also the

like  relationship, with the one exception that only a single party has  been changed, may endow the object

with the same independent  qualities, yet with their significance dependent upon its own  objective conditions.

Desire and the feeling of the agent stand,  to be sure, as the motor energy behind all this, but from this in  and

of itself this value form could not proceed. It rather comes  only from the reciprocal counterbalancing of the

objects. 

To be sure, in order that equivalence and exchange of values  may emerge, some material to which value can

attach must be at  the basis. For industry as such the fact that these materials are  equivalent to each other and

exchangeable is the turningpoint.  It guides the stream of appraisal through the form of exchange,  at the

same time creating a middle realm between desires, in  which all human movement has its source, and the

satisfaction of  enjoyment in which it culminates. The specific character of  economic activity as a special form

of commerce exists, if we may  venture the paradox, not so much in the fact that it exchanges  values as that it

exchanges values. To be sure, the significance  which things gain in and with exchange rests never isolated by

the side of their subjectiveimmediate significance, that is, the  one originally decisive of the relationship. It is

rather the  case that the two belong together, as form and content connote  each other. But the Objective

procedure makes an abstraction, so  to speak, from the fact that values constitute its material, and  derives its

peculiar character from the equality of the same   somewhat as geometry finds its tasks only in connection

with the  magnitude  relations of things, without bringing into its  consideration the substances in

connection with which alone these  relationships actually have existence. That thus not only  reflection upon

industry, but industry itself, consists, so to  speak, in a real abstraction from the surrounding actuality of  the

appraising processes is not so wonderful as it at first  appears when we once make clear to ourselves how

extensively  human practice, cognition included, reckons with abstractions.  The energies, relationships,

qualities of things  to which in  so far our own proper essence also belongs_constitute objectively  a unified

interrelationship, which is divided into a multiplicity  of independent series or motives only after the

interposition of  our interests, and in order to be manipulated by us. Accordingly,  each science investigates

phenomena which possess an exclusive  unity, and cleancut lines of division from the problems of other

sciences, only from the point of view which the special science  proposes as its own. Reality, on the other

hand, has no regard to  these boundary lines, but every section of the world presents a  conglomeration of tasks

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 1



Top




Page No 4


for the most numerous sciences. Likewise  our practice dissects from the external or internal complexity of

things onesided series. Notice, for example, into how many  systems a forest is divided. These in turn

become objects of  special interest to a hunter, a proprietor, a poet, a painter, a  civic official, a botanist, and a

tourist. The forest is  objectively always the same. It is a real, indivisible unity of  all the determinations and

relationships out of which the  interested parties select each a certain group, and make it into  a picture of the

forest. The same is the case with the great  systems of interest of which a civilization is composed. We

distinguish, for instance, interests and relationships as the  ethical, the egoistic, the economic, the domestic,

etc. The  reciprocal weaving together of these constitutes actual life.  Certain of these, however, dissociated

from this concrete  reality, constitute the content of the civic structure. The state  is an abstraction of energies

and reciprocal actions which, in  the concrete, exist only within a unity that is not separable  into its parts.

Again, in like manner, pedagogy abstracts from  the web of cosmic contents into the totality of which the

pupil  is subsequently to enter certain ones, and forms them into a  world which is completely abstract, in

comparison with reality.  In this world the pupil is to live. To what extent all art runs a  'division line of its own

through the conditions of things, in  addition to those that are traced out in the real structure of  the objective

world, needs no elaboration. In opposition to that  naturalism which wanted to lead art away from the selective

abstraction, and to open to it the whole breadth and unity of  reality, in which all elements have equally rights,

in so far as  they are actualprecisely in opposition to this has criticism  shown the complete impracticability

of the tendency,. and that  even the extremest purpose, to be satisfied in art only with  undifferentiated

completeness of the object, must at last end in  an abstraction. It will merely be the product of another

selective. principle. Accordingly,. this is one of the formulas  in which we may express the relation of man to

the world, viz.,  from the unity and the interpenetration of things in which each  bears the other and all have

equal rights our practice not less  than our theory constantly abstracts isolated elements, and forms  them into

unities relatively complete in themselves. Except in  quite general feelings, we have no relationship to the

totality  of being. Only when in obedience to the necessities of our  thought and action we derive perpetual

abstractions from  phenomena, and endow these with the relative independence of a  merely subjective

coherence to which the continuity of the  worldmovement as objective gives no room, do we reach a

relationship to the. world that is definite in its details.  Indeed, we may adopt a scale of values for our culture

systems,  according to the degree in which they combine the demands of our  singular purposes with the

possibility of passing over without a  gap from each abstraction which they present to the other, so  that a

subsequent combination is possible which approximates that  objective coherence and unity. Accordingly, the

economic system  of the world is assuredly founded upon an abstraction, that is,  upon the relation of

reciprocity and exchange, the balance  between sacrifice and gain; while in the actual process in which  this

takes place it is inseparably amalgamated with its  foundations and its results, the desires and the satisfactions.

But this form of existence does not distinguish it from the other  territories into which, for the purposes of our

interests, we  subdivide the totality of phenomena. 

The objectivity of economic value which we assume as defining  the scope of economics, and which is

thought as the independent  characteristic of the same in distinction from its subjective  vehicles and

consequences, consists in its being true of many, or  rather all, subjects. The decisive factor is its extension in

principle beyond the individual. The fact that for one object  another must be given shows that not merely for

me, but also for  itself, that is, also for another person, the object is of some  value. The appraisal takes place in

the form of economic value. 

