Title: The Critique of Pure Reason
Subject:
Author: Immanuel Kant
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
The Critique of Pure Reason
Immanuel Kant
Page No 2
Table of Contents
The Critique of Pure Reason.............................................................................................................................1
Immanuel Kant .........................................................................................................................................1
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 .........................................................................................2
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 ....................................................................................6
INTRODUCTION................................................................................................................................15
I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge...............................................................15
II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in Possession of Certain
Cognitions "a priori". .............................................................................................................................16
III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the Possibility, Principles, and
Extent of Human Knowledge "a priori" ................................................................................................17
IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements. ..............................................18
V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a priori" are contained as
Principles...............................................................................................................................................19
VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason. ..........................................................................................21
VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a Critique of Pure Reason...........23
SS I. Introductory. .................................................................................................................................24
SECTION I. Of Space. ..........................................................................................................................25
SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception. ..............................................................................25
SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space. ..............................................................26
SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions.............................................................................27
SECTION II. Of Time..........................................................................................................................28
SS 5 Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception. ................................................................................28
SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time. ................................................................29
SS 7 Conclusions from the above Conceptions....................................................................................29
SS 8 Elucidation. ...................................................................................................................................30
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. ...........................................................................32
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic...............................................................................36
Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC. SS I. ......................40
BOOK I. ................................................................................................................................................41
SS 2 Analytic of Conceptions. .............................................................................................................41
CHAPTER I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure Conceptions of the
Understanding. .......................................................................................................................................41
SS 3. Introductory. ................................................................................................................................41
SECTION I. Of defined above Use of understanding in General. ........................................................41
SS 4........................................................................................................................................................41
SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgements. ......................................42
SS 5. ......................................................................................................................................................42
SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories. .....................................44
SS 6.......................................................................................................................................................44
SS 7.......................................................................................................................................................47
SS 8.......................................................................................................................................................48
CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. .................................49
SECTION I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in general. ..........................................49
SS 9........................................................................................................................................................49
Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. SS 10.................................................51
SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the Understanding. ....................53
SS 11 Of the Possibility of a Conjunction of the manifold representations given by Sense.................53
Of the Originally Synthetical Unity of Apperception. SS 12...............................................................53
The Critique of Pure Reason
i
Page No 3
Table of Contents
The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception is the highest Principle of all exercise of
the Understanding. SS 13 .......................................................................................................................55
What Objective Unity of Selfconsciousness is. SS 14.......................................................................56
The Logical Form of all Judgements consists in the Objective Unity of Apperception of the
Conceptions contained therein. SS 15..................................................................................................56
All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as Conditions under which alone the
manifold Content of them can be united in one Consciousness. SS 16 ................................................57
Observation. SS 17...............................................................................................................................57
In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is the only legitimate use of the
Category. SS 18.....................................................................................................................................58
SS 19.....................................................................................................................................................58
Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the Senses in general. SS 20...............................59
SS 21.....................................................................................................................................................61
Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the Understanding. SS 23.........................................63
BOOK II. Analytic of Principles..........................................................................................................65
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding...........................66
CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding.....................................................70
SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements. ..................................................71
SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements. ...............................................72
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. ...73
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena...........103
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. .........................................................................................118
BOOK I. OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON.................................................................123
SECTION I Of Ideas in General. .....................................................................................................124
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas. ..............................................................................................126
SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas. .................................................................................130
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON........................................132
CHAPTER I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason. .............................................................................132
CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason. ...................................................................................142
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas. ......................................................................................143
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. ............................................................................................147
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions. ..............................................159
SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its
Transcendental Problems. ....................................................................................................................163
SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems presented in the four
Transcendental Ideas. ...........................................................................................................................166
SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Pure Cosmological
Dialectic...............................................................................................................................................168
SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem........................................................169
SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the Cosmological Ideas. ...........172
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the
Cosmological Ideas. .............................................................................................................................174
CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason. ..........................................................................................189
SECTION I. Of the Ideal in General..................................................................................................189
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale)..........................................190
SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of
a Supreme Being. .................................................................................................................................194
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God.......................196
The Critique of Pure Reason
ii
Page No 4
Table of Contents
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God......................200
SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof.................................................205
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason...................208
CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason. ....................................................................................230
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism........................................231
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics.................................................................239
SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis............................................................248
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs.................................................251
CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason. .........................................................................................255
SECTION I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason. ...........................................................255
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate
End of Pure Reason. .............................................................................................................................257
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief...........................................................................262
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. ............................................................................266
CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason......................................................................................271
The Critique of Pure Reason
iii
Page No 5
The Critique of Pure Reason
Immanuel Kant
translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787
INTRODUCTION
Section I. Of Space.
Section II. Of Time.
Transcendental Logic. First Division
Book I
Chapter I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure Conceptions of the Understanding.
Section I. Of defined above Use of understanding in General.
Section II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgements.
Section III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories.
Chapter II. Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding
Section I. Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in general.
Section II. Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the Understanding.
BOOK II. Analytic of Principles
Chapter I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding
Chapter II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding
Section I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements
Section II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements
Section III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding.
Chapter III. Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena
Section I. Of Ideas in General
Section II. Of Transcendental Ideas
Section III. System of Transcendental Ideas
Transcendental Logic. Second Division
BOOK I. OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON
Chapter I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason
Chapter II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason
Section I. System of Cosmological Ideas
Section II. Antithetic of Pure Reason
Section III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions
Section IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental
Problems
Section V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems presented in the four Transcendental Ideas
Section VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Pure Cosmological Dialectic
Section VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem
Section VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the Cosmological Ideas
Section IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological
Ideas
Chapter III. The Ideal of Pure Reason
Section I. Of the Ideal in General
Section II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale)
Section III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme
Being
The Critique of Pure Reason 1
Page No 6
Section IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God
Section V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God
Section VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof
Section VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON
Chapter I. The Discipline of Pure Reason
Section I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism
Section II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics
Section III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis
Section IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs
Chapter II. The Canon of Pure Reason
Section I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason
Section II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure
Reason
Section III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief
Chapter III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason
Chapter IV. The History of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781
Human reason, in one sphere of its cognition, is called upon to consider questions, which it cannot decline, as
they are presented by its own nature, but which it cannot answer, as they transcend every faculty of the mind.
It falls into this difficulty without any fault of its own. It begins with principles, which cannot be dispensed
with in the field of experience, and the truth and sufficiency of which are, at the same time, insured by
experience. With these principles it rises, in obedience to the laws of its own nature, to ever higher and more
remote conditions. But it quickly discovers that, in this way, its labours must remain ever incomplete,
because new questions never cease to present themselves; and thus it finds itself compelled to have recourse
to principles which transcend the region of experience, while they are regarded by common sense without
distrust. It thus falls into confusion and contradictions, from which it conjectures the presence of latent errors,
which, however, it is unable to discover, because the principles it employs, transcending the limits of
experience, cannot be tested by that criterion. The arena of these endless contests is called Metaphysic.
Time was, when she was the queen of all the sciences; and, if we take the will for the deed, she certainly
deserves, so far as regards the high importance of her objectmatter, this title of honour. Now, it is the
fashion of the time to heap contempt and scorn upon her; and the matron mourns, forlorn and forsaken, like
Hecuba:
Modo maxima rerum,
Tot generis, natisque potens...
Nunc trahor exul, inops.*
*Ovid, Metamorphoses. [xiii, "But late on the pinnacle of fame, strong in my many sons. now exiled,
penniless."]
At first, her government, under the administration of the dogmatists, was an absolute despotism. But, as the
legislative continued to show traces of the ancient barbaric rule, her empire gradually broke up, and intestine
wars introduced the reign of anarchy; while the sceptics, like nomadic tribes, who hate a permanent
habitation and settled mode of living, attacked from time to time those who had organized themselves into
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 2
Page No 7
civil communities. But their number was, very happily, small; and thus they could not entirely put a stop to
the exertions of those who persisted in raising new edifices, although on no settled or uniform plan. In recent
times the hope dawned upon us of seeing those disputes settled, and the legitimacy of her claims established
by a kind of physiology of the human understanding that of the celebrated Locke. But it was found that
although it was affirmed that this socalled queen could not refer her descent to any higher source than that
of common experience, a circumstance which necessarily brought suspicion on her claims as this genealogy
was incorrect, she persisted in the advancement of her claims to sovereignty. Thus metaphysics necessarily
fell back into the antiquated and rotten constitution of dogmatism, and again became obnoxious to the
contempt from which efforts had been made to save it. At present, as all methods, according to the general
persuasion, have been tried in vain, there reigns nought but weariness and complete indifferentism the
mother of chaos and night in the scientific world, but at the same time the source of, or at least the prelude to,
the recreation and reinstallation of a science, when it has fallen into confusion, obscurity, and disuse from ill
directed effort.
For it is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to such inquiries, the object of which cannot be
indifferent to humanity. Besides, these pretended indifferentists, however much they may try to disguise
themselves by the assumption of a popular style and by changes on the language of the schools, unavoidably
fall into metaphysical declarations and propositions, which they profess to regard with so much contempt. At
the same time, this indifference, which has arisen in the world of science, and which relates to that kind of
knowledge which we should wish to see destroyed the last, is a phenomenon that well deserves our attention
and reflection. It is plainly not the effect of the levity, but of the matured judgement* of the age, which
refuses to be any longer entertained with illusory knowledge, It is, in fact, a call to reason, again to undertake
the most laborious of all tasks that of selfexamination and to establish a tribunal, which may secure it in
its wellgrounded claims, while it pronounces against all baseless assumptions and pretensions, not in an
arbitrary manner, but according to its own eternal and unchangeable laws. This tribunal is nothing less than
the critical investigation of pure reason.
*We very often hear complaints of the shallowness of the present age, and of the decay of profound science.
But I do not think that those which rest upon a secure foundation, such as mathematics, physical science, etc.,
in the least deserve this reproach, but that they rather maintain their ancient fame, and in the latter case,
indeed, far surpass it. The same would be the case with the other kinds of cognition, if their principles were
but firmly established. In the absence of this security, indifference, doubt, and finally, severe criticism are
rather signs of a profound habit of thought. Our age is the age of criticism, to which everything must be
subjected. The sacredness of religion, and the authority of legislation, are by many regarded as grounds of
exemption from the examination of this tribunal. But, if they on they are exempted, they become the subjects
of just suspicion, and cannot lay claim to sincere respect, which reason accords only to that which has stood
the test of a free and public examination.
I do not mean by this a criticism of books and systems, but a critical inquiry into the faculty of reason, with
reference to the cognitions to which it strives to attain without the aid of experience; in other words, the
solution of the question regarding the possibility or impossibility of metaphysics, and the determination of the
origin, as well as of the extent and limits of this science. All this must be done on the basis of principles.
This path the only one now remaining has been entered upon by me; and I flatter myself that I have, in this
way, discovered the cause of and consequently the mode of removing all the errors which have hitherto set
reason at variance with itself, in the sphere of nonempirical thought. I have not returned an evasive answer
to the questions of reason, by alleging the inability and limitation of the faculties of the mind; I have, on the
contrary, examined them completely in the light of principles, and, after having discovered the cause of the
doubts and contradictions into which reason fell, have solved them to its perfect satisfaction. It is true, these
questions have not been solved as dogmatism, in its vain fancies and desires, had expected; for it can only be
satisfied by the exercise of magical arts, and of these I have no knowledge. But neither do these come within
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 3
Page No 8
the compass of our mental powers; and it was the duty of philosophy to destroy the illusions which had their
origin in misconceptions, whatever darling hopes and valued expectations may be ruined by its explanations.
My chief aim in this work has been thoroughness; and I make bold to say that there is not a single
metaphysical problem that does not find its solution, or at least the key to its solution, here. Pure reason is a
perfect unity; and therefore, if the if the principle presented by it prove to be insufficient for the solution of
even a single one of those questions to which the very nature of reason gives birth, we must reject it, as we
could not be perfectly certain of its sufficiency in the case of the others.
While I say this, I think I see upon the countenance of the reader signs of dissatisfaction mingled with
contempt, when he hears declarations which sound so boastful and extravagant; and yet they are beyond
comparison more moderate than those advanced by the commonest author of the commonest philosophical
programme, in which the dogmatist professes to demonstrate the simple nature of the soul, or the necessity of
a primal being. Such a dogmatist promises to extend human knowledge beyond the limits of possible
experience; while I humbly confess that this is completely beyond my power. Instead of any such attempt, I
confine myself to the examination of reason alone and its pure thought; and I do not need to seek far for the
sumtotal of its cognition, because it has its seat in my own mind. Besides, common logic presents me with a
complete and systematic catalogue of all the simple operations of reason; and it is my task to answer the
question how far reason can go, without the material presented and the aid furnished by experience.
So much for the completeness and thoroughness necessary in the execution of the present task. The aims set
before us are not arbitrarily proposed, but are imposed upon us by the nature of cognition itself.
The above remarks relate to the matter of our critical inquiry. As regards the form, there are two
indispensable conditions, which any one who undertakes so difficult a task as that of a critique of pure
reason, is bound to fulfil. These conditions are certitude and clearness.
As regards certitude, I have fully convinced myself that, in this sphere of thought, opinion is perfectly
inadmissible, and that everything which bears the least semblance of an hypothesis must be excluded, as of
no value in such discussions. For it is a necessary condition of every cognition that is to be established upon a
priori grounds that it shall be held to be absolutely necessary; much more is this the case with an attempt to
determine all pure a priori cognition, and to furnish the standard and consequently an example of all
apodeictic (philosophical) certitude. Whether I have succeeded in what I professed to do, it is for the reader to
determine; it is the author's business merely to adduce grounds and reasons, without determining what
influence these ought to have on the mind of his judges. But, lest anything he may have said may become the
innocent cause of doubt in their minds, or tend to weaken the effect which his arguments might otherwise
produce he may be allowed to point out those passages which may occasion mistrust or difficulty, although
these do not concern the main purpose of the present work. He does this solely with the view of removing
from the mind of the reader any doubts which might affect his judgement of the work as a whole, and in
regard to its ultimate aim.
I know no investigations more necessary for a full insight into the nature of the faculty which we call
understanding, and at the same time for the determination of the rules and limits of its use, than those
undertaken in the second chapter of the "Transcendental Analytic," under the title of "Deduction of the Pure
Conceptions of the Understanding"; and they have also cost me by far the greatest labour labour which, I
hope, will not remain uncompensated. The view there taken, which goes somewhat deeply into the subject,
has two sides, The one relates to the objects of the pure understanding, and is intended to demonstrate and to
render comprehensible the objective validity of its a priori conceptions; and it forms for this reason an
essential part of the Critique. The other considers the pure understanding itself, its possibility and its powers
of cognition that is, from a subjective point of view; and, although this exposition is of great importance, it
does not belong essentially to the main purpose of the work, because the grand question is what and how
much can reason and understanding, apart from experience, cognize, and not, how is the faculty of thought
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 4
Page No 9
itself possible? As the latter is an, inquiry into the cause of a given effect, and has thus in it some semblance
of an hypothesis (although, as I shall show on another occasion, this is really not the fact), it would seem that,
in the present instance, I had allowed myself to enounce a mere opinion, and that the reader must therefore be
at liberty to hold a different opinion. But I beg to remind him that, if my subjective deduction does not
produce in his mind the conviction of its certitude at which I aimed, the objective deduction, with which
alone the present work is properly concerned, is in every respect satisfactory.
As regards clearness, the reader has a right to demand, in the first place, discursive or logical clearness, that
is, on the basis of conceptions, and, secondly, intuitive or aesthetic clearness, by means of intuitions, that is,
by examples or other modes of illustration in concreto. I have done what I could for the first kind of
intelligibility. This was essential to my purpose; and it thus became the accidental cause of my inability to do
complete justice to the second requirement. I have been almost always at a loss, during the progress of this
work, how to settle this question. Examples and illustrations always appeared to me necessary, and, in the
first sketch of the Critique, naturally fell into their proper places. But I very soon became aware of the
magnitude of my task, and the numerous problems with which I should be engaged; and, as I perceived that
this critical investigation would, even if delivered in the driest scholastic manner, be far from being brief, I
found it unadvisable to enlarge it still more with examples and explanations, which are necessary only from a
popular point of view. I was induced to take this course from the consideration also that the present work is
not intended for popular use, that those devoted to science do not require such helps, although they are
always acceptable, and that they would have materially interfered with my present purpose. Abbe Terrasson
remarks with great justice that, if we estimate the size of a work, not from the number of its pages, but from
the time which we require to make ourselves master of it, it may be said of many a book that it would be
much shorter, if it were not so short. On the other hand, as regards the comprehensibility of a system of
speculative cognition, connected under a single principle, we may say with equal justice: many a book would
have been much clearer, if it had not been intended to be so very clear. For explanations and examples, and
other helps to intelligibility, aid us in the comprehension of parts, but they distract the attention, dissipate the
mental power of the reader, and stand in the way of his forming a clear conception of the whole; as he cannot
attain soon enough to a survey of the system, and the colouring and embellishments bestowed upon it prevent
his observing its articulation or organization which is the most important consideration with him, when he
comes to judge of its unity and stability.
The reader must naturally have a strong inducement to cooperate with the present author, if he has formed
the intention of erecting a complete and solid edifice of metaphysical science, according to the plan now laid
before him. Metaphysics, as here represented, is the only science which admits of completion and with little
labour, if it is united, in a short time; so that nothing will be left to future generations except the task of
illustrating and applying it didactically. For this science is nothing more than the inventory of all that is given
us by pure reason, systematically arranged. Nothing can escape our notice; for what reason produces from
itself cannot lie concealed, but must be brought to the light by reason itself, so soon as we have discovered
the common principle of the ideas we seek. The perfect unity of this kind of cognitions, which are based upon
pure conceptions, and uninfluenced by any empirical element, or any peculiar intuition leading to determinate
experience, renders this completeness not only practicable, but also necessary.
Tecum habita, et noris quam sit tibi curta supellex.*
*Persius. [Satirae iv. 52. "Dwell with yourself, and you will know how short your household stuff is."
Such a system of pure speculative reason I hope to be able to publish under the title of Metaphysic of Nature.
The content of this work (which will not be half so long) will be very much richer than that of the present
Critique, which has to discover the sources of this cognition and expose the conditions of its possibility, and
at the same time to clear and level a fit foundation for the scientific edifice. In the present work, I look for the
patient hearing and the impartiality of a judge; in the other, for the goodwill and assistance of a colabourer.
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781 5
Page No 10
For, however complete the list of principles for this system may be in the Critique, the correctness of the
system requires that no deduced conceptions should be absent. These cannot be presented a priori, but must
be gradually discovered; and, while the synthesis of conceptions has been fully exhausted in the Critique, it is
necessary that, in the proposed work, the same should be the case with their analysis. But this will be rather
an amusement than a labour.
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787
Whether the treatment of that portion of our knowledge which lies within the province of pure reason
advances with that undeviating certainty which characterizes the progress of science, we shall be at no loss to
determine. If we find those who are engaged in metaphysical pursuits, unable to come to an understanding as
to the method which they ought to follow; if we find them, after the most elaborate preparations, invariably
brought to a stand before the goal is reached, and compelled to retrace their steps and strike into fresh paths,
we may then feel quite sure that they are far from having attained to the certainty of scientific progress and
may rather be said to be merely groping about in the dark. In these circumstances we shall render an
important service to reason if we succeed in simply indicating the path along which it must travel, in order to
arrive at any results even if it should be found necessary to abandon many of those aims which, without
reflection, have been proposed for its attainment.
That logic has advanced in this sure course, even from the earliest times, is apparent from the fact that, since
Aristotle, it has been unable to advance a step and, thus, to all appearance has reached its completion. For, if
some of the moderns have thought to enlarge its domain by introducing psychological discussions on the
mental faculties, such as imagination and wit, metaphysical, discussions on the origin of knowledge and the
different kinds of certitude, according to the difference of the objects (idealism, scepticism, and so on), or
anthropological discussions on prejudices, their causes and remedies: this attempt, on the part of these
authors, only shows their ignorance of the peculiar nature of logical science. We do not enlarge but disfigure
the sciences when we lose sight of their respective limits and allow them to run into one another. Now logic
is enclosed within limits which admit of perfectly clear definition; it is a science which has for its object
nothing but the exposition and proof of the formal laws of all thought, whether it be a priori or empirical,
whatever be its origin or its object, and whatever the difficulties natural or accidental which it encounters
in the human mind.
The early success of logic must be attributed exclusively to the narrowness of its field, in which abstraction
may, or rather must, be made of all the objects of cognition with their characteristic distinctions, and in which
the understanding has only to deal with itself and with its own forms. It is, obviously, a much more difficult
task for reason to strike into the sure path of science, where it has to deal not simply with itself, but with
objects external to itself. Hence, logic is properly only a propaedeutic forms, as it were, the vestibule of the
sciences; and while it is necessary to enable us to form a correct judgement with regard to the various
branches of knowledge, still the acquisition of real, substantive knowledge is to be sought only in the
sciences properly so called, that is, in the objective sciences.
Now these sciences, if they can be termed rational at all, must contain elements of a priori cognition, and this
cognition may stand in a twofold relation to its object. Either it may have to determine the conception of the
object which must be supplied extraneously, or it may have to establish its reality. The former is theoretical,
the latter practical, rational cognition. In both, the pure or a priori element must be treated first, and must be
carefully distinguished from that which is supplied from other sources. Any other method can only lead to
irremediable confusion.
Mathematics and physics are the two theoretical sciences which have to determine their objects a priori. The
former is purely a priori, the latter is partially so, but is also dependent on other sources of cognition.
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 6
Page No 11
In the earliest times of which history affords us any record, mathematics had already entered on the sure
course of science, among that wonderful nation, the Greeks. Still it is not to be supposed that it was as easy
for this science to strike into, or rather to construct for itself, that royal road, as it was for logic, in which
reason has only to deal with itself. On the contrary, I believe that it must have remained long chiefly among
the Egyptians in the stage of blind groping after its true aims and destination, and that it was revolutionized
by the happy idea of one man, who struck out and determined for all time the path which this science must
follow, and which admits of an indefinite advancement. The history of this intellectual revolution much
more important in its results than the discovery of the passage round the celebrated Cape of Good Hope and
of its author, has not been preserved. But Diogenes Laertius, in naming the supposed discoverer of some of
the simplest elements of geometrical demonstration elements which, according to the ordinary opinion, do
not even require to be proved makes it apparent that the change introduced by the first indication of this new
path, must have seemed of the utmost importance to the mathematicians of that age, and it has thus been
secured against the chance of oblivion. A new light must have flashed on the mind of the first man (Thales, or
whatever may have been his name) who demonstrated the properties of the isosceles triangle. For he found
that it was not sufficient to meditate on the figure, as it lay before his eyes, or the conception of it, as it
existed in his mind, and thus endeavour to get at the knowledge of its properties, but that it was necessary to
produce these properties, as it were, by a positive a priori construction; and that, in order to arrive with
certainty at a priori cognition, he must not attribute to the object any other properties than those which
necessarily followed from that which he had himself, in accordance with his conception, placed in the object.
A much longer period elapsed before physics entered on the highway of science. For it is only about a
century and a half since the wise Bacon gave a new direction to physical studies, or rather as others were
already on the right track imparted fresh vigour to the pursuit of this new direction. Here, too, as in the case
of mathematics, we find evidence of a rapid intellectual revolution. In the remarks which follow I shall
confine myself to the empirical side of natural science.
When Galilei experimented with balls of a definite weight on the inclined plane, when Torricelli caused the
air to sustain a weight which he had calculated beforehand to be equal to that of a definite column of water,
or when Stahl, at a later period, converted metals into lime, and reconverted lime into metal, by the addition
and subtraction of certain elements;* a light broke upon all natural philosophers. They learned that reason
only perceives that which it produces after its own design; that it must not be content to follow, as it were, in
the leadingstrings of nature, but must proceed in advance with principles of judgement according to
unvarying laws, and compel nature to reply its questions. For accidental observations, made according to no
preconceived plan, cannot be united under a necessary law. But it is this that reason seeks for and requires. It
is only the principles of reason which can give to concordant phenomena the validity of laws, and it is only
when experiment is directed by these rational principles that it can have any real utility. Reason must
approach nature with the view, indeed, of receiving information from it, not, however, in the character of a
pupil, who listens to all that his master chooses to tell him, but in that of a judge, who compels the witnesses
to reply to those questions which he himself thinks fit to propose. To this single idea must the revolution be
ascribed, by which, after groping in the dark for so many centuries, natural science was at length conducted
into the path of certain progress.
*I do not here follow with exactness the history of the experimental method, of which, indeed, the first steps
are involved in some obscurity.
We come now to metaphysics, a purely speculative science, which occupies a completely isolated position
and is entirely independent of the teachings of experience. It deals with mere conceptions not, like
mathematics, with conceptions applied to intuition and in it, reason is the pupil of itself alone. It is the oldest
of the sciences, and would still survive, even if all the rest were swallowed up in the abyss of an
alldestroying barbarism. But it has not yet had the good fortune to attain to the sure scientific method. This
will be apparent; if we apply the tests which we proposed at the outset. We find that reason perpetually comes
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 7
Page No 12
to a stand, when it attempts to gain a priori the perception even of those laws which the most common
experience confirms. We find it compelled to retrace its steps in innumerable instances, and to abandon the
path on which it had entered, because this does not lead to the desired result. We find, too, that those who are
engaged in metaphysical pursuits are far from being able to agree among themselves, but that, on the
contrary, this science appears to furnish an arena specially adapted for the display of skill or the exercise of
strength in mockcontests a field in which no combatant ever yet succeeded in gaining an inch of ground, in
which, at least, no victory was ever yet crowned with permanent possession.
This leads us to inquire why it is that, in metaphysics, the sure path of science has not hitherto been found.
Shall we suppose that it is impossible to discover it? Why then should nature have visited our reason with
restless aspirations after it, as if it were one of our weightiest concerns? Nay, more, how little cause should
we have to place confidence in our reason, if it abandons us in a matter about which, most of all, we desire to
know the truth and not only so, but even allures us to the pursuit of vain phantoms, only to betray us in the
end? Or, if the path has only hitherto been missed, what indications do we possess to guide us in a renewed
investigation, and to enable us to hope for greater success than has fallen to the lot of our predecessors?
It appears to me that the examples of mathematics and natural philosophy, which, as we have seen, were
brought into their present condition by a sudden revolution, are sufficiently remarkable to fix our attention on
the essential circumstances of the change which has proved so advantageous to them, and to induce us to
make the experiment of imitating them, so far as the analogy which, as rational sciences, they bear to
metaphysics may permit. It has hitherto been assumed that our cognition must conform to the objects; but all
attempts to ascertain anything about these objects a priori, by means of conceptions, and thus to extend the
range of our knowledge, have been rendered abortive by this assumption. Let us then make the experiment
whether we may not be more successful in metaphysics, if we assume that the objects must conform to our
cognition. This appears, at all events, to accord better with the possibility of our gaining the end we have in
view, that is to say, of arriving at the cognition of objects a priori, of determining something with respect to
these objects, before they are given to us. We here propose to do just what Copernicus did in attempting to
explain the celestial movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming that all the
heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator, he reversed the process, and tried the experiment of assuming
that the spectator revolved, while the stars remained at rest. We may make the same experiment with regard
to the intuition of objects. If the intuition must conform to the nature of the objects, I do not see how we can
know anything of them a priori. If, on the other hand, the object conforms to the nature of our faculty of
intuition, I can then easily conceive the possibility of such an a priori knowledge. Now as I cannot rest in the
mere intuitions, but if they are to become cognitions must refer them, as representations, to something, as
object, and must determine the latter by means of the former, here again there are two courses open to me.
Either, first, I may assume that the conceptions, by which I effect this determination, conform to the object
and in this case I am reduced to the same perplexity as before; or secondly, I may assume that the objects, or,
which is the same thing, that experience, in which alone as given objects they are cognized, conform to my
conceptions and then I am at no loss how to proceed. For experience itself is a mode of cognition which
requires understanding. Before objects, are given to me, that is, a priori, I must presuppose in myself laws of
the understanding which are expressed in conceptions a priori. To these conceptions, then, all the objects of
experience must necessarily conform. Now there are objects which reason thinks, and that necessarily, but
which cannot be given in experience, or, at least, cannot be given so as reason thinks them. The attempt to
think these objects will hereafter furnish an excellent test of the new method of thought which we have
adopted, and which is based on the principle that we only cognize in things a priori that which we ourselves
place in them.*
*This method, accordingly, which we have borrowed from the natural philosopher, consists in seeking for the
elements of pure reason in that which admits of confirmation or refutation by experiment. Now the
propositions of pure reason, especially when they transcend the limits of possible experience, do not admit of
our making any experiment with their objects, as in natural science. Hence, with regard to those conceptions
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 8
Page No 13
and principles which we assume a priori, our only course ill be to view them from two different sides. We
must regard one and the same conception, on the one hand, in relation to experience as an object of the senses
and of the understanding, on the other hand, in relation to reason, isolated and transcending the limits of
experience, as an object of mere thought. Now if we find that, when we regard things from this double point
of view, the result is in harmony with the principle of pure reason, but that, when we regard them from a
single point of view, reason is involved in selfcontradiction, then the experiment will establish the
correctness of this distinction.
This attempt succeeds as well as we could desire, and promises to metaphysics, in its first part that is, where
it is occupied with conceptions a priori, of which the corresponding objects may be given in experience the
certain course of science. For by this new method we are enabled perfectly to explain the possibility of a
priori cognition, and, what is more, to demonstrate satisfactorily the laws which lie a priori at the foundation
of nature, as the sum of the objects of experience neither of which was possible according to the procedure
hitherto followed. But from this deduction of the faculty of a priori cognition in the first part of metaphysics,
we derive a surprising result, and one which, to all appearance, militates against the great end of metaphysics,
as treated in the second part. For we come to the conclusion that our faculty of cognition is unable to
transcend the limits of possible experience; and yet this is precisely the most essential object of this science.
The estimate of our rational cognition a priori at which we arrive is that it has only to do with phenomena,
and that things in themselves, while possessing a real existence, lie beyond its sphere. Here we are enabled to
put the justice of this estimate to the test. For that which of necessity impels us to transcend the limits of
experience and of all phenomena is the unconditioned, which reason absolutely requires in things as they are
in themselves, in order to complete the series of conditions. Now, if it appears that when, on the one hand, we
assume that our cognition conforms to its objects as things in themselves, the unconditioned cannot be
thought without contradiction, and that when, on the other hand, we assume that our representation of things
as they are given to us, does not conform to these things as they are in themselves, but that these objects, as
phenomena, conform to our mode of representation, the contradiction disappears: we shall then be convinced
of the truth of that which we began by assuming for the sake of experiment; we may look upon it as
established that the unconditioned does not lie in things as we know them, or as they are given to us, but in
things as they are in themselves, beyond the range of our cognition.*
*This experiment of pure reason has a great similarity to that of the chemists, which they term the experiment
of reduction, or, more usually, the synthetic process. The analysis of the metaphysician separates pure
cognition a priori into two heterogeneous elements, viz., the cognition of things as phenomena, and of things
in themselves. Dialectic combines these again into harmony with the necessary rational idea of the
unconditioned, and finds that this harmony never results except through the above distinction, which is,
therefore, concluded to be just.
But, after we have thus denied the power of speculative reason to make any progress in the sphere of the
supersensible, it still remains for our consideration whether data do not exist in practical cognition which may
enable us to determine the transcendent conception of the unconditioned, to rise beyond the limits of all
possible experience from a practical point of view, and thus to satisfy the great ends of metaphysics.
Speculative reason has thus, at least, made room for such an extension of our knowledge: and, if it must leave
this space vacant, still it does not rob us of the liberty to fill it up, if we can, by means of practical data nay,
it even challenges us to make the attempt.*
*So the central laws of the movements of the heavenly bodies established the truth of that which Copernicus,
first, assumed only as a hypothesis, and, at the same time, brought to light that invisible force (Newtonian
attraction) which holds the universe together. The latter would have remained forever undiscovered, if
Copernicus had not ventured on the experiment contrary to the senses but still just of looking for the
observed movements not in the heavenly bodies, but in the spectator. In this Preface I treat the new
metaphysical method as a hypothesis with the view of rendering apparent the first attempts at such a change
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 9
Page No 14
of method, which are always hypothetical. But in the Critique itself it will be demonstrated, not
hypothetically, but apodeictically, from the nature of our representations of space and time. and from the
elementary conceptions of the understanding.
This attempt to introduce a complete revolution in the procedure of metaphysics, after the example of the
geometricians and natural philosophers, constitutes the aim of the Critique of Pure Speculative Reason. It is a
treatise on the method to be followed, not a system of the science itself. But, at the same time, it marks out
and defines both the external boundaries and the internal structure of this science. For pure speculative reason
has this peculiarity, that, in choosing the various objects of thought, it is able to define the limits of its own
faculties, and even to give a complete enumeration of the possible modes of proposing problems to itself, and
thus to sketch out the entire system of metaphysics. For, on the one hand, in cognition a priori, nothing must
be attributed to the objects but what the thinking subject derives from itself; and, on the other hand, reason is,
in regard to the principles of cognition, a perfectly distinct, independent unity, in which, as in an organized
body, every member exists for the sake of the others, and all for the sake of each, so that no principle can be
viewed, with safety, in one relationship, unless it is, at the same time, viewed in relation to the total use of
pure reason. Hence, too, metaphysics has this singular advantage an advantage which falls to the lot of no
other science which has to do with objects that, if once it is conducted into the sure path of science, by
means of this criticism, it can then take in the whole sphere of its cognitions, and can thus complete its work,
and leave it for the use of posterity, as a capital which can never receive fresh accessions. For metaphysics
has to deal only with principles and with the limitations of its own employment as determined by these
principles. To this perfection it is, therefore, bound, as the fundamental science, to attain, and to it the maxim
may justly be applied:
Nil actum reputans, si quid superesset agendum.*
*"He considered nothing done, so long as anything remained to be done."
But, it will be asked, what kind of a treasure is this that we propose to bequeath to posterity? What is the real
value of this system of metaphysics, purified by criticism, and thereby reduced to a permanent condition? A
cursory view of the present work will lead to the supposition that its use is merely negative, that it only serves
to warn us against venturing, with speculative reason, beyond the limits of experience. This is, in fact, its
primary use. But this, at once, assumes a positive value, when we observe that the principles with which
speculative reason endeavours to transcend its limits lead inevitably, not to the extension, but to the
contraction of the use of reason, inasmuch as they threaten to extend the limits of sensibility, which is their
proper sphere, over the entire realm of thought and, thus, to supplant the pure (practical) use of reason. So far,
then, as this criticism is occupied in confining speculative reason within its proper bounds, it is only negative;
but, inasmuch as it thereby, at the same time, removes an obstacle which impedes and even threatens to
destroy the use of practical reason, it possesses a positive and very important value. In order to admit this, we
have only to be convinced that there is an absolutely necessary use of pure reason the moral use in which it
inevitably transcends the limits of sensibility, without the aid of speculation, requiring only to be insured
against the effects of a speculation which would involve it in contradiction with itself. To deny the positive
advantage of the service which this criticism renders us would be as absurd as. to maintain that the system of
police is productive of no positive benefit, since its main business is to prevent the violence which citizen has
to apprehend from citizen, that so each may pursue his vocation in peace and security. That space and time
are only forms of sensible intuition, and hence are only conditions of the existence of things as phenomena;
that, moreover, we have no conceptions of the understanding, and, consequently, no elements for the
cognition of things, except in so far as a corresponding intuition can be given to these conceptions; that,
accordingly, we can have no cognition of an object, as a thing in itself, but only as an object of sensible
intuition, that is, as phenomenon all this is proved in the analytical part of the Critique; and from this the
limitation of all possible speculative cognition to the mere objects of experience, follows as a necessary
result. At the same time, it must be carefully borne in mind that, while we surrender the power of cognizing,
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 10
Page No 15
we still reserve the power of thinking objects, as things in themselves.* For, otherwise, we should require to
affirm the existence of an appearance, without something that appears which would be absurd. Now let us
suppose, for a moment, that we had not undertaken this criticism and, accordingly, had not drawn the
necessary distinction between things as objects of experience and things as they are in themselves. The
principle of causality, and, by consequence, the mechanism of nature as determined by causality, would then
have absolute validity in relation to all things as efficient causes. I should then be unable to assert, with
regard to one and the same being, e.g., the human soul, that its will is free, and yet, at the same time, subject
to natural necessity, that is, not free, without falling into a palpable contradiction, for in both propositions I
should take the soul in the same signification, as a thing in general, as a thing in itself as, without previous
criticism, I could not but take it. Suppose now, on the other hand, that we have undertaken this criticism, and
have learnt that an object may be taken in two senses, first, as a phenomenon, secondly, as a thing in itself;
and that, according to the deduction of the conceptions of the understanding, the principle of causality has
reference only to things in the first sense. We then see how it does not involve any contradiction to assert, on
the one hand, that the will, in the phenomenal sphere in visible action is necessarily obedient to the law of
nature, and, in so far, not free; and, on the other hand, that, as belonging to a thing in itself, it is not subject to
that law, and, accordingly, is free. Now, it is true that I cannot, by means of speculative reason, and still less
by empirical observation, cognize my soul as a thing in itself and consequently, cannot cognize liberty as the
property of a being to which I ascribe effects in the world of sense. For, to do so, I must cognize this being as
existing, and yet not in time, which since I cannot support my conception by any intuition is impossible.
At the same time, while I cannot cognize, I can quite well think freedom, that is to say, my representation of
it involves at least no contradiction, if we bear in mind the critical distinction of the two modes of
representation (the sensible and the intellectual) and the consequent limitation of the conceptions of the pure
understanding and of the principles which flow from them. Suppose now that morality necessarily
presupposed liberty, in the strictest sense, as a property of our will; suppose that reason contained certain
practical, original principles a priori, which were absolutely impossible without this presupposition; and
suppose, at the same time, that speculative reason had proved that liberty was incapable of being thought at
all. It would then follow that the moral presupposition must give way to the speculative affirmation, the
opposite of which involves an obvious contradiction, and that liberty and, with it, morality must yield to the
mechanism of nature; for the negation of morality involves no contradiction, except on the presupposition of
liberty. Now morality does not require the speculative cognition of liberty; it is enough that I can think it, that
its conception involves no contradiction, that it does not interfere with the mechanism of nature. But even this
requirement we could not satisfy, if we had not learnt the twofold sense in which things may be taken; and it
is only in this way that the doctrine of morality and the doctrine of nature are confined within their proper
limits. For this result, then, we are indebted to a criticism which warns us of our unavoidable ignorance with
regard to things in themselves, and establishes the necessary limitation of our theoretical cognition to mere
phenomena.
*In order to cognize an object, I must be able to prove its possibility, either from its reality as attested by
experience, or a priori, by means of reason. But I can think what I please, provided only I do not contradict
myself; that is, provided my conception is a possible thought, though I may be unable to answer for the
existence of a corresponding object in the sum of possibilities. But something more is required before I can
attribute to such a conception objective validity, that is real possibility the other possibility being merely
logical. We are not, however, confined to theoretical sources of cognition for the means of satisfying this
additional requirement, but may derive them from practical sources.
The positive value of the critical principles of pure reason in relation to the conception of God and of the
simple nature of the soul, admits of a similar exemplification; but on this point I shall not dwell. I cannot
even make the assumption as the practical interests of morality require of God, freedom, and immortality,
if I do not deprive speculative reason of its pretensions to transcendent insight. For to arrive at these, it must
make use of principles which, in fact, extend only to the objects of possible experience, and which cannot be
applied to objects beyond this sphere without converting them into phenomena, and thus rendering the
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 11
Page No 16
practical extension of pure reason impossible. I must, therefore, abolish knowledge, to make room for belief.
The dogmatism of metaphysics, that is, the presumption that it is possible to advance in metaphysics without
previous criticism, is the true source of the unbelief (always dogmatic) which militates against morality.