The exchange of objects, moreover,. in which this  objectivication, and therewith the specific character of

economic  activity, realizes itself belongs, from the standpoint of each of  the contracting parties, in the quite

general category of gain  and loss, purpose and means. If any object over which we have  control is to help us

to the possession or enjoyment of another,  it is generally under the condition that we forego the enjoyment  of

its own peculiar worth. As a rule the purpose consumes either  the substance or the force of the means, so that

the value of the  same constitutes the price which must be paid for the value of  the purpose. Only within

certain spiritual interests is that not  the case as a rule. The mind has been properly compared to a  fire, in

which countless candles may be lighted without loss of  its own peculiar intensity. For example, intellectual


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 2



Top




Page No 5


products  sometimes (not always) retain for purposes of instruction their  own worth, which does not lose any

of its independent energy and  significance by functioning as means to the pedagogical end. In  the case of

causal series in external nature, however, the  relationship is usually different. Here must the object, if on  the

one hand it is conceived immediately as valuable, and on the  other hand as means to the attainment of another

value, be  sacrificed as a value in itself, in order to perform its office  as means. This procedure rules all values

the enjoyment of which  is connected with a conscious action on our part. What we call  exchange is obviously

nothing but a special case of this typical  form in human life. We must regard this, however, not merely as a

placing of exchange in the universal category of creation of  value; but, conversely, this latter as an exchange

in the wider  sense of the word. This possibility, which has so many  consequences for the theory of value, will

become clear by the  discussion of the doctrine that all economic value consists in  exchange value. 

To this theory the objection has been made that even the  quite isolated economic man  he who neither sells

nor buys   must estimate his products and means of production according to  their value, if expenditures and

results are to stand in proper  relation to each other. This objection, however, is not so  striking as it appears,

for all consideration whether a definite  product is worth enough to justify a definite expenditure of  labor or

other goods is, for the economic agent, precisely the  same as the appraisal which takes place in connection

with  exchange. In confronting the concept,, exchange,, there is  frequently the confusion of ideas which

consists in speaking of a  relationship as though it were something apart from the elements  between which it

plays. It means, however, only a condition or a  change within each of these elements, but nothing that is

between  them in the sense of a spatial object that can be distinguished  in space between two other objects.

When we compose the two acts  or changes of condition which in reality take place into the  notion

"exchange," the conception is attractive that something  has happened in addition to or beyond that which took

place in  each of the contracting parties. Considered with reference to its  immediate content, exchange is

nothing but the twofold repetition  of the fact that an actor now has something which he previously  did not

have, and on the other hand does not have something which  he previously had. That being the case, the

isolated economic  man, who surely must make a sacrifice to gain certain products,  acts precisely like the one

who makes exchanges. The only  difference is that the party with whom he contracts is not a  second sentient

being, but the natural order and regularity of  things, which no more satisfy our desires without a sacrifice on

our part than would another person. His appraisals of value, in  accordance with which he governs his actions,

are, as a rule,  precisely the same as in the case of exchange; for the economic  actor, as such, it is surely quite

immaterial whether the  substances or laborenergies in his possession are sunk in the  ground or given to

another man, if only there accrues to him the  same result from the sacrifice. This subjective process of

sacrifice and gain in the individual soul is by no means  something secondary or imitative in comparison with

interindividual exchange; on the contrary, the giveandtake  between sacrifice and accomplishment, within

the individual, is  the basal presumption, and at the same time the persistent  substance, of every twosided

exchange. The latter is merely a  subspecies of the former; that is, the sort in which the  sacrifice is

occasioned by the demand of another individual. At  the same time, it can only be occasioned by the same sort

of  result for the actor so far as objects and their qualities are  concerned. It is of extreme importance to make

this reduction of  the economic process to that which actually takes place, that is,  in the soul of every

economic agent. We must not allow ourselves  to be deceived about the essential thing by the fact that in the

case of exchange this process is reciprocal; that is, that it is  conditioned by the like procedure in another. The

main thing is  that the natural and solitary economic transaction, if we may  conceive of such a thing, runs back

to the same fundamental form  as twosided exchange: to the process of equalization between two  subjective

occurrences within the individual. This is in its  proper essence not affected by the secondary question

whether the  impulse to the process proceeds from the nature of things or the  nature of man; whether it is a

matter of purely natural economy  or of exchange economy. All feelings of value, in other words,  which are

set free by producible objects are in general to be  gained only by foregoing other values. At the same time,

such  sacrifice may consist, not only in that mediate labor for  ourselves which appears as labor for others, but

frequently  enough in that quite immediate labor for our own personal  purposes. 


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 3



Top




Page No 6


Moreover, those theories of value which discover in labor the  absolute element of value accommodate

themselves to this form of  conception as to the higher and more abstract idea. Whoever  labors sacrifices

something which he possesses  his  laborpower, or his leisure, or his pleasure merely in the  selfsatisfying

play of his powers  in order to get in exchange  for these something which he does not possess. Through the

fact  that labor accomplishes this it acquires value, just as, on the  other side, the attained object is valuable for

the reason that  it has cost labor. In so far there is not the slightest ground to  give labor a special position as

contrasted with all other  conditions of value. The difference between these is only of a  quantitative nature.

Labor is the most frequent object of  exchange. In this assertion we forbear to enter into the  discussion

whether labor or laborpower, and in what form,  constitute an object of exchange. Because labor is regarded

as a  sacrifice, as something painful, it is performed only when an  object can be secured by it which

corresponds to the  eudaemonistic or some other demand. If labor were nothing but  pleasure, the products that

it wrings from nature would have no  value whatever, provided we disregard the difference in abundance  of

objects. On the contrary, if objects that satisfy our desires  came to us of their own accord, labor would have

no more value.  Thus on the whole we may say that, considered from the standpoint  of value, every economic

transaction is an exchange, and every  single article of value furnishes its additional quota to the  total value of

life only after deduction of a certain sacrificed  quantum of value. 

In all the foregoing it is presupposed that a definite scale  of value exists in the case of the objects, and that

each of the  two objects concerned in the transaction signifies, for the one  contracting party the desired gain,

for the other the necessary  sacrifice. But this presumption is, as a matter of fact, much too  simple. If, as is

necessary, we regard economic activity as a  special case of the universal lifeform of exchange, as a  sacrifice

in return for a gain, we shall from the beginning  suspect something of what takes place within this form,

namely,  that the value of the gain is not, so to speak, brought with it,  readymade, but it accrues to the

desired object, in part or even  entirely, through the measure of the sacrifice demanded in  acquiring it. These

cases, which are as frequent as they are  important for the theory of value, seem, to be sure, to harbor an

essential contradiction; for they require us to make a sacrifice  of value for things which in themselves are

worthless. As a  matter of course, no one would forego value without receiving for  it at least equal value; and,

on the contrary, that the end  should receive its value only through the price that we must give  for it could be

the case only in a crazy world. This is now, for  immediate consciousness, correct. Indeed, it is more correct

than  that popular standpoint is apt to allow in other cases. As a  matter of fact, the value which an actor

surrenders for another  value can never be greater for this actor himself, under the  actual circumstances of the

moment, than the one for which it is  given. All contrary appearances rest upon confusion of the value  actually

estimated by the actor with the value which the object  of exchange in question usually has. For instance,

when one at  the point of death from hunger offers a jewel for a piece of  bread, he does it only because the

latter, under the given  circumstances, is of more value to him than the former.  Particular circumstances,

however, are necessary in order to  attach to an object a valuation, for every such valuation is an  incident of

the whole complex system of our. feelings, which is  in constant flux, adaptation, and reconstruction. Whether

these  circumstances are exceptional or relatively constant is obviously  in principle a matter of indifference.

There can be no doubt, at  any rate, that in the moment of the exchange, that is, of the  making of the sacrifice,

the value of the exchanged object forms  the limit which is the highest point to which the value of the

sacrificed object can rise. Quite independent of this is the  question whence that former object derives its so

necessary  value, and whether it may come from the objects that are to be  sacrificed for it, so that the

equivalence between gain and price  would be established at once a posteriori, and by the latter. We  shall see

presently how often value comes into existence,  psychologically, in this apparently illogical manner. If,

however, it is once in existence, the psychological necessity  exists in its case, not less than in that of value

constituted in  any other way, of regarding it as a positive good at least equal  to the negative good sacrificed

for it. In fact, there is a  series of cases in which the sacrifice not merely raises the  value of the aim, but even

produces it. It is the joy of  exertion, of overcoming difficulties, frequently indeed that of  contradiction, which

expresses itself in this process. The  necessary detour to the attainment of certain things is often the  occasion,

often also the cause, of regarding them as valuable. In  the relationships of men to each other, most frequently

and  evidently in erotic relations, we notice how reserve,  indifference, or repulse inflames the most passionate


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 4



Top




Page No 7


desire to  conquer in spite of these obstacles, and spurs us to efforts and  sacrifices which, without these

obstacles, would surely seem to  us excessive. For many people the aesthetic results of ascending  the high

Alps would not be considered worth further notice, if it  did not demand extraordinary effort and danger, and

if it did not  thereby acquire tone, attractiveness, and consecration. The charm  of antiquities and curiosities is

frequently no other. If no sort  of aesthetic or historical interest attaches to them, a  substitute for it is furnished

by the mere difficulty of  acquiring them. They are worth just what they cost. This, then,  appears secondarily

to mean that they cost what they are worth.  Furthermore, all moral merit signifies that for the sake of the

morally desirable deed contrary impulses and wishes must be  fought down and sacrificed. If the act occurs

without any  conquest, as the matterofcourse outflow of unrestrained  impulse, it is not appraised so high in

the scale of subjective  moral value, however desirable objectively its content may be. In  this latter case we

are not moral in any other sense than the  flower is beautiful; we do not reckon the beauty of the flower as  an

ethical merit. Only through the sacrifice of the lower and  still.so seductive good is the height of moral merit

attained,  and a more lofty height, the more attractive the temptation and  the deeper and more comprehensive

the sacrifice. We might array  illustrations, beginning with the ordinary selfishness of the  day, the overcoming

of which alone rewards us with.the  consciousness of being somewhat worthy, and rising to that force  of logic

whose sacrifice in favor of belief in the absurd seemed  to the schoolmen an extreme religious merit. If we

observe which  human achievements attain to the highest honors and appraisals,  we find it to be always those

which betray a maximum of humility,  effort, persistent concentration of the whole being, or at least  seem to

betray these. In other words, they seem to manifest the  most selfdenial, sacrifice of all that is subsidiary, and

of  devotion of the subjective to the objective ideal. And if, in  contrast with all this, aesthetic production and

everything easy,  inviting, springing from the naturalness of impulse, unfolds an  incomparable charm, this

owes its special quality still to the  undefined feeling of the burdens and sacrifices which are usually  the

condition of gaining such things. The mobility and  inexhaustible power of combination of our mental content

frequently brings it about that the significance of a correlation  is carried over to its direct converse, somewhat

as the  association between two ideas occurs equally when they are  asserted or denied of each other. The

specific value of anything  which we gain without conquered difficulty and as the gift of  fortunate accident is

felt by us only on the ground of the  significance which the things have for us that are gained with  difficulty

and measured by sacrifice. It is the same value, but  with the negative sign, and this is the primary from which

the  other may be derived; but the reverse is not the case. 