Thus, while it may be no very difficult task to bequeath a legacy to posterity, in the shape of a system of
metaphysics constructed in accordance with the Critique of Pure Reason, still the value of such a bequest is
not to be depreciated. It will render an important service to reason, by substituting the certainty of scientific
method for that random groping after results without the guidance of principles, which has hitherto
characterized the pursuit of metaphysical studies. It will render an important service to the inquiring mind of
youth, by leading the student to apply his powers to the cultivation of. genuine science, instead of wasting
them, as at present, on speculations which can never lead to any result, or on the idle attempt to invent new
ideas and opinions. But, above all, it will confer an inestimable benefit on morality and religion, by showing
that all the objections urged against them may be silenced for ever by the Socratic method, that is to say, by
proving the ignorance of the objector. For, as the world has never been, and, no doubt, never will be without a
system of metaphysics of one kind or another, it is the highest and weightiest concern of philosophy to render
it powerless for harm, by closing up the sources of error.
This important change in the field of the sciences, this loss of its fancied possessions, to which speculative
reason must submit, does not prove in any way detrimental to the general interests of humanity. The
advantages which the world has derived from the teachings of pure reason are not at all impaired. The loss
falls, in its whole extent, on the monopoly of the schools, but does not in the slightest degree touch the
interests of mankind. I appeal to the most obstinate dogmatist, whether the proof of the continued existence of
the soul after death, derived from the simplicity of its substance; of the freedom of the will in opposition to
the general mechanism of nature, drawn from the subtle but impotent distinction of subjective and objective
practical necessity; or of the existence of God, deduced from the conception of an ens realissimum the
contingency of the changeable, and the necessity of a prime mover, has ever been able to pass beyond the
limits of the schools, to penetrate the public mind, or to exercise the slightest influence on its convictions. It
must be admitted that this has not been the case and that, owing to the unfitness of the common
understanding for such subtle speculations, it can never be expected to take place. On the contrary, it is plain
that the hope of a future life arises from the feeling, which exists in the breast of every man, that the temporal
is inadequate to meet and satisfy the demands of his nature. In like manner, it cannot be doubted that the clear
exhibition of duties in opposition to all the claims of inclination, gives rise to the consciousness of freedom,
and that the glorious order, beauty, and providential care, everywhere displayed in nature, give rise to the
belief in a wise and great Author of the Universe. Such is the genesis of these general convictions of
mankind, so far as they depend on rational grounds; and this public property not only remains undisturbed,
but is even raised to greater importance, by the doctrine that the schools have no right to arrogate to
themselves a more profound insight into a matter of general human concernment than that to which the great
mass of men, ever held by us in the highest estimation, can without difficulty attain, and that the schools
should, therefore, confine themselves to the elaboration of these universally comprehensible and, from a
moral point of view, amply satisfactory proofs. The change, therefore, affects only the arrogant pretensions of
the schools, which would gladly retain, in their own exclusive possession, the key to the truths which they
impart to the public.
Quod mecum nescit, solus vult scire videri.
At the same time it does not deprive the speculative philosopher of his just title to be the sole depositor of a
science which benefits the public without its knowledge I mean, the Critique of Pure Reason. This can never
become popular and, indeed, has no occasion to be so; for finespun arguments in favour of useful truths make
just as little impression on the public mind as the equally subtle objections brought against these truths. On
the other hand, since both inevitably force themselves on every man who rises to the height of speculation, it
becomes the manifest duty of the schools to enter upon a thorough investigation of the rights of speculative
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 12
Page No 17
reason and, thus, to prevent the scandal which metaphysical controversies are sure, sooner or later, to cause
even to the masses. It is only by criticism that metaphysicians (and, as such, theologians too) can be saved
from these controversies and from the consequent perversion of their doctrines. Criticism alone can strike a
blow at the root of materialism, fatalism, atheism, freethinking, fanaticism, and superstition, which are
universally injurious as well as of idealism and scepticism, which are dangerous to the schools, but can
scarcely pass over to the public. If governments think proper to interfere with the affairs of the learned, it
would be more consistent with a wise regard for the interests of science, as well as for those of society, to
favour a criticism of this kind, by which alone the labours of reason can be established on a firm basis, than to
support the ridiculous despotism of the schools, which raise a loud cry of danger to the public over the
destruction of cobwebs, of which the public has never taken any notice, and the loss of which, therefore, it
can never feel.
This critical science is not opposed to the dogmatic procedure of reason in pure cognition; for pure cognition
must always be dogmatic, that is, must rest on strict demonstration from sure principles a priori but to
dogmatism, that is, to the presumption that it is possible to make any progress with a pure cognition, derived
from (philosophical) conceptions, according to the principles which reason has long been in the habit of
employing without first inquiring in what way and by what right reason has come into the possession of
these principles. Dogmatism is thus the dogmatic procedure of pure reason without previous criticism of its
own powers, and in opposing this procedure, we must not be supposed to lend any countenance to that
loquacious shallowness which arrogates to itself the name of popularity, nor yet to scepticism, which makes
short work with the whole science of metaphysics. On the contrary, our criticism is the necessary preparation
for a thoroughly scientific system of metaphysics which must perform its task entirely a priori, to the
complete satisfaction of speculative reason, and must, therefore, be treated, not popularly, but scholastically.
In carrying out the plan which the Critique prescribes, that is, in the future system of metaphysics, we must
have recourse to the strict method of the celebrated Wolf, the greatest of all dogmatic philosophers. He was
the first to point out the necessity of establishing fixed principles, of clearly defining our conceptions, and of
subjecting our demonstrations to the most severe scrutiny, instead of rashly jumping at conclusions. The
example which he set served to awaken that spirit of profound and thorough investigation which is not yet
extinct in Germany. He would have been peculiarly well fitted to give a truly scientific character to
metaphysical studies, had it occurred to him to prepare the field by a criticism of the organum, that is, of pure
reason itself. That be failed to perceive the necessity of such a procedure must be ascribed to the dogmatic
mode of thought which characterized his age, and on this point the philosophers of his time, as well as of all
previous times, have nothing to reproach each other with. Those who reject at once the method of Wolf, and
of the Critique of Pure Reason, can have no other aim but to shake off the fetters of science, to change labour
into sport, certainty into opinion, and philosophy into philodoxy.
In this second edition, I have endeavoured, as far as possible, to remove the difficulties and obscurity which,
without fault of mine perhaps, have given rise to many misconceptions even among acute thinkers. In the
propositions themselves, and in the demonstrations by which they are supported, as well as in the form and
the entire plan of the work, I have found nothing to alter; which must be attributed partly to the long
examination to which I had subjected the whole before offering it to the public and partly to the nature of the
case. For pure speculative reason is an organic structure in which there is nothing isolated or independent, but
every Single part is essential to all the rest; and hence, the slightest imperfection, whether defect or positive
error, could not fail to betray itself in use. I venture, further, to hope, that this system will maintain the same
unalterable character for the future. I am led to entertain this confidence, not by vanity, but by the evidence
which the equality of the result affords, when we proceed, first, from the simplest elements up to the
complete whole of pure reason and, and then, backwards from the whole to each part. We find that the
attempt to make the slightest alteration, in any part, leads inevitably to contradictions, not merely in this
system, but in human reason itself. At the same time, there is still much room for improvement in the
exposition of the doctrines contained in this work. In the present edition, I have endeavoured to remove
misapprehensions of the aesthetical part, especially with regard to the conception of time; to clear away the
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 13
Page No 18
obscurity which has been found in the deduction of the conceptions of the understanding; to supply the
supposed want of sufficient evidence in the demonstration of the principles of the pure understanding; and,
lastly, to obviate the misunderstanding of the paralogisms which immediately precede the rational
psychology. Beyond this point the end of the second main division of the "Transcendental Dialectic" I
have not extended my alterations,* partly from want of time, and partly because I am not aware that any
portion of the remainder has given rise to misconceptions among intelligent and impartial critics, whom I do
not here mention with that praise which is their due, but who will find that their suggestions have been
attended to in the work itself.
*The only addition, properly so called and that only in the method of proof which I have made in the
present edition, consists of a new refutation of psychological idealism, and a strict demonstration the only
one possible, as I believe of the objective reality of external intuition. However harmless idealism may be
considered although in reality it is not so in regard to the essential ends of metaphysics, it must still remain
a scandal to philosophy and to the general human reason to be obliged to assume, as an article of mere belief,
the existence of things external to ourselves (from which, yet, we derive the whole material of cognition for
the internal sense), and not to be able to oppose a satisfactory proof to any one who may call it in question.
As there is some obscurity of expression in the demonstration as it stands in the text, I propose to alter the
passage in question as follows: "But this permanent cannot be an intuition in me. For all the determining
grounds of my existence which can be found in me are representations and, as such, do themselves require a
permanent, distinct from them, which may determine my existence in relation to their changes, that is, my
existence in time, wherein they change." It may, probably, be urged in opposition to this proof that, after all, I
am only conscious immediately of that which is in me, that is, of my representation of external things, and
that, consequently, it must always remain uncertain whether anything corresponding to this representation
does or does not exist externally to me. But I am conscious, through internal experience, of my existence in
time (consequently, also, of the determinability of the former in the latter), and that is more than the simple
consciousness of my representation. It is, in fact, the same as the empirical consciousness of my existence,
which can only be determined in relation to something, which, while connected with my existence, is external
to me. This consciousness of my existence in time is, therefore, identical with the consciousness of a relation
to something external to me, and it is, therefore, experience, not fiction, sense, not imagination, which
inseparably connects the external with my internal sense. For the external sense is, in itself, the relation of
intuition to something real, external to me; and the reality of this something, as opposed to the mere
imagination of it, rests solely on its inseparable connection with internal experience as the condition of its
possibility. If with the intellectual consciousness of my existence, in the representation: I am, which
accompanies all my judgements, and all the operations of my understanding, I could, at the same time,
connect a determination of my existence by intellectual intuition, then the consciousness of a relation to
something external to me would not be necessary. But the internal intuition in which alone my existence can
be determined, though preceded by that purely intellectual consciousness, is itself sensible and attached to the
condition of time. Hence this determination of my existence, and consequently my internal experience itself,
must depend on something permanent which is not in me, which can be, therefore, only in something external
to me, to which I must look upon myself as being related. Thus the reality of the external sense is necessarily
connected with that of the internal, in order to the possibility of experience in general; that is, I am just as
certainly conscious that there are things external to me related to my sense as I am that I myself exist as
determined in time. But in order to ascertain to what given intuitions objects, external me, really correspond,
in other words, what intuitions belong to the external sense and not to imagination, I must have recourse, in
every particular case, to those rules according to which experience in general (even internal experience) is
distinguished from imagination, and which are always based on the proposition that there really is an external
experience. We may add the remark that the representation of something permanent in existence, is not the
same thing as the permanent representation; for a representation may be very variable and changing as all
our representations, even that of matter, are and yet refer to something permanent, which must, therefore, be
distinct from all my representations and external to me, the existence of which is necessarily included in the
determination of my own existence, and with it constitutes one experience an experience which would not
The Critique of Pure Reason
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787 14
Page No 19
even be possible internally, if it were not also at the same time, in part, external. To the question How? we are
no more able to reply, than we are, in general, to think the stationary in time, the coexistence of which with
the variable, produces the conception of change.
In attempting to render the exposition of my views as intelligible as possible, I have been compelled to leave
out or abridge various passages which were not essential to the completeness of the work, but which many
readers might consider useful in other respects, and might be unwilling to miss. This trifling loss, which
could not be avoided without swelling the book beyond due limits, may be supplied, at the pleasure of the
reader, by a comparison with the first edition, and will, I hope, be more than compensated for by the greater
clearness of the exposition as it now stands.
I have observed, with pleasure and thankfulness, in the pages of various reviews and treatises, that the spirit
of profound and thorough investigation is not extinct in Germany, though it may have been overborne and
silenced for a time by the fashionable tone of a licence in thinking, which gives itself the airs of genius, and
that the difficulties which beset the paths of criticism have not prevented energetic and acute thinkers from
making themselves masters of the science of pure reason to which these paths conduct a science which is
not popular, but scholastic in its character, and which alone can hope for a lasting existence or possess an
abiding value. To these deserving men, who so happily combine profundity of view with a talent for lucid
exposition a talent which I myself am not conscious of possessing I leave the task of removing any
obscurity which may still adhere to the statement of my doctrines. For, in this case, the danger is not that of
being refuted, but of being misunderstood. For my own part, I must henceforward abstain from controversy,
although I shall carefully attend to all suggestions, whether from friends or adversaries, which may be of use
in the future elaboration of the system of this propaedeutic. As, during these labours, I have advanced pretty
far in years this month I reach my sixtyfourth year it will be necessary for me to economize time, if I am to
carry out my plan of elaborating the metaphysics of nature as well as of morals, in confirmation of the
correctness of the principles established in this Critique of Pure Reason, both speculative and practical; and I
must, therefore, leave the task of clearing up the obscurities of the present work inevitable, perhaps, at the
outset as well as, the defence of the whole, to those deserving men, who have made my system their own. A
philosophical system cannot come forward armed at all points like a mathematical treatise, and hence it may
be quite possible to take objection to particular passages, while the organic structure of the system,
considered as a unity, has no danger to apprehend. But few possess the ability, and still fewer the inclination,
to take a comprehensive view of a new system. By confining the view to particular passages, taking these out
of their connection and comparing them with one another, it is easy to pick out apparent contradictions,
especially in a work written with any freedom of style. These contradictions place the work in an
unfavourable light in the eyes of those who rely on the judgement of others, but are easily reconciled by those
who have mastered the idea of the whole. If a theory possesses stability in itself, the action and reaction
which seemed at first to threaten its existence serve only, in the course of time, to smooth down any
superficial roughness or inequality, and if men of insight, impartiality, and truly popular gifts, turn their
attention to it to secure to it, in a short time, the requisite elegance also.
Konigsberg, April 1787.
INTRODUCTION.
I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge
That all our knowledge begins with experience there can be no doubt. For how is it possible that the faculty
of cognition should be awakened into exercise otherwise than by means of objects which affect our senses,
and partly of themselves produce representations, partly rouse our powers of understanding into activity, to
compare to connect, or to separate these, and so to convert the raw material of our sensuous impressions into
The Critique of Pure Reason
INTRODUCTION. 15
Page No 20
a knowledge of objects, which is called experience? In respect of time, therefore, no knowledge of ours is
antecedent to experience, but begins with it.
But, though all our knowledge begins with experience, it by no means follows that all arises out of
experience. For, on the contrary, it is quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound of that
which we receive through impressions, and that which the faculty of cognition supplies from itself (sensuous
impressions giving merely the occasion), an addition which we cannot distinguish from the original element
given by sense, till long practice has made us attentive to, and skilful in separating it. It is, therefore, a
question which requires close investigation, and not to be answered at first sight, whether there exists a
knowledge altogether independent of experience, and even of all sensuous impressions? Knowledge of this
kind is called a priori, in contradistinction to empirical knowledge, which has its sources a posteriori, that is,
in experience.
But the expression, "a priori," is not as yet definite enough adequately to indicate the whole meaning of the
question above started. For, in speaking of knowledge which has its sources in experience, we are wont to
say, that this or that may be known a priori, because we do not derive this knowledge immediately from
experience, but from a general rule, which, however, we have itself borrowed from experience. Thus, if a
man undermined his house, we say, "he might know a priori that it would have fallen;" that is, he needed not
to have waited for the experience that it did actually fall. But still, a priori, he could not know even this much.
For, that bodies are heavy, and, consequently, that they fall when their supports are taken away, must have
been known to him previously, by means of experience.
By the term "knowledge a priori," therefore, we shall in the sequel understand, not such as is independent of
this or that kind of experience, but such as is absolutely so of all experience. Opposed to this is empirical
knowledge, or that which is possible only a posteriori, that is, through experience. Knowledge a priori is
either pure or impure. Pure knowledge a priori is that with which no empirical element is mixed up. For
example, the proposition, "Every change has a cause," is a proposition a priori, but impure, because change is
a conception which can only be derived from experience.
II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in
Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori".
The question now is as to a criterion, by which we may securely distinguish a pure from an empirical
cognition. Experience no doubt teaches us that this or that object is constituted in such and such a manner,
but not that it could not possibly exist otherwise. Now, in the first place, if we have a proposition which
contains the idea of necessity in its very conception, it is a if, moreover, it is not derived from any other
proposition, unless from one equally involving the idea of necessity, it is absolutely priori. Secondly, an
empirical judgement never exhibits strict and absolute, but only assumed and comparative universality (by
induction); therefore, the most we can say is so far as we have hitherto observed, there is no exception to
this or that rule. If, on the other hand, a judgement carries with it strict and absolute universality, that is,
admits of no possible exception, it is not derived from experience, but is valid absolutely a priori.
Empirical universality is, therefore, only an arbitrary extension of validity, from that which may be
predicated of a proposition valid in most cases, to that which is asserted of a proposition which holds good in
all; as, for example, in the affirmation, "All bodies are heavy." When, on the contrary, strict universality
characterizes a judgement, it necessarily indicates another peculiar source of knowledge, namely, a faculty of
cognition a priori. Necessity and strict universality, therefore, are infallible tests for distinguishing pure from
empirical knowledge, and are inseparably connected with each other. But as in the use of these criteria the
empirical limitation is sometimes more easily detected than the contingency of the judgement, or the
unlimited universality which we attach to a judgement is often a more convincing proof than its necessity, it
The Critique of Pure Reason
II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori". 16
Page No 21
may be advisable to use the criteria separately, each being by itself infallible.
Now, that in the sphere of human cognition we have judgements which are necessary, and in the strictest
sense universal, consequently pure a priori, it will be an easy matter to show. If we desire an example from
the sciences, we need only take any proposition in mathematics. If we cast our eyes upon the commonest
operations of the understanding, the proposition, "Every change must have a cause," will amply serve our
purpose. In the latter case, indeed, the conception of a cause so plainly involves the conception of a necessity
of connection with an effect, and of a strict universality of the law, that the very notion of a cause would
entirely disappear, were we to derive it, like Hume, from a frequent association of what happens with that
which precedes; and the habit thence originating of connecting representations the necessity inherent in the
judgement being therefore merely subjective. Besides, without seeking for such examples of principles
existing a priori in cognition, we might easily show that such principles are the indispensable basis of the
possibility of experience itself, and consequently prove their existence a priori. For whence could our
experience itself acquire certainty, if all the rules on which it depends were themselves empirical, and
consequently fortuitous? No one, therefore, can admit the validity of the use of such rules as first principles.
But, for the present, we may content ourselves with having established the fact, that we do possess and
exercise a faculty of pure a priori cognition; and, secondly, with having pointed out the proper tests of such
cognition, namely, universality and necessity.
Not only in judgements, however, but even in conceptions, is an a priori origin manifest. For example, if we
take away by degrees from our conceptions of a body all that can be referred to mere sensuous experience
colour, hardness or softness, weight, even impenetrability the body will then vanish; but the space which it
occupied still remains, and this it is utterly impossible to annihilate in thought. Again, if we take away, in like
manner, from our empirical conception of any object, corporeal or incorporeal, all properties which mere
experience has taught us to connect with it, still we cannot think away those through which we cogitate it as
substance, or adhering to substance, although our conception of substance is more determined than that of an
object. Compelled, therefore, by that necessity with which the conception of substance forces itself upon us,
we must confess that it has its seat in our faculty of cognition a priori.
III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the
Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human Knowledge "a priori"
Of far more importance than all that has been above said, is the consideration that certain of our cognitions
rise completely above the sphere of all possible experience, and by means of conceptions, to which there
exists in the whole extent of experience no corresponding object, seem to extend the range of our judgements
beyond its bounds. And just in this transcendental or supersensible sphere, where experience affords us
neither instruction nor guidance, lie the investigations of reason, which, on account of their importance, we
consider far preferable to, and as having a far more elevated aim than, all that the understanding can achieve
within the sphere of sensuous phenomena. So high a value do we set upon these investigations, that even at
the risk of error, we persist in following them out, and permit neither doubt nor disregard nor indifference to
restrain us from the pursuit. These unavoidable problems of mere pure reason are God, freedom (of will), and
immortality. The science which, with all its preliminaries, has for its especial object the solution of these
problems is named metaphysics a science which is at the very outset dogmatical, that is, it confidently takes
upon itself the execution of this task without any previous investigation of the ability or inability of reason for
such an undertaking.
Now the safe ground of experience being thus abandoned, it seems nevertheless natural that we should
hesitate to erect a building with the cognitions we possess, without knowing whence they come, and on the
strength of principles, the origin of which is undiscovered. Instead of thus trying to build without a
foundation, it is rather to be expected that we should long ago have put the question, how the understanding
The Critique of Pure Reason
III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human Knowledge "a priori" 17
Page No 22
can arrive at these a priori cognitions, and what is the extent, validity, and worth which they may possess?
We say, "This is natural enough," meaning by the word natural, that which is consistent with a just and
reasonable way of thinking; but if we understand by the term, that. which usually happens, nothing indeed
could be more natural and more comprehensible than that this investigation should be left long unattempted.
For one part of our pure knowledge, the science of mathematics, has been long firmly established, and thus
leads us to form flattering expectations with regard to others, though these may be of quite a different nature.
Besides, when we get beyond the bounds of experience, we are of course safe from opposition in that quarter;
and the charm of widening the range of our knowledge is so great that, unless we are brought to a standstill
by some evident contradiction, we hurry on undoubtingly in our course. This, however, may be avoided, if
we are sufficiently cautious in the construction of our fictions, which are not the less fictions on that account.
Mathematical science affords us a brilliant example, how far, independently of all experience, we may carry
our a priori knowledge. It is true that the mathematician occupies himself with objects and cognitions only in
so far as they can be represented by means of intuition. But this circumstance is easily overlooked, because
the said intuition can itself be given a priori, and therefore is hardly to be distinguished from a mere pure
conception. Deceived by such a proof of the power of reason, we can perceive no limits to the extension of
our knowledge. The light dove cleaving in free flight the thin air, whose resistance it feels, might imagine that
her movements would be far more free and rapid in airless space. just in the same way did Plato, abandoning
the world of sense because of the narrow limits it sets to the understanding, venture upon the wings of ideas
beyond it, into the void space of pure intellect. He did not reflect that he made no real progress by all his
efforts; for he met with no resistance which might serve him for a support, as it were, whereon to rest, and on
which he might apply his powers, in order to let the intellect acquire momentum for its progress. It is, indeed,
the common fate of human reason in speculation, to finish the imposing edifice of thought as rapidly as
possible, and then for the first time to begin to examine whether the foundation is a solid one or no. Arrived
at this point, all sorts of excuses are sought after, in order to console us for its want of stability, or rather,
indeed, to enable Us to dispense altogether with so late and dangerous an investigation. But what frees us
during the process of building from all apprehension or suspicion, and flatters us into the belief of its solidity,
is this. A great part, perhaps the greatest part, of the business of our reason consists in the analysation of the
conceptions which we already possess of objects. By this means we gain a multitude of cognitions, which
although really nothing more than elucidations or explanations of that which (though in a confused manner)
was already thought in our conceptions, are, at least in respect of their form, prized as new introspections;
whilst, so far as regards their matter or content, we have really made no addition to our conceptions, but only
disinvolved them. But as this process does furnish a real priori knowledge, which has a sure progress and
useful results, reason, deceived by this, slips in, without being itself aware of it, assertions of a quite different
kind; in which, to given conceptions it adds others, a priori indeed, but entirely foreign to them, without our
knowing how it arrives at these, and, indeed, without such a question ever suggesting itself. I shall therefore
at once proceed to examine the difference between these two modes of knowledge.
IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements.
In all judgements wherein the relation of a subject to the predicate is cogitated (I mention affirmative
judgements only here; the application to negative will be very easy), this relation is possible in two different
ways. Either the predicate B belongs to the subject A, as somewhat which is contained (though covertly) in
the conception A; or the predicate B lies completely out of the conception A, although it stands in connection
with it. In the first instance, I term the judgement analytical, in the second, synthetical. Analytical judgements
(affirmative) are therefore those in which the connection of the predicate with the subject is cogitated through
identity; those in which this connection is cogitated without identity, are called synthetical judgements. The
former may be called explicative, the latter augmentative judgements; because the former add in the predicate
nothing to the conception of the subject, but only analyse it into its constituent conceptions, which were
thought already in the subject, although in a confused manner; the latter add to our conceptions of the subject
a predicate which was not contained in it, and which no analysis could ever have discovered therein. For
The Critique of Pure Reason
IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements. 18
Page No 23
example, when I say, "All bodies are extended," this is an analytical judgement. For I need not go beyond the
conception of body in order to find extension connected with it, but merely analyse the conception, that is,
become conscious of the manifold properties which I think in that conception, in order to discover this
predicate in it: it is therefore an analytical judgement. On the other hand, when I say, "All bodies are heavy,"
the predicate is something totally different from that which I think in the mere conception of a body. By the
addition of such a predicate, therefore, it becomes a synthetical judgement.
Judgements of experience, as such, are always synthetical. For it would be absurd to think of grounding an
analytical judgement on experience, because in forming such a judgement I need not go out of the sphere of
my conceptions, and therefore recourse to the testimony of experience is quite unnecessary. That "bodies are
extended" is not an empirical judgement, but a proposition which stands firm a priori. For before addressing
myself to experience, I already have in my conception all the requisite conditions for the judgement, and I
have only to extract the predicate from the conception, according to the principle of contradiction, and
thereby at the same time become conscious of the necessity of the judgement, a necessity which I could never
learn from experience. On the other hand, though at first I do not at all include the predicate of weight in my
conception of body in general, that conception still indicates an object of experience, a part of the totality of
experience, to which I can still add other parts; and this I do when I recognize by observation that bodies are
heavy. I can cognize beforehand by analysis the conception of body through the characteristics of extension,
impenetrability, shape, etc., all which are cogitated in this conception. But now I extend my knowledge, and
looking back on experience from which I had derived this conception of body, I find weight at all times
connected with the above characteristics, and therefore I synthetically add to my conceptions this as a
predicate, and say, "All bodies are heavy." Thus it is experience upon which rests the possibility of the
synthesis of the predicate of weight with the conception of body, because both conceptions, although the one
is not contained in the other, still belong to one another (only contingently, however), as parts of a whole,
namely, of experience, which is itself a synthesis of intuitions.
But to synthetical judgements a priori, such aid is entirely wanting. If I go out of and beyond the conception
A, in order to recognize another B as connected with it, what foundation have I to rest on, whereby to render
the synthesis possible? I have here no longer the advantage of looking out in the sphere of experience for
what I want. Let us take, for example, the proposition, "Everything that happens has a cause." In the
conception of "something that happens," I indeed think an existence which a certain time antecedes, and from
this I can derive analytical judgements. But the conception of a cause lies quite out of the above conception,
and indicates something entirely different from "that which happens," and is consequently not contained in
that conception. How then am I able to assert concerning the general conception "that which happens"
something entirely different from that conception, and to recognize the conception of cause although not
contained in it, yet as belonging to it, and even necessarily? what is here the unknown = X, upon which the
understanding rests when it believes it has found, out of the conception A a foreign predicate B, which it
nevertheless considers to be connected with it? It cannot be experience, because the principle adduced
annexes the two representations, cause and effect, to the representation existence, not only with universality,
which experience cannot give, but also with the expression of necessity, therefore completely a priori and
from pure conceptions. Upon such synthetical, that is augmentative propositions, depends the whole aim of
our speculative knowledge a priori; for although analytical judgements are indeed highly important and
necessary, they are so, only to arrive at that clearness of conceptions which is requisite for a sure and
extended synthesis, and this alone is a real acquisition.
V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a
priori" are contained as Principles.
1. Mathematical judgements are always synthetical. Hitherto this fact, though incontestably true and very
important in its consequences, seems to have escaped the analysts of the human mind, nay, to be in complete
The Critique of Pure Reason
V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a priori" are contained as Principles. 19
Page No 24
opposition to all their conjectures. For as it was found that mathematical conclusions all proceed according to
the principle of contradiction (which the nature of every apodeictic certainty requires), people became
persuaded that the fundamental principles of the science also were recognized and admitted in the same way.
But the notion is fallacious; for although a synthetical proposition can certainly be discerned by means of the
principle of contradiction, this is possible only when another synthetical proposition precedes, from which the
latter is deduced, but never of itself which
Before all, be it observed, that proper mathematical propositions are always judgements a priori, and not
empirical, because they carry along with them the conception of necessity, which cannot be given by
experience. If this be demurred to, it matters not; I will then limit my assertion to pure mathematics, the very
conception of which implies that it consists of knowledge altogether nonempirical and a priori.
We might, indeed at first suppose that the proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is a merely analytical proposition, following
(according to the principle of contradiction) from the conception of a sum of seven and five. But if we regard
it more narrowly, we find that our conception of the sum of seven and five contains nothing more than the
uniting of both sums into one, whereby it cannot at all be cogitated what this single number is which
embraces both. The conception of twelve is by no means obtained by merely cogitating the union of seven
and five; and we may analyse our conception of such a possible sum as long as we will, still we shall never
discover in it the notion of twelve. We must go beyond these conceptions, and have recourse to an intuition
which corresponds to one of the two our five fingers, for example, or like Segner in his Arithmetic five
points, and so by degrees, add the units contained in the five given in the intuition, to the conception of seven.
For I first take the number 7, and, for the conception of 5 calling in the aid of the fingers of my hand as
objects of intuition, I add the units, which I before took together to make up the number 5, gradually now by
means of the material image my hand, to the number 7, and by this process, I at length see the number 12
arise. That 7 should be added to 5, I have certainly cogitated in my conception of a sum = 7 + 5, but not that
this sum was equal to 12. Arithmetical propositions are therefore always synthetical, of which we may
become more clearly convinced by trying large numbers. For it will thus become quite evident that, turn and
twist our conceptions as we may, it is impossible, without having recourse to intuition, to arrive at the sum
total or product by means of the mere analysis of our conceptions. just as little is any principle of pure
geometry analytical. "A straight line between two points is the shortest," is a synthetical proposition. For my
conception of straight contains no notion of quantity, but is merely qualitative. The conception of the shortest
is therefore fore wholly an addition, and by no analysis can it be extracted from our conception of a straight
line. Intuition must therefore here lend its aid, by means of which, and thus only, our synthesis is possible.
Some few principles preposited by geometricians are, indeed, really analytical, and depend on the principle of
contradiction. They serve, however, like identical propositions, as links in the chain of method, not as
principles for example, a = a, the whole is equal to itself, or (a+b) > a, the whole is greater than its part. And
yet even these principles themselves, though they derive their validity from pure conceptions, are only
admitted in mathematics because they can be presented in intuition. What causes us here commonly to
believe that the predicate of such apodeictic judgements is already contained in our conception, and that the
judgement is therefore analytical, is merely the equivocal nature of the expression. We must join in thought a
certain predicate to a given conception, and this necessity cleaves already to the conception. But the question
is, not what we must join in thought to the given conception, but what we really think therein, though only
obscurely, and then it becomes manifest that the predicate pertains to these conceptions, necessarily indeed,
yet not as thought in the conception itself, but by virtue of an intuition, which must be added to the
conception.
2. The science of natural philosophy (physics) contains in itself synthetical judgements a priori, as principles.
I shall adduce two propositions. For instance, the proposition, "In all changes of the material world, the
quantity of matter remains unchanged"; or, that, "In all communication of motion, action and reaction must
always be equal." In both of these, not only is the necessity, and therefore their origin a priori clear, but also
The Critique of Pure Reason
V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a priori" are contained as Principles. 20
Page No 25
that they are synthetical propositions. For in the conception of matter, I do not cogitate its permanency, but
merely its presence in space, which it fills. I therefore really go out of and beyond the conception of matter, in
order to think on to it something a priori, which I did not think in it. The proposition is therefore not
analytical, but synthetical, and nevertheless conceived a priori; and so it is with regard to the other
propositions of the pure part of natural philosophy.
3. As to metaphysics, even if we look upon it merely as an attempted science, yet, from the nature of human
reason, an indispensable one, we find that it must contain synthetical propositions a priori. It is not merely the
duty of metaphysics to dissect, and thereby analytically to illustrate the conceptions which we form a priori of
things; but we seek to widen the range of our a priori knowledge. For this purpose, we must avail ourselves of
such principles as add something to the original conception something not identical with, nor contained in it,
and by means of synthetical judgements a priori, leave far behind us the limits of experience; for example, in
the proposition, "the world must have a beginning," and such like. Thus metaphysics, according to the proper
aim of the science, consists merely of synthetical propositions a priori.
VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason.
It is extremely advantageous to be able to bring a number of investigations under the formula of a single
problem. For in this manner, we not only facilitate our own labour, inasmuch as we define it clearly to
ourselves, but also render it more easy for others to decide whether we have done justice to our undertaking.
The proper problem of pure reason, then, is contained in the question: "How are synthetical judgements a
priori possible?"
That metaphysical science has hitherto remained in so vacillating a state of uncertainty and contradiction, is
only to be attributed to the fact that this great problem, and perhaps even the difference between analytical
and synthetical judgements, did not sooner suggest itself to philosophers. Upon the solution of this problem,
or upon sufficient proof of the impossibility of synthetical knowledge a priori, depends the existence or
downfall of the science of metaphysics. Among philosophers, David Hume came the nearest of all to this
problem; yet it never acquired in his mind sufficient precision, nor did he regard the question in its
universality. On the contrary, he stopped short at the synthetical proposition of the connection of an effect
with its cause (principium causalitatis), insisting that such proposition a priori was impossible. According to
his conclusions, then, all that we term metaphysical science is a mere delusion, arising from the fancied
insight of reason into that which is in truth borrowed from experience, and to which habit has given the
appearance of necessity. Against this assertion, destructive to all pure philosophy, he would have been
guarded, had he had our problem before his eyes in its universality. For he would then have perceived that,
according to his own argument, there likewise could not be any pure mathematical science, which assuredly
cannot exist without synthetical propositions a priori an absurdity from which his good understanding must
have saved him.
In the solution of the above problem is at the same time comprehended the possibility of the use of pure
reason in the foundation and construction of all sciences which contain theoretical knowledge a priori of
objects, that is to say, the answer to the following questions:
How is pure mathematical science possible?
How is pure natural science possible?
Respecting these sciences, as they do certainly exist, it may with propriety be asked, how they are possible?
for that they must be possible is shown by the fact of their really existing.* But as to metaphysics, the
miserable progress it has hitherto made, and the fact that of no one system yet brought forward, far as regards
its true aim, can it be said that this science really exists, leaves any one at liberty to doubt with reason the
very possibility of its existence.
The Critique of Pure Reason
VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason. 21
Page No 26
*As to the existence of pure natural science, or physics, perhaps many may still express doubts. But we have
only to look at the different propositions which are commonly treated of at the commencement of proper
(empirical) physical science those, for example, relating to the permanence of the same quantity of matter,
the vis inertiae, the equality of action and reaction, etc. to be soon convinced that they form a science of
pure physics (physica pura, or rationalis), which well deserves to be separately exposed as a special science,
in its whole extent, whether that be great or confined.
Yet, in a certain sense, this kind of knowledge must unquestionably be looked upon as given; in other words,
metaphysics must be considered as really existing, if not as a science, nevertheless as a natural disposition of
the human mind (metaphysica naturalis). For human reason, without any instigations imputable to the mere
vanity of great knowledge, unceasingly progresses, urged on by its own feeling of need, towards such
questions as cannot be answered by any empirical application of reason, or principles derived therefrom; and
so there has ever really existed in every man some system of metaphysics. It will always exist, so soon as
reason awakes to the exercise of its power of speculation. And now the question arises: "How is metaphysics,
as a natural disposition, possible?" In other words, how, from the nature of universal human reason, do those
questions arise which pure reason proposes to itself, and which it is impelled by its own feeling of need to
answer as well as it can?
But as in all the attempts hitherto made to answer the questions which reason is prompted by its very nature
to propose to itself, for example, whether the world had a beginning, or has existed from eternity, it has
always met with unavoidable contradictions, we must not rest satisfied with the mere natural disposition of
the mind to metaphysics, that is, with the existence of the faculty of pure reason, whence, indeed, some sort
of metaphysical system always arises; but it must be possible to arrive at certainty in regard to the question
whether we know or do not know the things of which metaphysics treats. We must be able to arrive at a
decision on the subjects of its questions, or on the ability or inability of reason to form any judgement
respecting them; and therefore either to extend with confidence the bounds of our pure reason, or to set
strictly defined and safe limits to its action. This last question, which arises out of the above universal
problem, would properly run thus: "How is metaphysics possible as a science?"
Thus, the critique of reason leads at last, naturally and necessarily, to science; and, on the other hand, the
dogmatical use of reason without criticism leads to groundless assertions, against which others equally
specious can always be set, thus ending unavoidably in scepticism.
Besides, this science cannot be of great and formidable prolixity, because it has not to do with objects of
reason, the variety of which is inexhaustible, but merely with Reason herself and her problems; problems
which arise out of her own bosom, and are not proposed to her by the nature of outward things, but by her
own nature. And when once Reason has previously become able completely to understand her own power in
regard to objects which she meets with in experience, it will be easy to determine securely the extent and
limits of her attempted application to objects beyond the confines of experience.
We may and must, therefore, regard the attempts hitherto made to establish metaphysical science
dogmatically as nonexistent. For what of analysis, that is, mere dissection of conceptions, is contained in
one or other, is not the aim of, but only a preparation for metaphysics proper, which has for its object the
extension, by means of synthesis, of our a priori knowledge. And for this purpose, mere analysis is of course
useless, because it only shows what is contained in these conceptions, but not how we arrive, a priori, at
them; and this it is her duty to show, in order to be able afterwards to determine their valid use in regard to all
objects of experience, to all knowledge in general. But little selfdenial, indeed, is needed to give up these
pretensions, seeing the undeniable, and in the dogmatic mode of procedure, inevitable contradictions of
Reason with herself, have long since ruined the reputation of every system of metaphysics that has appeared
up to this time. It will require more firmness to remain undeterred by difficulty from within, and opposition
from without, from endeavouring, by a method quite opposed to all those hitherto followed, to further the
The Critique of Pure Reason
VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason. 22
Page No 27
growth and fruitfulness of a science indispensable to human reason a science from which every branch it
has borne may be cut away, but whose roots remain indestructible.
VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a
Critique of Pure Reason.
From all that has been said, there results the idea of a particular science, which may be called the Critique of
Pure Reason. For reason is the faculty which furnishes us with the principles of knowledge a priori. Hence,
pure reason is the faculty which contains the principles of cognizing anything absolutely a priori. An organon
of pure reason would be a compendium of those principles according to which alone all pure cognitions a
priori can be obtained. The completely extended application of such an organon would afford us a system of
pure reason. As this, however, is demanding a great deal, and it is yet doubtful whether any extension of our
knowledge be here possible, or, if so, in what cases; we can regard a science of the mere criticism of pure
reason, its sources and limits, as the propaedeutic to a system of pure reason. Such a science must not be
called a doctrine, but only a critique of pure reason; and its use, in regard to speculation, would be only
negative, not to enlarge the bounds of, but to purify, our reason, and to shield it against error which alone is
no little gain. I apply the term transcendental to all knowledge which is not so much occupied with objects as
with the mode of our cognition of these objects, so far as this mode of cognition is possible a priori. A system
of such conceptions would be called transcendental philosophy. But this, again, is still beyond the bounds of
our present essay. For as such a science must contain a complete exposition not only of our synthetical a
priori, but of our analytical a priori knowledge, it is of too wide a range for our present purpose, because we
do not require to carry our analysis any farther than is necessary to understand, in their full extent, the
principles of synthesis a priori, with which alone we have to do. This investigation, which we cannot properly
call a doctrine, but only a transcendental critique, because it aims not at the enlargement, but at the correction
and guidance, of our knowledge, and is to serve as a touchstone of the worth or worthlessness of all
knowledge a priori, is the sole object of our present essay. Such a critique is consequently, as far as possible,
a preparation for an organon; and if this new organon should be found to fail, at least for a canon of pure
reason, according to which the complete system of the philosophy of pure reason, whether it extend or limit
the bounds of that reason, might one day be set forth both analytically and synthetically. For that this is
possible, nay, that such a system is not of so great extent as to preclude the hope of its ever being completed,
is evident. For we have not here to do with the nature of outward objects, which is infinite, but solely with the
mind, which judges of the nature of objects, and, again, with the mind only in respect of its cognition a priori.
And the object of our investigations, as it is not to be sought without, but, altogether within, ourselves, cannot
remain concealed, and in all probability is limited enough to be completely surveyed and fairly estimated,
according to its worth or worthlessness. Still less let the reader here expect a critique of books and systems of
pure reason; our present object is exclusively a critique of the faculty of pure reason itself. Only when we
make this critique our foundation, do we possess a pure touchstone for estimating the philosophical value of
ancient and modern writings on this subject; and without this criterion, the incompetent historian or judge
decides upon and corrects the groundless assertions of others with his own, which have themselves just as
little foundation.
Transcendental philosophy is the idea of a science, for which the Critique of Pure Reason must sketch the
whole plan architectonically, that is, from principles, with a full guarantee for the validity and stability of all
the parts which enter into the building. It is the system of all the principles of pure reason. If this Critique
itself does not assume the title of transcendental philosophy, it is only because, to be a complete system, it
ought to contain a full analysis of all human knowledge a priori. Our critique must, indeed, lay before us a
complete enumeration of all the radical conceptions which constitute the said pure knowledge. But from the
complete analysis of these conceptions themselves, as also from a complete investigation of those derived
from them, it abstains with reason; partly because it would be deviating from the end in view to occupy itself
with this analysis, since this process is not attended with the difficulty and insecurity to be found in the
The Critique of Pure Reason
VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a Critique of Pure Reason. 23
Page No 28
synthesis, to which our critique is entirely devoted, and partly because it would be inconsistent with the unity
of our plan to burden this essay with the vindication of the completeness of such an analysis and deduction,
with which, after all, we have at present nothing to do. This completeness of the analysis of these radical
conceptions, as well as of the deduction from the conceptions a priori which may be given by the analysis, we
can, however, easily attain, provided only that we are in possession of all these radical conceptions, which are
to serve as principles of the synthesis, and that in respect of this main purpose nothing is wanting.
To the Critique of Pure Reason, therefore, belongs all that constitutes transcendental philosophy; and it is the
complete idea of transcendental philosophy, but still not the science itself; because it only proceeds so far
with the analysis as is necessary to the power of judging completely of our synthetical knowledge a priori.
The principal thing we must attend to, in the division of the parts of a science like this, is that no conceptions
must enter it which contain aught empirical; in other words, that the knowledge a priori must be completely
pure. Hence, although the highest principles and fundamental conceptions of morality are certainly cognitions
a priori, yet they do not belong to transcendental philosophy; because, though they certainly do not lay the
conceptions of pain, pleasure, desires, inclinations, etc. (which are all of empirical origin), at the foundation
of its precepts, yet still into the conception of duty as an obstacle to be overcome, or as an incitement which
should not be made into a motive these empirical conceptions must necessarily enter, in the construction of
a system of pure morality. Transcendental philosophy is consequently a philosophy of the pure and merely
speculative reason. For all that is practical, so far as it contains motives, relates to feelings, and these belong
to empirical sources of cognition.
If we wish to divide this science from the universal point of view of a science in general, it ought to
comprehend, first, a Doctrine of the Elements, and, secondly, a Doctrine of the Method of pure reason. Each
of these main divisions will have its subdivisions, the separate reasons for which we cannot here
particularize. Only so much seems necessary, by way of introduction of premonition, that there are two
sources of human knowledge (which probably spring from a common, but to us unknown root), namely,
sense and understanding. By the former, objects are given to us; by the latter, thought. So far as the faculty of
sense may contain representations a priori, which form the conditions under which objects are given, in so far
it belongs to transcendental philosophy. The transcendental doctrine of sense must form the first part of our
science of elements, because the conditions under which alone the objects of human knowledge are given
must precede those under which they are thought.
I. TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS.
FIRST PART. TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC.
SS I. Introductory.
In whatsoever mode, or by whatsoever means, our knowledge may relate to objects, it is at least quite clear
that the only manner in which it immediately relates to them is by means of an intuition. To this as the
indispensable groundwork, all thought points. But an intuition can take place only in so far as the object is
given to us. This, again, is only possible, to man at least, on condition that the object affect the mind in a
certain manner. The capacity for receiving representations (receptivity) through the mode in which we are
affected by objects, objects, is called sensibility. By means of sensibility, therefore, objects are given to us,
and it alone furnishes us with intuitions; by the understanding they are thought, and from it arise conceptions.
But an thought must directly, or indirectly, by means of certain signs, relate ultimately to intuitions;
consequently, with us, to sensibility, because in no other way can an object be given to us.
The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far as we are affected by the said object, is
sensation. That sort of intuition which relates to an object by means of sensation is called an empirical
intuition. The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is called phenomenon. That which in the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS I. Introductory. 24
Page No 29
phenomenon corresponds to the sensation, I term its matter; but that which effects that the content of the
phenomenon can be arranged under certain relations, I call its form. But that in which our sensations are
merely arranged, and by which they are susceptible of assuming a certain form, cannot be itself sensation. It
is, then, the matter of all phenomena that is given to us a posteriori; the form must lie ready a priori for them
in the mind, and consequently can be regarded separately from all sensation.
I call all representations pure, in the transcendental meaning of the word, wherein nothing is met with that
belongs to sensation. And accordingly we find existing in the mind a priori, the pure form of sensuous
intuitions in general, in which all the manifold content of the phenomenal world is arranged and viewed
under certain relations. This pure form of sensibility I shall call pure intuition. Thus, if I take away from our
representation of a body all that the understanding thinks as belonging to it, as substance, force, divisibility,
etc., and also whatever belongs to sensation, as impenetrability, hardness, colour, etc.; yet there is still
something left us from this empirical intuition, namely, extension and shape. These belong to pure intuition,
which exists a priori in the mind, as a mere form of sensibility, and without any real object of the senses or
any sensation.
The science of all the principles of sensibility a priori, I call transcendental aesthetic.* There must, then, be
such a science forming the first part of the transcendental doctrine of elements, in contradistinction to that
part which contains the principles of pure thought, and which is called transcendental logic.
*The Germans are the only people who at present use this word to indicate what others call the critique of
taste. At the foundation of this term lies the disappointed hope, which the eminent analyst, Baumgarten,
conceived, of subjecting the criticism of the beautiful to principles of reason, and so of elevating its rules into
a science. But his endeavours were vain. For the said rules or criteria are, in respect to their chief sources,
merely empirical, consequently never can serve as determinate laws a priori, by which our judgement in
matters of taste is to be directed. It is rather our judgement which forms the proper test as to the correctness
of the principles. On this account it is advisable to give up the use of the term as designating the critique of
taste, and to apply it solely to that doctrine, which is true science the science of the laws of sensibility and
thus come nearer to the language and the sense of the ancients in their wellknown division of the objects of
cognition into aiotheta kai noeta, or to share it with speculative philosophy, and employ it partly in a
transcendental, partly in a psychological signification.
In the science of transcendental aesthetic accordingly, we shall first isolate sensibility or the sensuous faculty,
by separating from it all that is annexed to its perceptions by the conceptions of understanding, so that
nothing be left but empirical intuition. In the next place we shall take away from this intuition all that belongs
to sensation, so that nothing may remain but pure intuition, and the mere form of phenomena, which is all
that the sensibility can afford a priori. From this investigation it will be found that there are two pure forms of
sensuous intuition, as principles of knowledge a priori, namely, space and time. To the consideration of these
we shall now proceed.
SECTION I. Of Space.
SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.
By means of the external sense (a property of the mind), we represent to ourselves objects as without us, and
these all in space. Herein alone are their shape, dimensions, and relations to each other determined or
determinable. The internal sense, by means of which the mind contemplates itself or its internal state, gives,
indeed, no intuition of the soul as an object; yet there is nevertheless a determinate form, under which alone
the contemplation of our internal state is possible, so that all which relates to the inward determinations of the
mind is represented in relations of time. Of time we cannot have any external intuition, any more than we can
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. Of Space. 25
Page No 30
have an internal intuition of space. What then are time and space? Are they real existences? Or, are they
merely relations or determinations of things, such, however, as would equally belong to these things in
themselves, though they should never become objects of intuition; or, are they such as belong only to the
form of intuition, and consequently to the subjective constitution of the mind, without which these predicates
of time and space could not be attached to any object? In order to become informed on these points, we shall
first give an exposition of the conception of space. By exposition, I mean the clear, though not detailed,
representation of that which belongs to a conception; and an exposition is metaphysical when it contains that
which represents the conception as given a priori.
1. Space is not a conception which has been derived from outward experiences. For, in order that certain
sensations may relate to something without me (that is, to something which occupies a different part of space
from that in which I am); in like manner, in order that I may represent them not merely as without, of, and
near to each other, but also in separate places, the representation of space must already exist as a foundation.
Consequently, the representation of space cannot be borrowed from the relations of external phenomena
through experience; but, on the contrary, this external experience is itself only possible through the said
antecedent representation.
2. Space then is a necessary representation a priori, which serves for the foundation of all external intuitions.
We never can imagine or make a representation to ourselves of the nonexistence of space, though we may
easily enough think that no objects are found in it. It must, therefore, be considered as the condition of the
possibility of phenomena, and by no means as a determination dependent on them, and is a representation a
priori, which necessarily supplies the basis for external phenomena.
3. Space is no discursive, or as we say, general conception of the relations of things, but a pure intuition. For,
in the first place, we can only represent to ourselves one space, and, when we talk of divers spaces, we mean
only parts of one and the same space. Moreover, these parts cannot antecede this one allembracing space, as
the component parts from which the aggregate can be made up, but can be cogitated only as existing in it.
Space is essentially one, and multiplicity in it, consequently the general notion of spaces, of this or that space,
depends solely upon limitations. Hence it follows that an a priori intuition (which is not empirical) lies at the
root of all our conceptions of space. Thus, moreover, the principles of geometry for example, that "in a
triangle, two sides together are greater than the third," are never deduced from general conceptions of line
and triangle, but from intuition, and this a priori, with apodeictic certainty.
4. Space is represented as an infinite given quantity. Now every conception must indeed be considered as a
representation which is contained in an infinite multitude of different possible representations, which,
therefore, comprises these under itself; but no conception, as such, can be so conceived, as if it contained
within itself an infinite multitude of representations. Nevertheless, space is so conceived of, for all parts of
space are equally capable of being produced to infinity. Consequently, the original representation of space is
an intuition a priori, and not a conception.
SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space.
By a transcendental exposition, I mean the explanation of a conception, as a principle, whence can be
discerned the possibility of other synthetical a priori cognitions. For this purpose, it is requisite, firstly, that
such cognitions do really flow from the given conception; and, secondly, that the said cognitions are only
possible under the presupposition of a given mode of explaining this conception.
Geometry is a science which determines the properties of space synthetically, and yet a priori. What, then,
must be our representation of space, in order that such a cognition of it may be possible? It must be originally
intuition, for from a mere conception, no propositions can be deduced which go out beyond the conception,
and yet this happens in geometry. (Introd. V.) But this intuition must be found in the mind a priori, that is,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space. 26
Page No 31
before any perception of objects, consequently must be pure, not empirical, intuition. For geometrical
principles are always apodeictic, that is, united with the consciousness of their necessity, as: "Space has only
three dimensions." But propositions of this kind cannot be empirical judgements, nor conclusions from them.
(Introd. II.) Now, how can an external intuition anterior to objects themselves, and in which our conception of
objects can be determined a priori, exist in the human mind? Obviously not otherwise than in so far as it has
its seat in the subject only, as the formal capacity of the subject's being affected by objects, and thereby of
obtaining immediate representation, that is, intuition; consequently, only as the form of the external sense in
general.
Thus it is only by means of our explanation that the possibility of geometry, as a synthetical science a priori,
becomes comprehensible. Every mode of explanation which does not show us this possibility, although in
appearance it may be similar to ours, can with the utmost certainty be distinguished from it by these marks.
SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions.
(a) Space does Space does not represent any property of objects as things in themselves, nor does it represent
them in their relations to each other; in other words, space does not represent to us any determination of
objects such as attaches to the objects themselves, and would remain, even though all subjective conditions of
the intuition were abstracted. For neither absolute nor relative determinations of objects can be intuited prior
to the existence of the things to which they belong, and therefore not a priori.
(b) Space is nothing else than the form of all phenomena of the external sense, that is, the subjective
condition of the sensibility, under which alone external intuition is possible. Now, because the receptivity or
capacity of the subject to be affected by objects necessarily antecedes all intuitions of these objects, it is
easily understood how the form of all phenomena can be given in the mind previous to all actual perceptions,
therefore a priori, and how it, as a pure intuition, in which all objects must be determined, can contain
principles of the relations of these objects prior to all experience.
It is therefore from the human point of view only that we can speak of space, extended objects, etc. If we
depart from the subjective condition, under which alone we can obtain external intuition, or, in other words,
by means of which we are affected by objects, the representation of space has no meaning whatsoever. This
predicate is only applicable to things in so far as they appear to us, that is, are objects of sensibility. The
constant form of this receptivity, which we call sensibility, is a necessary condition of all relations in which
objects can be intuited as existing without us, and when abstraction of these objects is made, is a pure
intuition, to which we give the name of space. It is clear that we cannot make the special conditions of
sensibility into conditions of the possibility of things, but only of the possibility of their existence as far as
they are phenomena. And so we may correctly say that space contains all which can appear to us externally,
but not all things considered as things in themselves, be they intuited or not, or by whatsoever subject one
will. As to the intuitions of other thinking beings, we cannot judge whether they are or are not bound by the
same conditions which limit our own intuition, and which for us are universally valid. If we join the
limitation of a judgement to the conception of the subject, then the judgement will possess unconditioned
validity. For example, the proposition, "All objects are beside each other in space," is valid only under the
limitation that these things are taken as objects of our sensuous intuition. But if I join the condition to the
conception and say, "All things, as external phenomena, are beside each other in space," then the rule is valid
universally, and without any limitation. Our expositions, consequently, teach the reality (i.e., the objective
validity) of space in regard of all which can be presented to us externally as object, and at the same time also
the ideality of space in regard to objects when they are considered by means of reason as things in
themselves, that is, without reference to the constitution of our sensibility. We maintain, therefore, the
empirical reality of space in regard to all possible external experience, although we must admit its
transcendental ideality; in other words, that it is nothing, so soon as we withdraw the condition upon which
the possibility of all experience depends and look upon space as something that belongs to things in
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions. 27
Page No 32
themselves.
But, with the exception of space, there is no representation, subjective and ref erring to something external to
us, which could be called objective a priori. For there are no other subjective representations from which we
can deduce synthetical propositions a priori, as we can from the intuition of space. (See SS 3.) Therefore, to
speak accurately, no ideality whatever belongs to these, although they agree in this respect with the
representation of space, that they belong merely to the subjective nature of the mode of sensuous perception;
such a mode, for example, as that of sight, of hearing, and of feeling, by means of the sensations of colour,
sound, and heat, but which, because they are only sensations and not intuitions, do not of themselves give us
the cognition of any object, least of all, an a priori cognition. My purpose, in the above remark, is merely this:
to guard any one against illustrating the asserted ideality of space by examples quite insufficient, for example,
by colour, taste, etc.; for these must be contemplated not as properties of things, but only as changes in the
subject, changes which may be different in different men. For, in such a case, that which is originally a mere
phenomenon, a rose, for example, is taken by the empirical understanding for a thing in itself, though to
every different eye, in respect of its colour, it may appear different. On the contrary, the transcendental
conception of phenomena in space is a critical admonition, that, in general, nothing which is intuited in space
is a thing in itself, and that space is not a form which belongs as a property to things; but that objects are quite
unknown to us in themselves, and what we call outward objects, are nothing else but mere representations of
our sensibility, whose form is space, but whose real correlate, the thing in itself, is not known by means of
these representations, nor ever can be, but respecting which, in experience, no inquiry is ever made.
SECTION II. Of Time.
SS 5 Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.
1. Time is not an empirical conception. For neither coexistence nor succession would be perceived by us, if
the representation of time did not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition we could not
represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is,
contemporaneously, or in succession.
2. Time is a necessary representation, lying at the foundation of all our intuitions. With regard to phenomena
in general, we cannot think away time from them, and represent them to ourselves as out of and unconnected
with time, but we can quite well represent to ourselves time void of phenomena. Time is therefore given a
priori. In it alone is all reality of phenomena possible. These may all be annihilated in thought, but time itself,
as the universal condition of their possibility, cannot be so annulled.
3. On this necessity a priori is also founded the possibility of apodeictic principles of the relations of time, or
axioms of time in general, such as: "Time has only one dimension," "Different times are not coexistent but
successive" (as different spaces are not successive but coexistent). These principles cannot be derived from
experience, for it would give neither strict universality, nor apodeictic certainty. We should only be able to
say, "so common experience teaches us," but not "it must be so." They are valid as rules, through which, in
general, experience is possible; and they instruct us respecting experience, and not by means of it.
4. Time is not a discursive, or as it is called, general conception, but a pure form of the sensuous intuition.
Different times are merely parts of one and the same time. But the representation which can only be given by
a single object is an intuition. Besides, the proposition that different times cannot be coexistent could not be
derived from a general conception. For this proposition is synthetical, and therefore cannot spring out of
conceptions alone. It is therefore contained immediately in the intuition and representation of time.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of Time. 28
Page No 33
5. The infinity of time signifies nothing more than that every determined quantity of time is possible only
through limitations of one time lying at the foundation. Consequently, the original representation, time, must
be given as unlimited. But as the determinate representation of the parts of time and of every quantity of an
object can only be obtained by limitation, the complete representation of time must not be furnished by
means of conceptions, for these contain only partial representations. Conceptions, on the contrary, must have
immediate intuition for their basis.
SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time.
I may here refer to what is said above (SS 5, 3), where, for or sake of brevity, I have placed under the head of
metaphysical exposition, that which is properly transcendental. Here I shall add that the conception of
change, and with it the conception of motion, as change of place, is possible only through and in the
representation of time; that if this representation were not an intuition (internal) a priori, no conception, of
whatever kind, could render comprehensible the possibility of change, in other words, of a conjunction of
contradictorily opposed predicates in one and the same object, for example, the presence of a thing in a place
and the nonpresence of the same thing in the same place. It is only in time that it is possible to meet with
two contradictorily opposed determinations in one thing, that is, after each other. thus our conception of time
explains the possibility of so much synthetical knowledge a priori, as is exhibited in the general doctrine of
motion, which is not a little fruitful.
SS 7 Conclusions from the above Conceptions.
(a) Time is not something which subsists of itself, or which inheres in things as an objective determination,
and therefore remains, when abstraction is made of the subjective conditions of the intuition of things. For in
the former case, it would be something real, yet without presenting to any power of perception any real
object. In the latter case, as an order or determination inherent in things themselves, it could not be antecedent
to things, as their condition, nor discerned or intuited by means of synthetical propositions a priori. But all
this is quite possible when we regard time as merely the subjective condition under which all our intuitions
take place. For in that case, this form of the inward intuition can be represented prior to the objects, and
consequently a priori.
(b) Time is nothing else than the form of the internal sense, that is, of the intuitions of self and of our internal
state. For time cannot be any determination of outward phenomena. It has to do neither with shape nor
position; on the contrary, it determines the relation of representations in our internal state. And precisely
because this internal intuition presents to us no shape or form, we endeavour to supply this want by analogies,
and represent the course of time by a line progressing to infinity, the content of which constitutes a series
which is only of one dimension; and we conclude from the properties of this line as to all the properties of
time, with this single exception, that the parts of the line are coexistent, whilst those of time are successive.
From this it is clear also that the representation of time is itself an intuition, because all its relations can be
expressed in an external intuition.
(c) Time is the formal condition a priori of all phenomena whatsoever. Space, as the pure form of external
intuition, is limited as a condition a priori to external phenomena alone. On the other hand, because all
representations, whether they have or have not external things for their objects, still in themselves, as
determinations of the mind, belong to our internal state; and because this internal state is subject to the formal
condition of the internal intuition, that is, to time time is a condition a priori of all phenomena whatsoever
the immediate condition of all internal, and thereby the mediate condition of all external phenomena. If I can
say a priori, "All outward phenomena are in space, and determined a priori according to the relations of
space," I can also, from the principle of the internal sense, affirm universally, "All phenomena in general, that
is, all objects of the senses, are in time and stand necessarily in relations of time."
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time. 29
Page No 34
If we abstract our internal intuition of ourselves and all external intuitions, possible only by virtue of this
internal intuition and presented to us by our faculty of representation, and consequently take objects as they
are in themselves, then time is nothing. It is only of objective validity in regard to phenomena, because these
are things which we regard as objects of our senses. It no longer objective we, make abstraction of the
sensuousness of our intuition, in other words, of that mode of representation which is peculiar to us, and
speak of things in general. Time is therefore merely a subjective condition of our (human) intuition (which is
always sensuous, that is, so far as we are affected by objects), and in itself, independently of the mind or
subject, is nothing. Nevertheless, in respect of all phenomena, consequently of all things which come within
the sphere of our experience, it is necessarily objective. We cannot say, "All things are in time," because in
this conception of things in general, we abstract and make no mention of any sort of intuition of things. But
this is the proper condition under which time belongs to our representation of objects. If we add the condition
to the conception, and say, "All things, as phenomena, that is, objects of sensuous intuition, are in time," then
the proposition has its sound objective validity and universality a priori.
What we have now set forth teaches, therefore, the empirical reality of time; that is, its objective validity in
reference to all objects which can ever be presented to our senses. And as our intuition is always sensuous, no
object ever can be presented to us in experience, which does not come under the conditions of time. On the
other hand, we deny to time all claim to absolute reality; that is, we deny that it, without having regard to the
form of our sensuous intuition, absolutely inheres in things as a condition or property. Such properties as
belong to objects as things in themselves never can be presented to us through the medium of the senses.
Herein consists, therefore, the transcendental ideality of time, according to which, if we abstract the
subjective conditions of sensuous intuition, it is nothing, and cannot be reckoned as subsisting or inhering in
objects as things in themselves, independently of its relation to our intuition. this ideality, like that of space, is
not to be proved or illustrated by fallacious analogies with sensations, for this reason that in such arguments
or illustrations, we make the presupposition that the phenomenon, in which such and such predicates inhere,
has objective reality, while in this case we can only find such an objective reality as is itself empirical, that is,
regards the object as a mere phenomenon. In reference to this subject, see the remark in Section I (SS 4)
SS 8 Elucidation.
Against this theory, which grants empirical reality to time, but denies to it absolute and transcendental reality,
I have heard from intelligent men an objection so unanimously urged that I conclude that it must naturally
present itself to every reader to whom these considerations are novel. It runs thus: "Changes are real" (this the
continual change in our own representations demonstrates, even though the existence of all external
phenomena, together with their changes, is denied). Now, changes are only possible in time, and therefore
time must be something real. But there is no difficulty in answering this. I grant the whole argument. Time,
no doubt, is something real, that is, it is the real form of our internal intuition. It therefore has subjective
reality, in reference to our internal experience, that is, I have really the representation of time and of my
determinations therein. Time, therefore, is not to be regarded as an object, but as the mode of representation
of myself as an object. But if I could intuite myself, or be intuited by another being, without this condition of
sensibility, then those very determinations which we now represent to ourselves as changes, would present to
us a knowledge in which the representation of time, and consequently of change, would not appear. The
empirical reality of time, therefore, remains, as the condition of all our experience. But absolute reality,
according to what has been said above, cannot be granted it. Time is nothing but the form of our internal
intuition.* If we take away from it the special condition of our sensibility, the conception of time also
vanishes; and it inheres not in the objects themselves, but solely in the subject (or mind) which intuites them.
*I can indeed say "my representations follow one another, or are successive"; but this means only that we are
conscious of them as in a succession, that is, according to the form of the internal sense. Time, therefore, is
not a thing in itself, nor is it any objective determination pertaining to, or inherent in things.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 8 Elucidation. 30
Page No 35
But the reason why this objection is so unanimously brought against our doctrine of time, and that too by
disputants who cannot start any intelligible arguments against the doctrine of the ideality of space, is this
they have no hope of demonstrating apodeictically the absolute reality of space, because the doctrine of
idealism is against them, according to which the reality of external objects is not capable of any strict proof.
On the other hand, the reality of the object of our internal sense (that is, myself and my internal state) is clear
immediately through consciousness. The former external objects in space might be a mere delusion, but
the latter the object of my internal perception is undeniably real. They do not, however, reflect that both,
without question of their reality as representations, belong only to the genus phenomenon, which has always
two aspects, the one, the object considered as a thing in itself, without regard to the mode of intuiting it, and
the nature of which remains for this very reason problematical, the other, the form of our intuition of the
object, which must be sought not in the object as a thing in itself, but in the subject to which it appears
which form of intuition nevertheless belongs really and necessarily to the phenomenal object.
Time and space are, therefore, two sources of knowledge, from which, a priori, various synthetical cognitions
can be drawn. Of this we find a striking example in the cognitions of space and its relations, which form the
foundation of pure mathematics. They are the two pure forms of all intuitions, and thereby make synthetical
propositions a priori possible. But these sources of knowledge being merely conditions of our sensibility, do
therefore, and as such, strictly determine their own range and purpose, in that they do not and cannot present
objects as things in themselves, but are applicable to them solely in so far as they are considered as sensuous
phenomena. The sphere of phenomena is the only sphere of their validity, and if we venture out of this, no
further objective use can be made of them. For the rest, this formal reality of time and space leaves the
validity of our empirical knowledge unshaken; for our certainty in that respect is equally firm, whether these
forms necessarily inhere in the things themselves, or only in our intuitions of them. On the other hand, those
who maintain the absolute reality of time and space, whether as essentially subsisting, or only inhering, as
modifications, in things, must find themselves at utter variance with the principles of experience itself. For, if
they decide for the first view, and make space and time into substances, this being the side taken by
mathematical natural philosophers, they must admit two selfsubsisting nonentities, infinite and eternal,
which exist (yet without there being anything real) for the purpose of containing in themselves everything
that is real. If they adopt the second view of inherence, which is preferred by some metaphysical natural
philosophers, and regard space and time as relations (contiguity in space or succession in time), abstracted
from experience, though represented confusedly in this state of separation, they find themselves in that case
necessitated to deny the validity of mathematical doctrines a priori in reference to real things (for example, in
space) at all events their apodeictic certainty. For such certainty cannot be found in an a posteriori
proposition; and the conceptions a priori of space and time are, according to this opinion, mere creations of
the imagination, having their source really in experience, inasmuch as, out of relations abstracted from
experience, imagination has made up something which contains, indeed, general statements of these relations,
yet of which no application can be made without the restrictions attached thereto by nature. The former of
these parties gains this advantage, that they keep the sphere of phenomena free for mathematical science. On
the other hand, these very conditions (space and time) embarrass them greatly, when the understanding
endeavours to pass the limits of that sphere. The latter has, indeed, this advantage, that the representations of
space and time do not come in their way when they wish to judge of objects, not as phenomena, but merely in
their relation to the understanding. Devoid, however, of a true and objectively valid a priori intuition, they
can neither furnish any basis for the possibility of mathematical cognitions a priori, nor bring the propositions
of experience into necessary accordance with those of mathematics. In our theory of the true nature of these
two original forms of the sensibility, both difficulties are surmounted.
In conclusion, that transcendental aesthetic cannot contain any more than these two elements space and
time, is sufficiently obvious from the fact that all other conceptions appertaining to sensibility, even that of
motion, which unites in itself both elements, presuppose something empirical. Motion, for example,
presupposes the perception of something movable. But space considered in itself contains nothing movable,
consequently motion must be something which is found in space only through experience in other words, an
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 8 Elucidation. 31
Page No 36
empirical datum. In like manner, transcendental aesthetic cannot number the conception of change among its
data a priori; for time itself does not change, but only something which is in time. To acquire the conception
of change, therefore, the perception of some existing object and of the succession of its determinations, in one
word, experience, is necessary.
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic.
I. In order to prevent any misunderstanding, it will be requisite, in the first place, to recapitulate, as clearly as
possible, what our opinion is with respect to the fundamental nature of our sensuous cognition in general. We
have intended, then, to say that all our intuition is nothing but the representation of phenomena; that the
things which we intuite, are not in themselves the same as our representations of them in intuition, nor are
their relations in themselves so constituted as they appear to us; and that if we take away the subject, or even
only the subjective constitution of our senses in general, then not only the nature and relations of objects in
space and time, but even space and time themselves disappear; and that these, as phenomena, cannot exist in
themselves, but only in us. What may be the nature of objects considered as things in themselves and without
reference to the receptivity of our sensibility is quite unknown to us. We know nothing more than our mode
of perceiving them, which is peculiar to us, and which, though not of necessity pertaining to every animated
being, is so to the whole human race. With this alone we have to do. Space and time are the pure forms
thereof; sensation the matter. The former alone can we cognize a priori, that is, antecedent to all actual
perception; and for this reason such cognition is called pure intuition. The latter is that in our cognition which
is called cognition a posteriori, that is, empirical intuition. The former appertain absolutely and necessarily to
our sensibility, of whatsoever kind our sensations may be; the latter may be of very diversified character.
Supposing that we should carry our empirical intuition even to the very highest degree of clearness, we
should not thereby advance one step nearer to a knowledge of the constitution of objects as things in
themselves. For we could only, at best, arrive at a complete cognition of our own mode of intuition, that is of
our sensibility, and this always under the conditions originally attaching to the subject, namely, the conditions
of space and time; while the question: "What are objects considered as things in themselves?" remains
unanswerable even after the most thorough examination of the phenomenal world.
To say, then, that all our sensibility is nothing but the confused representation of things containing
exclusively that which belongs to them as things in themselves, and this under an accumulation of
characteristic marks and partial representations which we cannot distinguish in consciousness, is a
falsification of the conception of sensibility and phenomenization, which renders our whole doctrine thereof
empty and useless. The difference between a confused and a clear representation is merely logical and has
nothing to do with content. No doubt the conception of right, as employed by a sound understanding, contains
all that the most subtle investigation could unfold from it, although, in the ordinary practical use of the word,
we are not conscious of the manifold representations comprised in the conception. But we cannot for this
reason assert that the ordinary conception is a sensuous one, containing a mere phenomenon, for right cannot
appear as a phenomenon; but the conception of it lies in the understanding, and represents a property (the
moral property) of actions, which belongs to them in themselves. On the other hand, the representation in
intuition of a body contains nothing which could belong to an object considered as a thing in itself, but
merely the phenomenon or appearance of something, and the mode in which we are affected by that
appearance; and this receptivity of our faculty of cognition is called sensibility, and remains toto caelo
different from the cognition of an object in itself, even though we should examine the content of the
phenomenon to the very bottom.
It must be admitted that the LeibnitzWolfian philosophy has assigned an entirely erroneous point of view to
all investigations into the nature and origin of our cognitions, inasmuch as it regards the distinction between
the sensuous and the intellectual as merely logical, whereas it is plainly transcendental, and concerns not
merely the clearness or obscurity, but the content and origin of both. For the faculty of sensibility not only
does not present us with an indistinct and confused cognition of objects as things in themselves, but, in fact,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. 32
Page No 37
gives us no knowledge of these at all. On the contrary, so soon as we abstract in thought our own subjective
nature, the object represented, with the properties ascribed to it by sensuous intuition, entirely disappears,
because it was only this subjective nature that determined the form of the object as a phenomenon.
In phenomena, we commonly, indeed, distinguish that which essentially belongs to the intuition of them, and
is valid for the sensuous faculty of every human being, from that which belongs to the same intuition
accidentally, as valid not for the sensuous faculty in general, but for a particular state or organization of this
or that sense. Accordingly, we are accustomed to say that the former is a cognition which represents the
object itself, whilst the latter presents only a particular appearance or phenomenon thereof. This distinction,
however, is only empirical. If we stop here (as is usual), and do not regard the empirical intuition as itself a
mere phenomenon (as we ought to do), in which nothing that can appertain to a thing in itself is to be found,
our transcendental distinction is lost, and we believe that we cognize objects as things in themselves,
although in the whole range of the sensuous world, investigate the nature of its objects as profoundly as we
may, we have to do with nothing but phenomena. Thus, we call the rainbow a mere appearance of
phenomenon in a sunny shower, and the rain, the reality or thing in itself; and this is right enough, if we
understand the latter conception in a merely physical sense, that is, as that which in universal experience, and
under whatever conditions of sensuous perception, is known in intuition to be so and so determined, and not
otherwise. But if we consider this empirical datum generally, and inquire, without reference to its accordance
with all our senses, whether there can be discovered in it aught which represents an object as a thing in itself
(the raindrops of course are not such, for they are, as phenomena, empirical objects), the question of the
relation of the representation to the object is transcendental; and not only are the raindrops mere phenomena,
but even their circular form, nay, the space itself through which they fall, is nothing in itself, but both are
mere modifications or fundamental dispositions of our sensuous intuition, whilst the transcendental object
remains for us utterly unknown.
The second important concern of our aesthetic is that it does not obtain favour merely as a plausible
hypothesis, but possess as undoubted a character of certainty as can be demanded of any theory which is to
serve for an organon. In order fully to convince the reader of this certainty, we shall select a case which will
serve to make its validity apparent, and also to illustrate what has been said in SS 3.
Suppose, then, that space and time are in themselves objective, and conditions of the possibility of objects
as things in themselves. In the first place, it is evident that both present us, with very many apodeictic and
synthetic propositions a priori, but especially space and for this reason we shall prefer it for investigation at
present. As the propositions of geometry are cognized synthetically a priori, and with apodeictic certainty, I
inquire: Whence do you obtain propositions of this kind, and on what basis does the understanding rest, in
order to arrive at such absolutely necessary and universally valid truths?
There is no other way than through intuitions or conceptions, as such; and these are given either a priori or a
posteriori. The latter, namely, empirical conceptions, together with the empirical intuition on which they are
founded, cannot afford any synthetical proposition, except such as is itself also empirical, that is, a
proposition of experience. But an empirical proposition cannot possess the qualities of necessity and absolute
universality, which, nevertheless, are the characteristics of all geometrical propositions. As to the first and
only means to arrive at such cognitions, namely, through mere conceptions or intuitions a priori, it is quite
clear that from mere conceptions no synthetical cognitions, but only analytical ones, can be obtained. Take,
for example, the proposition: "Two straight lines cannot enclose a space, and with these alone no figure is
possible," and try to deduce it from the conception of a straight line and the number two; or take the
proposition: "It is possible to construct a figure with three straight lines," and endeavour, in like manner, to
deduce it from the mere conception of a straight line and the number three. All your endeavours are in vain,
and you find yourself forced to have recourse to intuition, as, in fact, geometry always does. You therefore
give yourself an object in intuition. But of what kind is this intuition? Is it a pure a priori, or is it an empirical
intuition? If the latter, then neither an universally valid, much less an apodeictic proposition can arise from it,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. 33
Page No 38
for experience never can give us any such proposition. You must, therefore, give yourself an object a priori in
intuition, and upon that ground your synthetical proposition. Now if there did not exist within you a faculty of
intuition a priori; if this subjective condition were not in respect to its form also the universal condition a
priori under which alone the object of this external intuition is itself possible; if the object (that is, the
triangle) were something in itself, without relation to you the subject; how could you affirm that that which
lies necessarily in your subjective conditions in order to construct a triangle, must also necessarily belong to
the triangle in itself? For to your conceptions of three lines, you could not add anything new (that is, the
figure); which, therefore, must necessarily be found in the object, because the object is given before your
cognition, and not by means of it. If, therefore, space (and time also) were not a mere form of your intuition,
which contains conditions a priori, under which alone things can become external objects for you, and
without which subjective conditions the objects are in themselves nothing, you could not construct any
synthetical proposition whatsoever regarding external objects. It is therefore not merely possible or probable,
but indubitably certain, that space and time, as the necessary conditions of all our external and internal
experience, are merely subjective conditions of all our intuitions, in relation to which all objects are therefore
mere phenomena, and not things in themselves, presented to us in this particular manner. And for this reason,
in respect to the form of phenomena, much may be said a priori, whilst of the thing in itself, which may lie at
the foundation of these phenomena, it is impossible to say anything.
II. In confirmation of this theory of the ideality of the external as well as internal sense, consequently of all
objects of sense, as mere phenomena, we may especially remark that all in our cognition that belongs to
intuition contains nothing more than mere relations. (The feelings of pain and pleasure, and the will, which
are not cognitions, are excepted.) The relations, to wit, of place in an intuition (extension), change of place
(motion), and laws according to which this change is determined (moving forces). That, however, which is
present in this or that place, or any operation going on, or result taking place in the things themselves, with
the exception of change of place, is not given to us by intuition. Now by means of mere relations, a thing
cannot be known in itself; and it may therefore be fairly concluded, that, as through the external sense
nothing but mere representations of relations are given us, the said external sense in its representation can
contain only the relation of the object to the subject, but not the essential nature of the object as a thing in
itself.
The same is the case with the internal intuition, not only because, in the internal intuition, the representation
of the external senses constitutes the material with which the mind is occupied; but because time, in which we
place, and which itself antecedes the consciousness of, these representations in experience, and which, as the
formal condition of the mode according to which objects are placed in the mind, lies at the foundation of
them, contains relations of the successive, the coexistent, and of that which always must be coexistent with
succession, the permanent. Now that which, as representation, can antecede every exercise of thought (of an
object), is intuition; and when it contains nothing but relations, it is the form of the intuition, which, as it
presents us with no representation, except in so far as something is placed in the mind, can be nothing else
than the mode in which the mind is affected by its own activity, to wit its presenting to itself
representations, consequently the mode in which the mind is affected by itself; that is, it can be nothing but
an internal sense in respect to its form. Everything that is represented through the medium of sense is so far
phenomenal; consequently, we must either refuse altogether to admit an internal sense, or the subject, which
is the object of that sense, could only be represented by it as phenomenon, and not as it would judge of itself,
if its intuition were pure spontaneous activity, that is, were intellectual. The difficulty here lies wholly in the
question: How can the subject have an internal intuition of itself? But this difficulty is common to every
theory. The consciousness of self (apperception) is the simple representation of the "ego"; and if by means of
that representation alone, all the manifold representations in the subject were spontaneously given, then our
internal intuition would be intellectual. This consciousness in man requires an internal perception of the
manifold representations which are previously given in the subject; and the manner in which these
representations are given in the mind without spontaneity, must, on account of this difference (the want of
spontaneity), be called sensibility. If the faculty of selfconsciousness is to apprehend what lies in the mind,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. 34
Page No 39
it must all act that and can in this way alone produce an intuition of self. But the form of this intuition, which
lies in the original constitution of the mind, determines, in the representation of time, the manner in which the
manifold representations are to combine themselves in the mind; since the subject intuites itself, not as it
would represent itself immediately and spontaneously, but according to the manner in which the mind is
internally affected, consequently, as it appears, and not as it is.
III. When we say that the intuition of external objects, and also the selfintuition of the subject, represent
both, objects and subject, in space and time, as they affect our senses, that is, as they appear this is by no
means equivalent to asserting that these objects are mere illusory appearances. For when we speak of things
as phenomena, the objects, nay, even the properties which we ascribe to them, are looked upon as really
given; only that, in so far as this or that property depends upon the mode of intuition of the subject, in the
relation of the given object to the subject, the object as phenomenon is to be distinguished from the object as
a thing in itself. Thus I do not say that bodies seem or appear to be external to me, or that my soul seems
merely to be given in my selfconsciousness, although I maintain that the properties of space and time, in
conformity to which I set both, as the condition of their existence, abide in my mode of intuition, and not in
the objects in themselves. It would be my own fault, if out of that which I should reckon as phenomenon, I
made mere illusory appearance.* But this will not happen, because of our principle of the ideality of all
sensuous intuitions. On the contrary, if we ascribe objective reality to these forms of representation, it
becomes impossible to avoid changing everything into mere appearance. For if we regard space and time as
properties, which must be found in objects as things in themselves, as sine quibus non of the possibility of
their existence, and reflect on the absurdities in which we then find ourselves involved, inasmuch as we are
compelled to admit the existence of two infinite things, which are nevertheless not substances, nor anything
really inhering in substances, nay, to admit that they are the necessary conditions of the existence of all
things, and moreover, that they must continue to exist, although all existing things were annihilated we
cannot blame the good Berkeley for degrading bodies to mere illusory appearances. Nay, even our own
existence, which would in this case depend upon the selfexistent reality of such a mere nonentity as time,
would necessarily be changed with it into mere appearance an absurdity which no one has as yet been guilty
of.