If we look for an occurrence of this relationship within the  economic realm, it seems to be demanded, in the

first place, that  we shall in thought separate the economic element, as a specific  difference or form, from the

fact of value as the universality or  the substance of the same. If for the present we take value as a  datum, and

not now to be discussed, it is at least, in accordance  with all the foregoing, not doubtful that economic value

as such  does not accrue to an object in its isolated selfexistence, but  only through the employment of

another object which is given for  it. Wild fruit picked without effort, and not given in exchange,  but

immediately consumed, is no economic good. It can count as  such only when its consumption saves some

other sort of economic  expense. If, however, all the demands of life were to be  satisfied in this fashion, so

that no sacrifice was at any point  necessary, men would simply not engage in industry, any more than  do the

birds or the fishes, or the denizens of fairyland.  Whatever be the way in which the two objects, A and B,

came to  have value, A came to have an. economic value only through the  fact that I must give B for it, B only

through the fact that I  can receive A for it. In this case, as above stated, it is in  principle indifferent whether

the sacrifice takes place by means  of the transfer of a thing of value to another person, that is,  through

interindividual exchange, or within the circle of the  individual's own interests, through a balancing of efforts

and  results. In the articles of commerce there is nothing to be found  but the significance which each has,

directly or indirectly, for  our need to consume, and the giveandtake that occurs between  them. Since, now,

as we have seen, the former does not of itself  suffice to make the given object an object of economic activity,

it follows that the latter alone can supply to it the specific  difference which we call economic. 

If thus, under the preliminary assumption of an existing  value, the economic character of the same coincides

with the  offer of another object for it, and of it for the other object,  there arises the further question whether


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 5



Top




Page No 8


this separation between  the value and its economic form is necessary and possible. As a  matter of fact, this

artificially dividing abstraction finds in  reality no counterpart. In the economic value the economic is as  little

sundered from the value as in the economic man the  economist is sundered from the man. To be sure, man is

possible  in times and relations in which he does not pursue economic  activity. The latter, however, is not

possible without being  accomplished by men, in absolute unity with them, and only in  unreal conceptual

abstraction is it to be sundered from them.  Thus there are enough objects of value which are not economic,

but there are no objects of economic value which are not also  valuable in every relation in which they are

economic. What is  true of the industry, as economic as such is, therefore, true of  the values of every condition

or quality or function is  necessarily a condition or quality or function of that general  object to which this

quality or function pertains. The economic  form of the value stands between two boundaries: on the one

hand,  the desire for the object, which attaches itself to the  anticipated feeling of satisfaction from its

possession and  enjoyment; on the other hand, to this enjoyment itself, which,  exactly considered, is not an

economic act. That is, so soon as  we concede, as is universally the case, what was just now  discussed,

namely, that the immediate consumption of wild fruits  is not an.economic procedure, and therefore the fruits

themselves  have no economic value (except in so far as they save the  production of economic values), then

the consumption of values  properly economic is no longer economic, for the act of  consumption, in this last

case, is not to be distinguished  absolutely from that in the first case. Whether the fruit which  one eats has

been found accidentally, or stolen or bought, makes  not the slightest difference in the act of eating itself, and

in  its direct consequences for the eater. Between desire and  consumption lies the economic realm in

unnumbered  interrelationships. Now, economic activity appears to be an  equalization of sacrifices and gains

(of forces or objects), a  mere form in the sense that it presupposes values as its content,  in order to be able to

draw them into the equalizing movement.  But this appearance is not invincible. It will rather appear that  the

same process which constructs into an industrial system the  values given as presuppositions itself produces

the economic  values. 

To see this we need only remind ourselves in principle of the  fact that the object is for us not a thing of value,

so long as  it is dissolved in the subjective process as an immediate  stimulator of feelings, and thus at the same

time is a  selfevident competence of our sensibility. The object must first  be detached from this sensibility, in

order to acquire for our  understanding the peculiar significance which we call value. For  it is not only sure

that desire, in and of itself, can never  establish a value if it does not encounter obstacles. But if  every desire

could find its satisfaction without struggle and  without diminution, an economic exchange of values would

never  come into existence. Indeed, desire itself would never have  arisen to any considerable height if it could

satisfy itself  thus. It is only the postponement of the satisfaction through  obstacles, the anxiety lest the object

may escape, the tension of  struggle for it, which brings into existence that aggregate of  desire elements which

may be designated as intensity or passion  of volition. If, however, even the highest energy of desire were

generated wholly from within, yet we would not accord value to  the object which satisfies the desire if it

came to us in  unlimited abundance. The important thing, in that case, would be  the total enjoyment, the

existence of which guarantees to us the  satisfaction of our wishes, but not that particular quantum of  which

we actually take possession, because this could be replaced  quite as easily by another. Our consciousness

would in this case  simply be filled with the rhythm of the subjective desires and  satisfactions, without

attaching any significance to the object  mediating the satisfaction. The desire, therefore, which on its  part

came into existence only through an absence of feelings of  satisfaction, a condition of want or limitation, is

the  psychological expression of the distance between subject and  object, in which the latter is represented as

of value. 