*The predicates of the phenomenon can be affixed to the object itself in relation to our sensuous faculty; for
example, the red colour or the perfume to the rose. But (illusory) appearance never can be attributed as a
predicate to an object, for this very reason, that it attributes to this object in itself that which belongs to it only
in relation to our sensuous faculty, or to the subject in general, e.g., the two handles which were formerly
ascribed to Saturn. That which is never to be found in the object itself, but always in the relation of the object
to the subject, and which moreover is inseparable from our representation of the object, we denominate
phenomenon. Thus the predicates of space and time are rightly attributed to objects of the senses as such, and
in this there is no illusion. On the contrary, if I ascribe redness of the rose as a thing in itself, or to Saturn his
handles, or extension to all external objects, considered as things in themselves, without regarding the
determinate relation of these objects to the subject, and without limiting my judgement to that relation then,
and then only, arises illusion.
IV. In natural theology, where we think of an object God which never can be an object of intuition to us,
and even to himself can never be an object of sensuous intuition, we carefully avoid attributing to his
intuition the conditions of space and time and intuition all his cognition must be, and not thought, which
always includes limitation. But with what right can we do this if we make them forms of objects as things in
themselves, and such, moreover, as would continue to exist as a priori conditions of the existence of things,
even though the things themselves were annihilated? For as conditions of all existence in general, space and
time must be conditions of the existence of the Supreme Being also. But if we do not thus make them
objective forms of all things, there is no other way left than to make them subjective forms of our mode of
intuition external and internal; which is called sensuous, because it is not primitive, that is, is not such as
gives in itself the existence of the object of the intuition (a mode of intuition which, so far as we can judge,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic. 35
Page No 40
can belong only to the Creator), but is dependent on the existence of the object, is possible, therefore, only on
condition that the representative faculty of the subject is affected by the object.
It is, moreover, not necessary that we should limit the mode of intuition in space and time to the sensuous
faculty of man. It may well be that all finite thinking beings must necessarily in this respect agree with man
(though as to this we cannot decide), but sensibility does not on account of this universality cease to be
sensibility, for this very reason, that it is a deduced (intuitus derivativus), and not an original (intuitus
originarius), consequently not an intellectual intuition, and this intuition, as such, for reasons above
mentioned, seems to belong solely to the Supreme Being, but never to a being dependent, quoad its existence,
as well as its intuition (which its existence determines and limits relatively to given objects). This latter
remark, however, must be taken only as an illustration, and not as any proof of the truth of our aesthetical
theory.
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic.
We have now completely before us one part of the solution of the grand general problem of transcendental
philosophy, namely, the question: "How are synthetical propositions a priori possible?" That is to say, we
have shown that we are in possession of pure a priori intuitions, namely, space and time, in which we find,
when in a judgement a priori we pass out beyond the given conception, something which is not discoverable
in that conception, but is certainly found a priori in the intuition which corresponds to the conception, and can
be united synthetically with it. But the judgements which these pure intuitions enable us to make, never reach
farther than to objects of the senses, and are valid only for objects of possible experience. INTRO
SECOND PART. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC.
INTRODUCTION. Idea of a Transcendental Logic.
I. Of Logic in General.
Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind, first of which is the faculty or power of receiving
representations (receptivity for impressions); the second is the power of cognizing by means of these
representations (spontaneity in the production of conceptions). Through the first an object is given to us;
through the second, it is, in relation to the representation (which is a mere determination of the mind),
thought. Intuition and conceptions constitute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither
conceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can
afford us a cognition. Both are either pure or empirical. They are. empirical, when sensation (which
presupposes the actual presence of the object) is contained in them; and pure, when no sensation is mixed
with the representation. Sensations we may call the matter of sensuous cognition. Pure intuition consequently
contains merely the form under which something is intuited, and pure conception only the form of the
thought of an object. Only pure intuitions and pure conceptions are possible a priori; the empirical only a
posteriori.
We apply the term sensibility to the receptivity of the mind for impressions, in so far as it is in some way
affected; and, on the other hand, we call the faculty of spontaneously producing representations, or the
spontaneity of cognition, understanding. Our nature is so constituted that intuition with us never can be other
than sensuous, that is, it contains only the mode in which we are affected by objects. On the other hand, the
faculty of thinking the object of sensuous intuition is the understanding. Neither of these faculties has a
preference over the other. Without the sensuous faculty no object would be given to us, and without the
understanding no object would be thought. Thoughts without content are void; intuitions without
conceptions, blind. Hence it is as necessary for the mind to make its conceptions sensuous (that is, to join to
them the object in intuition), as to make its intuitions intelligible (that is, to bring them under conceptions).
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic. 36
Page No 41
Neither of these faculties can exchange its proper function. Understanding cannot intuite, and the sensuous
faculty cannot think. in no other way than from the united operation of both, can knowledge arise. But no one
ought, on this account, to overlook the difference of the elements contributed by each; we have rather great
reason carefully to separate and distinguish them. We therefore distinguish the science of the laws of
sensibility, that is, aesthetic, from the science of the laws of the understanding, that is, logic.
Now, logic in its turn may be considered as twofold namely, as logic of the general, or of the particular use
of the understanding. The first contains the absolutely necessary laws of thought, without which no use
whatsoever of the understanding is possible, and gives laws therefore to the understanding, without regard to
the difference of objects on which it may be employed. The logic of the particular use of the understanding
contains the laws of correct thinking upon a particular class of objects. The former may be called elemental
logic the latter, the organon of this or that particular science. The latter is for the most part employed in the
schools, as a propaedeutic to the sciences, although, indeed, according to the course of human reason, it is the
last thing we arrive at, when the science has been already matured, and needs only the finishing touches
towards its correction and completion; for our knowledge of the objects of our attempted science must be
tolerably extensive and complete before we can indicate the laws by which a science of these objects can be
established.
General logic is again either pure or applied. In the former, we abstract all the empirical conditions under
which the understanding is exercised; for example, the influence of the senses, the play of the fantasy or
imagination, the laws of the memory, the force of habit, of inclination, etc., consequently also, the sources of
prejudice in a word, we abstract all causes from which particular cognitions arise, because these causes
regard the understanding under certain circumstances of its application, and, to the knowledge of them
experience is required. Pure general logic has to do, therefore, merely with pure a priori principles, and is a
canon of understanding and reason, but only in respect of the formal part of their use, be the content what it
may, empirical or transcendental. General logic is called applied, when it is directed to the laws of the use of
the understanding, under the subjective empirical conditions which psychology teaches us. It has therefore
empirical principles, although, at the same time, it is in so far general, that it applies to the exercise of the
understanding, without regard to the difference of objects. On this account, moreover, it is neither a canon of
the understanding in general, nor an organon of a particular science, but merely a cathartic of the human
understanding.
In general logic, therefore, that part which constitutes pure logic must be carefully distinguished from that
which constitutes applied (though still general) logic. The former alone is properly science, although short
and dry, as the methodical exposition of an elemental doctrine of the understanding ought to be. In this,
therefore, logicians must always bear in mind two rules:
1. As general logic, it makes abstraction of all content of the cognition of the understanding, and of the
difference of objects, and has to do with nothing but the mere form of thought.
2. As pure logic, it has no empirical principles, and consequently draws nothing (contrary to the common
persuasion) from psychology, which therefore has no influence on the canon of the understanding. It is a
demonstrated doctrine, and everything in it must be certain completely a priori.
What I called applied logic (contrary to the common acceptation of this term, according to which it should
contain certain exercises for the scholar, for which pure logic gives the rules), is a representation of the
understanding, and of the rules of its necessary employment in concreto, that is to say, under the accidental
conditions of the subject, which may either hinder or promote this employment, and which are all given only
empirically. Thus applied logic treats of attention, its impediments and consequences, of the origin of error,
of the state of doubt, hesitation, conviction, etc., and to it is related pure general logic in the same way that
pure morality, which contains only the necessary moral laws of a free will, is related to practical ethics, which
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic. 37
Page No 42
considers these laws under all the impediments of feelings, inclinations, and passions to which men are more
or less subjected, and which never can furnish us with a true and demonstrated science, because it, as well as
applied logic, requires empirical and psychological principles.
II. Of Transcendental Logic.
General logic, as we have seen, makes abstraction of all content of cognition, that is, of all relation of
cognition to its object, and regards only the logical form in the relation of cognitions to each other, that is, the
form of thought in general. But as we have both pure and empirical intuitions (as transcendental aesthetic
proves), in like manner a distinction might be drawn between pure and empirical thought (of objects). In this
case, there would exist a kind of logic, in which we should not make abstraction of all content of cognition;
for or logic which should comprise merely the laws of pure thought (of an object), would of course exclude
all those cognitions which were of empirical content. This kind of logic would also examine the origin of our
cognitions of objects, so far as that origin cannot be ascribed to the objects themselves; while, on the
contrary, general logic has nothing to do with the origin of our cognitions, but contemplates our
representations, be they given primitively a priori in ourselves, or be they only of empirical origin, solely
according to the laws which the understanding observes in employing them in the process of thought, in
relation to each other. Consequently, general logic treats of the form of the understanding only, which can be
applied to representations, from whatever source they may have arisen.
And here I shall make a remark, which the reader must bear well in mind in the course of the following
considerations, to wit, that not every cognition a priori, but only those through which we cognize that and
how certain representations (intuitions or conceptions) are applied or are possible only a priori; that is to say,
the a priori possibility of cognition and the a priori use of it are transcendental. Therefore neither is space, nor
any a priori geometrical determination of space, a transcendental Representation, but only the knowledge that
such a representation is not of empirical origin, and the possibility of its relating to objects of experience,
although itself a priori, can be called transcendental. So also, the application of space to objects in general
would be transcendental; but if it be limited to objects of sense it is empirical. Thus, the distinction of the
transcendental and empirical belongs only to the critique of cognitions, and does not concern the relation of
these to their object.
Accordingly, in the expectation that there may perhaps be conceptions which relate a priori to objects, not as
pure or sensuous intuitions, but merely as acts of pure thought (which are therefore conceptions, but neither
of empirical nor aesthetical origin) in this expectation, I say, we form to ourselves, by anticipation, the idea
of a science of pure understanding and rational cognition, by means of which we may cogitate objects
entirely a priori. A science of this kind, which should determine the origin, the extent, and the objective
validity of such cognitions, must be called transcendental logic, because it has not, like general logic, to do
with the laws of understanding and reason in relation to empirical as well as pure rational cognitions without
distinction, but concerns itself with these only in an a priori relation to objects.
III. Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic.
The old question with which people sought to push logicians into a corner, so that they must either have
recourse to pitiful sophisms or confess their ignorance, and consequently the vanity of their whole art, is this:
"What is truth?" The definition of the word truth, to wit, "the accordance of the cognition with its object," is
presupposed in the question; but we desire to be told, in the answer to it, what is the universal and secure
criterion of the truth of every cognition.
To know what questions we may reasonably propose is in itself a strong evidence of sagacity and
intelligence. For if a question be in itself absurd and unsusceptible of a rational answer, it is attended with the
danger not to mention the shame that falls upon the person who proposes it of seducing the unguarded
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic. 38
Page No 43
listener into making absurd answers, and we are presented with the ridiculous spectacle of one (as the
ancients said) "milking the hegoat, and the other holding a sieve."
If truth consists in the accordance of a cognition with its object, this object must be, ipso facto, distinguished
from all others; for a cognition is false if it does not accord with the object to which it relates, although it
contains something which may be affirmed of other objects. Now an universal criterion of truth would be that
which is valid for all cognitions, without distinction of their objects. But it is evident that since, in the case of
such a criterion, we make abstraction of all the content of a cognition (that is, of all relation to its object), and
truth relates precisely to this content, it must be utterly absurd to ask for a mark of the truth of this content of
cognition; and that, accordingly, a sufficient, and at the same time universal, test of truth cannot possibly be
found. As we have already termed the content of a cognition its matter, we shall say: "Of the truth of our
cognitions in respect of their matter, no universal test can be demanded, because such a demand is
selfcontradictory."
On the other hand, with regard to our cognition in respect of its mere form (excluding all content), it is
equally manifest that logic, in so far as it exhibits the universal and necessary laws of the understanding, must
in these very laws present us with criteria of truth. Whatever contradicts these rules is false, because thereby
the understanding is made to contradict its own universal laws of thought; that is, to contradict itself. These
criteria, however, apply solely to the form of truth, that is, of thought in general, and in so far they are
perfectly accurate, yet not sufficient. For although a cognition may be perfectly accurate as to logical form,
that is, not selfcontradictory, it is notwithstanding quite possible that it may not stand in agreement with its
object. Consequently, the merely logical criterion of truth, namely, the accordance of a cognition with the
universal and formal laws of understanding and reason, is nothing more than the conditio sine qua non, or
negative condition of all truth. Farther than this logic cannot go, and the error which depends not on the form,
but on the content of the cognition, it has no test to discover.
General logic, then, resolves the whole formal business of understanding and reason into its elements, and
exhibits them as principles of all logical judging of our cognitions. This part of logic may, therefore, be called
analytic, and is at least the negative test of truth, because all cognitions must first of an be estimated and tried
according to these laws before we proceed to investigate them in respect of their content, in order to discover
whether they contain positive truth in regard to their object. Because, however, the mere form of a cognition,
accurately as it may accord with logical laws, is insufficient to supply us with material (objective) truth, no
one, by means of logic alone, can venture to predicate anything of or decide concerning objects, unless he has
obtained, independently of logic, wellgrounded information about them, in order afterwards to examine,
according to logical laws, into the use and connection, in a cohering whole, of that information, or, what is
still better, merely to test it by them. Notwithstanding, there lies so seductive a charm in the possession of a
specious art like this an art which gives to all our cognitions the form of the understanding, although with
respect to the content thereof we may be sadly deficient that general logic, which is merely a canon of
judgement, has been employed as an organon for the actual production, or rather for the semblance of
production, of objective assertions, and has thus been grossly misapplied. Now general logic, in its assumed
character of organon, is called dialectic.
Different as are the significations in which the ancients used this term for a science or an art, we may safely
infer, from their actual employment of it, that with them it was nothing else than a logic of illusion a
sophistical art for giving ignorance, nay, even intentional sophistries, the colouring of truth, in which the
thoroughness of procedure which logic requires was imitated, and their topic employed to cloak the empty
pretensions. Now it may be taken as a safe and useful warning, that general logic, considered as an organon,
must always be a logic of illusion, that is, be dialectical, for, as it teaches us nothing whatever respecting the
content of our cognitions, but merely the formal conditions of their accordance with the understanding, which
do not relate to and are quite indifferent in respect of objects, any attempt to employ it as an instrument
(organon) in order to extend and enlarge the range of our knowledge must end in mere prating; any one being
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic. 39
Page No 44
able to maintain or oppose, with some appearance of truth, any single assertion whatever.
Such instruction is quite unbecoming the dignity of philosophy. For these reasons we have chosen to
denominate this part of logic dialectic, in the sense of a critique of dialectical illusion, and we wish the term
to be so understood in this place.
IV. Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Transcendental
Analytic and Dialectic.
In transcendental logic we isolate the understanding (as in transcendental aesthetic the sensibility) and select
from our cognition merely that part of thought which has its origin in the understanding alone. The exercise
of this pure cognition, however, depends upon this as its condition, that objects to which it may be applied be
given to us in intuition, for without intuition the whole of our cognition is without objects, and is therefore
quite void. That part of transcendental logic, then, which treats of the elements of pure cognition of the
understanding, and of the principles without which no object at all can be thought, is transcendental analytic,
and at the same time a logic of truth. For no cognition can contradict it, without losing at the same time all
content, that is, losing all reference to an object, and therefore all truth. But because we are very easily
seduced into employing these pure cognitions and principles of the understanding by themselves, and that
even beyond the boundaries of experience, which yet is the only source whence we can obtain matter
(objects) on which those pure conceptions may be employed understanding runs the risk of making, by
means of empty sophisms, a material and objective use of the mere formal principles of the pure
understanding, and of passing judgements on objects without distinction objects which are not given to us,
nay, perhaps cannot be given to us in any way. Now, as it ought properly to be only a canon for judging of
the empirical use of the understanding, this kind of logic is misused when we seek to employ it as an organon
of the universal and unlimited exercise of the understanding, and attempt with the pure understanding alone
to judge synthetically, affirm, and determine respecting objects in general. In this case the exercise of the
pure understanding becomes dialectical. The second part of our transcendental logic must therefore be a
critique of dialectical illusion, and this critique we shall term transcendental dialectic not meaning it as an
art of producing dogmatically such illusion (an art which is unfortunately too current among the practitioners
of metaphysical juggling), but as a critique of understanding and reason in regard to their hyperphysical use.
This critique will expose the groundless nature of the pretensions of these two faculties, and invalidate their
claims to the discovery and enlargement of our cognitions merely by means of transcendental principles, and
show that the proper employment of these faculties is to test the judgements made by the pure understanding,
and to guard it from sophistical delusion.
Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC.
SS I.
Transcendental analytic is the dissection of the whole of our a priori knowledge into the elements of the pure
cognition of the understanding. In order to effect our purpose, it is necessary: (1) That the conceptions be
pure and not empirical; (2) That they belong not to intuition and sensibility, but to thought and understanding;
(3) That they be elementary conceptions, and as such, quite different from deduced or compound
conceptions; (4) That our table of these elementary conceptions be complete, and fill up the whole sphere of
the pure understanding. Now this completeness of a science cannot be accepted with confidence on the
guarantee of a mere estimate of its existence in an aggregate formed only by means of repeated experiments
and attempts. The completeness which we require is possible only by means of an idea of the totality of the a
priori cognition of the understanding, and through the thereby determined division of the conceptions which
form the said whole; consequently, only by means of their connection in a system. Pure understanding
distinguishes itself not merely from everything empirical, but also completely from all sensibility. It is a unity
The Critique of Pure Reason
Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC. SS I. 40
Page No 45
selfsubsistent, selfsufficient, and not to be enlarged by any additions from without. Hence the sum of its
cognition constitutes a system to be determined by and comprised under an idea; and the completeness and
articulation of this system can at the same time serve as a test of the correctness and genuineness of all the
parts of cognition that belong to it. The whole of this part of transcendental logic consists of two books, of
which the one contains the conceptions, and the other the principles of pure understanding.
BOOK I.
SS 2 Analytic of Conceptions.
By the term Analytic of Conceptions, I do not understand the analysis of these, or the usual process in
philosophical investigations of dissecting the conceptions which present themselves, according to their
content, and so making them clear; but I mean the hitherto little attempted dissection of the faculty of
understanding itself, in order to investigate the possibility of conceptions a priori, by looking for them in the
understanding alone, as their birthplace, and analysing the pure use of this faculty. For this is the proper duty
of a transcendental philosophy; what remains is the logical treatment of the conceptions in philosophy in
general. We shall therefore follow up the pure conceptions even to their germs and beginnings in the human
understanding, in which they lie, until they are developed on occasions presented by experience, and, freed
by the same understanding from the empirical conditions attaching to them, are set forth in their unalloyed
purity.
CHAPTER I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure
Conceptions of the Understanding.
SS 3. Introductory.
When we call into play a faculty of cognition, different conceptions manifest themselves according to the
different circumstances, and make known this faculty, and assemble themselves into a more or less extensive
collection, according to the time or penetration that has been applied to the consideration of them. Where this
process, conducted as it is mechanically, so to speak, will end, cannot be determined with certainty. Besides,
the conceptions which we discover in this haphazard manner present themselves by no means in order and
systematic unity, but are at last coupled together only according to resemblances to each other, and arranged
in series, according to the quantity of their content, from the simpler to the more complex series which are
anything but systematic, though not altogether without a certain kind of method in their construction.
Transcendental philosophy has the advantage, and moreover the duty, of searching for its conceptions
according to a principle; because these conceptions spring pure and unmixed out of the understanding as an
absolute unity, and therefore must be connected with each other according to one conception or idea. A
connection of this kind, however, furnishes us with a ready prepared rule, by which its proper place may be
assigned to every pure conception of the understanding, and the completeness of the system of all be
determined a priori both which would otherwise have been dependent on mere choice or chance.
SECTION I. Of defined above Use of understanding in General.
SS 4
The understanding was defined above only negatively, as a nonsensuous faculty of cognition. Now,
independently of sensibility, we cannot possibly have any intuition; consequently, the understanding is no
faculty of intuition. But besides intuition there is no other mode of cognition, except through conceptions;
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK I. 41
Page No 46
consequently, the cognition of every, at least of every human, understanding is a cognition through
conceptions not intuitive, but discursive. All intuitions, as sensuous, depend on affections; conceptions,
therefore, upon functions. By the word function I understand the unity of the act of arranging diverse
representations under one common representation. Conceptions, then, are based on the spontaneity of
thought, as sensuous intuitions are on the receptivity of impressions. Now, the understanding cannot make
any other use of these conceptions than to judge by means of them. As no representation, except an intuition,
relates immediately to its object, a conception never relates immediately to an object, but only to some other
representation thereof, be that an intuition or itself a conception. A judgement, therefore, is the mediate
cognition of an object, consequently the representation of a representation of it. In every judgement there is a
conception which applies to, and is valid for many other conceptions, and which among these comprehends
also a given representation, this last being immediately connected with an object. For example, in the
judgement "All bodies are divisible," our conception of divisible applies to various other conceptions;
among these, however, it is here particularly applied to the conception of body, and this conception of body
relates to certain phenomena which occur to us. These objects, therefore, are mediately represented by the
conception of divisibility. All judgements, accordingly, are functions of unity in our representations,
inasmuch as, instead of an immediate, a higher representation, which comprises this and various others, is
used for our cognition of the object, and thereby many possible cognitions are collected into one. But we can
reduce all acts of the understanding to judgements, so that understanding may be represented as the faculty of
judging. For it is, according to what has been said above, a faculty of thought. Now thought is cognition by
means of conceptions. But conceptions, as predicates of possible judgements, relate to some representation of
a yet undetermined object. Thus the conception of body indicates something for example, metal which can
be cognized by means of that conception. It is therefore a conception, for the reason alone that other
representations are contained under it, by means of which it can relate to objects. It is therefore the predicate
to a possible judgement; for example: "Every metal is a body." All the functions of the understanding
therefore can be discovered, when we can completely exhibit the functions of unity in judgements. And that
this may be effected very easily, the following section will show.
SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in
Judgements.
SS 5.
If we abstract all the content of a judgement, and consider only the intellectual form thereof, we find that the
function of thought in a judgement can be brought under four heads, of which each contains three momenta.
These may be conveniently represented in the following table:
1
Quantity of judgements
Universal
Particular
Singular
2 3
Quality Relation
Affirmative Categorical
Negative Hypothetical
Infinite Disjunctive
4
Modality
Problematical
Assertorical
Apodeictical
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgements. 42
Page No 47
As this division appears to differ in some, though not essential points, from the usual technique of logicians,
the following observations, for the prevention of otherwise possible misunderstanding, will not be without
their use.
1. Logicians say, with justice, that in the use of judgements in syllogisms, singular judgements may be treated
like universal ones. For, precisely because a singular judgement has no extent at all, its predicate cannot refer
to a part of that which is contained in the conception of the subject and be excluded from the rest. The
predicate is valid for the whole conception just as if it were a general conception, and had extent, to the whole
of which the predicate applied. On the other hand, let us compare a singular with a general judgement, merely
as a cognition, in regard to quantity. The singular judgement relates to the general one, as unity to infinity,
and is therefore in itself essentially different. Thus, if we estimate a singular judgement (judicium singulare)
not merely according to its intrinsic validity as a judgement, but also as a cognition generally, according to its
quantity in comparison with that of other cognitions, it is then entirely different from a general judgement
(judicium commune), and in a complete table of the momenta of thought deserves a separate place though,
indeed, this would not be necessary in a logic limited merely to the consideration of the use of judgements in
reference to each other.
2. In like manner, in transcendental logic, infinite must be distinguished from affirmative judgements,
although in general logic they are rightly enough classed under affirmative. General logic abstracts all content
of the predicate (though it be negative), and only considers whether the said predicate be affirmed or denied
of the subject. But transcendental logic considers also the worth or content of this logical affirmation an
affirmation by means of a merely negative predicate, and inquires how much the sum total of our cognition
gains by this affirmation. For example, if I say of the soul, "It is not mortal" by this negative judgement I
should at least ward off error. Now, by the proposition, "The soul is not mortal," I have, in respect of the
logical form, really affirmed, inasmuch as I thereby place the soul in the unlimited sphere of immortal beings.
Now, because of the whole sphere of possible existences, the mortal occupies one part, and the immortal the
other, neither more nor less is affirmed by the proposition than that the soul is one among the infinite
multitude of things which remain over, when I take away the whole mortal part. But by this proceeding we
accomplish only this much, that the infinite sphere of all possible existences is in so far limited that the
mortal is excluded from it, and the soul is placed in the remaining part of the extent of this sphere. But this
part remains, notwithstanding this exception, infinite, and more and more parts may be taken away from the
whole sphere, without in the slightest degree thereby augmenting or affirmatively determining our conception
of the soul. These judgements, therefore, infinite in respect of their logical extent, are, in respect of the
content of their cognition, merely limitative; and are consequently entitled to a place in our transcendental
table of all the momenta of thought in judgements, because the function of the understanding exercised by
them may perhaps be of importance in the field of its pure a priori cognition.
3. All relations of thought in judgements are those (a) of the predicate to the subject; (b) of the principle to its
consequence; (c) of the divided cognition and all the members of the division to each other. In the first of
these three classes, we consider only two conceptions; in the second, two judgements; in the third, several
judgements in relation to each other. The hypothetical proposition, "If perfect justice exists, the obstinately
wicked are punished," contains properly the relation to each other of two propositions, namely, "Perfect
justice exists," and "The obstinately wicked are punished." Whether these propositions are in themselves true
is a question not here decided. Nothing is cogitated by means of this judgement except a certain consequence.
Finally, the disjunctive judgement contains a relation of two or more propositions to each other a relation
not of consequence, but of logical opposition, in so far as the sphere of the one proposition excludes that of
the other. But it contains at the same time a relation of community, in so far as all the propositions taken
together fill up the sphere of the cognition. The disjunctive judgement contains, therefore, the relation of the
parts of the whole sphere of a cognition, since the sphere of each part is a complemental part of the sphere of
the other, each contributing to form the sum total of the divided cognition. Take, for example, the
proposition, "The world exists either through blind chance, or through internal necessity, or through an
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgements. 43
Page No 48
external cause." Each of these propositions embraces a part of the sphere of our possible cognition as to the
existence of a world; all of them taken together, the whole sphere. To take the cognition out of one of these
spheres, is equivalent to placing it in one of the others; and, on the other hand, to place it in one sphere is
equivalent to taking it out of the rest. There is, therefore, in a disjunctive judgement a certain community of
cognitions, which consists in this, that they mutually exclude each other, yet thereby determine, as a whole,
the true cognition, inasmuch as, taken together, they make up the complete content of a particular given
cognition. And this is all that I find necessary, for the sake of what follows, to remark in this place.
4. The modality of judgements is a quite peculiar function, with this distinguishing characteristic, that it
contributes nothing to the content of a judgement (for besides quantity, quality, and relation, there is nothing
more that constitutes the content of a judgement), but concerns itself only with the value of the copula in
relation to thought in general. Problematical judgements are those in which the affirmation or negation is
accepted as merely possible (ad libitum). In the assertorical, we regard the proposition as real (true); in the
apodeictical, we look on it as necessary.* Thus the two judgements (antecedens et consequens), the relation
of which constitutes a hypothetical judgement, likewise those (the members of the division) in whose
reciprocity the disjunctive consists, are only problematical. In the example above given the proposition,
"There exists perfect justice," is not stated assertorically, but as an ad libitum judgement, which someone may
choose to adopt, and the consequence alone is assertorical. Hence such judgements may be obviously false,
and yet, taken problematically, be conditions of our cognition of the truth. Thus the proposition, "The world
exists only by blind chance," is in the disjunctive judgement of problematical import only: that is to say, one
may accept it for the moment, and it helps us (like the indication of the wrong road among all the roads that
one can take) to find out the true proposition. The problematical proposition is, therefore, that which
expresses only logical possibility (which is not objective); that is, it expresses a free choice to admit the
validity of such a proposition a merely arbitrary reception of it into the understanding. The assertorical
speaks of logical reality or truth; as, for example, in a hypothetical syllogism, the antecedens presents itself in
a problematical form in the major, in an assertorical form in the minor, and it shows that the proposition is in
harmony with the laws of the understanding. The apodeictical proposition cogitates the assertorical as
determined by these very laws of the understanding, consequently as affirming a priori, and in this manner it
expresses logical necessity. Now because all is here gradually incorporated with the understanding
inasmuch as in the first place we judge problematically; then accept assertorically our judgement as true;
lastly, affirm it as inseparably united with the understanding, that is, as necessary and apodeictical we may
safely reckon these three functions of modality as so many momenta of thought.
*Just as if thought were in the first instance a function of the understanding; in the second, of judgement; in
the third, of reason. A remark which will be explained in the sequel.
SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or
Categories.
SS 6
General logic, as has been repeatedly said, makes abstraction of all content of cognition, and expects to
receive representations from some other quarter, in order, by means of analysis, to convert them into
conceptions. On the contrary, transcendental logic has lying before it the manifold content of a priori
sensibility, which transcendental aesthetic presents to it in order to give matter to the pure conceptions of the
understanding, without which transcendental logic would have no content, and be therefore utterly void. Now
space and time contain an infinite diversity of determinations of pure a priori intuition, but are nevertheless
the condition of the mind's receptivity, under which alone it can obtain representations of objects, and which,
consequently, must always affect the conception of these objects. But the spontaneity of thought requires that
this diversity be examined after a certain manner, received into the mind, and connected, in order afterwards
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories. 44
Page No 49
to form a cognition out of it. This Process I call synthesis.
By the word synthesis, in its most general signification, I understand the process of joining different
representations to each other and of comprehending their diversity in one cognition. This synthesis is pure
when the diversity is not given empirically but a priori (as that in space and time). Our representations must
be given previously to any analysis of them; and no conceptions can arise, quoad their content, analytically.
But the synthesis of a diversity (be it given a priori or empirically) is the first requisite for the production of a
cognition, which in its beginning, indeed, may be crude and confused, and therefore in need of analysis still,
synthesis is that by which alone the elements of our cognitions are collected and united into a certain content,
consequently it is the first thing on which we must fix our attention, if we wish to investigate the origin of our
knowledge.
Synthesis, generally speaking, is, as we shall afterwards see, the mere operation of the imagination a blind
but indispensable function of the soul, without which we should have no cognition whatever, but of the
working of which we are seldom even conscious. But to reduce this synthesis to conceptions is a function of
the understanding, by means of which we attain to cognition, in the proper meaning of the term.
Pure synthesis, represented generally, gives us the pure conception of the understanding. But by this pure
synthesis, I mean that which rests upon a basis of a priori synthetical unity. Thus, our numeration (and this is
more observable in large numbers) is a synthesis according to conceptions, because it takes place according
to a common basis of unity (for example, the decade). By means of this conception, therefore, the unity in the
synthesis of the manifold becomes necessary.
By means of analysis different representations are brought under one conception an operation of which
general logic treats. On the other hand, the duty of transcendental logic is to reduce to conceptions, not
representations, but the pure synthesis of representations. The first thing which must be given to us for the
sake of the a priori cognition of all objects, is the diversity of the pure intuition; the synthesis of this diversity
by means of the imagination is the second; but this gives, as yet, no cognition. The conceptions which give
unity to this pure synthesis, and which consist solely in the representation of this necessary synthetical unity,
furnish the third requisite for the cognition of an object, and these conceptions are given by the
understanding.
The same function which gives unity to the different representation in a judgement, gives also unity to the
mere synthesis of different representations in an intuition; and this unity we call the pure conception of the
understanding. Thus, the same understanding, and by the same operations, whereby in conceptions, by means
of analytical unity, it produced the logical form of a judgement, introduces, by means of the synthetical unity
of the manifold in intuition, a transcendental content into its representations, on which account they are called
pure conceptions of the understanding, and they apply a priori to objects, a result not within the power of
general logic.
In this manner, there arise exactly so many pure conceptions of the understanding, applying a priori to objects
of intuition in general, as there are logical functions in all possible judgements. For there is no other function
or faculty existing in the understanding besides those enumerated in that table. These conceptions we shall,
with Aristotle, call categories, our purpose being originally identical with his, notwithstanding the great
difference in the execution.
TABLE OF THE CATEGORIES
1 2
Of Quantity Of Quality
Unity Reality
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories. 45
Page No 50
Plurality Negation
Totality Limitation
3
Of Relation
Of Inherence and Subsistence (substantia et accidens)
Of Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)
Of Community (reciprocity between the agent and patient)
4
Of Modality
Possibility Impossibility
Existence Nonexistence
Necessity Contingence
This, then, is a catalogue of all the originally pure conceptions of the synthesis which the understanding
contains a priori, and these conceptions alone entitle it to be called a pure understanding; inasmuch as only by
them it can render the manifold of intuition conceivable, in other words, think an object of intuition. This
division is made systematically from a common principle, namely the faculty of judgement (which is just the
same as the power of thought), and has not arisen rhapsodically from a search at haphazard after pure
conceptions, respecting the full number of which we never could be certain, inasmuch as we employ
induction alone in our search, without considering that in this way we can never understand wherefore
precisely these conceptions, and none others, abide in the pure understanding. It was a design worthy of an
acute thinker like Aristotle, to search for these fundamental conceptions. Destitute, however, of any guiding
principle, he picked them up just as they occurred to him, and at first hunted out ten, which he called
categories (predicaments). Afterwards be believed that he had discovered five others, which were added
under the name of post predicaments. But his catalogue still remained defective. Besides, there are to be
found among them some of the modes of pure sensibility (quando, ubi, situs, also prius, simul), and likewise
an empirical conception (motus) which can by no means belong to this genealogical register of the pure
understanding. Moreover, there are deduced conceptions (actio, passio) enumerated among the original
conceptions, and, of the latter, some are entirely wanting.
With regard to these, it is to be remarked, that the categories, as the true primitive conceptions of the pure
understanding, have also their pure deduced conceptions, which, in a complete system of transcendental
philosophy, must by no means be passed over; though in a merely critical essay we must be contented with
the simple mention of the fact.
Let it be allowed me to call these pure, but deduced conceptions of the understanding, the predicables of the
pure understanding, in contradistinction to predicaments. If we are in possession of the original and primitive,
the deduced and subsidiary conceptions can easily be added, and the genealogical tree of the understanding
completely delineated. As my present aim is not to set forth a complete system, but merely the principles of
one, I reserve this task for another time. It may be easily executed by any one who will refer to the
ontological manuals, and subordinate to the category of causality, for example, the predicables of force,
action, passion; to that of community, those of presence and resistance; to the categories of modality, those of
origination, extinction, change; and so with the rest. The categories combined with the modes of pure
sensibility, or with one another, afford a great number of deduced a priori conceptions; a complete
enumeration of which would be a useful and not unpleasant, but in this place a perfectly dispensable,
occupation.
I purposely omit the definitions of the categories in this treatise. I shall analyse these conceptions only so far
as is necessary for the doctrine of method, which is to form a part of this critique. In a system of pure reason,
definitions of them would be with justice demanded of me, but to give them here would only bide from our
view the main aim of our investigation, at the same time raising doubts and objections, the consideration of
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories. 46
Page No 51
which, without injustice to our main purpose, may be very well postponed till another opportunity.
Meanwhile, it ought to be sufficiently clear, from the little we have already said on this subject, that the
formation of a complete vocabulary of pure conceptions, accompanied by all the requisite explanations, is not
only a possible, but an easy undertaking. The compartments already exist; it is only necessary to fill them up;
and a systematic topic like the present, indicates with perfect precision the proper place to which each
conception belongs, while it readily points out any that have not yet been filled up.
SS 7
Our table of the categories suggests considerations of some importance, which may perhaps have significant
results in regard to the scientific form of all rational cognitions. For, that this table is useful in the theoretical
part of philosophy, nay, indispensable for the sketching of the complete plan of a science, so far as that
science rests upon conceptions a priori, and for dividing it mathematically, according to fixed principles, is
most manifest from the fact that it contains all the elementary conceptions of the understanding, nay, even the
form of a system of these in the understanding itself, and consequently indicates all the momenta, and also
the internal arrangement of a projected speculative science, as I have elsewhere shown.* Here follow some of
these observations.
*In the Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science.
I. This table, which contains four classes of conceptions of the understanding, may, in the first instance, be
divided into two classes, the first of which relates to objects of intuition pure as well as empirical; the
second, to the existence of these objects, either in relation to one another, or to the understanding.
The former of these classes of categories I would entitle the mathematical, and the latter the dynamical
categories. The former, as we see, has no correlates; these are only to be found in the second class. This
difference must have a ground in the nature of the human understanding.
II. The number of the categories in each class is always the same, namely, three a fact which also demands
some consideration, because in all other cases division a priori through conceptions is necessarily dichotomy.
It is to be added, that the third category in each triad always arises from the combination of the second with
the first.
Thus totality is nothing else but plurality contemplated as unity; limitation is merely reality conjoined with
negation; community is the causality of a substance, reciprocally determining, and determined by other
substances; and finally, necessity is nothing but existence, which is given through the possibility itself. Let it
not be supposed, however, that the third category is merely a deduced, and not a primitive conception of the
pure understanding. For the conjunction of the first and second, in order to produce the third conception,
requires a particular function of the understanding, which is by no means identical with those which are
exercised in the first and second. Thus, the conception of a number (which belongs to the category of totality)
is not always possible, where the conceptions of multitude and unity exist (for example, in the representation
of the infinite). Or, if I conjoin the conception of a cause with that of a substance, it does not follow that the
conception of influence, that is, how one substance can be the cause of something in another substance, will
be understood from that. Thus it is evident that a particular act of the understanding is here necessary; and so
in the other instances.
III. With respect to one category, namely, that of community, which is found in the third class, it is not so
easy as with the others to detect its accordance with the form of the disjunctive judgement which corresponds
to it in the table of the logical functions.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 7 47
Page No 52
In order to assure ourselves of this accordance, we must observe that in every disjunctive judgement, the
sphere of the judgement (that is, the complex of all that is contained in it) is represented as a whole divided
into parts; and, since one part cannot be contained in the other, they are cogitated as coordinated with, not
subordinated to each other, so that they do not determine each other unilaterally, as in a linear series, but
reciprocally, as in an aggregate (if one member of the division is posited, all the rest are excluded; and
conversely).
Now a like connection is cogitated in a whole of things; for one thing is not subordinated, as effect, to another
as cause of its existence, but, on the contrary, is coordinated contemporaneously and reciprocally, as a cause
in relation to the determination of the others (for example, in a body the parts of which mutually attract and
repel each other). And this is an entirely different kind of connection from that which we find in the mere
relation of the cause to the effect (the principle to the consequence), for in such a connection the consequence
does not in its turn determine the principle, and therefore does not constitute, with the latter, a whole just as
the Creator does not with the world make up a whole. The process of understanding by which it represents to
itself the sphere of a divided conception, is employed also when we think of a thing as divisible; and in the
same manner as the members of the division in the former exclude one another, and yet are connected in one
sphere, so the understanding represents to itself the parts of the latter, as having each of them an existence
(as substances), independently of the others, and yet as united in one whole.
SS 8
In the transcendental philosophy of the ancients there exists one more leading division, which contains pure
conceptions of the understanding, and which, although not numbered among the categories, ought, according
to them, as conceptions a priori, to be valid of objects. But in this case they would augment the number of the
categories; which cannot be. These are set forth in the proposition, so renowned among the schoolmen
"Quodlibet ens est UNUM, VERUM, BONUM." Now, though the inferences from this principle were mere
tautological propositions, and though it is allowed only by courtesy to retain a place in modern metaphysics,
yet a thought which maintained itself for such a length of time, however empty it seems to be, deserves an
investigation of its origin, and justifies the conjecture that it must be grounded in some law of the
understanding, which, as is often the case, has only been erroneously interpreted. These pretended
transcendental predicates are, in fact, nothing but logical requisites and criteria of all cognition of objects, and
they employ, as the basis for this cognition, the categories of quantity, namely, unity, plurality, and totality.
But these, which must be taken as material conditions, that is, as belonging to the possibility of things
themselves, they employed merely in a formal signification, as belonging to the logical requisites of all
cognition, and yet most unguardedly changed these criteria of thought into properties of objects, as things in
themselves. Now, in every cognition of an object, there is unity of conception, which may be called
qualitative unity, so far as by this term we understand only the unity in our connection of the manifold; for
example, unity of the theme in a play, an oration, or a story. Secondly, there is truth in respect of the
deductions from it. The more true deductions we have from a given conception, the more criteria of its
objective reality. This we might call the qualitative plurality of characteristic marks, which belong to a
conception as to a common foundation, but are not cogitated as a quantity in it. Thirdly, there is perfection
which consists in this, that the plurality falls back upon the unity of the conception, and accords completely
with that conception and with no other. This we may denominate qualitative completeness. Hence it is
evident that these logical criteria of the possibility of cognition are merely the three categories of quantity
modified and transformed to suit an unauthorized manner of applying them. That is to say, the three
categories, in which the unity in the production of the quantum must be homogeneous throughout, are
transformed solely with a view to the connection of heterogeneous parts of cognition in one act of
consciousness, by means of the quality of the cognition, which is the principle of that connection. Thus the
criterion of the possibility of a conception (not of its object) is the definition of it, in which the unity of the
conception, the truth of all that may be immediately deduced from it, and finally, the completeness of what
has been thus deduced, constitute the requisites for the reproduction of the whole conception. Thus also, the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 8 48
Page No 53
criterion or test of an hypothesis is the intelligibility of the received principle of explanation, or its unity
(without help from any subsidiary hypothesis) the truth of our deductions from it (consistency with each
other and with experience) and lastly, the completeness of the principle of the explanation of these
deductions, which refer to neither more nor less than what was admitted in the hypothesis, restoring
analytically and a posteriori, what was cogitated synthetically and a priori. By the conceptions, therefore, of
unity, truth, and perfection, we have made no addition to the transcendental table of the categories, which is
complete without them. We have, on the contrary, merely employed the three categories of quantity, setting
aside their application to objects of experience, as general logical laws of the consistency of cognition with
itself.
CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the
Understanding.
SECTION I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in general.
SS 9
Teachers of jurisprudence, when speaking of rights and claims, distinguish in a cause the question of right
(quid juris) from the question of fact (quid facti), and while they demand proof of both, they give to the proof
of the former, which goes to establish right or claim in law, the name of deduction. Now we make use of a
great number of empirical conceptions, without opposition from any one; and consider ourselves, even
without any attempt at deduction, justified in attaching to them a sense, and a supposititious signification,
because we have always experience at hand to demonstrate their objective reality. There exist also, however,
usurped conceptions, such as fortune, fate, which circulate with almost universal indulgence, and yet are
occasionally challenged by the question, "quid juris?" In such cases, we have great difficulty in discovering
any deduction for these terms, inasmuch as we cannot produce any manifest ground of right, either from
experience or from reason, on which the claim to employ them can be founded.
Among the many conceptions, which make up the very variegated web of human cognition, some are
destined for pure use a priori, independent of all experience; and their title to be so employed always requires
a deduction, inasmuch as, to justify such use of them, proofs from experience are not sufficient; but it is
necessary to know how these conceptions can apply to objects without being derived from experience. I term,
therefore, an examination of the manner in which conceptions can apply a priori to objects, the transcendental
deduction of conceptions, and I distinguish it from the empirical deduction, which indicates the mode in
which conception is obtained through experience and reflection thereon; consequently, does not concern itself
with the right, but only with the fact of our obtaining conceptions in such and such a manner. We have
already seen that we are in possession of two perfectly different kinds of conceptions, which nevertheless
agree with each other in this, that they both apply to objects completely a priori. These are the conceptions of
space and time as forms of sensibility, and the categories as pure conceptions of the understanding. To
attempt an empirical deduction of either of these classes would be labour in vain, because the distinguishing
characteristic of their nature consists in this, that they apply to their objects, without having borrowed
anything from experience towards the representation of them. Consequently, if a deduction of these
conceptions is necessary, it must always be transcendental.
Meanwhile, with respect to these conceptions, as with respect to all our cognition, we certainly may discover
in experience, if not the principle of their possibility, yet the occasioning causes of their production. It will be
found that the impressions of sense give the first occasion for bringing into action the whole faculty of
cognition, and for the production of experience, which contains two very dissimilar elements, namely, a
matter for cognition, given by the senses, and a certain form for the arrangement of this matter, arising out of
the inner fountain of pure intuition and thought; and these, on occasion given by sensuous impressions, are
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 49
Page No 54
called into exercise and produce conceptions. Such an investigation into the first efforts of our faculty of
cognition to mount from particular perceptions to general conceptions is undoubtedly of great utility; and we
have to thank the celebrated Locke for having first opened the way for this inquiry. But a deduction of the
pure a priori conceptions of course never can be made in this way, seeing that, in regard to their future
employment, which must be entirely independent of experience, they must have a far different certificate of
birth to show from that of a descent from experience. This attempted physiological derivation, which cannot
properly be called deduction, because it relates merely to a quaestio facti, I shall entitle an explanation of the
possession of a pure cognition. It is therefore manifest that there can only be a transcendental deduction of
these conceptions and by no means an empirical one; also, that all attempts at an empirical deduction, in
regard to pure a priori conceptions, are vain, and can only be made by one who does not understand the
altogether peculiar nature of these cognitions.
But although it is admitted that the only possible deduction of pure a priori cognition is a transcendental
deduction, it is not, for that reason, perfectly manifest that such a deduction is absolutely necessary. We have
already traced to their sources the conceptions of space and time, by means of a transcendental deduction, and
we have explained and determined their objective validity a priori. Geometry, nevertheless, advances steadily
and securely in the province of pure a priori cognitions, without needing to ask from philosophy any
certificate as to the pure and legitimate origin of its fundamental conception of space. But the use of the
conception in this science extends only to the external world of sense, the pure form of the intuition of which
is space; and in this world, therefore, all geometrical cognition, because it is founded upon a priori intuition,
possesses immediate evidence, and the objects of this cognition are given a priori (as regards their form) in
intuition by and through the cognition itself. With the pure conceptions of understanding, on the contrary,
commences the absolute necessity of seeking a transcendental deduction, not only of these conceptions
themselves, but likewise of space, because, inasmuch as they make affirmations concerning objects not by
means of the predicates of intuition and sensibility, but of pure thought a priori, they apply to objects without
any of the conditions of sensibility. Besides, not being founded on experience, they are not presented with
any object in a priori intuition upon which, antecedently to experience, they might base their synthesis. Hence
results, not only doubt as to the objective validity and proper limits of their use, but that even our conception
of space is rendered equivocal; inasmuch as we are very ready with the aid of the categories, to carry the use
of this conception beyond the conditions of sensuous intuition and, for this reason, we have already found a
transcendental deduction of it needful. The reader, then, must be quite convinced of the absolute necessity of
a transcendental deduction, before taking a single step in the field of pure reason; because otherwise he goes
to work blindly, and after he has wondered about in all directions, returns to the state of utter ignorance from
which he started. He ought, moreover, clearly to recognize beforehand the unavoidable difficulties in his
undertaking, so that he may not afterwards complain of the obscurity in which the subject itself is deeply
involved, or become too soon impatient of the obstacles in his path; because we have a choice of only two
things either at once to give up all pretensions to knowledge beyond the limits of possible experience, or to
bring this critical investigation to completion.
We have been able, with very little trouble, to make it comprehensible how the conceptions of space and
time, although a priori cognitions, must necessarily apply to external objects, and render a synthetical
cognition of these possible, independently of all experience. For inasmuch as only by means of such pure
form of sensibility an object can appear to us, that is, be an object of empirical intuition, space and time are
pure intuitions, which contain a priori the condition of the possibility of objects as phenomena, and an a priori
synthesis in these intuitions possesses objective validity.
On the other hand, the categories of the understanding do not represent the conditions under which objects
are given to us in intuition; objects can consequently appear to us without necessarily connecting themselves
with these, and consequently without any necessity binding on the understanding to contain a priori the
conditions of these objects. Thus we find ourselves involved in a difficulty which did not present itself in the
sphere of sensibility, that is to say, we cannot discover how the subjective conditions of thought can have
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 50
Page No 55
objective validity, in other words, can become conditions of the possibility of all cognition of objects; for
phenomena may certainly be given to us in intuition without any help from the functions of the
understanding. Let us take, for example, the conception of cause, which indicates a peculiar kind of synthesis,
namely, that with something, A, something entirely different, B, is connected according to a law. It is not a
priori manifest why phenomena should contain anything of this kind (we are of course debarred from
appealing for proof to experience, for the objective validity of this conception must be demonstrated a priori),
and it hence remains doubtful a priori, whether such a conception be not quite void and without any
corresponding object among phenomena. For that objects of sensuous intuition must correspond to the formal
conditions of sensibility existing a priori in the mind is quite evident, from the fact that without these they
could not be objects for us; but that they must also correspond to the conditions which understanding requires
for the synthetical unity of thought is an assertion, the grounds for which are not so easily to be discovered.
For phenomena might be so constituted as not to correspond to the conditions of the unity of thought; and all
things might lie in such confusion that, for example, nothing could be met with in the sphere of phenomena to
suggest a law of synthesis, and so correspond to the conception of cause and effect; so that this conception
would be quite void, null, and without significance. Phenomena would nevertheless continue to present
objects to our intuition; for mere intuition does not in any respect stand in need of the functions of thought.
If we thought to free ourselves from the labour of these investigations by saying: "Experience is constantly
offering us examples of the relation of cause and effect in phenomena, and presents us with abundant
opportunity of abstracting the conception of cause, and so at the same time of corroborating the objective
validity of this conception"; we should in this case be overlooking the fact, that the conception of cause
cannot arise in this way at all; that, on the contrary, it must either have an a priori basis in the, understanding,
or be rejected as a mere chimera. For this conception demands that something, A, should be of such a nature
that something else, B, should follow from it necessarily, and according to an absolutely universal law. We
may certainly collect from phenomena a law, according to which this or that usually happens, but the element
of necessity is not to be found in it. Hence it is evident that to the synthesis of cause and effect belongs a
dignity, which is utterly wanting in any empirical synthesis; for it is no mere mechanical synthesis, by means
of addition, but a dynamical one; that is to say, the effect is not to be cogitated as merely annexed to the
cause, but as posited by and through the cause, and resulting from it. The strict universality of this law never
can be a characteristic of empirical laws, which obtain through induction only a comparative universality, that
is, an extended range of practical application. But the pure conceptions of the understanding would entirely
lose all their peculiar character, if we treated them merely as the productions of experience.
Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. SS 10
There are only two possible ways in which synthetical representation and its objects can coincide with and
relate necessarily to each other, and, as it were, meet together. Either the object alone makes the
representation possible, or the representation alone makes the object possible. In the former case, the relation
between them is only empirical, and an a priori representation is impossible. And this is the case with
phenomena, as regards that in them which is referable to mere sensation. In the latter case although
representation alone (for of its causality, by means of the will, we do not here speak) does not produce the
object as to its existence, it must nevertheless be a priori determinative in regard to the object, if it is only by
means of the representation that we can cognize anything as an object. Now there are only two conditions of
the possibility of a cognition of objects; firstly, intuition, by means of which the object, though only as
phenomenon, is given; secondly, conception, by means of which the object which corresponds to this
intuition is thought. But it is evident from what has been said on aesthetic that the first condition, under
which alone objects can be intuited, must in fact exist, as a formal basis for them, a priori in the mind. With
this formal condition of sensibility, therefore, all phenomena necessarily correspond, because it is only
through it that they can be phenomena at all; that is, can be empirically intuited and given. Now the question
is whether there do not exist, a priori in the mind, conceptions of understanding also, as conditions under
which alone something, if not intuited, is yet thought as object. If this question be answered in the
The Critique of Pure Reason
Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. SS 10 51
Page No 56
affirmative, it follows that all empirical cognition of objects is necessarily conformable to such conceptions,
since, if they are not presupposed, it is impossible that anything can be an object of experience. Now all
experience contains, besides the intuition of the senses through which an object is given, a conception also of
an object that is given in intuition. Accordingly, conceptions of objects in general must lie as a priori
conditions at the foundation of all empirical cognition; and consequently, the objective validity of the
categories, as a priori conceptions, will rest upon this, that experience (as far as regards the form of thought)
is possible only by their means. For in that case they apply necessarily and a priori to objects of experience,
because only through them can an object of experience be thought.
The whole aim of the transcendental deduction of all a priori conceptions is to show that these conceptions
are a priori conditions of the possibility of all experience. Conceptions which afford us the objective
foundation of the possibility of experience are for that very reason necessary. But the analysis of the
experiences in which they are met with is not deduction, but only an illustration of them, because from
experience they could never derive the attribute of necessity. Without their original applicability and relation
to all possible experience, in which all objects of cognition present themselves, the relation of the categories
to objects, of whatever nature, would be quite incomprehensible.
The celebrated Locke, for want of due reflection on these points, and because he met with pure conceptions
of the understanding in experience, sought also to deduce them from experience, and yet proceeded so
inconsequently as to attempt, with their aid, to arrive it cognitions which lie far beyond the limits of all
experience. David Hume perceived that, to render this possible, it was necessary that the conceptions should
have an a priori origin. But as he could not explain how it was possible that conceptions which are not
connected with each other in the understanding must nevertheless be thought as necessarily connected in the
object and it never occurred to him that the understanding itself might, perhaps, by means of these
conceptions, be the author of the experience in which its objects were presented to it he was forced to drive
these conceptions from experience, that is, from a subjective necessity arising from repeated association of
experiences erroneously considered to be objective in one word, from habit. But he proceeded with perfect
consequence and declared it to be impossible, with such conceptions and the principles arising from them, to
overstep the limits of experience. The empirical derivation, however, which both of these philosophers
attributed to these conceptions, cannot possibly be reconciled with the fact that we do possess scientific a
priori cognitions, namely, those of pure mathematics and general physics.
The former of these two celebrated men opened a wide door to extravagance (for if reason has once
undoubted right on its side, it will not allow itself to be confined to set limits, by vague recommendations of
moderation); the latter gave himself up entirely to scepticism a natural consequence, after having
discovered, as he thought, that the faculty of cognition was not trustworthy. We now intend to make a trial
whether it be not possible safely to conduct reason between these two rocks, to assign her determinate limits,
and yet leave open for her the entire sphere of her legitimate activity.
I shall merely premise an explanation of what the categories are. They are conceptions of an object in
general, by means of which its intuition is contemplated as determined in relation to one of the logical
functions of judgement. The following will make this plain. The function of the categorical judgement is that
of the relation of subject to predicate; for example, in the proposition: "All bodies are divisible." But in
regard to the merely logical use of the understanding, it still remains undetermined to which Of these two
conceptions belongs the function Of subject and to which that of predicate. For we could also say: "Some
divisible is a body." But the category of substance, when the conception of a body is brought under it,
determines that; and its empirical intuition in experience must be contemplated always as subject and never
as mere predicate. And so with all the other categories.
The Critique of Pure Reason
Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. SS 10 52
Page No 57
SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the
Understanding.
SS 11 Of the Possibility of a Conjunction of the manifold
representations given by Sense.
The manifold content in our representations can be given in an intuition which is merely sensuous in other
words, is nothing but susceptibility; and the form of this intuition can exist a priori in our faculty of
representation, without being anything else but the mode in which the subject is affected. But the conjunction
(conjunctio) of a manifold in intuition never can be given us by the senses; it cannot therefore be contained in
the pure form of sensuous intuition, for it is a spontaneous act of the faculty of representation. And as we
must, to distinguish it from sensibility, entitle this faculty understanding; so all conjunction whether
conscious or unconscious, be it of the manifold in intuition, sensuous or nonsensuous, or of several
conceptions is an act of the understanding. To this act we shall give the general appellation of synthesis,
thereby to indicate, at the same time, that we cannot represent anything as conjoined in the object without
having previously conjoined it ourselves. Of all mental notions, that of conjunction is the only one which
cannot be given through objects, but can be originated only by the subject itself, because it is an act of its
purely spontaneous activity. The reader will easily enough perceive that the possibility of conjunction must
be grounded in the very nature of this act, and that it must be equally valid for all conjunction, and that
analysis, which appears to be its contrary, must, nevertheless, always presuppose it; for where the
understanding has not previously conjoined, it cannot dissect or analyse, because only as conjoined by it,
must that which is to be analysed have been given to our faculty of representation.
But the conception of conjunction includes, besides the conception of the manifold and of the synthesis of it,
that of the unity of it also. Conjunction is the representation of the synthetical unity of the manifold.* This
idea of unity, therefore, cannot arise out of that of conjunction; much rather does that idea, by combining
itself with the representation of the manifold, render the conception of conjunction possible. This unity,
which a priori precedes all conceptions of conjunction, is not the category of unity (SS 6); for all the
categories are based upon logical functions of judgement, and in these functions we already have conjunction,
and consequently unity of given conceptions. It is therefore evident that the category of unity presupposes
conjunction. We must therefore look still higher for this unity (as qualitative, SS 8), in that, namely, which
contains the ground of the unity of diverse conceptions in judgements, the ground, consequently, of the
possibility of the existence of the understanding, even in regard to its logical use.
*Whether the representations are in themselves identical, and consequently whether one can be thought
analytically by means of and through the other, is a question which we need not at present consider. Our
Consciousness of the one, when we speak of the manifold, is always distinguishable from our consciousness
of the other; and it is only respecting the synthesis of this (possible) consciousness that we here treat.
Of the Originally Synthetical Unity of Apperception. SS 12
The "I think" must accompany all my representations, for otherwise something would be represented in me
which could not be thought; in other words, the representation would either be impossible, or at least be, in
relation to me, nothing. That representation which can be given previously to all thought is called intuition.
All the diversity or manifold content of intuition, has, therefore, a necessary relation to the 'I think," in the
subject in which this diversity is found. But this representation, "I think," is an act of spontaneity; that is to
say, it cannot be regarded as belonging to mere sensibility. I call it pure apperception, in order to distinguish
it from empirical; or primitive apperception, because it is selfconsciousness which, whilst it gives birth to
the representation" I think," must necessarily be capable of accompanying all our representations. It is in all
acts of consciousness one and the same, and unaccompanied by it, no representation can exist for me. The
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 53
Page No 58
unity of this apperception I call the transcendental unity of selfconsciousness, in order to indicate the
possibility of a priori cognition arising from it. For the manifold representations which are given in an
intuition would not all of them be my representations, if they did not all belong to one selfconsciousness,
that is, as my representations (even although I am not conscious of them as such), they must conform to the
condition under which alone they can exist together in a common selfconsciousness, because otherwise they
would not all without exception belong to me. From this primitive conjunction follow many important
results.
For example, this universal identity of the apperception of the manifold given in intuition contains a synthesis
of representations and is possible only by means of the consciousness of this synthesis. For the empirical
consciousness which accompanies different representations is in itself fragmentary and disunited, and without
relation to the identity of the subject. This relation, then, does not exist because I accompany every
representation with consciousness, but because I join one representation to another, and am conscious of the
synthesis of them. Consequently, only because I can connect a variety of given representations in one
consciousness, is it possible that I can represent to myself the identity of consciousness in these
representations; in other words, the analytical unity of apperception is possible only under the presupposition
of a synthetical unity.* The thought, "These representations given in intuition belong all of them to me," is
accordingly just the same as, "I unite them in one selfconsciousness, or can at least so unite them"; and
although this thought is not itself the consciousness of the synthesis of representations, it presupposes the
possibility of it; that is to say, for the reason alone that I can comprehend the variety of my representations in
one consciousness, do I call them my representations, for otherwise I must have as manycoloured and
various a self as are the representations of which I am conscious. Synthetical unity of the manifold in
intuitions, as given a priori, is therefore the foundation of the identity of apperception itself, which antecedes
a priori all determinate thought. But the conjunction of representations into a conception is not to be found in
objects themselves, nor can it be, as it were, borrowed from them and taken up into the understanding by
perception, but it is on the contrary an operation of the understanding itself, which is nothing more than the
faculty of conjoining a priori and of bringing the variety of given representations under the unity of
apperception. This principle is the highest in all human cognition.
*All general conceptions as such depend, for their existence, on the analytical unity of consciousness. For
example, when I think of red in general, I thereby think to myself a property which (as a characteristic mark)
can be discovered somewhere, or can be united with other representations; consequently, it is only by means
of a forethought possible synthetical unity that I can think to myself the analytical. A representation which is
cogitated as common to different representations, is regarded as belonging to such as, besides this common
representation, contain something different; consequently it must be previously thought in synthetical unity
with other although only possible representations, before I can think in it the analytical unity of
consciousness which makes it a conceptas communis. And thus the synthetical unity of apperception is the
highest point with which we must connect every operation of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and
after it our transcendental philosophy; indeed, this faculty is the understanding itself.
This fundamental principle of the necessary unity of apperception is indeed an identical, and therefore
analytical, proposition; but it nevertheless explains the necessity for a synthesis of the manifold given in an
intuition, without which the identity of selfconsciousness would be incogitable. For the ego, as a simple
representation, presents us with no manifold content; only in intuition, which is quite different from the
representation ego, can it be given us, and by means of conjunction it is cogitated in one selfconsciousness.
An understanding, in which all the manifold should be given by means of consciousness itself, would be
intuitive; our understanding can only think and must look for its intuition to sense. I am, therefore, conscious
of my identical self, in relation to all the variety of representations given to me in an intuition, because I call
all of them my representations. In other words, I am conscious myself of a necessary a priori synthesis of my
representations, which is called the original synthetical unity of apperception, under which rank all the
representations presented to me, but that only by means of a synthesis.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 54
Page No 59
The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception is the highest
Principle of all exercise of the Understanding. SS 13
The supreme principle of the possibility of all intuition in relation to sensibility was, according to our
transcendental aesthetic, that all the manifold in intuition be subject to the formal conditions of space and
time. The supreme principle of the possibility of it in relation to the understanding is that all the manifold in it
be subject to conditions of the originally synthetical unity or apperception.* To the former of these two
principles are subject all the various representations of intuition, in so far as they are given to us; to the latter,
in so far as they must be capable of conjunction in one consciousness; for without this nothing can be thought
or cognized, because the given representations would not have in common the act Of the apperception "I
think" and therefore could not be connected in one selfconsciousness.
*Space and time, and all portions thereof, are intuitions; consequently are, with a manifold for their content,
single representations. (See the Transcendental Aesthetic.) Consequently, they are not pure conceptions, by
means of which the same consciousness is found in a great number of representations; but, on the contrary,
they are many representations contained in one, the consciousness of which is, so to speak, compounded. The
unity of consciousness is nevertheless synthetical and, therefore, primitive. From this peculiar character of
consciousness follow many important consequences. (See SS 21.)
Understanding is, to speak generally, the faculty Of cognitions. These consist in the determined relation of
given representation to an object. But an object is that, in the conception of which the manifold in a given
intuition is united. Now all union of representations requires unity of consciousness in the synthesis of them.
Consequently, it is the unity of consciousness alone that constitutes the possibility of representations relating
to an object, and therefore of their objective validity, and of their becoming cognitions, and consequently, the
possibility of the existence of the understanding itself.
The first pure cognition of understanding, then, upon which is founded all its other exercise, and which is at
the same time perfectly independent of all conditions of mere sensuous intuition, is the principle of the
original synthetical unity of apperception. Thus the mere form of external sensuous intuition, namely, space,
affords us, per se, no cognition; it merely contributes the manifold in a priori intuition to a possible cognition.
But, in order to cognize something in space (for example, a line), I must draw it, and thus produce
synthetically a determined conjunction of the given manifold, so that the unity of this act is at the same time
the unity of consciousness (in the conception of a line), and by this means alone is an object (a determinate
space) cognized. The synthetical unity of consciousness is, therefore, an objective condition of all cognition,
which I do not merely require in order to cognize an object, but to which every intuition must necessarily be
subject, in order to become an object for me; because in any other way, and without this synthesis, the
manifold in intuition could not be united in one consciousness.
This proposition is, as already said, itself analytical, although it constitutes the synthetical unity, the condition
of all thought; for it states nothing more than that all my representations in any given intuition must be
subject to the condition which alone enables me to connect them, as my representation with the identical self,
and so to unite them synthetically in one apperception, by means of the general expression, "I think."
But this principle is not to be regarded as a principle for every possible understanding, but only for the
understanding by means of whose pure apperception in the thought I am, no manifold content is given. The
understanding or mind which contained the manifold in intuition, in and through the act itself of its own
selfconsciousness, in other words, an understanding by and in the representation of which the objects of the
representation should at the same time exist, would not require a special act of synthesis of the manifold as
the condition of the unity of its consciousness, an act of which the human understanding, which thinks only
and cannot intuite, has absolute need. But this principle is the first principle of all the operations of our
The Critique of Pure Reason
The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception is the highest Principle of all exercise of the Understanding. SS 13 55
Page No 60
understanding, so that we cannot form the least conception of any other possible understanding, either of one
such as should be itself intuition, or possess a sensuous intuition, but with forms different from those of space
and time.
What Objective Unity of Selfconsciousness is. SS 14
It is by means of the transcendental unity of apperception that all the manifold, given in an intuition is united
into a conception of the object. On this account it is called objective, and must be distinguished from the
subjective unity of consciousness, which is a determination of the internal sense, by means of which the said
manifold in intuition is given empirically to be so united. Whether I can be empirically conscious of the
manifold as coexistent or as successive, depends upon circumstances, or empirical conditions. Hence the
empirical unity of consciousness by means of association of representations, itself relates to a phenomenal
world and is wholly contingent. On the contrary, the pure form of intuition in time, merely as an intuition,
which contains a given manifold, is subject to the original unity of consciousness, and that solely by means of
the necessary relation of the manifold in intuition to the "I think," consequently by means of the pure
synthesis of the understanding, which lies a priori at the foundation of all empirical synthesis. The
transcendental unity of apperception is alone objectively valid; the empirical which we do not consider in this
essay, and which is merely a unity deduced from the former under given conditions in concreto, possesses
only subjective validity. One person connects the notion conveyed in a word with one thing, another with
another thing; and the unity of consciousness in that which is empirical, is, in relation to that which is given
by experience, not necessarily and universally valid.
The Logical Form of all Judgements consists in the Objective Unity of
Apperception of the Conceptions contained therein. SS 15
I could never satisfy myself with the definition which logicians give of a judgement. It is, according to them,
the representation of a relation between two conceptions. I shall not dwell here on the faultiness of this
definition, in that it suits only for categorical and not for hypothetical or disjunctive judgements, these latter
containing a relation not of conceptions but of judgements themselves a blunder from which many evil
results have followed.* It is more important for our present purpose to observe, that this definition does not
determine in what the said relation consists.
*The tedious doctrine of the four syllogistic figures concerns only categorical syllogisms; and although it is
nothing more than an artifice by surreptitiously introducing immediate conclusions (consequentiae
immediatae) among the premises of a pure syllogism, to give ism' give rise to an appearance of more modes
of drawing a conclusion than that in the first figure, the artifice would not have had much success, had not its
authors succeeded in bringing categorical judgements into exclusive respect, as those to which all others must
be referred a doctrine, however, which, according to SS 5, is utterly false.
But if I investigate more closely the relation of given cognitions in every judgement, and distinguish it, as
belonging to the understanding, from the relation which is produced according to laws of the reproductive
imagination (which has only subjective validity), I find that judgement is nothing but the mode of bringing
given cognitions under the objective unit of apperception. This is plain from our use of the term of relation is
in judgements, in order to distinguish the objective unity of given representations from the subjective unity.
For this term indicates the relation of these representations to the original apperception, and also their
necessary unity, even although the judgement is empirical, therefore contingent, as in the judgement: "All
bodies are heavy." I do not mean by this, that these representations do necessarily belong to each other in
empirical intuition, but that by means of the necessary unity of appreciation they belong to each other in the
synthesis of intuitions, that is to say, they belong to each other according to principles of the objective
determination of all our representations, in so far as cognition can arise from them, these principles being all
The Critique of Pure Reason
What Objective Unity of Selfconsciousness is. SS 14 56
Page No 61
deduced from the main principle of the transcendental unity of apperception. In this way alone can there arise
from this relation a judgement, that is, a relation which has objective validity, and is perfectly distinct from
that relation of the very same representations which has only subjective validity a relation, to wit, which is
produced according to laws of association. According to these laws, I could only say: "When I hold in my
hand or carry a body, I feel an impression of weight"; but I could not say: "It, the body, is heavy"; for this is
tantamount to saying both these representations are conjoined in the object, that is, without distinction as to
the condition of the subject, and do not merely stand together in my perception, however frequently the
perceptive act may be repeated.
All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as Conditions
under which alone the manifold Content of them can be united in one
Consciousness. SS 16
The manifold content given in a sensuous intuition comes necessarily under the original synthetical unity of
apperception, because thereby alone is the unity of intuition possible (SS 13). But that act of the
understanding, by which the manifold content of given representations (whether intuitions or conceptions) is
brought under one apperception, is the logical function of judgements (SS 15). All the manifold, therefore, in
so far as it is given in one empirical intuition, is determined in relation to one of the logical functions of
judgement, by means of which it is brought into union in one consciousness. Now the categories are nothing
else than these functions of judgement so far as the manifold in a given intuition is determined in relation to
them (SS 9). Consequently, the manifold in a given intuition is necessarily subject to the categories of the
understanding.
Observation. SS 17
The manifold in an intuition, which I call mine, is represented by means of the synthesis of the
understanding, as belonging to the necessary unity of selfconsciousness, and this takes place by means of
the category.* The category indicates accordingly that the empirical consciousness of a given manifold in an
intuition is subject to a pure selfconsciousness a priori, in the same manner as an empirical intuition is
subject to a pure sensuous intuition, which is also a priori. In the above proposition, then, lies the beginning
of a deduction of the pure conceptions of the understanding. Now, as the categories have their origin in the
understanding alone, independently of sensibility, I must in my deduction make abstraction of the mode in
which the manifold of an empirical intuition is given, in order to fix my attention exclusively on the unity
which is brought by the understanding into the intuition by means of the category. In what follows (SS 22), it
will be shown, from the mode in which the empirical intuition is given in the faculty of sensibility, that the
unity which belongs to it is no other than that which the category (according to SS 16) imposes on the
manifold in a given intuition, and thus, its a priori validity in regard to all objects of sense being established,
the purpose of our deduction will be fully attained.
*The proof of this rests on the represented unity of intuition, by means of which an object is given, and which
always includes in itself a synthesis of the manifold to be intuited, and also the relation of this latter to unity
of apperception.
But there is one thing in the above demonstration of which I could not make abstraction, namely, that the
manifold to be intuited must be given previously to the synthesis of the understanding, and independently of
it. How this takes place remains here undetermined. For if I cogitate an understanding which was itself
intuitive (as, for example, a divine understanding which should not represent given objects, but by whose
representation the objects themselves should be given or produced), the categories would possess no
significance in relation to such a faculty of cognition. They are merely rules for an understanding, whose
whole power consists in thought, that is, in the act of submitting the synthesis of the manifold which is
The Critique of Pure Reason
All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as Conditions under which alone the manifold Content of them can be united in one Consciousness. SS 16 57
Page No 62
presented to it in intuition from a very different quarter, to the unity of apperception; a faculty, therefore,
which cognizes nothing per se, but only connects and arranges the material of cognition, the intuition,
namely, which must be presented to it by means of the object. But to show reasons for this peculiar character
of our understandings, that it produces unity of apperception a priori only by means of categories, and a
certain kind and number thereof, is as impossible as to explain why we are endowed with precisely so many
functions of judgement and no more, or why time and space are the only forms of our intuition.
In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is the only
legitimate use of the Category. SS 18
To think an object and to cognize an object are by no means the same thing. In cognition there are two
elements: firstly, the conception, whereby an object is cogitated (the category); and, secondly, the intuition,
whereby the object is given. For supposing that to the conception a corresponding intuition could not be
given, it would still be a thought as regards its form, but without any object, and no cognition of anything
would be possible by means of it, inasmuch as, so far as I knew, there existed and could exist nothing to
which my thought could be applied. Now all intuition possible to us is sensuous; consequently, our thought of
an object by means of a pure conception of the understanding, can become cognition for us only in so far as
this conception is applied to objects of the senses. Sensuous intuition is either pure intuition (space and time)
or empirical intuition of that which is immediately represented in space and time by means of sensation as
real. Through the determination of pure intuition we obtain a priori cognitions of objects, as in mathematics,
but only as regards their form as phenomena; whether there can exist things which must be intuited in this
form is not thereby established. All mathematical conceptions, therefore, are not per se cognition, except in
so far as we presuppose that there exist things which can only be represented conformably to the form of our
pure sensuous intuition. But things in space and time are given only in so far as they are perceptions
(representations accompanied with sensation), therefore only by empirical representation. Consequently the
pure conceptions of the understanding, even when they are applied to intuitions a priori (as in mathematics),
produce cognition only in so far as these (and therefore the conceptions of the understanding by means of
them) can be applied to empirical intuitions. Consequently the categories do not, even by means of pure
intuition afford us any cognition of things; they can only do so in so far as they can be applied to empirical
intuition. That is to say, the, categories serve only to render empirical cognition possible. But this is what we
call experience. Consequently, in cognition, their application to objects of experience is the only legitimate
use of the categories.
SS 19
The foregoing proposition is of the utmost importance, for it determines the limits of the exercise of the pure
conceptions of the understanding in regard to objects, just as transcendental aesthetic determined the limits of
the exercise of the pure form of our sensuous intuition. Space and time, as conditions of the possibility of the
presentation of objects to us, are valid no further than for objects of sense, consequently, only for experience.
Beyond these limits they represent to us nothing, for they belong only to sense, and have no reality apart from
it. The pure conceptions of the understanding are free from this limitation, and extend to objects of intuition
in general, be the intuition like or unlike to ours, provided only it be sensuous, and not intellectual. But this
extension of conceptions beyond the range of our intuition is of no advantage; for they are then mere empty
conceptions of objects, as to the possibility or impossibility of the existence of which they furnish us with no
means of discovery. They are mere forms of thought, without objective reality, because we have no intuition
to which the synthetical unity of apperception, which alone the categories contain, could be applied, for the
purpose of determining an object. Our sensuous and empirical intuition can alone give them significance and
meaning.
The Critique of Pure Reason
In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is the only legitimate use of the Category. SS 18 58
Page No 63
If, then, we suppose an object of a nonsensuous intuition to be given we can in that case represent it by all
those predicates which are implied in the presupposition that nothing appertaining to sensuous intuition
belongs to it; for example, that it is not extended, or in space; that its duration is not time; that in it no change
(the effect of the determinations in time) is to be met with, and so on. But it is no proper knowledge if I
merely indicate what the intuition of the object is not, without being able to say what is contained in it, for I
have not shown the possibility of an object to which my pure conception of understanding could be
applicable, because I have not been able to furnish any intuition corresponding to it, but am only able to say
that our intuition is not valid for it. But the most important point is this, that to a something of this kind not
one category can be found applicable. Take, for example, the conception of substance, that is, something that
can exist as subject, but never as mere predicate; in regard to this conception I am quite ignorant whether
there can really be anything to correspond to such a determination of thought, if empirical intuition did not
afford me the occasion for its application. But of this more in the sequel.
Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the Senses in general.
SS 20
The pure conceptions of the understanding apply to objects of intuition in general, through the understanding
alone, whether the intuition be our own or some other, provided only it be sensuous, but are, for this very
reason, mere forms of thought, by means of which alone no determined object can be cognized. The synthesis
or conjunction of the manifold in these conceptions relates, we have said, only to the unity of apperception,
and is for this reason the ground of the possibility of a priori cognition, in so far as this cognition is dependent
on the understanding. This synthesis is, therefore, not merely transcendental, but also purely intellectual. But
because a certain form of sensuous intuition exists in the mind a priori which rests on the receptivity of the
representative faculty (sensibility), the understanding, as a spontaneity, is able to determine the internal sense
by means of the diversity of given representations, conformably to the synthetical unity of apperception, and
thus to cogitate the synthetical unity of the apperception of the manifold of sensuous intuition a priori, as the
condition to which must necessarily be submitted all objects of human intuition. And in this manner the
categories as mere forms of thought receive objective reality, that is, application to objects which are given to
us in intuition, but that only as phenomena, for it is only of phenomena that we are capable of a priori
intuition.
This synthesis of the manifold of sensuous intuition, which is possible and necessary a priori, may be called
figurative (synthesis speciosa), in contradistinction to that which is cogitated in the mere category in regard to
the manifold of an intuition in general, and is called connection or conjunction of the understanding
(synthesis intellectualis). Both are transcendental, not merely because they themselves precede a priori all
experience, but also because they form the basis for the possibility of other cognition a priori.
But the figurative synthesis, when it has relation only to the originally synthetical unity of apperception, that
is to the transcendental unity cogitated in the categories, must, to be distinguished from the purely intellectual
conjunction, be entitled the transcendental synthesis of imagination. Imagination is the faculty of representing
an object even without its presence in intuition. Now, as all our intuition is sensuous, imagination, by reason
of the subjective condition under which alone it can give a corresponding intuition to the conceptions of the
understanding, belongs to sensibility. But in so far as the synthesis of the imagination is an act of spontaneity,
which is determinative, and not, like sense, merely determinable, and which is consequently able to determine
sense a priori, according to its form, conformably to the unity of apperception, in so far is the imagination a
faculty of determining sensibility a priori, and its synthesis of intuitions according to the categories must be
the transcendental synthesis of the imagination. It is an operation of the understanding on sensibility, and the
first application of the understanding to objects of possible intuition, and at the same time the basis for the
exercise of the other functions of that faculty. As figurative, it is distinguished from the merely intellectual
synthesis, which is produced by the understanding alone, without the aid of imagination. Now, in so far as
The Critique of Pure Reason
Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the Senses in general. SS 20 59
Page No 64
imagination is spontaneity, I sometimes call it also the productive imagination, and distinguish it from the
reproductive, the synthesis of which is subject entirely to empirical laws, those of association, namely, and
which, therefore, contributes nothing to the explanation of the possibility of a priori cognition, and for this
reason belongs not to transcendental philosophy, but to psychology.
We have now arrived at the proper place for explaining the paradox which must have struck every one in our
exposition of the internal sense (SS 6), namely how this sense represents us to our own consciousness, only
as we appear to ourselves, not as we are in ourselves, because, to wit, we intuite ourselves only as we are
inwardly affected. Now this appears to be contradictory, inasmuch as we thus stand in a passive relation to
ourselves; and therefore in the systems of psychology, the internal sense is commonly held to be one with the
faculty of apperception, while we, on the contrary, carefully distinguish them.
That which determines the internal sense is the understanding, and its original power of conjoining the
manifold of intuition, that is, of bringing this under an apperception (upon which rests the possibility of the
understanding itself). Now, as the human understanding is not in itself a faculty of intuition, and is unable to
exercise such a power, in order to conjoin, as it were, the manifold of its own intuition, the synthesis of
understanding is, considered per se, nothing but the unity of action, of which, as such, it is selfconscious,
even apart from sensibility, by which, moreover, it is able to determine our internal sense in respect of the
manifold which may be presented to it according to the form of sensuous intuition. Thus, under the name of a
transcendental synthesis of imagination, the understanding exercises an activity upon the passive subject,
whose faculty it is; and so we are right in saying that the internal sense is affected thereby. Apperception and
its synthetical unity are by no means one and the same with the internal sense. The former, as the source of all
our synthetical conjunction, applies, under the name of the categories, to the manifold of intuition in general,
prior to all sensuous intuition of objects. The internal sense, on the contrary, contains merely the form of
intuition, but without any synthetical conjunction of the manifold therein, and consequently does not contain
any determined intuition, which is possible only through consciousness of the determination of the manifold
by the transcendental act of the imagination (synthetical influence of the understanding on the internal sense),
which I have named figurative synthesis.