This distance necessary to the consequence in question is  produced in certain cases by exchange, sacrifice,

abstinence from  objects; that is, in a word, the foregoing of feelings of  satisfaction. This takes place, now, in

the form of traffic  cotemporaneous between two actors, each of whom requires of the  other the abstinence in

question as condition of the feeling of  satisfaction. The feeling of satisfaction, as must be repeatedly

emphasized, would not place itself in antithesis with its object  as a value in our consciousness if the value

were always near to  us, so that we should have no occasion to separate the object  from that consequence in us


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 6



Top




Page No 9


which is alone interesting. Through  exchange, that is, through the economic system, there arise at  the same

time the values of industry, because exchange is the  vehicle or producer of the distance between the subject

and the  object which transmutes the subjective state of feeling into  objective valuation. Kant once

summarized his Theory of Knowledge  in the proposition: "The conditions of experience are at the same  time

the conditions of the objects of experience." By this he  meant that the process which we call experience and

the  conceptions which constitute its contents or objects are subject  to the selfsame laws of the reason. The

objects can come into our  experience, that is, be experienced by us, because they are  conceptions in us; and

the same energy which makes and defines  the experience has also manifested itself in the structure of the

objects. In the same sense we may say here: the possibility of  the economic system is, at the same time, the

possibility of  economic objects. The very procedure between two possessors of  objects (substances,

laborpowers, rights, exchangeabilities of  any sort), which procedure brings them into the socalled

economic relationship, namely, reciprocal dedication, at the same  time raises each of these objects into the

category of values.  The difficulty which threatens from the side of logic, namely,  that the values must first

exist, and exist as values, in order  to enter into the form and movement of industry, is now obviated,  and by

means of the perceived significance of that psychical  relationship which we designated as the distance

between us and  the thing; for this differentiates the original subjective state  of feeling into, first, the desiring

subject anticipating the  feelings; and, second, the object in antithesis with the subject,  and containing in itself

the value; while the distance, on its  side, is produced by exchange, that is, by the twosided  operation of

limitations, restriction, abstinence. The values of  industry emerge, therefore, in the same reciprocity and

relativity in which the economic character of values consists. 

This transference of the idea of economic value from the  character of isolating substantiality into the living

process of  relation may be further explained on the ground of those factors  which we are accustomed to

regard as the constituents of value,  namely, availability and rarity. Availability appears here as the  first

condition, based upon the constitution of the industrial  actor, under which alone an object can under any

circumstances  come into question. in economics. At the same time it is the  presupposition of economic

activity. In order that the value may  reach a given degree, rarity must be associated with  availability, as a

characteristic of the objects themselves. If  we wish to fix economic values through demand and supply,

demand  would correspond with availability, supply with rarity. For the  availability would decide whether we

demand the object at all,  the rarity the price which we are compelled to pay. The avail.  ability serves as the

absolute constituent of the economic  as  that the extent of which must be determined in order that it may

come into the course of economic exchange. We must from the  beginning concede rarity as a merely relative

element, since it  means exclusively the quantitative relation in which the object  in question stands to the

existing aggregate of its kind; the  qualitative nature of the object is not touched by its rarity.  The availability,

however, seems to exist before all economic  action, all comparison, all relation with other objects, and as  the

substantial factor of economic activity, whose movements are  dependent upon itself. 

The circumstance whose efficacy is herewith outlined is not  correctly designated by the notion of utility or

serviceableness.  What we mean in reality is the fact that the object is desired.  All availability is, therefore, not

in a situation to occasion  economic operations with the object possessing the quality, if  the availability does

not at the same time have as a consequence  that the objects are desired. As a matter of fact, this does not

always occur. Any wish whatever may accord with any coNception of  things useful to us; actual desire,

however, which has economic  significance and which sets our acts in motion, is not present in  such wishes in

case long poverty, constitutional laziness,  diversion into other regions of interest, indifference of feeling

toward the theoretically recognized utility, perceived  impossibility of attaining the desired object, and other

positive  and negative elements work in the contrary direction. On the  other hand, many sorts of things are

desired by us, and also  economically valued, which we cannot designate as useful or  available without

arbitrary distortion of verbal usage. Since,  however, not everything that is available is also desired, if we

decide to subsume everything. that is economically desired under  the concept of "availability", it is logically

demanded that we  shall make the fact of being desired the definitively decisive  element for economic

movement. Even with this correction the  criterion is not absolute, totally separable from the relativity  of


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 7



Top




Page No 10


valuation. In the first place, as we saw above, the desire  itself does not come to conscious definiteness unless

obstacles,  difficulties, interpose themselves between the object and the  subject. We do not desire actually

until enjoyment of the object  measures itself upon intermediaries, where at least the price of  patience, of

resignment of other exertion or enjoyment, places at  a distance from us the object to conquer which is the

essence of  desire for it. Its economic value now, second, which rises upon  the basis of its being desired, can

consist only in heightening  or sublimating of that relativity which resides in desire. For  the desired object

does not pass into practical value, that is,  into value that enters into the industrial movement, until its

desirability is compared with that of another object, and thereby  acquires a measure. Only when a second

object is present, with  reference to which I am sure that I am willing to give it for the  first object, or vice

versa, has each of the two an assignable  economic value. The mere desire for an object does not lead to  this

valuation, since it finds in itself alone no measure. Only  the comparison of desires, that is, the

exchangeability of their  objects, fixes each of the same as a value defined in accordance  with its scale, that is,

an economic value. The intensity of the  individual desire, in and of itself, need not have a cumulative  effect

upon the economic value of the object, for since the  latter comes to expression only in exchange, desire can

determine  it only in so far as it modifies the exchange. If now I desire an  object very intensely, its exchange

value is not thereby  determined; for either I have the object not yet in my  possession; in which case my

desire, if I do not manifest it, can  exert no influence upon the demand of the present possessor; he  will rather

adjust his claims according to the measure of his own  interest in the object, or in accordance with his

suppositions  with reference to average interest; or, I have the object in my  possession; in which case my

terms will be either so high that  the object is entirely excluded from exchange, in which instance  it is to that

extent no longer an economic value, or my demands  must fall to the measure of the interest which a

calculating  person takes in the object. The decisive factor is this: that the  economic, practically effective

value is never a value in the  abstract, but rather in its essence and idea a determined quantum  of value; that

this quantity in general can come into existence  only through measurements of two intensities of desire

against  each other; that the form in which this measurement takes place  within the industrial system is that of

reciprocal gain and  sacrifice; that consequently the economic object does not, as  superficially appears,

possess in its desirability an absolute  element of value, but rather that this fact of being desired  operates to

give the object a value exclusively as being the  foundation or the material of an actual or putative exchange. 