This we can indeed always perceive in ourselves. We cannot cogitate a geometrical line without drawing it in
thought, nor a circle without describing it, nor represent the three dimensions of space without drawing three
lines from the same point perpendicular to one another. We cannot even cogitate time, unless, in drawing a
straight line (which is to serve as the external figurative representation of time), we fix our attention on the
act of the synthesis of the manifold, whereby we determine successively the internal sense, and thus attend
also to the succession of this determination. Motion as an act of the subject (not as a determination of an
object),* consequently the synthesis of the manifold in space, if we make abstraction of space and attend
merely to the act by which we determine the internal sense according to its form, is that which produces the
conception of succession. The understanding, therefore, does by no means find in the internal sense any such
synthesis of the manifold, but produces it, in that it affects this sense. At the same time, how "I who think" is
distinct from the "I" which intuites itself (other modes of intuition being cogitable as at least possible), and
yet one and the same with this latter as the same subject; how, therefore, I am able to say: "I, as an
intelligence and thinking subject, cognize myself as an object thought, so far as I am, moreover, given to
myself in intuition only, like other phenomena, not as I am in myself, and as considered by the
understanding, but merely as I appear" is a question that has in it neither more nor less difficulty than the
question "How can I be an object to myself?" or this "How I can be an object of my own intuition and
internal perceptions?" But that such must be the fact, if we admit that space is merely a pure form of the
phenomena of external sense, can be clearly proved by the consideration that we cannot represent time, which
is not an object of external intuition, in any other way than under the image of a line, which we draw in
thought, a mode of representation without which we could not cognize the unity of its dimension, and also
that we are necessitated to take our determination of periods of time, or of points of time, for all our internal
perceptions from the changes which we perceive in outward things. It follows that we must arrange the
The Critique of Pure Reason
Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the Senses in general. SS 20 60
Page No 65
determinations of the internal sense, as phenomena in time, exactly in the same manner as we arrange those
of the external senses in space. And consequently, if we grant, respecting this latter, that by means of them
we know objects only in so far as we are affected externally, we must also confess, with regard to the internal
sense, that by means of it we intuite ourselves only as we are internally affected by ourselves; in other words,
as regards internal intuition, we cognize our own subject only as phenomenon, and not as it is in itself.*[2]
*Motion of an object in space does not belong to a pure science, consequently not to geometry; because, that
a thing is movable cannot be known a priori, but only from experience. But motion, considered as the
description of a space, is a pure act of the successive synthesis of the manifold in external intuition by means
of productive imagination, and belongs not only to geometry, but even to transcendental philosophy.
*[2] I do not see why so much difficulty should be found in admitting that our internal sense is affected by
ourselves. Every act of attention exemplifies it. In such an act the understanding determines the internal sense
by the synthetical conjunction which it cogitates, conformably to the internal intuition which corresponds to
the manifold in the synthesis of the understanding. How much the mind is usually affected thereby every one
will be able to perceive in himself.
SS 21
On the other hand, in the transcendental synthesis of the manifold content of representations, consequently in
the synthetical unity of apperception, I am conscious of myself, not as I appear to myself, nor as I am in
myself, but only that "I am." This representation is a thought, not an intuition. Now, as in order to cognize
ourselves, in addition to the act of thinking, which subjects the manifold of every possible intuition to the
unity of apperception, there is necessary a determinate mode of intuition, whereby this manifold is given;
although my own existence is certainly not mere phenomenon (much less mere illusion), the determination of
my existence* Can only take place conformably to the form of the internal sense, according to the particular
mode in which the manifold which I conjoin is given in internal intuition, and I have therefore no knowledge
of myself as I am, but merely as I appear to myself. The consciousness of self is thus very far from a
knowledge of self, in which I do not use the categories, whereby I cogitate an object, by means of the
conjunction of the manifold in one apperception. In the same way as I require, for the sake of the cognition of
an object distinct from myself, not only the thought of an object in general (in the category), but also an
intuition by which to determine that general conception, in the same way do I require, in order to the
cognition of myself, not only the consciousness of myself or the thought that I think myself, but in addition
an intuition of the manifold in myself, by which to determine this thought. It is true that I exist as an
intelligence which is conscious only of its faculty of conjunction or synthesis, but subjected in relation to the
manifold which this intelligence has to conjoin to a limitative conjunction called the internal sense. My
intelligence (that is, I) can render that conjunction or synthesis perceptible only according to the relations of
time, which are quite beyond the proper sphere of the conceptions of the understanding and consequently
cognize itself in respect to an intuition (which cannot possibly be intellectual, nor given by the
understanding), only as it appears to itself, and not as it would cognize itself, if its intuition were intellectual.
*The "I think" expresses the act of determining my own existence. My existence is thus already given by the
act of consciousness; but the mode in which I must determine my existence, that is, the mode in which I must
place the manifold belonging to my existence, is not thereby given. For this purpose intuition of self is
required, and this intuition possesses a form given a priori, namely, time, which is sensuous, and belongs to
our receptivity of the determinable. Now, as I do not possess another intuition of self which gives the
determining in me (of the spontaneity of which I am conscious), prior to the act of determination, in the same
manner as time gives the determinable, it is clear that I am unable to determine my own existence as that of a
spontaneous being, but I am only able to represent to myself the spontaneity of my thought, that is, of my
determination, and my existence remains ever determinable in a purely sensuous manner, that is to say, like
the existence of a phenomenon. But it is because of this spontaneity that I call myself an intelligence.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 21 61
Page No 66
Transcendental Deduction of the universally possible
employment in experience of the Pure Conceptions
of the Understanding. SS 22
In the metaphysical deduction, the a priori origin of categories was proved by their complete accordance with
the general logical of thought; in the transcendental deduction was exhibited the possibility of the categories
as a priori cognitions of objects of an intuition in general (SS 16 and 17).At present we are about to explain
the possibility of cognizing, a priori, by means of the categories, all objects which can possibly be presented
to our senses, not, indeed, according to the form of their intuition, but according to the laws of their
conjunction or synthesis, and thus, as it were, of prescribing laws to nature and even of rendering nature
possible. For if the categories were inadequate to this task, it would not be evident to us why everything that
is presented to our senses must be subject to those laws which have an a priori origin in the understanding
itself.
I premise that by the term synthesis of apprehension I understand the combination of the manifold in an
empirical intuition, whereby perception, that is, empirical consciousness of the intuition (as phenomenon), is
possible.
We have a priori forms of the external and internal sensuous intuition in the representations of space and
time, and to these must the synthesis of apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon be always
comformable, because the synthesis itself can only take place according to these forms. But space and time
are not merely forms of sensuous intuition, but intuitions themselves (which contain a manifold), and
therefore contain a priori the determination of the unity of this manifold.* (See the Transcendent Aesthetic.)
Therefore is unity of the synthesis of the manifold without or within us, consequently also a conjunction to
which all that is to be represented as determined in space or time must correspond, given a priori along with
(not in) these intuitions, as the condition of the synthesis of all apprehension of them. But this synthetical
unity can be no other than that of the conjunction of the manifold of a given intuition in general, in a
primitive act of consciousness, according to the categories, but applied to our sensuous intuition.
Consequently all synthesis, whereby alone is even perception possible, is subject to the categories. And, as
experience is cognition by means of conjoined perceptions, the categories are conditions of the possibility of
experience and are therefore valid a priori for all objects of experience.
*Space represented as an object (as geometry really requires it to be) contains more than the mere form of the
intuition; namely, a combination of the manifold given according to the form of sensibility into a
representation that can be intuited; so that the form of the intuition gives us merely the manifold, but the
formal intuition gives unity of representation. In the aesthetic, I regarded this unity as belonging entirely to
sensibility, for the purpose of indicating that it antecedes all conceptions, although it presupposes a synthesis
which does not belong to sense, through which alone, however, all our conceptions of space and time are
possible. For as by means of this unity alone (the understanding determining the sensibility) space and time
are given as intuitions, it follows that the unity of this intuition a priori belongs to space and time, and not to
the conception of the understanding (SS 20).
When, then, for example, I make the empirical intuition of a house by apprehension of the manifold
contained therein into a perception, the necessary unity of space and of my external sensuous intuition lies at
the foundation of this act, and I, as it were, draw the form of the house conformably to this synthetical unity
of the manifold in space. But this very synthetical unity remains, even when I abstract the form of space, and
has its seat in the understanding, and is in fact the category of the synthesis of the homogeneous in an
intuition; that is to say, the category of quantity, to which the aforesaid synthesis of apprehension, that is, the
perception, must be completely conformable.*
*In this manner it is proved, that the synthesis of apprehension, which is empirical, must necessarily be
conformable to the synthesis of apperception, which is intellectual, and contained a priori in the category. It is
The Critique of Pure Reason
SS 21 62
Page No 67
one and the same spontaneity which at one time, under the name of imagination, at another under that of
understanding, produces conjunction in the manifold of intuition.
To take another example, when I perceive the freezing of water, I apprehend two states (fluidity and solidity),
which, as such, stand toward each other mutually in a relation of time. But in the time, which I place as an
internal intuition, at the foundation of this phenomenon, I represent to myself synthetical unity of the
manifold, without which the aforesaid relation could not be given in an intuition as determined (in regard to
the succession of time). Now this synthetical unity, as the a priori condition under which I conjoin the
manifold of an intuition, is, if I make abstraction of the permanent form of my internal intuition (that is to
say, of time), the category of cause, by means of which, when applied to my sensibility, I determine
everything that occurs according to relations of time. Consequently apprehension in such an event, and the
event itself, as far as regards the possibility of its perception, stands under the conception of the relation of
cause and effect: and so in all other cases.
Categories are conceptions which prescribe laws a priori to phenomena, consequently to nature as the
complex of all phenomena (natura materialiter spectata). And now the question arises inasmuch as these
categories are not derived from nature, and do not regulate themselves according to her as their model (for in
that case they would be empirical) how it is conceivable that nature must regulate herself according to them,
in other words, how the categories can determine a priori the synthesis of the manifold of nature, and yet not
derive their origin from her. The following is the solution of this enigma.
It is not in the least more difficult to conceive how the laws of the phenomena of nature must harmonize with
the understanding and with its a priori form that is, its faculty of conjoining the manifold than it is to
understand how the phenomena themselves must correspond with the a priori form of our sensuous intuition.
For laws do not exist in the phenomena any more than the phenomena exist as things in themselves. Laws do
not exist except by relation to the subject in which the phenomena inhere, in so far as it possesses
understanding, just as phenomena have no existence except by relation to the same existing subject in so far
as it has senses. To things as things in themselves, conformability to law must necessarily belong
independently of an understanding to cognize them. But phenomena are only representations of things which
are utterly unknown in respect to what they are in themselves. But as mere representations, they stand under
no law of conjunction except that which the conjoining faculty prescribes. Now that which conjoins the
manifold of sensuous intuition is imagination, a mental act to which understanding contributes unity of
intellectual synthesis, and sensibility, manifoldness of apprehension. Now as all possible perception depends
on the synthesis of apprehension, and this empirical synthesis itself on the transcendental, consequently on
the categories, it is evident that all possible perceptions, and therefore everything that can attain to empirical
consciousness, that is, all phenomena of nature, must, as regards their conjunction, be subject to the
categories. And nature (considered merely as nature in general) is dependent on them. as the original ground
of her necessary conformability to law (as natura formaliter spectata). But the pure faculty (of the
understanding) of prescribing laws a priori to phenomena by means of mere categories, is not competent to
enounce other or more laws than those on which a nature in general, as a conformability to law of phenomena
of space and time, depends. Particular laws, inasmuch as they concern empirically determined phenomena,
cannot be entirely deduced from pure laws, although they all stand under them. Experience must be
superadded in order to know these particular laws; but in regard to experience in general, and everything that
can be cognized as an object thereof, these a priori laws are our only rule and guide.
Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the Understanding. SS 23
We cannot think any object except by means of the categories; we cannot cognize any thought except by
means of intuitions corresponding to these conceptions. Now all our intuitions are sensuous, and our
cognition, in so far as the object of it is given, is empirical. But empirical cognition is experience;
consequently no a priori cognition is possible for us, except of objects of possible experience.*
The Critique of Pure Reason
Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the Understanding. SS 23 63
Page No 68
*Lest my readers should stumble at this assertion, and the conclusions that may be too rashly drawn from it, I
must remind them that the categories in the act of thought are by no means limited by the conditions of our
sensuous intuition, but have an unbounded sphere of action. It is only the cognition of the object of thought,
the determining of the object, which requires intuition. In the absence of intuition, our thought of an object
may still have true and useful consequences in regard to the exercise of reason by the subject. But as this
exercise of reason is not always directed on the determination of the object, in other words, on cognition
thereof, but also on the determination of the subject and its volition, I do not intend to treat of it in this place.
But this cognition, which is limited to objects of experience, is not for that reason derived entirely, from,
experience, but and this is asserted of the pure intuitions and the pure conceptions of the understanding
there are, unquestionably, elements of cognition, which exist in the mind a priori. Now there are only two
ways in which a necessary harmony of experience with the conceptions of its objects can be cogitated. Either
experience makes these conceptions possible, or the conceptions make experience possible. The former of
these statements will not bold good with respect to the categories (nor in regard to pure sensuous intuition),
for they are a priori conceptions, and therefore independent of experience. The assertion of an empirical
origin would attribute to them a sort of generatio aequivoca. Consequently, nothing remains but to adopt the
second alternative (which presents us with a system, as it were, of the epigenesis of pure reason), namely, that
on the part of the understanding the categories do contain the grounds of the possibility of all experience. But
with respect to the questions how they make experience possible, and what are the principles of the
possibility thereof with which they present us in their application to phenomena, the following section on the
transcendental exercise of the faculty of judgement will inform the reader.
It is quite possible that someone may propose a species of preformationsystem of pure reason a middle
way between the two to wit, that the categories are neither innate and first a priori principles of cognition,
nor derived from experience, but are merely subjective aptitudes for thought implanted in us
contemporaneously with our existence, which were so ordered and disposed by our Creator, that their
exercise perfectly harmonizes with the laws of nature which regulate experience. Now, not to mention that
with such an hypothesis it is impossible to say at what point we must stop in the employment of
predetermined aptitudes, the fact that the categories would in this case entirely lose that character of necessity
which is essentially involved in the very conception of them, is a conclusive objection to it. The conception
of cause, for example, which expresses the necessity of an effect under a presupposed condition, would be
false, if it rested only upon such an arbitrary subjective necessity of uniting certain empirical representations
according to such a rule of relation. I could not then say "The effect is connected with its cause in the object
(that is, necessarily)," but only, "I am so constituted that I can think this representation as so connected, and
not otherwise." Now this is just what the sceptic wants. For in this case, all our knowledge, depending on the
supposed objective validity of our judgement, is nothing but mere illusion; nor would there be wanting
people who would deny any such subjective necessity in respect to themselves, though they must feel it. At
all events, we could not dispute with any one on that which merely depends on the manner in which his
subject is organized.
Short view of the above Deduction.
The foregoing deduction is an exposition of the pure conceptions of the understanding (and with them of all
theoretical a priori cognition), as principles of the possibility of experience, but of experience as the
determination of all phenomena in space and time in general of experience, finally, from the principle of the
original synthetical unity of apperception, as the form of the understanding in relation to time and space as
original forms of sensibility.
I consider the division by paragraphs to be necessary only up to this point, because we had to treat of the
elementary conceptions. As we now proceed to the exposition of the employment of these, I shall not
designate the chapters in this manner any further.
The Critique of Pure Reason
Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the Understanding. SS 23 64
Page No 69
BOOK II. Analytic of Principles.
General logic is constructed upon a plan which coincides exactly with the division of the higher faculties of
cognition. These are, understanding, judgement, and reason. This science, accordingly, treats in its analytic of
conceptions, judgements, and conclusions in exact correspondence with the functions and order of those
mental powers which we include generally under the generic denomination of understanding.
As this merely formal logic makes abstraction of all content of cognition, whether pure or empirical, and
occupies itself with the mere form of thought (discursive cognition), it must contain in its analytic a canon for
reason. For the form of reason has its law, which, without taking into consideration the particular nature of
the cognition about which it is employed, can be discovered a priori, by the simple analysis of the action of
reason into its momenta.
Transcendental logic, limited as it is to a determinate content, that of pure a priori cognitions, to wit, cannot
imitate general logic in this division. For it is evident that the transcendental employment of reason is not
objectively valid, and therefore does not belong to the logic of truth (that is, to analytic), but as a logic of
illusion, occupies a particular department in the scholastic system under the name of transcendental dialectic.
Understanding and judgement accordingly possess in transcendental logic a canon of objectively valid, and
therefore true exercise, and are comprehended in the analytical department of that logic. But reason, in her
endeavours to arrive by a priori means at some true statement concerning objects and to extend cognition
beyond the bounds of possible experience, is altogether dialectic, and her illusory assertions cannot be
constructed into a canon such as an analytic ought to contain.
Accordingly, the analytic of principles will be merely a canon for the faculty of judgement, for the instruction
of this faculty in its application to phenomena of the pure conceptions of the understanding, which contain
the necessary condition for the establishment of a priori laws. On this account, although the subject of the
following chapters is the especial principles of understanding, I shall make use of the term Doctrine of the
faculty of judgement, in order to define more particularly my present purpose.
INTRODUCTION. Of the Transcendental Faculty of judgement in General.
If understanding in general be defined as the faculty of laws or rules, the faculty of judgement may be termed
the faculty of subsumption under these rules; that is, of distinguishing whether this or that does or does not
stand under a given rule (casus datae legis). General logic contains no directions or precepts for the faculty of
judgement, nor can it contain any such. For as it makes abstraction of all content of cognition, no duty is left
for it, except that of exposing analytically the mere form of cognition in conceptions, judgements, and
conclusions, and of thereby establishing formal rules for all exercise of the understanding. Now if this logic
wished to give some general direction how we should subsume under these rules, that is, how we should
distinguish whether this or that did or did not stand under them, this again could not be done otherwise than
by means of a rule. But this rule, precisely because it is a rule, requires for itself direction from the faculty of
judgement. Thus, it is evident that the understanding is capable of being instructed by rules, but that the
judgement is a peculiar talent, which does not, and cannot require tuition, but only exercise. This faculty is
therefore the specific quality of the socalled mother wit, the want of which no scholastic discipline can
compensate.
For although education may furnish, and, as it were, engraft upon a limited understanding rules borrowed
from other minds, yet the power of employing these rules correctly must belong to the pupil himself; and no
rule which we can prescribe to him with this purpose is, in the absence or deficiency of this gift of nature,
secure from misuse.* A physician therefore, a judge or a statesman, may have in his head many admirable
pathological, juridical, or political rules, in a degree that may enable him to be a profound teacher in his
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. Analytic of Principles. 65
Page No 70
particular science, and yet in the application of these rules he may very possibly blunder either because he is
wanting in natural judgement (though not in understanding) and, whilst he can comprehend the general in
abstracto, cannot distinguish whether a particular case in concreto ought to rank under the former; or because
his faculty of judgement bas not been sufficiently exercised by examples and real practice. Indeed, the grand
and only use of examples, is to sharpen the judgement. For as regards the correctness and precision of the
insight of the understanding, examples are commonly injurious rather than otherwise, because, as casus in
terminis they seldom adequately fulfil the conditions of the rule. Besides, they often weaken the power of our
understanding to apprehend rules or laws in their universality, independently of particular circumstances of
experience; and hence, accustom us to employ them more as formulae than as principles. Examples are thus
the gocart of the judgement, which he who is naturally deficient in that faculty cannot afford to dispense
with.
*Deficiency in judgement is properly that which is called stupidity; and for such a failing we know no
remedy. A dull or narrowminded person, to whom nothing is wanting but a proper degree of understanding,
may be improved by tuition, even so far as to deserve the epithet of learned. But as such persons frequently
labour under a deficiency in the faculty of judgement, it is not uncommon to find men extremely learned who
in the application of their science betray a lamentable degree this irremediable want.
But although general logic cannot give directions to the faculty of judgement, the case is very different as
regards transcendental logic, insomuch that it appears to be the especial duty of the latter to secure and direct,
by means of determinate rules, the faculty of judgement in the employment of the pure understanding. For, as
a doctrine, that is, as an endeavour to enlarge the sphere of the understanding in regard to pure a priori
cognitions, philosophy is worse than useless, since from all the attempts hitherto made, little or no ground has
been gained. But, as a critique, in order to guard against the mistakes of the faculty of judgement (lapsus
judicii) in the employment of the few pure conceptions of the understanding which we possess, although its
use is in this case purely negative, philosophy is called upon to apply all its acuteness and penetration.
But transcendental philosophy has this peculiarity, that besides indicating the rule, or rather the general
condition for rules, which is given in the pure conception of the understanding, it can, at the same time,
indicate a priori the case to which the rule must be applied. The cause of the superiority which, in this respect,
transcendental philosophy possesses above all other sciences except mathematics, lies in this: it treats of
conceptions which must relate a priori to their objects, whose objective validity consequently cannot be
demonstrated a posteriori, and is, at the same time, under the obligation of presenting in general but sufficient
tests, the conditions under which objects can be given in harmony with those conceptions; otherwise they
would be mere logical forms, without content, and not pure conceptions of the understanding.
Our transcendental doctrine of the faculty of judgement will contain two chapters. The first will treat of the
sensuous condition under which alone pure conceptions of the understanding can be employed that is, of the
schematism of the pure understanding. The second will treat of those synthetical judgements which are
derived a priori from pure conceptions of the understanding under those conditions, and which lie a priori at
the foundation of all other cognitions, that is to say, it will treat of the principles of the pure understanding.
TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF THE FACULTY OF JUDGEMENT
OR, ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES.
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the
Understanding.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 66
Page No 71
In all subsumptions of an object under a conception, the representation of the object must be homogeneous
with the conception; in other words, the conception must contain that which is represented in the object to be
subsumed under it. For this is the meaning of the expression: "An object is contained under a conception."
Thus the empirical conception of a plate is homogeneous with the pure geometrical conception of a circle,
inasmuch as the roundness which is cogitated in the former is intuited in the latter.
But pure conceptions of the understanding, when compared with empirical intuitions, or even with sensuous
intuitions in general, are quite heterogeneous, and never can be discovered in any intuition. How then is the
subsumption of the latter under the former, and consequently the application of the categories to phenomena,
possible? For it is impossible to say, for example: "Causality can be intuited through the senses and is
contained in the phenomenon." This natural and important question forms the real cause of the necessity of
a transcendental doctrine of the faculty of judgement, with the purpose, to wit, of showing how pure
conceptions of the understanding can be applied to phenomena. In all other sciences, where the conceptions
by which the object is thought in the general are not so different and heterogeneous from those which
represent the object in concreto as it is given, it is quite unnecessary to institute any special inquiries
concerning the application of the former to the latter.
Now it is quite clear that there must be some third thing, which on the one side is homogeneous with the
category, and with the phenomenon on the other, and so makes the application of the former to the latter
possible. This mediating representation must be pure (without any empirical content), and yet must on the
one side be intellectual, on the other sensuous. Such a representation is the transcendental schema.
The conception of the understanding contains pure synthetical unity of the manifold in general. Time, as the
formal condition of the manifold of the internal sense, consequently of the conjunction of all representations,
contains a priori a manifold in the pure intuition. Now a transcendental determination of time is so far
homogeneous with the category, which constitutes the unity thereof, that it is universal and rests upon a rule a
priori. On the other hand, it is so far homogeneous with the phenomenon, inasmuch as time is contained in
every empirical representation of the manifold. Thus an application of the category to phenomena becomes
possible, by means of the transcendental determination of time, which, as the schema of the conceptions of
the understanding, mediates the subsumption of the latter under the former.
After what has been proved in our deduction of the categories, no one, it is to be hoped, can hesitate as to the
proper decision of the question, whether the employment of these pure conceptions of the understanding
ought to be merely empirical or also transcendental; in other words, whether the categories, as conditions of a
possible experience, relate a priori solely to phenomena, or whether, as conditions of the possibility of things
in general, their application can be extended to objects as things in themselves. For we have there seen that
conceptions are quite impossible, and utterly without signification, unless either to them, or at least to the
elements of which they consist, an object be given; and that, consequently, they cannot possibly apply to
objects as things in themselves without regard to the question whether and how these may be given to us;
and, further, that the only manner in which objects can be given to us is by means of the modification of our
sensibility; and, finally, that pure a priori conceptions, in addition to the function of the understanding in the
category, must contain a priori formal conditions of sensibility (of the internal sense, namely), which again
contain the general condition under which alone the category can be applied to any object. This formal and
pure condition of sensibility, to which the conception of the understanding is restricted in its employment, we
shall name the schema of the conception of the understanding, and the procedure of the understanding with
these schemata we shall call the schematism of the pure understanding.
The schema is, in itself, always a mere product of the imagination. But, as the synthesis of imagination has
for its aim no single intuition, but merely unity in the determination of sensibility, the schema is clearly
distinguishable from the image. Thus, if I place five points one after another.... this is an image of the number
five. On the other hand, if I only think a number in general, which may be either five or a hundred, this
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 67
Page No 72
thought is rather the representation of a method of representing in an image a sum (e.g., a thousand) in
conformity with a conception, than the image itself, an image which I should find some little difficulty in
reviewing, and comparing with the conception. Now this representation of a general procedure of the
imagination to present its image to a conception, I call the schema of this conception.
In truth, it is not images of objects, but schemata, which lie at the foundation of our pure sensuous
conceptions. No image could ever be adequate to our conception of a triangle in general. For the generalness
of the conception it never could attain to, as this includes under itself all triangles, whether rightangled,
acuteangled, etc., whilst the image would always be limited to a single part of this sphere. The schema of
the triangle can exist nowhere else than in thought, and it indicates a rule of the synthesis of the imagination
in regard to pure figures in space. Still less is an object of experience, or an image of the object, ever to the
empirical conception. On the contrary, the conception always relates immediately to the schema of the
imagination, as a rule for the determination of our intuition, in conformity with a certain general conception.
The conception of a dog indicates a rule, according to which my imagination can delineate the figure of a
fourfooted animal in general, without being limited to any particular individual form which experience
presents to me, or indeed to any possible image that I can represent to myself in concreto. This schematism of
our understanding in regard to phenomena and their mere form, is an art, hidden in the depths of the human
soul, whose true modes of action we shall only with difficulty discover and unveil. Thus much only can we
say: "The image is a product of the empirical faculty of the productive imagination the schema of sensuous
conceptions (of figures in space, for example) is a product, and, as it were, a monogram of the pure
imagination a priori, whereby and according to which images first become possible, which, however, can be
connected with the conception only mediately by means of the schema which they indicate, and are in
themselves never fully adequate to it." On the other hand, the schema of a pure conception of the
understanding is something that cannot be reduced into any image it is nothing else than the pure synthesis
expressed by the category, conformably, to a rule of unity according to conceptions. It is a transcendental
product of the imagination, a product which concerns the determination of the internal sense, according to
conditions of its form (time) in respect to all representations, in so far as these representations must be
conjoined a priori in one conception, conformably to the unity of apperception.
Without entering upon a dry and tedious analysis of the essential requisites of transcendental schemata of the
pure conceptions of the understanding, we shall rather proceed at once to give an explanation of them
according to the order of the categories, and in connection therewith.
For the external sense the pure image of all quantities (quantorum) is space; the pure image of all objects of
sense in general, is time. But the pure schema of quantity (quantitatis) as a conception of the understanding, is
number, a representation which comprehends the successive addition of one to one (homogeneous quantities).
Thus, number is nothing else than the unity of the synthesis of the manifold in a homogeneous intuition, by
means of my generating time itself in my apprehension of the intuition.
Reality, in the pure conception of the understanding, is that which corresponds to a sensation in general; that,
consequently, the conception of which indicates a being (in time). Negation is that the conception of which
represents a notbeing (in time). The opposition of these two consists therefore in the difference of one and
the same time, as a time filled or a time empty. Now as time is only the form of intuition, consequently of
objects as phenomena, that which in objects corresponds to sensation is the transcendental matter of all
objects as things in themselves (Sachheit, reality). Now every sensation has a degree or quantity by which it
can fill time, that is to say, the internal sense in respect of the representation of an object, more or less, until it
vanishes into nothing (= 0 = negatio). Thus there is a relation and connection between reality and negation, or
rather a transition from the former to the latter, which makes every reality representable to us as a quantum;
and the schema of a reality as the quantity of something in so far as it fills time, is exactly this continuous and
uniform generation of the reality in time, as we descend in time from the sensation which has a certain
degree, down to the vanishing thereof, or gradually ascend from negation to the quantity thereof.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 68
Page No 73
The schema of substance is the permanence of the real in time; that is, the representation of it as a substratum
of the empirical determination of time; a substratum which therefore remains, whilst all else changes. (Time
passes not, but in it passes the existence of the changeable. To time, therefore, which is itself unchangeable
and permanent, corresponds that which in the phenomenon is unchangeable in existence, that is, substance,
and it is only by it that the succession and coexistence of phenomena can be determined in regard to time.)
The schema of cause and of the causality of a thing is the real which, when posited, is always followed by
something else. It consists, therefore, in the succession of the manifold, in so far as that succession is
subjected to a rule.
The schema of community (reciprocity of action and reaction), or the reciprocal causality of substances in
respect of their accidents, is the coexistence of the determinations of the one with those of the other,
according to a general rule.
The schema of possibility is the accordance of the synthesis of different representations with the conditions of
time in general (as, for example, opposites cannot exist together at the same time in the same thing, but only
after each other), and is therefore the determination of the representation of a thing at any time.
The schema of reality is existence in a determined time.
The schema of necessity is the existence of an object in all time.
It is clear, from all this, that the schema of the category of quantity contains and represents the generation
(synthesis) of time itself, in the successive apprehension of an object; the schema of quality the synthesis of
sensation with the representation of time, or the filling up of time; the schema of relation the relation of
perceptions to each other in all time (that is, according to a rule of the determination of time): and finally, the
schema of modality and its categories, time itself, as the correlative of the determination of an object
whether it does belong to time, and how. The schemata, therefore, are nothing but a priori determinations of
time according to rules, and these, in regard to all possible objects, following the arrangement of the
categories, relate to the series in time, the content in time, the order in time, and finally, to the complex or
totality in time.
Hence it is apparent that the schematism of the understanding, by means of the transcendental synthesis of the
imagination, amounts to nothing else than the unity of the manifold of intuition in the internal sense, and thus
indirectly to the unity of apperception, as a function corresponding to the internal sense (a receptivity). Thus,
the schemata of the pure conceptions of the understanding are the true and only conditions whereby our
understanding receives an application to objects, and consequently significance. Finally, therefore, the
categories are only capable of empirical use, inasmuch as they serve merely to subject phenomena to the
universal rules of synthesis, by means of an a priori necessary unity (on account of the necessary union of all
consciousness in one original apperception); and so to render them susceptible of a complete connection in
one experience. But within this whole of possible experience lie all our cognitions, and in the universal
relation to this experience consists transcendental truth, which antecedes all empirical truth, and renders the
latter possible.
It is, however, evident at first sight, that although the schemata of sensibility are the sole agents in realizing
the categories, they do, nevertheless, also restrict them, that is, they limit the categories by conditions which
lie beyond the sphere of understanding namely, in sensibility. Hence the schema is properly only the
phenomenon, or the sensuous conception of an object in harmony with the category. (Numerus est quantitas
phaenomenon sensatio realitas phaenomenon; constans et perdurabile rerum substantia phaenomenon
aeternitas, necessitas, phaenomena, etc.) Now, if we remove a restrictive condition, we thereby amplify, it
appears, the formerly limited conception. In this way, the categories in their pure signification, free from all
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding. 69
Page No 74
conditions of sensibility, ought to be valid of things as they are, and not, as the schemata represent them,
merely as they appear; and consequently the categories must have a significance far more extended, and
wholly independent of all schemata. In truth, there does always remain to the pure conceptions of the
understanding, after abstracting every sensuous condition, a value and significance, which is, however,
merely logical. But in this case, no object is given them, and therefore they have no meaning sufficient to
afford us a conception of an object. The notion of substance, for example, if we leave out the sensuous
determination of permanence, would mean nothing more than a something which can be cogitated as subject,
without the possibility of becoming a predicate to anything else. Of this representation I can make nothing,
inasmuch as it does not indicate to me what determinations the thing possesses which must thus be valid as
premier subject. Consequently, the categories, without schemata are merely functions of the understanding
for the production of conceptions, but do not represent any object. This significance they derive from
sensibility, which at the same time realizes the understanding and restricts it.
CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding.
In the foregoing chapter we have merely considered the general conditions under which alone the
transcendental faculty of judgement is justified in using the pure conceptions of the understanding for
synthetical judgements. Our duty at present is to exhibit in systematic connection those judgements which the
understanding really produces a priori. For this purpose, our table of the categories will certainly afford us the
natural and safe guidance. For it is precisely the categories whose application to possible experience must
constitute all pure a priori cognition of the understanding; and the relation of which to sensibility will, on that
very account, present us with a complete and systematic catalogue of all the transcendental principles of the
use of the understanding.
Principles a priori are so called, not merely because they contain in themselves the grounds of other
judgements, but also because they themselves are not grounded in higher and more general cognitions. This
peculiarity, however, does not raise them altogether above the need of a proof. For although there could be
found no higher cognition, and therefore no objective proof, and although such a principle rather serves as the
foundation for all cognition of the object, this by no means hinders us from drawing a proof from the
subjective sources of the possibility of the cognition of an object. Such a proof is necessary, moreover,
because without it the principle might be liable to the imputation of being a mere gratuitous assertion.
In the second place, we shall limit our investigations to those principles which relate to the categories. For as
to the principles of transcendental aesthetic, according to which space and time are the conditions of the
possibility of things as phenomena, as also the restriction of these principles, namely, that they cannot be
applied to objects as things in themselves these, of course, do not fall within the scope of our present
inquiry. In like manner, the principles of mathematical science form no part of this system, because they are
all drawn from intuition, and not from the pure conception of the understanding. The possibility of these
principles, however, will necessarily be considered here, inasmuch as they are synthetical judgements a
priori, not indeed for the purpose of proving their accuracy and apodeictic certainty, which is unnecessary,
but merely to render conceivable and deduce the possibility of such evident a priori cognitions.
But we shall have also to speak of the principle of analytical judgements, in opposition to synthetical
judgements, which is the proper subject of our inquiries, because this very opposition will free the theory of
the latter from all ambiguity, and place it clearly before our eyes in its true nature.
SYSTEM OF THE PRINCIPLES OF THE PURE UNDERSTANDING.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding. 70
Page No 75
SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements.
Whatever may be the content of our cognition, and in whatever manner our cognition may be related to its
object, the universal, although only negative conditions of all our judgements is that they do not contradict
themselves; otherwise these judgements are in themselves (even without respect to the object) nothing. But
although there may exist no contradiction in our judgement, it may nevertheless connect conceptions in such
a manner that they do not correspond to the object, or without any grounds either a priori or a posteriori for
arriving at such a judgement, and thus, without being selfcontradictory, a judgement may nevertheless be
either false or groundless.
Now, the proposition: "No subject can have a predicate that contradicts it," is called the principle of
contradiction, and is a universal but purely negative criterion of all truth. But it belongs to logic alone,
because it is valid of cognitions, merely as cognitions and without respect to their content, and declares that
the contradiction entirely nullifies them. We can also, however, make a positive use of this principle, that is,
not merely to banish falsehood and error (in so far as it rests upon contradiction), but also for the cognition of
truth. For if the judgement is analytical, be it affirmative or negative, its truth must always be recognizable by
means of the principle of contradiction. For the contrary of that which lies and is cogitated as conception in
the cognition of the object will be always properly negatived, but the conception itself must always be
affirmed of the object, inasmuch as the contrary thereof would be in contradiction to the object.
We must therefore hold the principle of contradiction to be the universal and fully sufficient Principle of all
analytical cognition. But as a sufficient criterion of truth, it has no further utility or authority. For the fact that
no cognition can be at variance with this principle without nullifying itself, constitutes this principle the sine
qua non, but not the determining ground of the truth of our cognition. As our business at present is properly
with the synthetical part of our knowledge only, we shall always be on our guard not to transgress this
inviolable principle; but at the same time not to expect from it any direct assistance in the establishment of
the truth of any synthetical proposition.
There exists, however, a formula of this celebrated principle a principle merely formal and entirely without
content which contains a synthesis that has been inadvertently and quite unnecessarily mixed up with it. It is
this: "It is impossible for a thing to be and not to be at the same time." Not to mention the superfluousness of
the addition of the word impossible to indicate the apodeictic certainty, which ought to be selfevident from
the proposition itself, the proposition is affected by the condition of time, and as it were says: "A thing = A,
which is something = B, cannot at the same time be nonB." But both, B as well as nonB, may quite well
exist in succession. For example, a man who is young cannot at the same time be old; but the same man can
very well be at one time young, and at another not young, that is, old. Now the principle of contradiction as a
merely logical proposition must not by any means limit its application merely to relations of time, and
consequently a formula like the preceding is quite foreign to its true purpose. The misunderstanding arises in
this way. We first of all separate a predicate of a thing from the conception of the thing, and afterwards
connect with this predicate its opposite, and hence do not establish any contradiction with the subject, but
only with its predicate, which has been conjoined with the subject synthetically a contradiction, moreover,
which obtains only when the first and second predicate are affirmed in the same time. If I say: "A man who is
ignorant is not learned," the condition "at the same time" must be added, for he who is at one time ignorant,
may at another be learned. But if I say: "No ignorant man is a learned man," the proposition is analytical,
because the characteristic ignorance is now a constituent part of the conception of the subject; and in this case
the negative proposition is evident immediately from the proposition of contradiction, without the necessity
of adding the condition "the same time." This is the reason why I have altered the formula of this principle
an alteration which shows very clearly the nature of an analytical proposition.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements. 71
Page No 76
SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements.
The explanation of the possibility of synthetical judgements is a task with which general logic has nothing to
do; indeed she needs not even be acquainted with its name. But in transcendental logic it is the most
important matter to be dealt with indeed the only one, if the question is of the possibility of synthetical
judgements a priori, the conditions and extent of their validity. For when this question is fully decided, it can
reach its aim with perfect ease, the determination, to wit, of the extent and limits of the pure understanding.
In an analytical judgement I do not go beyond the given conception, in order to arrive at some decision
respecting it. If the judgement is affirmative, I predicate of the conception only that which was already
cogitated in it; if negative, I merely exclude from the conception its contrary. But in synthetical judgements, I
must go beyond the given conception, in order to cogitate, in relation with it, something quite different from
that which was cogitated in it, a relation which is consequently never one either of identity or contradiction,
and by means of which the truth or error of the judgement cannot be discerned merely from the judgement
itself.
Granted, then, that we must go out beyond a given conception, in order to compare it synthetically with
another, a third thing is necessary, in which alone the synthesis of two conceptions can originate. Now what
is this tertium quid that is to be the medium of all synthetical judgements? It is only a complex in which all
our representations are contained, the internal sense to wit, and its form a priori, time.
The synthesis of our representations rests upon the imagination; their synthetical unity (which is requisite to a
judgement), upon the unity of apperception. In this, therefore, is to be sought the possibility of synthetical
judgements, and as all three contain the sources of a priori representations, the possibility of pure synthetical
judgements also; nay, they are necessary upon these grounds, if we are to possess a knowledge of objects,
which rests solely upon the synthesis of representations.
If a cognition is to have objective reality, that is, to relate to an object, and possess sense and meaning in
respect to it, it is necessary that the object be given in some way or another. Without this, our conceptions are
empty, and we may indeed have thought by means of them, but by such thinking we have not, in fact,
cognized anything, we have merely played with representation. To give an object, if this expression be
understood in the sense of "to present" the object, not mediately but immediately in intuition, means nothing
else than to apply the representation of it to experience, be that experience real or only possible. Space and
time themselves, pure as these conceptions are from all that is empirical, and certain as it is that they are
represented fully a priori in the mind, would be completely without objective validity, and without sense and
significance, if their necessary use in the objects of experience were not shown. Nay, the representation of
them is a mere schema, that always relates to the reproductive imagination, which calls up the objects of
experience, without which they have no meaning. And so it is with all conceptions without distinction.
The possibility of experience is, then, that which gives objective reality to all our a priori cognitions. Now
experience depends upon the synthetical unity of phenomena, that is, upon a synthesis according to
conceptions of the object of phenomena in general, a synthesis without which experience never could become
knowledge, but would be merely a rhapsody of perceptions, never fitting together into any connected text,
according to rules of a thoroughly united (possible) consciousness, and therefore never subjected to the
transcendental and necessary unity of apperception. Experience has therefore for a foundation, a priori
principles of its form, that is to say, general rules of unity in the synthesis of phenomena, the objective reality
of which rules, as necessary conditions even of the possibility of experience can which rules, as necessary
conditions even of the possibility of experience can always be shown in experience. But apart from this
relation, a priori synthetical propositions are absolutely impossible, because they have no third term, that is,
no pure object, in which the synthetical unity can exhibit the objective reality of its conceptions.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements. 72
Page No 77
Although, then, respecting space, or the forms which productive imagination describes therein, we do cognize
much a priori in synthetical judgements, and are really in no need of experience for this purpose, such
knowledge would nevertheless amount to nothing but a busy trifling with a mere chimera, were not space to
be considered as the condition of the phenomena which constitute the material of external experience. Hence
those pure synthetical judgements do relate, though but mediately, to possible experience, or rather to the
possibility of experience, and upon that alone is founded the objective validity of their synthesis.
While then, on the one hand, experience, as empirical synthesis, is the only possible mode of cognition which
gives reality to all other synthesis; on the other hand, this latter synthesis, as cognition a priori, possesses
truth, that is, accordance with its object, only in so far as it contains nothing more than what is necessary to
the synthetical unity of experience.
Accordingly, the supreme principle of all synthetical judgements is: "Every object is subject to the necessary
conditions of the synthetical unity of the manifold of intuition in a possible experience."
A priori synthetical judgements are possible when we apply the formal conditions of the a priori intuition, the
synthesis of the imagination, and the necessary unity of that synthesis in a transcendental apperception, to a
possible cognition of experience, and say: "The conditions of the possibility of experience in general are at
the same time conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience, and have, for that reason, objective
validity in an a priori synthetical judgement."
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of
the Pure Understanding.
That principles exist at all is to be ascribed solely to the pure understanding, which is not only the faculty of
rules in regard to that which happens, but is even the source of principles according to which everything that
can be presented to us as an object is necessarily subject to rules, because without such rules we never could
attain to cognition of an object. Even the laws of nature, if they are contemplated as principles of the
empirical use of the understanding, possess also a characteristic of necessity, and we may therefore at least
expect them to be determined upon grounds which are valid a priori and antecedent to all experience. But all
laws of nature, without distinction, are subject to higher principles of the understanding, inasmuch as the
former are merely applications of the latter to particular cases of experience. These higher principles alone
therefore give the conception, which contains the necessary condition, and, as it were, the exponent of a rule;
experience, on the other hand, gives the case which comes under the rule.
There is no danger of our mistaking merely empirical principles for principles of the pure understanding, or
conversely; for the character of necessity, according to conceptions which distinguish the latter, and the
absence of this in every empirical proposition, how extensively valid soever it may be, is a perfect safeguard
against confounding them. There are, however, pure principles a priori, which nevertheless I should not
ascribe to the pure understanding for this reason, that they are not derived from pure conceptions, but
(although by the mediation of the understanding) from pure intuitions. But understanding is the faculty of
conceptions. Such principles mathematical science possesses, but their application to experience,
consequently their objective validity, nay the possibility of such a priori synthetical cognitions (the deduction
thereof) rests entirely upon the pure understanding.
On this account, I shall not reckon among my principles those of mathematics; though I shall include those
upon the possibility and objective validity a priori, of principles of the mathematical science, which,
consequently, are to be looked upon as the principle of these, and which proceed from conceptions to
intuition, and not from intuition to conceptions.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 73
Page No 78
In the application of the pure conceptions of the understanding to possible experience, the employment of
their synthesis is either mathematical or dynamical, for it is directed partly on the intuition alone, partly on
the existence of a phenomenon. But the a priori conditions of intuition are in relation to a possible experience
absolutely necessary, those of the existence of objects of a possible empirical intuition are in themselves
contingent. Hence the principles of the mathematical use of the categories will possess a character of absolute
necessity, that is, will be apodeictic; those, on the other hand, of the dynamical use, the character of an a
priori necessity indeed, but only under the condition of empirical thought in an experience, therefore only
mediately and indirectly. Consequently they will not possess that immediate evidence which is peculiar to the
former, although their application to experience does not, for that reason, lose its truth and certitude. But of
this point we shall be better able to judge at the conclusion of this system of principles.
The table of the categories is naturally our guide to the table of principles, because these are nothing else than
rules for the objective employment of the former. Accordingly, all principles of the pure understanding are:
1
Axioms
of Intuition
2 3
Anticipations Analogies
of Perception of Experience
4
Postulates of
Empirical Thought
in general
These appellations I have chosen advisedly, in order that we might not lose sight of the distinctions in respect
of the evidence and the employment of these principles. It will, however, soon appear that a fact which
concerns both the evidence of these principles, and the a priori determination of phenomena according to
the categories of quantity and quality (if we attend merely to the form of these), the principles of these
categories are distinguishable from those of the two others, in as much as the former are possessed of an
intuitive, but the latter of a merely discursive, though in both instances a complete, certitude. I shall therefore
call the former mathematical, and the latter dynamical principles.* It must be observed, however, that by
these terms I mean just as little in the one case the principles of mathematics as those of general (physical)
dynamics in the other. I have here in view merely the principles of the pure understanding, in their
application to the internal sense (without distinction of the representations given therein), by means of which
the sciences of mathematics and dynamics become possible. Accordingly, I have named these principles
rather with reference to their application than their content; and I shall now proceed to consider them in the
order in which they stand in the table.
*All combination (conjunctio) is either composition (compositio) or connection (nexus). The former is the
synthesis of a manifold, the parts of which do not necessarily belong to each other. For example, the two
triangles into which a square is divided by a diagonal, do not necessarily belong to each other, and of this
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 74
Page No 79
kind is the synthesis of the homogeneous in everything that can be mathematically considered. This synthesis
can be divided into those of aggregation and coalition, the former of which is applied to extensive, the latter
to intensive quantities. The second sort of combination (nexus) is the synthesis of a manifold, in so far as its
parts do belong necessarily to each other; for example, the accident to a substance, or the effect to the cause.
Consequently it is a synthesis of that which though heterogeneous, is represented as connected a priori. This
combination not an arbitrary one I entitle dynamical because it concerns the connection of the existence of
the manifold. This, again, may be divided into the physical synthesis, of the phenomena divided among each
other, and the metaphysical synthesis, or the connection of phenomena a priori in the faculty of cognition.
1. AXIOMS OF INTUITION.
The principle of these is: All Intuitions are Extensive
Quantities.
PROOF.
All phenomena contain, as regards their form, an intuition in space and time, which lies a priori at the
foundation of all without exception. Phenomena, therefore, cannot be apprehended, that is, received into
empirical consciousness otherwise than through the synthesis of a manifold, through which the
representations of a determinate space or time are generated; that is to say, through the composition of the
homogeneous and the consciousness of the synthetical unity of this manifold (homogeneous). Now the
consciousness of a homogeneous manifold in intuition, in so far as thereby the representation of an object is
rendered possible, is the conception of a quantity (quanti). Consequently, even the perception of an object as
phenomenon is possible only through the same synthetical unity of the manifold of the given sensuous
intuition, through which the unity of the composition of the homogeneous manifold in the conception of a
quantity is cogitated; that is to say, all phenomena are quantities, and extensive quantities, because as
intuitions in space or time they must be represented by means of the same synthesis through which space and
time themselves are determined.
An extensive quantity I call that wherein the representation of the parts renders possible (and therefore
necessarily antecedes) the representation of the whole. I cannot represent to myself any line, however small,
without drawing it in thought, that is, without generating from a point all its parts one after another, and in
this way alone producing this intuition. Precisely the same is the case with every, even the smallest, portion
of time. I cogitate therein only the successive progress from one moment to another, and hence, by means of
the different portions of time and the addition of them, a determinate quantity of time is produced. As the
pure intuition in all phenomena is either time or space, so is every phenomenon in its character of intuition an
extensive quantity, inasmuch as it can only be cognized in our apprehension by successive synthesis (from
part to part). All phenomena are, accordingly, to be considered as aggregates, that is, as a collection of
previously given parts; which is not the case with every sort of quantities, but only with those which are
represented and apprehended by us as extensive.
On this successive synthesis of the productive imagination, in the generation of figures, is founded the
mathematics of extension, or geometry, with its axioms, which express the conditions of sensuous intuition a
priori, under which alone the schema of a pure conception of external intuition can exist; for example, "be
tween two points only one straight line is possible," "two straight lines cannot enclose a space," etc. These are
the axioms which properly relate only to quantities (quanta) as such.
But, as regards the quantity of a thing (quantitas), that is to say, the answer to the question: "How large is this
or that object?" although, in respect to this question, we have various propositions synthetical and
immediately certain (indemonstrabilia); we have, in the proper sense of the term, no axioms. For example, the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 75
Page No 80
propositions: "If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal"; "If equals be taken from equals, the
remainders are equal"; are analytical, because I am immediately conscious of the identity of the production of
the one quantity with the production of the other; whereas axioms must be a priori synthetical propositions.
On the other hand, the selfevident propositions as to the relation of numbers, are certainly synthetical but
not universal, like those of geometry, and for this reason cannot be called axioms, but numerical formulae.
That 7 + 5 = 12 is not an analytical proposition. For neither in the representation of seven, nor of five, nor of
the composition of the two numbers, do I cogitate the number twelve. (Whether I cogitate the number in the
addition of both, is not at present the question; for in the case of an analytical proposition, the only point is
whether I really cogitate the predicate in the representation of the subject.) But although the proposition is
synthetical, it is nevertheless only a singular proposition. In so far as regard is here had merely to the
synthesis of the homogeneous (the units), it cannot take place except in one manner, although our use of these
numbers is afterwards general. If I say: "A triangle can be constructed with three lines, any two of which
taken together are greater than the third," I exercise merely the pure function of the productive imagination,
which may draw the lines longer or shorter and construct the angles at its pleasure. On the contrary, the
number seven is possible only in one manner, and so is likewise the number twelve, which results from the
synthesis of seven and five. Such propositions, then, cannot be termed axioms (for in that case we should
have an infinity of these), but numerical formulae.
This transcendental principle of the mathematics of phenomena greatly enlarges our a priori cognition. For it
is by this principle alone that pure mathematics is rendered applicable in all its precision to objects of
experience, and without it the validity of this application would not be so selfevident; on the contrary,
contradictions and confusions have often arisen on this very point. Phenomena are not things in themselves.
Empirical intuition is possible only through pure intuition (of space and time); consequently, what geometry
affirms of the latter, is indisputably valid of the former. All evasions, such as the statement that objects of
sense do not conform to the rules of construction in space (for example, to the rule of the infinite divisibility
of lines or angles), must fall to the ground. For, if these objections hold good, we deny to space, and with it to
all mathematics, objective validity, and no longer know wherefore, and how far, mathematics can be applied
to phenomena. The synthesis of spaces and times as the essential form of all intuition, is that which renders
possible the apprehension of a phenomenon, and therefore every external experience, consequently all
cognition of the objects of experience; and whatever mathematics in its pure use proves of the former, must
necessarily hold good of the latter. All objections are but the chicaneries of an illinstructed reason, which
erroneously thinks to liberate the objects of sense from the formal conditions of our sensibility, and represents
these, although mere phenomena, as things in themselves, presented as such to our understanding. But in this
case, no a priori synthetical cognition of them could be possible, consequently not through pure conceptions
of space and the science which determines these conceptions, that is to say, geometry, would itself be
impossible.
2. ANTICIPATIONS OF PERCEPTION.
The principle of these is: In all phenomena the Real, that
which is an object of sensation, has Intensive Quantity,
that is, has a Degree.
PROOF.
Perception is empirical consciousness, that is to say, a consciousness which contains an element of sensation.
Phenomena as objects of perception are not pure, that is, merely formal intuitions, like space and time, for
they cannot be perceived in themselves. They contain, then, over and above the intuition, the materials for an
object (through which is represented something existing in space or time), that is to say, they contain the real
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 76
Page No 81
of sensation, as a representation merely subjective, which gives us merely the consciousness that the subject
is affected, and which we refer to some external object. Now, a gradual transition from empirical
consciousness to pure consciousness is possible, inasmuch as the real in this consciousness entirely vanishes,
and there remains a merely formal consciousness (a priori) of the manifold in time and space; consequently
there is possible a synthesis also of the production of the quantity of a sensation from its commencement, that
is, from the pure intuition = 0 onwards up to a certain quantity of the sensation. Now as sensation in itself is
not an objective representation, and in it is to be found neither the intuition of space nor of time, it cannot
possess any extensive quantity, and yet there does belong to it a quantity (and that by means of its
apprehension, in which empirical consciousness can within a certain time rise from nothing = 0 up to its
given amount), consequently an intensive quantity. And thus we must ascribe intensive quantity, that is, a
degree of influence on sense to all objects of perception, in so far as this perception contains sensation.
All cognition, by means of which I am enabled to cognize and determine a priori what belongs to empirical
cognition, may be called an anticipation; and without doubt this is the sense in which Epicurus employed his
expression prholepsis. But as there is in phenomena something which is never cognized a priori, which on
this account constitutes the proper difference between pure and empirical cognition, that is to say, sensation
(as the matter of perception), it follows, that sensation is just that element in cognition which cannot be at all
anticipated. On the other hand, we might very well term the pure determinations in space and time, as well in
regard to figure as to quantity, anticipations of phenomena, because they represent a priori that which may
always be given a posteriori in experience. But suppose that in every sensation, as sensation in general,
without any particular sensation being thought of, there existed something which could be cognized a priori,
this would deserve to be called anticipation in a special sense special, because it may seem surprising to
forestall experience, in that which concerns the matter of experience, and which we can only derive from
itself. Yet such really is the case here.
Apprehension, by means of sensation alone, fills only one moment, that is, if I do not take into consideration
a succession of many sensations. As that in the phenomenon, the apprehension of which is not a successive
synthesis advancing from parts to an entire representation, sensation has therefore no extensive quantity; the
want of sensation in a moment of time would represent it as empty, consequently = O. That which in the
empirical intuition corresponds to sensation is reality (realitas phaenomenon); that which corresponds to the
absence of it, negation = O. Now every sensation is capable of a diminution, so that it can decrease, and thus
gradually disappear. Therefore, between reality in a phenomenon and negation, there exists a continuous
concatenation of many possible intermediate sensations, the difference of which from each other is always
smaller than that between the given sensation and zero, or complete negation. That is to say, the real in a
phenomenon has always a quantity, which however is not discoverable in apprehension, inasmuch as
apprehension take place by means of mere sensation in one instant, and not by the successive synthesis of
many sensations, and therefore does not progress from parts to the whole. Consequently, it has a quantity, but
not an extensive quantity.
Now that quantity which is apprehended only as unity, and in which plurality can be represented only by
approximation to negation = O, I term intensive quantity. Consequently, reality in a phenomenon has
intensive quantity, that is, a degree. if we consider this reality as cause (be it of sensation or of another reality
in the phenomenon, for example, a change), we call the degree of reality in its character of cause a
momentum, for example, the momentum of weight; and for this reason, that the degree only indicates that
quantity the apprehension of which is not successive, but instantaneous. This, however, I touch upon only in
passing, for with causality I have at present nothing to do.
Accordingly, every sensation, consequently every reality in phenomena, however small it may be, has a
degree, that is, an intensive quantity, which may always be lessened, and between reality and negation there
exists a continuous connection of possible realities, and possible smaller perceptions. Every colour for
example, red has a degree, which, be it ever so small, is never the smallest, and so is it always with heat, the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 77
Page No 82
momentum of weight, etc.
This property of quantities, according to which no part of them is the smallest possible (no part simple), is
called their continuity. Space and time are quanta continua, because no part of them can be given, without
enclosing it within boundaries (points and moments), consequently, this given part is itself a space or a time.
Space, therefore, consists only of spaces, and time of times. Points and moments are only boundaries, that is,
the mere places or positions of their limitation. But places always presuppose intuitions which are to limit or
determine them; and we cannot conceive either space or time composed of constituent parts which are given
before space or time. Such quantities may also be called flowing, because synthesis (of the productive
imagination) in the production of these quantities is a progression in time, the continuity of which we are
accustomed to indicate by the expression flowing.
All phenomena, then, are continuous quantities, in respect both to intuition and mere perception (sensation,
and with it reality). In the former case they are extensive quantities; in the latter, intensive. When the
synthesis of the manifold of a phenomenon is interrupted, there results merely an aggregate of several
phenomena, and not properly a phenomenon as a quantity, which is not produced by the mere continuation of
the productive synthesis of a certain kind, but by the repetition of a synthesis always ceasing. For example, if
I call thirteen dollars a sum or quantity of money, I employ the term quite correctly, inasmuch as I understand
by thirteen dollars the value of a mark in standard silver, which is, to be sure, a continuous quantity, in which
no part is the smallest, but every part might constitute a piece of money, which would contain material for
still smaller pieces. If, however, by the words thirteen dollars I understand so many coins (be their value in
silver what it may), it would be quite erroneous to use the expression a quantity of dollars; on the contrary, I
must call them aggregate, that is, a number of coins. And as in every number we must have unity as the
foundation, so a phenomenon taken as unity is a quantity, and as such always a continuous quantity (quantum
continuum).
Now, seeing all phenomena, whether considered as extensive or intensive, are continuous quantities, the
proposition: "All change (transition of a thing from one state into another) is continuous," might be proved
here easily, and with mathematical evidence, were it not that the causality of a change lies, entirely beyond
the bounds of a transcendental philosophy, and presupposes empirical principles. For of the possibility of a
cause which changes the condition of things, that is, which determines them to the contrary to a certain given
state, the understanding gives us a priori no knowledge; not merely because it has no insight into the
possibility of it (for such insight is absent in several a priori cognitions), but because the notion of change
concerns only certain determinations of phenomena, which experience alone can acquaint us with, while their
cause lies in the unchangeable. But seeing that we have nothing which we could here employ but the pure
fundamental conceptions of all possible experience, among which of course nothing empirical can be
admitted, we dare not, without injuring the unity of our system, anticipate general physical science, which is
built upon certain fundamental experiences.
Nevertheless, we are in no want of proofs of the great influence which the principle above developed
exercises in the anticipation of perceptions, and even in supplying the want of them, so far as to shield us
against the false conclusions which otherwise we might rashly draw.
If all reality in perception has a degree, between which and negation there is an endless sequence of ever
smaller degrees, and if, nevertheless, every sense must have a determinate degree of receptivity for
sensations; no perception, and consequently no experience is possible, which can prove, either immediately
or mediately, an entire absence of all reality in a phenomenon; in other words, it is impossible ever to draw
from experience a proof of the existence of empty space or of empty time. For in the first place, an entire
absence of reality in a sensuous intuition cannot of course be an object of perception; secondly, such absence
cannot be deduced from the contemplation of any single phenomenon, and the difference of the degrees in its
reality; nor ought it ever to be admitted in explanation of any phenomenon. For if even the complete intuition
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 78
Page No 83
of a determinate space or time is thoroughly real, that is, if no part thereof is empty, yet because every reality
has its degree, which, with the extensive quantity of the phenomenon unchanged, can diminish through
endless gradations down to nothing (the void), there must be infinitely graduated degrees, with which space
or time is filled, and the intensive quantity in different phenomena may be smaller or greater, although the
extensive quantity of the intuition remains equal and unaltered.
We shall give an example of this. Almost all natural philosophers, remarking a great difference in the
quantity of the matter of different kinds in bodies with the same volume (partly on account of the momentum
of gravity or weight, partly on account of the momentum of resistance to other bodies in motion), conclude
unanimously that this volume (extensive quantity of the phenomenon) must be void in all bodies, although in
different proportion. But who would suspect that these for the most part mathematical and mechanical
inquirers into nature should ground this conclusion solely on a metaphysical hypothesis a sort of hypothesis
which they profess to disparage and avoid? Yet this they do, in assuming that the real in space (I must not
here call it impenetrability or weight, because these are empirical conceptions) is always identical, and can
only be distinguished according to its extensive quantity, that is, multiplicity. Now to this presupposition, for
which they can have no ground in experience, and which consequently is merely metaphysical, I oppose a
transcendental demonstration, which it is true will not explain the difference in the filling up of spaces, but
which nevertheless completely does away with the supposed necessity of the abovementioned
presupposition that we cannot explain the said difference otherwise than by the hypothesis of empty spaces.
This demonstration, moreover, has the merit of setting the understanding at liberty to conceive this distinction
in a different manner, if the explanation of the fact requires any such hypothesis. For we perceive that
although two equal spaces may be completely filled by matters altogether different, so that in neither of them
is there left a single point wherein matter is not present, nevertheless, every reality has its degree (of
resistance or of weight), which, without diminution of the extensive quantity, can become less and less ad
infinitum, before it passes into nothingness and disappears. Thus an expansion which fills a space for
example, caloric, or any other reality in the phenomenal world can decrease in its degrees to infinity, yet
without leaving the smallest part of the space empty; on the contrary, filling it with those lesser degrees as
completely as another phenomenon could with greater. My intention here is by no means to maintain that this
is really the case with the difference of matters, in regard to their specific gravity; I wish only to prove, from
a principle of the pure understanding, that the nature of our perceptions makes such a mode of explanation
possible, and that it is erroneous to regard the real in a phenomenon as equal quoad its degree, and different
only quoad its aggregation and extensive quantity, and this, too, on the pretended authority of an a priori
principle of the understanding.
Nevertheless, this principle of the anticipation of perception must somewhat startle an inquirer whom
initiation into transcendental philosophy has rendered cautious. We must naturally entertain some doubt
whether or not the understanding can enounce any such synthetical proposition as that respecting the degree
of all reality in phenomena, and consequently the possibility of the internal difference of sensation itself
abstraction being made of its empirical quality. Thus it is a question not unworthy of solution: "How the
understanding can pronounce synthetically and a priori respecting phenomena, and thus anticipate these, even
in that which is peculiarly and merely empirical, that, namely, which concerns sensation itself?"
The quality of sensation is in all cases merely empirical, and cannot be represented a priori (for example,
colours, taste, etc.). But the real that which corresponds to sensation in opposition to negation = O, only
represents something the conception of which in itself contains a being (ein seyn), and signifies nothing but
the synthesis in an empirical consciousness. That is to say, the empirical consciousness in the internal sense
can be raised from 0 to every higher degree, so that the very same extensive quantity of intuition, an
illuminated surface, for example, excites as great a sensation as an aggregate of many other surfaces less
illuminated. We can therefore make complete abstraction of the extensive quantity of a phenomenon, and
represent to ourselves in the mere sensation in a certain momentum, a synthesis of homogeneous ascension
from 0 up to the given empirical consciousness, All sensations therefore as such are given only a posteriori,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 79
Page No 84
but this property thereof, namely, that they have a degree, can be known a priori. It is worthy of remark, that
in respect to quantities in general, we can cognize a priori only a single quality, namely, continuity; but in
respect to all quality (the real in phenomena), we cannot cognize a priori anything more than the intensive
quantity thereof, namely, that they have a degree. All else is left to experience.
3. ANALOGIES OF EXPERIENCE.
The principle of these is: Experience is possible only
through the representation of a necessary connection
of Perceptions.
PROOF.
Experience is an empirical cognition; that is to say, a cognition which determines an object by means of
perceptions. It is therefore a synthesis of perceptions, a synthesis which is not itself contained in perception,
but which contains the synthetical unity of the manifold of perception in a consciousness; and this unity
constitutes the essential of our cognition of objects of the senses, that is, of experience (not merely of
intuition or sensation). Now in experience our perceptions come together contingently, so that no character of
necessity in their connection appears, or can appear from the perceptions themselves, because apprehension is
only a placing together of the manifold of empirical intuition, and no representation of a necessity in the
connected existence of the phenomena which apprehension brings together, is to be discovered therein. But as
experience is a cognition of objects by means of perceptions, it follows that the relation of the existence of
the existence of the manifold must be represented in experience not as it is put together in time, but as it is
objectively in time. And as time itself cannot be perceived, the determination of the existence of objects in
time can only take place by means of their connection in time in general, consequently only by means of a
priori connecting conceptions. Now as these conceptions always possess the character of necessity,
experience is possible only by means of a representation of the necessary connection of perception.
The three modi of time are permanence, succession, and coexistence. Accordingly, there are three rules of all
relations of time in phenomena, according to which the existence of every phenomenon is determined in
respect of the unity of all time, and these antecede all experience and render it possible.
The general principle of all three analogies rests on the necessary unity of apperception in relation to all
possible empirical consciousness (perception) at every time, consequently, as this unity lies a priori at the
foundation of all mental operations, the principle rests on the synthetical unity of all phenomena according to
their relation in time. For the original apperception relates to our internal sense (the complex of all
representations), and indeed relates a priori to its form, that is to say, the relation of the manifold empirical
consciousness in time. Now this manifold must be combined in original apperception according to relations
of time a necessity imposed by the a priori transcendental unity of apperception, to which is subjected all
that can belong to my (i.e., my own) cognition, and therefore all that can become an object for me. This
synthetical and a priori determined unity in relation of perceptions in time is therefore the rule: "All empirical
determinations of time must be subject to rules of the general determination of time"; and the analogies of
experience, of which we are now about to treat, must be rules of this nature.
These principles have this peculiarity, that they do not concern phenomena, and the synthesis of the empirical
intuition thereof, but merely the existence of phenomena and their relation to each other in regard to this
existence. Now the mode in which we apprehend a thing in a phenomenon can be determined a priori in such
a manner that the rule of its synthesis can give, that is to say, can produce this a priori intuition in every
empirical example. But the existence of phenomena cannot be known a priori, and although we could arrive
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 80
Page No 85
by this path at a conclusion of the fact of some existence, we could not cognize that existence determinately,
that is to say, we should be incapable of anticipating in what respect the empirical intuition of it would be
distinguishable from that of others.
The two principles above mentioned, which I called mathematical, in consideration of the fact of their
authorizing the application of mathematic phenomena, relate to these phenomena only in regard to their
possibility, and instruct us how phenomena, as far as regards their intuition or the real in their perception, can
be generated according to the rules of a mathematical synthesis. Consequently, numerical quantities, and with
them the determination of a phenomenon as a quantity, can be employed in the one case as well as in the
other. Thus, for example, out of 200,000 illuminations by the moon, I might compose and give a priori, that is
construct, the degree of our sensations of the sunlight. We may therefore entitle these two principles
constitutive.
The case is very different with those principles whose province it is to subject the existence of phenomena to
rules a priori. For as existence does not admit of being constructed, it is clear that they must only concern the
relations of existence and be merely regulative principles. In this case, therefore, neither axioms nor
anticipations are to be thought of. Thus, if a perception is given us, in a certain relation of time to other
(although undetermined) perceptions, we cannot then say a priori, what and how great (in quantity) the other
perception necessarily connected with the former is, but only how it is connected, quoad its existence, in this
given modus of time. Analogies in philosophy mean something very different from that which they represent
in mathematics. In the latter they are formulae, which enounce the equality of two relations of quantity, and
are always constitutive, so that if two terms of the proportion are given, the third is also given, that is, can be
constructed by the aid of these formulae. But in philosophy, analogy is not the equality of two quantitative
but of two qualitative relations. In this case, from three given terms, I can give a priori and cognize the
relation to a fourth member, but not this fourth term itself, although I certainly possess a rule to guide me in
the search for this fourth term in experience, and a mark to assist me in discovering it. An analogy of
experience is therefore only a rule according to which unity of experience must arise out of perceptions in
respect to objects (phenomena) not as a constitutive, but merely as a regulative principle. The same holds
good also of the postulates of empirical thought in general, which relate to the synthesis of mere intuition
(which concerns the form of phenomena), the synthesis of perception (which concerns the matter of
phenomena), and the synthesis of experience (which concerns the relation of these perceptions). For they are
only regulative principles, and clearly distinguishable from the mathematical, which are constitutive, not
indeed in regard to the certainty which both possess a priori, but in the mode of evidence thereof,
consequently also in the manner of demonstration.
But what has been observed of all synthetical propositions, and must be particularly remarked in this place, is
this, that these analogies possess significance and validity, not as principles of the transcendental, but only as
principles of the empirical use of the understanding, and their truth can therefore be proved only as such, and
that consequently the phenomena must not be subjoined directly under the categories, but only under their
schemata. For if the objects to which those principles must be applied were things in themselves, it would be
quite impossible to cognize aught concerning them synthetically a priori. But they are nothing but
phenomena; a complete knowledge of which a knowledge to which all principles a priori must at last relate
is the only possible experience. It follows that these principles can have nothing else for their aim than the
conditions of the empirical cognition in the unity of synthesis of phenomena. But this synthesis is cogitated
only in the schema of the pure conception of the understanding, of whose unity, as that of a synthesis in
general, the category contains the function unrestricted by any sensuous condition. These principles will
therefore authorize us to connect phenomena according to an analogy, with the logical and universal unity of
conceptions, and consequently to employ the categories in the principles themselves; but in the application of
them to experience, we shall use only their schemata, as the key to their proper application, instead of the
categories, or rather the latter as restricting conditions, under the title of "formulae" of the former.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 81
Page No 86
A. FIRST ANALOGY.
Principle of the Permanence of Substance.
In all changes of phenomena, substance is permanent, and the
quantum thereof in nature is neither increased nor diminished.
PROOF.
All phenomena exist in time, wherein alone as substratum, that is, as the permanent form of the internal
intuition, coexistence and succession can be represented. Consequently time, in which all changes of
phenomena must be cogitated, remains and changes not, because it is that in which succession and
coexistence can be represented only as determinations thereof. Now, time in itself cannot be an object of
perception. It follows that in objects of perception, that is, in phenomena, there must be found a substratum
which represents time in general, and in which all change or coexistence can be perceived by means of the
relation of phenomena to it. But the substratum of all reality, that is, of all that pertains to the existence of
things, is substance; all that pertains to existence can be cogitated only as a determination of substance.
Consequently, the permanent, in relation to which alone can all relations of time in phenomena be
determined, is substance in the world of phenomena, that is, the real in phenomena, that which, as the
substratum of all change, remains ever the same. Accordingly, as this cannot change in existence, its quantity
in nature can neither be increased nor diminished.
Our apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon is always successive, is Consequently always changing.
By it alone we could, therefore, never determine whether this manifold, as an object of experience, is
coexistent or successive, unless it had for a foundation something fixed and permanent, of the existence of
which all succession and coexistence are nothing but so many modes (modi of time). Only in the permanent,
then, are relations of time possible (for simultaneity and succession are the only relations in time); that is to
say, the permanent is the substratum of our empirical representation of time itself, in which alone all
determination of time is possible. Permanence is, in fact, just another expression for time, as the abiding
correlate of all existence of phenomena, and of all change, and of all coexistence. For change does not affect
time itself, but only the phenomena in time (just as coexistence cannot be regarded as a modus of time itself,
seeing that in time no parts are coexistent, but all successive). If we were to attribute succession to time itself,
we should be obliged to cogitate another time, in which this succession would be possible. It is only by
means of the permanent that existence in different parts of the successive series of time receives a quantity,
which we entitle duration. For in mere succession, existence is perpetually vanishing and recommencing, and
therefore never has even the least quantity. Without the permanent, then, no relation in time is possible. Now,
time in itself is not an object of perception; consequently the permanent in phenomena must be regarded as
the substratum of all determination of time, and consequently also as the condition of the possibility of all
synthetical unity of perceptions, that is, of experience; and all existence and all change in time can only be
regarded as a mode in the existence of that which abides unchangeably. Therefore, in all phenomena, the
permanent is the object in itself, that is, the substance (phenomenon); but all that changes or can change
belongs only to the mode of the existence of this substance or substances, consequently to its determinations.
I find that in all ages not only the philosopher, but even the common understanding, has preposited this
permanence as a substratum of all change in phenomena; indeed, I am compelled to believe that they will
always accept this as an indubitable fact. Only the philosopher expresses himself in a more precise and
definite manner, when he says: "In all changes in the world, the substance remains, and the accidents alone
are changeable." But of this decidedly synthetical proposition, I nowhere meet with even an attempt at proof;
nay, it very rarely has the good fortune to stand, as it deserves to do, at the head of the pure and entirely a
priori laws of nature. In truth, the statement that substance is permanent, is tautological. For this very
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 82
Page No 87
permanence is the ground on which we apply the category of substance to the phenomenon; and we should
have been obliged to prove that in all phenomena there is something permanent, of the existence of which the
changeable is nothing but a determination. But because a proof of this nature cannot be dogmatical, that is,
cannot be drawn from conceptions, inasmuch as it concerns a synthetical proposition a priori, and as
philosophers never reflected that such propositions are valid only in relation to possible experience, and
therefore cannot be proved except by means of a deduction of the possibility of experience, it is no wonder
that while it has served as the foundation of all experience (for we feel the need of it in empirical cognition),
it has never been supported by proof.
A philosopher was asked: "What is the weight of smoke?" He answered: "Subtract from the weight of the
burnt wood the weight of the remaining ashes, and you will have the weight of the smoke." Thus he
presumed it to be incontrovertible that even in fire the matter (substance) does not perish, but that only the
form of it undergoes a change. In like manner was the saying: "From nothing comes nothing," only another
inference from the principle or permanence, or rather of the everabiding existence of the true subject in
phenomena. For if that in the phenomenon which we call substance is to be the proper substratum of all
determination of time, it follows that all existence in past as well as in future time, must be determinable by
means of it alone. Hence we are entitled to apply the term substance to a phenomenon, only because we
suppose its existence in all time, a notion which the word permanence does not fully express, as it seems
rather to be referable to future time. However, the internal necessity perpetually to be, is inseparably
connected with the necessity always to have been, and so the expression may stand as it is. "Gigni de nihilo
nihil; in nihilum nil posse reverti,"* are two propositions which the ancients never parted, and which people
nowadays sometimes mistakenly disjoin, because they imagine that the propositions apply to objects as
things in themselves, and that the former might be inimical to the dependence (even in respect of its
substance also) of the world upon a supreme cause. But this apprehension is entirely needless, for the
question in this case is only of phenomena in the sphere of experience, the unity of which never could be
possible, if we admitted the possibility that new things (in respect of their substance) should arise. For in that
case, we should lose altogether that which alone can represent the unity of time, to wit, the identity of the
substratum, as that through which alone all change possesses complete and thorough unity. This permanence
is, however, nothing but the manner in which we represent to ourselves the existence of things in the
phenomenal world.
*[Persius, Satirae, iii.8384. "Nothing can be produced from nothing; nothing can be returned into nothing."]
The determinations of a substance, which are only particular modes of its existence, are called accidents.
They are always real, because they concern the existence of substance (negations are only determinations,
which express the nonexistence of something in the substance). Now, if to this real in the substance we
ascribe a particular existence (for example, to motion as an accident of matter), this existence is called
inherence, in contradistinction to the existence of substance, which we call subsistence. But hence arise many
misconceptions, and it would be a more accurate and just mode of expression to designate the accident only
as the mode in which the existence of a substance is positively determined. Meanwhile, by reason of the
conditions of the logical exercise of our understanding, it is impossible to avoid separating, as it were, that
which in the existence of a substance is subject to change, whilst the substance remains, and regarding it in
relation to that which is properly permanent and radical. On this account, this category of substance stands
under the title of relation, rather because it is the condition thereof than because it contains in itself any
relation.
Now, upon this notion of permanence rests the proper notion of the conception change. Origin and extinction
are not changes of that which originates or becomes extinct. Change is but a mode of existence, which
follows on another mode of existence of the same object; hence all that changes is permanent, and only the
condition thereof changes. Now since this mutation affects only determinations, which can have a beginning
or an end, we may say, employing an expression which seems somewhat paradoxical: "Only the permanent
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 83
Page No 88
(substance) is subject to change; the mutable suffers no change, but rather alternation, that is, when certain
determinations cease, others begin."
Change, when, cannot be perceived by us except in substances, and origin or extinction in an absolute sense,
that does not concern merely a determination of the permanent, cannot be a possible perception, for it is this
very notion of the permanent which renders possible the representation of a transition from one state into
another, and from nonbeing to being, which, consequently, can be empirically cognized only as alternating
determinations of that which is permanent. Grant that a thing absolutely begins to be; we must then have a
point of time in which it was not. But how and by what can we fix and determine this point of time, unless by
that which already exists? For a void time preceding is not an object of perception; but if we connect this
beginning with objects which existed previously, and which continue to exist till the object in question in
question begins to be, then the latter can only be a determination of the former as the permanent. The same
holds good of the notion of extinction, for this presupposes the empirical representation of a time, in which a
phenomenon no longer exists.
Substances (in the world of phenomena) are the substratum of all determinations of time. The beginning of
some, and the ceasing to be of other substances, would utterly do away with the only condition of the
empirical unity of time; and in that case phenomena would relate to two different times, in which, side by
side, existence would pass; which is absurd. For there is only one time in which all different times must be
placed, not as coexistent, but as successive.
Accordingly, permanence is a necessary condition under which alone phenomena, as things or objects, are
determinable in a possible experience. But as regards the empirical criterion of this necessary permanence,
and with it of the substantiality of phenomena, we shall find sufficient opportunity to speak in the sequel.
B. SECOND ANALOGY.
Principle of the Succession of Time According
to the Law of Causality.
All changes take place according to the law of the
connection of Cause and Effect.
PROOF.
(That all phenomena in the succession of time are only changes, that is, a successive being and nonbeing of
the determinations of substance, which is permanent; consequently that a being of substance itself which
follows on the nonbeing thereof, or a nonbeing of substance which follows on the being thereof, in other
words, that the origin or extinction of substance itself, is impossible all this has been fully established in
treating of the foregoing principle. This principle might have been expressed as follows: "All alteration
(succession) of phenomena is merely change"; for the changes of substance are not origin or extinction,
because the conception of change presupposes the same subject as existing with two opposite determinations,
and consequently as permanent. After this premonition, we shall proceed to the proof.)
I perceive that phenomena succeed one another, that is to say, a state of things exists at one time, the opposite
of which existed in a former state. In this case, then, I really connect together two perceptions in time. Now
connection is not an operation of mere sense and intuition, but is the product of a synthetical faculty of
imagination, which determines the internal sense in respect of a relation of time. But imagination can connect
these two states in two ways, so that either the one or the other may antecede in time; for time in itself cannot
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 84
Page No 89
be an object of perception, and what in an object precedes and what follows cannot be empirically determined
in relation to it. I am only conscious, then, that my imagination places one state before and the other after; not
that the one state antecedes the other in the object. In other words, the objective relation of the successive
phenomena remains quite undetermined by means of mere perception. Now in order that this relation may be
cognized as determined, the relation between the two states must be so cogitated that it is thereby determined
as necessary, which of them must be placed before and which after, and not conversely. But the conception
which carries with it a necessity of synthetical unity, can be none other than a pure conception of the
understanding which does not lie in mere perception; and in this case it is the conception of "the relation of
cause and effect," the former of which determines the latter in time, as its necessary consequence, and not as
something which might possibly antecede (or which might in some cases not be perceived to follow). It
follows that it is only because we subject the sequence of phenomena, and consequently all change, to the law
of causality, that experience itself, that is, empirical cognition of phenomena, becomes possible; and
consequently, that phenomena themselves, as objects of experience, are possible only by virtue of this law.