Even in case we derive the valuation of objects from an  absolute motive, namely, the labor expended upon

them, and even  if we assert that the value of goods is in inverse ratio to the  productive capacity of the labor,

yet we must still recognize the  determination of the value of the objects as purely reciprocal,  instead of a

derivative from a single absolute standard. This  being admitted, there arises the following relationship: A pair

of boots has at a given time the same value as twenty meters of  shirting. If now, through a new arrangement,

the total labor  demanded for the boots falls to onehalf, they are worth only ten  meters of shirting. Suppose

now the labor time demanded for  shirting is reduced onehalf by improved machinery; the boots  will then

once more be the equivalent to twenty meters of  shirting. If, again, the corresponding improvement affects all

the laborers, and no goods are introduced which affect the  relations between them, the two articles remain

unchanged in  their value as expressed in terms of each other. The change in  the productive power of labor has

an influence upon the value of  the products only when it affects isolated portions of the  economic organism,

but not when it affects the organism as a  whole. However we may exert ourselves, therefore, to express the

value of the object through an absolute quantitative symbol,  however qualified, it remains still only the

relation, in which  the various wares participate in this vehicle of value, which  determines the value of each.

Even under that presupposition, it  is for the value of the separate objects as individuals wholly  irrelevant how

much or how little labor is invested in them. Only  in so far as it is a quantity of labor greater or less in

comparison with the quantity of labor invested in another object  does each of the two acquire an

economically effective value. But  for the same reason it is, on the other hand, also unwarranted to  complain

at absence of the necessary stability of value in the  daily wage of labor  by which expression it is implied

that the  average return of a day's labor is a valueunity. That accusation  is founded on the fact that the labor

day constantly increases in  productivity and power in exchange. Assuming, however, for the  moment that

labor is the one creator of value, the value of the  timeunit of labor for the purpose of exchange of related


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 8



Top




Page No 11


goods  is always the same; although, absolutely considered, it has  increased, and corresponds to a larger

quantum of each separate  product. Since the reciprocal relation of the goods has remained  the same, the

relation of the labor time to each is the same as  to the others. It may, therefore, remain, for the purpose of

reckoning their relative values, a constant term. 

This relativity of value, in consequence of which the given  things stimulating feeling and desire come to be

values only in  the reciprocity of the giveandtake process, appears to lead to  the consequence that value is

nothing but the price, and that  between the two objects no differences of scale can exist.  Consequently, the

frequent falling away of the two from each  other would refute the theory. Against that undeniable fact of

varying ratio our theory asserts, to be sure, that there would  never have been such a thing as a value if the

universal  phenomenon which we call price had not emerged. That a thing is  worth something in a purely

economic sense means that it is worth  something to me, that is, that I am ready to give something for  it. What

in the world can move us to go beyond that naive  subjective enjoyment of the things themselves, and to credit

to  them that peculiar significance which we call their value? This  certainly cannot come from their scarcity in

and of itself, for  if this existed simply as a fact, and were not in some way or  other modifiable by us, we

would regard it as a natural, and, on  account of the defective differentiations, perhaps entirely  unrecognized,

quality of the external cosmos. For, since it could  not be otherwise; it would receive no emphasis beyond its

inherent qualities. This valuation arises only from the fact that  something must be paid for things: the

patience of waiting, the  effort of search, the application of laborpower, the abstinence  from things otherwise

desirable. Without price, therefore   price originally in this extensive sense  value does not come  into

being. That of two objects the one is more valuable than the  other comes to pass subjectively as well as

objectively only  where one agent is ready to give this for that, but conversely  that is not to be obtained for

this. In transactions that have  not become complicated the higher or lower value can be only the  consequence

or the expression of this immediate practical will to  exchange. And if we say we exchange the things for each

other  because they are equally valuable, it is only that frequent  inversion of thought and speech by which we

also say that things  pleased us because they were beautiful, whereas, in reality, they  are beautiful because

they please us. 

If, thus, value is at the same time the offspring of price,  it seems to be an identical proposition that their

height must be  the same. I refer now to the above proof, that in each individual  case no contracting party pays

the price which is to him, under  the given circumstances, too high for the thing obtained. If in  the poem of

Chamisso the highwayman at the point of the pistol  compels the victim to sell him his watch and rings for

three  coppers, the fact is that under the circumstances, since the  victim could not otherwise save his life, the

thing obtained in  exchange was actually worth the price. No laborer would work for  starvation wages if, in

the situation in which he actually found  himself, he did not prefer this wage to not working. The  appearance

of paradox in the assertion of the equivalence of  value and price in every individual case arises only from the

fact that certain conceptions of other kinds of equivalence of  value and price are brought into our estimate of

the case. The  relative stability of the relationships by which the majority of  exchanges are determined; on the

other hand the analogies which  fix still uncertain valuerelations according to the norm of  others already

existing, produce the conceptions: if for a  definite object this and that other definite object were exchange

equivalents, these two or this group of objects would have  equality in the scale of value; and if abnormal

circumstances  caused us to exchange the one object for values higher or lower  in the scale, price and value

would fall away from each other,  although in each individual case, as a matter of fact, under  consideration of

its circumstances, they would coincide. We  should not forget that the objective and just equivalence of  value

and price which we make the norm of the actual and the  specific works only under very definite historical and

technical  conditions; and, with change of these conditions, at once  vanishes. Between the norm itself and the

cases which are  characterized as exceptional or as adequate no general difference  exists, but, so to speak,

only a numerical difference  somewhat  as we say of an extraordinarily eminent or degraded individual,

"He is really no longer a man." The fact is that this idea of man  is only an average; it would lose its normative

character at the  moment in which the majority of men ascended or descended to that  grade, which then would

pass for the generically human. 


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 9



Top




Page No 12


In order to reach this perception we must, to be sure,  extricate ourselves from deeprooted conceptions of

value, which  also have an assured practical justification. These conceptions,  in the case of relationships that

are somewhat complex, rest in  two strata with reference to each other. The one is formed from  the traditions

of society, from the majority of experiences, from  demands that seem to be purely logical; the other, from

individual correlations, from the demands of the moment, from the  constraint of given facts. In contrast with

the rapid changes  within this latter stratum, the gradual evolution of the former  and its construction out of

elaboration of our perceptions is  lost to sight, and the former appears as alone justified as the  expression of an

objective ratio. Where now, in case of an  exchange under the given circumstances, the valuations of  sacrifice

and gain at least balance each other  for otherwise  no agent would consummate the exchange  yet

judged by those  general criteria a discrepancy appears, in such a case we speak  of a divergence between value

and price. This occurs most  decisively under the two presuppositions (almost always united),  viz., first, that a

single valuequality passes as economic value  in general, and two objects consequently can be recognized as

equal in value, only in so far as the like quantum of that  fundamental value is present in them; and, second,

that a  definite proportion between two values appears as a something  that must be, with the emphasis of a not

merely objective, but  also a moral demand. The conception, for example, that the  essential valueelement in

all values is the labor time  objectified in them is utilized in both these assumptions, and  thus gives a direct or

an indirect standard which fixes the value  independent of price, and makes the latter vibrate in changing  plus

and minus differences, as compared with the former. Now it  is evident, to be sure, that if we from the start

recognize only  a single valuesubstance, only that price corresponds to the  value so contained which contains

precisely an equivalent amount  of that same value. According to this principle the value should  be the first

and fixed element; the price should constitute a  more or less adequate secondary element. But this

consequence,  supposing everything else is conceded, does not in fact follow.  The fact of that single measure

of value leaves entirely  unexplained how laborpower comes to have value. It would hardly  have occurred if

the laborpower had not, by acting upon various  materials and by creating various products, made the

possibility  of exchange; or unless the exercise of the power had been  recognized as a sacrifice made for the

gain of the object  achieved by the sacrifice. Thus laborpower also comes into the  valuecategory through

the possibility and reality of exchange,  quite unaffected by the circumstance that later laborpower may  itself

furnish a measure, within the valuecategory, for the  other contents. If the laborpower is thus also the

content of  that value, it receives its form as value only through the fact  that it enters into the relation of

sacrifice and gain, or price  and value (here in the narrower sense). In the cases of  discrepancy between price

and value, the one contracting party  would, according to this theory, give a quantum of immediately

realizable laborpower for a lesser quantum of the same. Yet  other circumstances, not containing

laborpower, are in such wise  connected with this case that the party still completes the  exchange; for

example: the satisfaction of an economic need,  amateurish fancy, fraud, monopoly, and similar

circumstances. In  the wider and subjective sense, therefore, the equivalence of  value and countervalue

remains in these cases, while the simple  norm, laborpower, which makes the discrepancy possible, does not

on its side cease to derive its genesis as a vehicle of value  from exchange. 

The qualitative determination of objects, which subjectively  signifies their desirability, can consequently not

maintain the  claim of constituting an absolute valuemagnitude. It is always  the relation of the desires to each

other, realized in exchange,  which makes their objects economic values. This determination  appears more

immediately in connection with the other element  supposed to constitute value, namely, scarcity, or relative

rarity. Exchange is, indeed, nothing else than the  interindividual attempt to improve conditions rising out of

scarcity of goods; that is, to reduce as far as possible the  amount of subjective abstinence by the mode of

distributing the  given stock. Thereupon follows immediately a universal  correlation between that which we

call scarcityvalue and that  which we call exchangevalue, a correlation which appears, for  instance, in the

relation of socialism to both. We may, perhaps,  indicate the economic purposes of socialism comprehensively

and  abstractly in this way, namely, that it strives to abolish  scarcityvalue; that is, that modification of the

value of things  which arises from their rarity or abundance; for it is abundance  which reduces the value of

labor. There should be less labor, in  order that labor may be appraised according to the qualityvalue,  without

depression on account of the quantity. On the other hand,  the means of enjoyment should lose that value


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 10



Top




Page No 13


which they now have  on account of their restricted quantity; that is, they should be  accessible to all.

Accordingly, Marx held that in the  capitalistic type of society, that is, the sort of society which  socialism

wishes to abolish, exchangevalue alone is decisive,  while usevalue no longer plays any role. While

socialism  despises exchangevalue quite as much as scarcityvalue, it calls  attention to the radical

connection between the two. 

For us, however, the connection is more important in the  reverse direction. I have already emphasized the fact

that  scarcity of goods would scarcely have a valuation of them as a  consequence if it were not modifiable by

us. It is, however,  modifiable in two ways: either through devotion of laborpower,  which increases the stock

of the goods in question, or through  devotion of already possessed objects, which as substitutes  abolish the

rarity of the most desired objects for the  individual. Accordingly, we may say immediately that the scarcity  of

goods in proportion to the desires centering upon them  objectively determines exchange; that, however, the

exchange on  its side brings scarcity into force as an element of value. It is  a thoroughgoing mistake of

theories of value to assume that, when  utility and rarity are given, economic value  that is, exchange

movement  is something to be taken for granted, a conceptually  necessary consequence of those premises.

In this they are by no  means correct. In case, for instance, there were alongside of  these presuppositions an

ascetic renunciation, or if they only  instigated to conflict or robbery  which is, to be sure, often  enough the

case  no economic value and no economic life would  emerge. Exchange is a sociological structure sui

generis, a  primary form and function of interindividual life, which by no  means emerges as a logical

consequence from those qualitative and  quantitative properties of things which we call availability and  rarity.

On the contrary, it is rather the case that these two  properties derive their valuecreating significance only

under  the presupposition of exchange. Where exchange, the offering of a  sacrifice for the purpose of a gain, is

for any reason excluded,  there no rarity of the desired object can confer upon it economic  value until the

possibility of that relation reappears. We may  express the relation in this way: The significance of the object

for the individual always rests merely in its desirability; so  far as that is concerned which the object is to do

for us, its  qualitative character is decisive, and when we have it, it is a  matter of indifference in this respect

whether there exist  besides many, few, or no specimens of the same sort. (I do not  treat here especially the

cases in which rarity itself is a  species of qualitative character, which makes the object  desirable to us, as in

the case of old postage stamps,  curiosities, antiquities without aesthetic or historical value,  etc. I also

disregard. other cases, interesting in themselves,  here however in principle insignificant, namely, those

psychological subsidiary phenomena which frequently arise from  scarcity itself, where they have no effect

upon acquisition of  the object.) The enjoyment of things, therefore, so soon as  possession of them is

achieved, the positive practical  significance of their actuality for us, is quite independent of  the scarcity

question, since this affects only a numerical  relation to things, which we do not have, to be sure, but which,

according to the hypothesis, we do not desire to have. The only  question in point with reference to things,

apart from enjoyment  of them, is the way to them. So soon as this way is a long and  difficult one, leading

over sacrifice in the shape of strain of  the patience, disappointment, labor, selfdenial, etc., we call  the object

scarce. Paradoxical as it is, things are not difficult  to obtain because they are scarce, but they are scarce

because  they are difficult to obtain. The inflexible external fact that  there is a deficient stock of certain goods

to satisfy all our  desires for them would be in itself insignificant. Whether they  are scarce in the sense of

economic value is decided simply by  the circumstance of the measure of energy, patience, devotion to

acquisition, which is necessary in order to obtain them. Let us  suppose a stock of goods which suffices to

cover all the demands  centered upon it, but which is so disposed that every portion of  it is to be obtained only

with considerable effort and sacrifice.  Then the result for its valuation and its practical significance  would be

precisely the same which, under the presupposition of  equal availability, we have been accustomed to derive

from its  scarcity. The difficulty of attainment, that is, the magnitude of  the sacrifice involved in exchange, is

thus the element that  peculiarly constitutes value. Scarcity constitutes only the  external appearance of this

element, only the externalizing of it  in the form of quantity. We fail to observe that scarcity, purely  as such, is

only a negative property, an existence characterized  by a nonexistence. The nonexistent, however, cannot

be  operative. Every positive consequence must proceed from a  positive property and force, of which that

negative property is  only the shadow. These concrete energies are, however, manifestly  only those that are


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 11



Top




Page No 14


put into action in the exchange, so that the  increase of value starts from that increasing magnitude whose

negative is the scarcity of the object. 

Finally, by way of corollary, I will add a more conceptual  deduction, namely, that the usual conception of the

scarcity  theory must presuppose the value which it tries to derive from  scarcity. According to this conception,

an object of economic  desire acquires value if no unlimited number of specimens of its  kind is at hand; that

is, if the present quantity of such objects  does not cover a series of needs that look to it for  satisfaction. The

failure of these needs to be covered is felt as  a painful condition which ought not to be, as the negation of

value. The covering of these needs must be something having  value. Otherwise the failure could exert no

such effect. If,  however, this defect is necessary to establish the value of the  present quantity, the value is

thereby presupposed whose  establishment is in question. The existing quantity has value  because the lacking

quantity has value. Otherwise its lack could  never establish a value. Let us suppose the quantity A, which

would completely cover the need, to be divided into two parts:  first, the portion actually present, M, and,

second, the merely  ideally present, N. According to the theory, the value M is  determined by the fact that N is

not present. N must, as we said,  have a value in order to produce this consequence. In order that  it may have

this value, we must, however, think it as present,  and, on the contrary, M as not present. Otherwise the whole

of A  would be accessible, and therefore, according to the scarcity  theory, no portion of it would have a value.

The value of the  actual quantity is based on that of the nonexisting quantity,  that of the nonexisting

quantity (which I must think in this  connection as present) on that of the existing quantity (which I  must think

as nonexistent). The scarcity element is thus to be  accounted for only relatively, equally with that element

which  has its source in the significance of the object for the  feelings. As little as the fact of being desired can

scarcity  create for the object a valuation otherwise than in the  reciprocal relation with another object existing

under like  conditions. We may examine the one object ever so closely with  reference to its selfsufficient

properties, we shall never find  the economic value; since this consists exclusively in the  reciprocal

relationship, which comes into being between several  objects on the basis of these properties, each

determining the  other, and each giving to the other the significance which each  in turn receives from the

other. 


A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value

A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value 12



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. A Chapter in the Philosophy of Value, page = 4

   3. by Georg Simmel, page = 4