Our apprehension of the manifold of phenomena is always successive. The representations of parts succeed
one another. Whether they succeed one another in the object also, is a second point for reflection, which was
not contained in the former. Now we may certainly give the name of object to everything, even to every
representation, so far as we are conscious thereof; but what this word may mean in the case of phenomena,
not merely in so far as they (as representations) are objects, but only in so far as they indicate an object, is a
question requiring deeper consideration. In so far as they, regarded merely as representations, are at the same
time objects of consciousness, they are not to be distinguished from apprehension, that is, reception into the
synthesis of imagination, and we must therefore say: "The manifold of phenomena is always produced
successively in the mind." If phenomena were things in themselves, no man would be able to conjecture from
the succession of our representations how this manifold is connected in the object; for we have to do only
with our representations. How things may be in themselves, without regard to the representations through
which they affect us, is utterly beyond the sphere of our cognition. Now although phenomena are not things
in themselves, and are nevertheless the only thing given to us to be cognized, it is my duty to show what sort
of connection in time belongs to the manifold in phenomena themselves, while the representation of this
manifold in apprehension is always successive. For example, the apprehension of the manifold in the
phenomenon of a house which stands before me, is successive. Now comes the question whether the
manifold of this house is in itself successive which no one will be at all willing to grant. But, so soon as I
raise my conception of an object to the transcendental signification thereof, I find that the house is not a thing
in itself, but only a phenomenon, that is, a representation, the transcendental object of which remains utterly
unknown. What then am I to understand by the question: "How can the manifold be connected in the
phenomenon itself not considered as a thing in itself, but merely as a phenomenon?" Here that which lies in
my successive apprehension is regarded as representation, whilst the phenomenon which is given me,
notwithstanding that it is nothing more than a complex of these representations, is regarded as the object
thereof, with which my conception, drawn from the representations of apprehension, must harmonize. It is
very soon seen that, as accordance of the cognition with its object constitutes truth, the question now before
us can only relate to the formal conditions of empirical truth; and that the phenomenon, in opposition to the
representations of apprehension, can only be distinguished therefrom as the object of them, if it is subject to a
rule which distinguishes it from every other apprehension, and which renders necessary a mode of connection
of the manifold. That in the phenomenon which contains the condition of this necessary rule of apprehension,
is the object.
Let us now proceed to our task. That something happens, that is to say, that something or some state exists
which before was not, cannot be empirically perceived, unless a phenomenon precedes, which does not
contain in itself this state. For a reality which should follow upon a void time, in other words, a beginning,
which no state of things precedes, can just as little be apprehended as the void time itself. Every apprehension
of an event is therefore a perception which follows upon another perception. But as this is the case with all
synthesis of apprehension, as I have shown above in the example of a house, my apprehension of an event is
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 85
Page No 90
not yet sufficiently distinguished from other apprehensions. But I remark also that if in a phenomenon which
contains an occurrence, I call the antecedent state of my perception, A, and the following state, B, the
perception B can only follow A in apprehension, and the perception A cannot follow B, but only precede it.
For example, I see a ship float down the stream of a river. My perception of its place lower down follows
upon my perception of its place higher up the course of the river, and it is impossible that, in the
apprehension of this phenomenon, the vessel should be perceived first below and afterwards higher up the
stream. Here, therefore, the order in the sequence of perceptions in apprehension is determined; and by this
order apprehension is regulated. In the former example, my perceptions in the apprehension of a house might
begin at the roof and end at the foundation, or vice versa; or I might apprehend the manifold in this empirical
intuition, by going from left to right, and from right to left. Accordingly, in the series of these perceptions,
there was no determined order, which necessitated my beginning at a certain point, in order empirically to
connect the manifold. But this rule is always to be met with in the perception of that which happens, and it
makes the order of the successive perceptions in the apprehension of such a phenomenon necessary.
I must, therefore, in the present case, deduce the subjective sequence of apprehension from the objective
sequence of phenomena, for otherwise the former is quite undetermined, and one phenomenon is not
distinguishable from another. The former alone proves nothing as to the connection of the manifold in an
object, for it is quite arbitrary. The latter must consist in the order of the manifold in a phenomenon,
according to which order the apprehension of one thing (that which happens) follows that of another thing
(which precedes), in conformity with a rule. In this way alone can I be authorized to say of the phenomenon
itself, and not merely of my own apprehension, that a certain order or sequence is to be found therein. That is,
in other words, I cannot arrange my apprehension otherwise than in this order.
In conformity with this rule, then, it is necessary that in that which antecedes an event there be found the
condition of a rule, according to which in this event follows always and necessarily; but I cannot reverse this
and go back from the event, and determine (by apprehension) that which antecedes it. For no phenomenon
goes back from the succeeding point of time to the preceding point, although it does certainly relate to a
preceding point of time; from a given time, on the other hand, there is always a necessary progression to the
determined succeeding time. Therefore, because there certainly is something that follows, I must of necessity
connect it with something else, which antecedes, and upon which it follows, in conformity with a rule, that is
necessarily, so that the event, as conditioned, affords certain indication of a condition, and this condition
determines the event.
Let us suppose that nothing precedes an event, upon which this event must follow in conformity with a rule.
All sequence of perception would then exist only in apprehension, that is to say, would be merely subjective,
and it could not thereby be objectively determined what thing ought to precede, and what ought to follow in
perception. In such a case, we should have nothing but a play of representations, which would possess no
application to any object. That is to say, it would not be possible through perception to distinguish one
phenomenon from another, as regards relations of time; because the succession in the act of apprehension
would always be of the same sort, and therefore there would be nothing in the phenomenon to determine the
succession, and to render a certain sequence objectively necessary. And, in this case, I cannot say that two
states in a phenomenon follow one upon the other, but only that one apprehension follows upon another. But
this is merely subjective, and does not determine an object, and consequently cannot be held to be cognition
of an object not even in the phenomenal world.
Accordingly, when we know in experience that something happens, we always presuppose that something
precedes, whereupon it follows in conformity with a rule. For otherwise I could not say of the object that it
follows; because the mere succession in my apprehension, if it be not determined by a rule in relation to
something preceding, does not authorize succession in the object. Only, therefore, in reference to a rule,
according to which phenomena are determined in their sequence, that is, as they happen, by the preceding
state, can I make my subjective synthesis (of apprehension) objective, and it is only under this presupposition
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 86
Page No 91
that even the experience of an event is possible.
No doubt it appears as if this were in thorough contradiction to all the notions which people have hitherto
entertained in regard to the procedure of the human understanding. According to these opinions, it is by
means of the perception and comparison of similar consequences following upon certain antecedent
phenomena that the understanding is led to the discovery of a rule, according to which certain events always
follow certain phenomena, and it is only by this process that we attain to the conception of cause. Upon such
a basis, it is clear that this conception must be merely empirical, and the rule which it furnishes us with
"Everything that happens must have a cause" would be just as contingent as experience itself. The
universality and necessity of the rule or law would be perfectly spurious attributes of it. Indeed, it could not
possess universal validity, inasmuch as it would not in this case be a priori, but founded on deduction. But the
same is the case with this law as with other pure a priori representations (e.g., space and time), which we can
draw in perfect clearness and completeness from experience, only because we had already placed them
therein, and by that means, and by that alone, had rendered experience possible. Indeed, the logical clearness
of this representation of a rule, determining the series of events, is possible only when we have made use
thereof in experience. Nevertheless, the recognition of this rule, as a condition of the synthetical unity of
phenomena in time, was the ground of experience itself and consequently preceded it a priori.
It is now our duty to show by an example that we never, even in experience, attribute to an object the notion
of succession or effect (of an event that is, the happening of something that did not exist before), and
distinguish it from the subjective succession of apprehension, unless when a rule lies at the foundation, which
compels us to observe this order of perception in preference to any other, and that, indeed, it is this necessity
which first renders possible the representation of a succession in the object.
We have representations within us, of which also we can be conscious. But, however widely extended,
however accurate and thoroughgoing this consciousness may be, these representations are still nothing more
than representations, that is, internal determinations of the mind in this or that relation of time. Now how
happens it that to these representations we should set an object, or that, in addition to their subjective reality,
as modifications, we should still further attribute to them a certain unknown objective reality? It is clear that
objective significancy cannot consist in a relation to another representation (of that which we desire to term
object), for in that case the question again arises: "How does this other representation go out of itself, and
obtain objective significancy over and above the subjective, which is proper to it, as a determination of a state
of mind?" If we try to discover what sort of new property the relation to an object gives to our subjective
representations, and what new importance they thereby receive, we shall find that this relation has no other
effect than that of rendering necessary the connection of our representations in a certain manner, and of
subjecting them to a rule; and that conversely, it is only because a certain order is necessary in the relations of
time of our representations, that objective significancy is ascribed to them.
In the synthesis of phenomena, the manifold of our representations is always successive. Now hereby is not
represented an object, for by means of this succession, which is common to all apprehension, no one thing is
distinguished from another. But so soon as I perceive or assume that in this succession there is a relation to a
state antecedent, from which the representation follows in accordance with a rule, so soon do I represent
something as an event, or as a thing that happens; in other words, I cognize an object to which I must assign a
certain determinate position in time, which cannot be altered, because of the preceding state in the object.
When, therefore, I perceive that something happens, there is contained in this representation, in the first
place, the fact, that something antecedes; because, it. is only in relation to this that the phenomenon obtains
its proper relation of time, in other words, exists after an antecedent time, in which it did not exist. But it can
receive its determined place in time only by the presupposition that something existed in the foregoing state,
upon which it follows inevitably and always, that is, in conformity with a rule. From all this it is evident that,
in the first place, I cannot reverse the order of succession, and make that which happens precede that upon
which it follows; and that, in the second place, if the antecedent state be posited, a certain determinate event
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 87
Page No 92
inevitably and necessarily follows. Hence it follows that there exists a certain order in our representations,
whereby the present gives a sure indication of some previously existing state, as a correlate, though still
undetermined, of the existing event which is given a correlate which itself relates to the event as its
consequence, conditions it, and connects it necessarily with itself in the series of time.
If then it be admitted as a necessary law of sensibility, and consequently a formal condition of all perception,
that the preceding necessarily determines the succeeding time (inasmuch as I cannot arrive at the succeeding
except through the preceding), it must likewise be an indispensable law of empirical representation of the
series of time that the phenomena of the past determine all phenomena in the succeeding time, and that the
latter, as events, cannot take place, except in so far as the former determine their existence in time, that is to
say, establish it according to a rule. For it is of course only in phenomena that we can empirically cognize this
continuity in the connection of times.
For all experience and for the possibility of experience, understanding is indispensable, and the first step
which it takes in this sphere is not to render the representation of objects clear, but to render the
representation of an object in general, possible. It does this by applying the order of time to phenomena, and
their existence. In other words, it assigns to each phenomenon, as a consequence, a place in relation to
preceding phenomena, determined a priori in time, without which it could not harmonize with time itself,
which determines a place a priori to all its parts. This determination of place cannot be derived from the
relation of phenomena to absolute time (for it is not an object of perception); but, on the contrary, phenomena
must reciprocally determine the places in time of one another, and render these necessary in the order of time.
In other words, whatever follows or happens, must follow in conformity with a universal rule upon that which
was contained in the foregoing state. Hence arises a series of phenomena, which, by means of the
understanding, produces and renders necessary exactly the same order and continuous connection in the
series of our possible perceptions, as is found a priori in the form of internal intuition (time), in which all our
perceptions must have place.
That something happens, then, is a perception which belongs to a possible experience, which becomes real
only because I look upon the phenomenon as determined in regard to its place in time, consequently as an
object, which can always be found by means of a rule in the connected series of my perceptions. But this rule
of the determination of a thing according to succession in time is as follows: "In what precedes may be found
the condition, under which an event always (that is, necessarily) follows." From all this it is obvious that the
principle of cause and effect is the principle of possible experience, that is, of objective cognition of
phenomena, in regard to their relations in the succession of time.
The proof of this fundamental proposition rests entirely on the following momenta of argument. To all
empirical cognition belongs the synthesis of the manifold by the imagination, a synthesis which is always
successive, that is, in which the representations therein always follow one another. But the order of
succession in imagination is not determined, and the series of successive representations may be taken
retrogressively as well as progressively. But if this synthesis is a synthesis of apprehension (of the manifold
of a given phenomenon),then the order is determined in the object, or to speak more accurately, there is
therein an order of successive synthesis which determines an object, and according to which something
necessarily precedes, and when this is posited, something else necessarily follows. If, then, my perception is
to contain the cognition of an event, that is, of something which really happens, it must be an empirical
judgement, wherein we think that the succession is determined; that is, it presupposes another phenomenon,
upon which this event follows necessarily, or in conformity with a rule. If, on the contrary, when I posited the
antecedent, the event did not necessarily follow, I should be obliged to consider it merely as a subjective play
of my imagination, and if in this I represented to myself anything as objective, I must look upon it as a mere
dream. Thus, the relation of phenomena (as possible perceptions), according to which that which happens is,
as to its existence, necessarily determined in time by something which antecedes, in conformity with a rule
in other words, the relation of cause and effect is the condition of the objective validity of our empirical
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 88
Page No 93
judgements in regard to the sequence of perceptions, consequently of their empirical truth, and therefore of
experience. The principle of the relation of causality in the succession of phenomena is therefore valid for all
objects of experience, because it is itself the ground of the possibility of experience.
Here, however, a difficulty arises, which must be resolved. The principle of the connection of causality
among phenomena is limited in our formula to the succession thereof, although in practice we find that the
principle applies also when the phenomena exist together in the same time, and that cause and effect may be
simultaneous. For example, there is heat in a room, which does not exist in the open air. I look about for the
cause, and find it to be the fire, Now the fire as the cause is simultaneous with its effect, the heat of the room.
In this case, then, there is no succession as regards time, between cause and effect, but they are simultaneous;
and still the law holds good. The greater part of operating causes in nature are simultaneous with their effects,
and the succession in time of the latter is produced only because the cause cannot achieve the total of its
effect in one moment. But at the moment when the effect first arises, it is always simultaneous with the
causality of its cause, because, if the cause had but a moment before ceased to be, the effect could not have
arisen. Here it must be specially remembered that we must consider the order of time and not the lapse
thereof. The relation remains, even though no time has elapsed. The time between the causality of the cause
and its immediate effect may entirely vanish, and the cause and effect be thus simultaneous, but the relation
of the one to the other remains always determinable according to time. If, for example, I consider a leaden
ball, which lies upon a cushion and makes a hollow in it, as a cause, then it is simultaneous with the effect.
But I distinguish the two through the relation of time of the dynamical connection of both. For if I lay the ball
upon the cushion, then the hollow follows upon the before smooth surface; but supposing the cushion has,
from some cause or another, a hollow, there does not thereupon follow a leaden ball.
Thus, the law of succession of time is in all instances the only empirical criterion of effect in relation to the
causality of the antecedent cause. The glass is the cause of the rising of the water above its horizontal surface,
although the two phenomena are contemporaneous. For, as soon as I draw some water with the glass from a
larger vessel, an effect follows thereupon, namely, the change of the horizontal state which the water had in
the large vessel into a concave, which it assumes in the glass.
This conception of causality leads us to the conception of action; that of action, to the conception of force;
and through it, to the conception of substance. As I do not wish this critical essay, the sole purpose of which
is to treat of the sources of our synthetical cognition a priori, to be crowded with analyses which merely
explain, but do not enlarge the sphere of our conceptions, I reserve the detailed explanation of the above
conceptions for a future system of pure reason. Such an analysis, indeed, executed with great particularity,
may already be found in wellknown works on this subject. But I cannot at present refrain from making a
few remarks on the empirical criterion of a substance, in so far as it seems to be more evident and more easily
recognized through the conception of action than through that of the permanence of a phenomenon.
Where action (consequently activity and force) exists, substance also must exist, and in it alone must be
sought the seat of that fruitful source of phenomena. Very well. But if we are called upon to explain what we
mean by substance, and wish to avoid the vice of reasoning in a circle, the answer is by no means so easy.
How shall we conclude immediately from the action to the permanence of that which acts, this being
nevertheless an essential and peculiar criterion of substance (phenomenon)? But after what has been said
above, the solution of this question becomes easy enough, although by the common mode of procedure
merely analysing our conceptions it would be quite impossible. The conception of action indicates the
relation of the subject of causality to the effect. Now because all effect consists in that which happens,
therefore in the changeable, the last subject thereof is the permanent, as the substratum of all that changes,
that is, substance. For according to the principle of causality, actions are always the first ground of all change
in phenomena and, consequently, cannot be a property of a subject which itself changes, because if this were
the case, other actions and another subject would be necessary to determine this change. From all this it
results that action alone, as an empirical criterion, is a sufficient proof of the presence of substantiality,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 89
Page No 94
without any necessity on my part of endeavouring to discover the permanence of substance by a comparison.
Besides, by this mode of induction we could not attain to the completeness which the magnitude and strict
universality of the conception requires. For that the primary subject of the causality of all arising and passing
away, all origin and extinction, cannot itself (in the sphere of phenomena) arise and pass away, is a sound and
safe conclusion, a conclusion which leads us to the conception of empirical necessity and permanence in
existence, and consequently to the conception of a substance as phenomenon.
When something happens, the mere fact of the occurrence, without regard to that which occurs, is an object
requiring investigation. The transition from the nonbeing of a state into the existence of it, supposing that
this state contains no quality which previously existed in the phenomenon, is a fact of itself demanding
inquiry. Such an event, as has been shown in No. A, does not concern substance (for substance does not thus
originate), but its condition or state. It is therefore only change, and not origin from nothing. If this origin be
regarded as the effect of a foreign cause, it is termed creation, which cannot be admitted as an event among
phenomena, because the very possibility of it would annihilate the unity of experience. If, however, I regard
all things not as phenomena, but as things in themselves and objects of understanding alone, they, although
substances, may be considered as dependent, in respect of their existence, on a foreign cause. But this would
require a very different meaning in the words, a meaning which could not apply to phenomena as objects of
possible experience.
How a thing can be changed, how it is possible that upon one state existing in one point of time, an opposite
state should follow in another point of time of this we have not the smallest conception a priori. There is
requisite for this the knowledge of real powers, which can only be given empirically; for example, knowledge
of moving forces, or, in other words, of certain successive phenomena (as movements) which indicate the
presence of such forces. But the form of every change, the condition under which alone it can take place as
the coming into existence of another state (be the content of the change, that is, the state which is changed,
what it may), and consequently the succession of the states themselves can very well be considered a priori,
in relation to the law of causality and the conditions of time.*
*It must be remarked that I do not speak of the change of certain relations, but of the change of the state.
Thus, when a body moves in a uniform manner, it does not change its state (of motion); but only when all
motion increases or decreases.
When a substance passes from one state, a, into another state, b, the point of time in which the latter exists is
different from, and subsequent to that in which the former existed. In like manner, the second state, as reality
(in the phenomenon), differs from the first, in which the reality of the second did not exist, as b from zero.
That is to say, if the state, b, differs from the state, a, only in respect to quantity, the change is a coming into
existence of b a, which in the former state did not exist, and in relation to which that state is = O.
Now the question arises how a thing passes from one state = a, into another state = b. Between two moments
there is always a certain time, and between two states existing in these moments there is always a difference
having a certain quantity (for all parts of phenomena are in their turn quantities). Consequently, every
transition from one state into another is always effected in a time contained between two moments, of which
the first determines the state which leaves, and the second determines the state into the thing passes. the thing
leaves, and the second determines the state into which the thing Both moments, then, are limitations of the
time of a change, consequently of the intermediate state between both, and as such they belong to the total of
the change. Now every change has a cause, which evidences its causality in the whole time during which the
charge takes place. The cause, therefore, does not produce the change all at once or in one moment, but in a
time, so that, as the time gradually increases from the commencing instant, a, to its completion at b, in like
manner also, the quantity of the reality (b a) is generated through the lesser degrees which are contained
between the first and last. All change is therefore possible only through a continuous action of the causality,
which, in so far as it is uniform, we call a momentum. The change does not consist of these momenta, but is
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 90
Page No 95
generated or produced by them as their effect.
Such is the law of the continuity of all change, the ground of which is that neither time itself nor any
phenomenon in time consists of parts which are the smallest possible, but that, notwithstanding, the state of a
thing passes in the process of a change through all these parts, as elements, to its second state. There is no
smallest degree of reality in a phenomenon, just as there is no smallest degree in the quantity of time; and so
the new state of reality grows up out of the former state, through all the infinite degrees thereof, the
differences of which one from another, taken all together, are less than the difference between o and a.
It is not our business to inquire here into the utility of this principle in the investigation of nature. But how
such a proposition, which appears so greatly to extend our knowledge of nature, is possible completely a
priori, is indeed a question which deserves investigation, although the first view seems to demonstrate the
truth and reality of the principle, and the question, how it is possible, may be considered superfluous. For
there are so many groundless pretensions to the enlargement of our knowledge by pure reason that we must
take it as a general rule to be mistrustful of all such, and without a thoroughgoing and radical deduction, to
believe nothing of the sort even on the clearest dogmatical evidence.
Every addition to our empirical knowledge, and every advance made in the exercise of our perception, is
nothing more than an extension of the determination of the internal sense, that is to say, a progression in time,
be objects themselves what they may, phenomena, or pure intuitions. This progression in time determines
everything, and is itself determined by nothing else. That is to say, the parts of the progression exist only in
time, and by means of the synthesis thereof, and are not given antecedently to it. For this reason, every
transition in perception to anything which follows upon another in time, is a determination of time by means
of the production of this perception. And as this determination of time is, always and in all its parts, a
quantity, the perception produced is to be considered as a quantity which proceeds through all its degrees no
one of which is the smallest possible from zero up to its determined degree. From this we perceive the
possibility of cognizing a priori a law of changes a law, however, which concerns their form merely. We
merely anticipate our own apprehension, the formal condition of which, inasmuch as it is itself to be found in
the mind antecedently to all given phenomena, must certainly be capable of being cognized a priori.
Thus, as time contains the sensuous condition a priori of the possibility of a continuous progression of that
which exists to that which follows it, the understanding, by virtue of the unity of apperception, contains the
condition a priori of the possibility of a continuous determination of the position in time of all phenomena,
and this by means of the series of causes and effects, the former of which necessitate the sequence of the
latter, and thereby render universally and for all time, and by consequence, objectively, valid the empirical
cognition of the relations of time.
C. THIRD ANALOGY.
Principle of Coexistence, According to the Law
of Reciprocity or Community.
All substances, in so far as they can be perceived in space
at the same time, exist in a state of complete reciprocity
of action.
PROOF.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 91
Page No 96
Things are coexistent, when in empirical intuition the perception of the one can follow upon the perception of
the other, and vice versa which cannot occur in the succession of phenomena, as we have shown in the
explanation of the second principle. Thus I can perceive the moon and then the earth, or conversely, first the
earth and then the moon; and for the reason that my perceptions of these objects can reciprocally follow each
other, I say, they exist contemporaneously. Now coexistence is the existence of the manifold in the same
time. But time itself is not an object of perception; and therefore we cannot conclude from the fact that things
are placed in the same time, the other fact, that the perception of these things can follow each other
reciprocally. The synthesis of the imagination in apprehension would only present to us each of these
perceptions as present in the subject when the other is not present, and contrariwise; but would not show that
the objects are coexistent, that is to say, that, if the one exists, the other also exists in the same time, and that
this is necessarily so, in order that the perceptions may be capable of following each other reciprocally. It
follows that a conception of the understanding or category of the reciprocal sequence of the determinations of
phenomena (existing, as they do, apart from each other, and yet contemporaneously), is requisite to justify us
in saying that the reciprocal succession of perceptions has its foundation in the object, and to enable us to
represent coexistence as objective. But that relation of substances in which the one contains determinations
the ground of which is in the other substance, is the relation of influence. And, when this influence is
reciprocal, it is the relation of community or reciprocity. Consequently the coexistence of substances in space
cannot be cognized in experience otherwise than under the precondition of their reciprocal action. This is
therefore the condition of the possibility of things themselves as objects of experience.
Things are coexistent, in so far as they exist in one and the same time. But how can we know that they exist
in one and the same time? Only by observing that the order in the synthesis of apprehension of the manifold
is arbitrary and a matter of indifference, that is to say, that it can proceed from A, through B, C, D, to E, or
contrariwise from E to A. For if they were successive in time (and in the order, let us suppose, which begins
with A), it is quite impossible for the apprehension in perception to begin with E and go backwards to A,
inasmuch as A belongs to past time and, therefore, cannot be an object of apprehension.
Let us assume that in a number of substances considered as phenomena each is completely isolated, that is,
that no one acts upon another. Then I say that the coexistence of these cannot be an object of possible
perception and that the existence of one cannot, by any mode of empirical synthesis, lead us to the existence
of another. For we imagine them in this case to be separated by a completely void space, and thus perception,
which proceeds from the one to the other in time, would indeed determine their existence by means of a
following perception, but would be quite unable to distinguish whether the one phenomenon follows
objectively upon the first, or is coexistent with it.
Besides the mere fact of existence, then, there must be something by means of which A determines the
position of B in time and, conversely, B the position of A; because only under this condition can substances
be empirically represented as existing contemporaneously. Now that alone determines the position of another
thing in time which is the cause of it or of its determinations. Consequently every substance (inasmuch as it
can have succession predicated of it only in respect of its determinations) must contain the causality of certain
determinations in another substance, and at the same time the effects of the causality of the other in itself.
That is to say, substances must stand (mediately or immediately) in dynamical community with each other, if
coexistence is to be cognized in any possible experience. But, in regard to objects of experience, that is
absolutely necessary without which the experience of these objects would itself be impossible. Consequently
it is absolutely necessary that all substances in the world of phenomena, in so far as they are coexistent, stand
in a relation of complete community of reciprocal action to each other.
The word community has in our language* two meanings, and contains the two notions conveyed in the Latin
communio and commercium. We employ it in this place in the latter sense that of a dynamical community,
without which even the community of place (communio spatii) could not be empirically cognized. In our
experiences it is easy to observe that it is only the continuous influences in all parts of space that can conduct
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 92
Page No 97
our senses from one object to another; that the light which plays between our eyes and the heavenly bodies
produces a mediating community between them and us, and thereby evidences their coexistence with us; that
we cannot empirically change our position (perceive this change), unless the existence of matter throughout
the whole of space rendered possible the perception of the positions we occupy; and that this perception can
prove the contemporaneous existence of these places only through their reciprocal influence, and thereby also
the coexistence of even the most remote objects although in this case the proof is only mediate. Without
community, every perception (of a phenomenon in space) is separated from every other and isolated, and the
chain of empirical representations, that is, of experience, must, with the appearance of a new object, begin
entirely de novo, without the least connection with preceding representations, and without standing towards
these even in the relation of time. My intention here is by no means to combat the notion of empty space; for
it may exist where our perceptions cannot exist, inasmuch as they cannot reach thereto, and where, therefore,
no empirical perception of coexistence takes place. But in this case it is not an object of possible experience.
*German.
The following remarks may be useful in the way of explanation. In the mind, all phenomena, as contents of a
possible experience, must exist in community (communio) of apperception or consciousness, and in so far as
it is requisite that objects be represented as coexistent and connected, in so far must they reciprocally
determine the position in time of each other and thereby constitute a whole. If this subjective community is to
rest upon an objective basis, or to be applied to substances as phenomena, the perception of one substance
must render possible the perception of another, and conversely. For otherwise succession, which is always
found in perceptions as apprehensions, would be predicated of external objects, and their representation of
their coexistence be thus impossible. But this is a reciprocal influence, that is to say, a real community
(commercium) of substances, without which therefore the empirical relation of coexistence would be a notion
beyond the reach of our minds. By virtue of this commercium, phenomena, in so far as they are apart from,
and nevertheless in connection with each other, constitute a compositum reale. Such composita are possible
in many different ways. The three dynamical relations then, from which all others spring, are those of
inherence, consequence, and composition.
These, then, are the three analogies of experience. They are nothing more than principles of the determination
of the existence of phenomena in time, according to the three modi of this determination; to wit, the relation
to time itself as a quantity (the quantity of existence, that is, duration), the relation in time as a series or
succession, finally, the relation in time as the complex of all existence (simultaneity). This unity of
determination in regard to time is thoroughly dynamical; that is to say, time is not considered as that in which
experience determines immediately to every existence its position; for this is impossible, inasmuch as
absolute time is not an object of perception, by means of which phenomena can be connected with each other.
On the contrary, the rule of the understanding, through which alone the existence of phenomena can receive
synthetical unity as regards relations of time, determines for every phenomenon its position in time, and
consequently a priori, and with validity for all and every time.
By nature, in the empirical sense of the word, we understand the totality of phenomena connected, in respect
of their existence, according to necessary rules, that is, laws. There are therefore certain laws (which are
moreover a priori) which make nature possible; and all empirical laws can exist only by means of experience,
and by virtue of those primitive laws through which experience itself becomes possible. The purpose of the
analogies is therefore to represent to us the unity of nature in the connection of all phenomena under certain
exponents, the only business of which is to express the relation of time (in so far as it contains all existence in
itself) to the unity of apperception, which can exist in synthesis only according to rules. The combined
expression of all is this: "All phenomena exist in one nature, and must so exist, inasmuch as without this a
priori unity, no unity of experience, and consequently no determination of objects in experience, is possible."
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 93
Page No 98
As regards the mode of proof which we have employed in treating of these transcendental laws of nature, and
the peculiar character of we must make one remark, which will at the same time be important as a guide in
every other attempt to demonstrate the truth of intellectual and likewise synthetical propositions a priori. Had
we endeavoured to prove these analogies dogmatically, that is, from conceptions; that is to say, had we
employed this method in attempting to show that everything which exists, exists only in that which is
permanent that every thing or event presupposes the existence of something in a preceding state, upon
which it follows in conformity with a rule lastly, that in the manifold, which is coexistent, the states coexist
in connection with each other according to a rule all our labour would have been utterly in vain. For more
conceptions of things, analyse them as we may, cannot enable us to conclude from the existence of one object
to the existence of another. What other course was left for us to pursue? This only, to demonstrate the
possibility of experience as a cognition in which at last all objects must be capable of being presented to us, if
the representation of them is to possess any objective reality. Now in this third, this mediating term, the
essential form of which consists in the synthetical unity of the apperception of all phenomena, we found a
priori conditions of the universal and necessary determination as to time of all existences in the world of
phenomena, without which the empirical determination thereof as to time would itself be impossible, and we
also discovered rules of synthetical unity a priori, by means of which we could anticipate experience. For
want of this method, and from the fancy that it was possible to discover a dogmatical proof of the synthetical
propositions which are requisite in the empirical employment of the understanding, has it happened that a
proof of the principle of sufficient reason has been so often attempted, and always in vain. The other two
analogies nobody has ever thought of, although they have always been silently employed by the mind,*
because the guiding thread furnished by the categories was wanting, the guide which alone can enable us to
discover every hiatus, both in the system of conceptions and of principles.
*The unity of the universe, in which all phenomena to be connected, is evidently a mere consequence of the
admitted principle of the community of all substances which are coexistent. For were substances isolated,
they could not as parts constitute a whole, and were their connection (reciprocal action of the manifold) not
necessary from the very fact of coexistence, we could not conclude from the fact of the latter as a merely
ideal relation to the former as a real one. We have, however, shown in its place that community is the proper
ground of the possibility of an empirical cognition of coexistence, and that we may therefore properly reason
from the latter to the former as its condition.
4. THE POSTULATES OF EMPIRICAL THOUGHT.
1. That which agrees with the formal conditions (intuition and conception) of experience, is possible.
2. That which coheres with the material conditions of experience (sensation), is real.
3. That whose coherence with the real is determined according to universal conditions of experience is
(exists) necessary.
Explanation.
The categories of modality possess this peculiarity, that they do not in the least determine the object, or
enlarge the conception to which they are annexed as predicates, but only express its relation to the faculty of
cognition. Though my conception of a thing is in itself complete, I am still entitled to ask whether the object
of it is merely possible, or whether it is also real, or, if the latter, whether it is also necessary. But hereby the
object itself is not more definitely determined in thought, but the question is only in what relation it,
including all its determinations, stands to the understanding and its employment in experience, to the
empirical faculty of judgement, and to the reason of its application to experience.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 94
Page No 99
For this very reason, too, the categories of modality are nothing more than explanations of the conceptions of
possibility, reality, and necessity, as employed in experience, and at the same time, restrictions of all the
categories to empirical use alone, not authorizing the transcendental employment of them. For if they are to
have something more than a merely logical significance, and to be something more than a mere analytical
expression of the form of thought, and to have a relation to things and their possibility, reality, or necessity,
they must concern possible experience and its synthetical unity, in which alone objects of cognition can be
given.
The postulate of the possibility of things requires also, that the conception of the things agree with the formal
conditions of our experience in general. But this, that is to say, the objective form of experience, contains all
the kinds of synthesis which are requisite for the cognition of objects. A conception which contains a
synthesis must be regarded as empty and, without reference to an object, if its synthesis does not belong to
experience either as borrowed from it, and in this case it is called an empirical conception, or such as is the
ground and a priori condition of experience (its form), and in this case it is a pure conception, a conception
which nevertheless belongs to experience, inasmuch as its object can be found in this alone. For where shall
we find the criterion or character of the possibility of an object which is cogitated by means of an a priori
synthetical conception, if not in the synthesis which constitutes the form of empirical cognition of objects?
That in such a conception no contradiction exists is indeed a necessary logical condition, but very far from
being sufficient to establish the objective reality of the conception, that is, the possibility of such an object as
is thought in the conception. Thus, in the conception of a figure which is contained within two straight lines,
there is no contradiction, for the conceptions of two straight lines and of their junction contain no negation of
a figure. The impossibility in such a case does not rest upon the conception in itself, but upon the
construction of it in space, that is to say, upon the conditions of space and its determinations. But these have
themselves objective reality, that is, they apply to possible things, because they contain a priori the form of
experience in general.
And now we shall proceed to point out the extensive utility and influence of this postulate of possibility.
When I represent to myself a thing that is permanent, so that everything in it which changes belongs merely
to its state or condition, from such a conception alone I never can cognize that such a thing is possible. Or, if I
represent to myself something which is so constituted that, when it is posited, something else follows always
and infallibly, my thought contains no selfcontradiction; but whether such a property as causality is to be
found in any possible thing, my thought alone affords no means of judging. Finally, I can represent to myself
different things (substances) which are so constituted that the state or condition of one causes a change in the
state of the other, and reciprocally; but whether such a relation is a property of things cannot be perceived
from these conceptions, which contain a merely arbitrary synthesis. Only from the fact, therefore, that these
conceptions express a priori the relations of perceptions in every experience, do we know that they possess
objective reality, that is, transcendental truth; and that independent of experience, though not independent of
all relation to form of an experience in general and its synthetical unity, in which alone objects can be
empirically cognized.
But when we fashion to ourselves new conceptions of substances, forces, action, and reaction, from the
material presented to us by perception, without following the example of experience in their connection, we
create mere chimeras, of the possibility of which we cannot discover any criterion, because we have not taken
experience for our instructress, though we have borrowed the conceptions from her. Such fictitious
conceptions derive their character of possibility not, like the categories, a priori, as conceptions on which all
experience depends, but only, a posteriori, as conceptions given by means of experience itself, and their
possibility must either be cognized a posteriori and empirically, or it cannot be cognized at all. A substance
which is permanently present in space, yet without filling it (like that tertium quid between matter and the
thinking subject which some have tried to introduce into metaphysics), or a peculiar fundamental power of
the mind of intuiting the future by anticipation (instead of merely inferring from past and present events), or,
finally, a power of the mind to place itself in community of thought with other men, however distant they
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 95
Page No 100
may be these are conceptions the possibility of which has no ground to rest upon. For they are not based
upon experience and its known laws; and, without experience, they are a merely arbitrary conjunction of
thoughts, which, though containing no internal contradiction, has no claim to objective reality, neither,
consequently, to the possibility of such an object as is thought in these conceptions. As far as concerns
reality, it is selfevident that we cannot cogitate such a possibility in concreto without the aid of experience;
because reality is concerned only with sensation, as the matter of experience, and not with the form of
thought, with which we can no doubt indulge in shaping fancies.
But I pass by everything which derives its possibility from reality in experience, and I purpose treating here
merely of the possibility of things by means of a priori conceptions. I maintain, then, that the possibility of
things is not derived from such conceptions per se, but only when considered as formal and objective
conditions of an experience in general.
It seems, indeed, as if the possibility of a triangle could be cognized from the conception of it alone (which is
certainly independent of experience); for we can certainly give to the conception a corresponding object
completely a priori, that is to say, we can construct it. But as a triangle is only the form of an object, it must
remain a mere product of the imagination, and the possibility of the existence of an object corresponding to it
must remain doubtful, unless we can discover some other ground, unless we know that the figure can be
cogitated under the conditions upon which all objects of experience rest. Now, the facts that space is a formal
condition a priori of external experience, that the formative synthesis, by which we construct a triangle in
imagination, is the very same as that we employ in the apprehension of a phenomenon for the purpose of
making an empirical conception of it, are what alone connect the notion of the possibility of such a thing,
with the conception of it. In the same manner, the possibility of continuous quantities, indeed of quantities in
general, for the conceptions of them are without exception synthetical, is never evident from the conceptions
in themselves, but only when they are considered as the formal conditions of the determination of objects in
experience. And where, indeed, should we look for objects to correspond to our conceptions, if not in
experience, by which alone objects are presented to us? It is, however, true that without antecedent
experience we can cognize and characterize the possibility of things, relatively to the formal conditions,
under which something is determined in experience as an object, consequently, completely a priori. But still
this is possible only in relation to experience and within its limits.
The postulate concerning the cognition of the reality of things requires perception, consequently conscious
sensation, not indeed immediately, that is, of the object itself, whose existence is to be cognized, but still that
the object have some connection with a real perception, in accordance with the analogies of experience,
which exhibit all kinds of real connection in experience.
From the mere conception of a thing it is impossible to conclude its existence. For, let the conception be ever
so complete, and containing a statement of all the determinations of the thing, the existence of it has nothing
to do with all this, but only with thew question whether such a thing is given, so that the perception of it can
in every case precede the conception. For the fact that the conception of it precedes the perception, merely
indicates the possibility of its existence; it is perception which presents matter to the conception, that is the
sole criterion of reality. Prior to the perception of the thing, however, and therefore comparatively a priori, we
are able to cognize its existence, provided it stands in connection with some perceptions according to the
principles of the empirical conjunction of these, that is, in conformity with the analogies of perception. For,
in this case, the existence of the supposed thing is connected with our perception in a possible experience,
and we are able, with the guidance of these analogies, to reason in the series of possible perceptions from a
thing which we do really perceive to the thing we do not perceive. Thus, we cognize the existence of a
magnetic matter penetrating all bodies from the perception of the attraction of the steelfilings by the magnet,
although the constitution of our organs renders an immediate perception of this matter impossible for us. For,
according to the laws of sensibility and the connected context of our perceptions, we should in an experience
come also on an immediate empirical intuition of this matter, if our senses were more acute but this
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 96
Page No 101
obtuseness has no influence upon and cannot alter the form of possible experience in general. Our knowledge
of the existence of things reaches as far as our perceptions, and what may be inferred from them according to
empirical laws, extend. If we do not set out from experience, or do not proceed according to the laws of the
empirical connection of phenomena, our pretensions to discover the existence of a thing which we do not
immediately perceive are vain. Idealism, however, brings forward powerful objections to these rules for
proving existence mediately. This is, therefore, the proper place for its refutation.
REFUTATION OF IDEALISM.
Idealism I mean material idealism is the theory which declares the existence of objects in space without us
to be either () doubtful and indemonstrable, or (2) false and impossible. The first is the problematical idealism
of Descartes, who admits the undoubted certainty of only one empirical assertion (assertio), to wit, "I am."
The second is the dogmatical idealism of Berkeley, who maintains that space, together with all the objects of
which it is the inseparable condition, is a thing which is in itself impossible, and that consequently the objects
in space are mere products of the imagination. The dogmatical theory of idealism is unavoidable, if we regard
space as a property of things in themselves; for in that case it is, with all to which it serves as condition, a
nonentity. But the foundation for this kind of idealism we have already destroyed in the transcendental
aesthetic. Problematical idealism, which makes no such assertion, but only alleges our incapacity to prove the
existence of anything besides ourselves by means of immediate experience, is a theory rational and
evidencing a thorough and philosophical mode of thinking, for it observes the rule not to form a decisive
judgement before sufficient proof be shown. The desired proof must therefore demonstrate that we have
experience of external things, and not mere fancies. For this purpose, we must prove, that our internal and, to
Descartes, indubitable experience is itself possible only under the previous assumption of external
experience.
THEOREM.
The simple but empirically determined consciousness of
my own existence proves the existence of external
objects in space.
PROOF
I am conscious of my own existence as determined in time. All determination in regard to time presupposes
the existence of something permanent in perception. But this permanent something cannot be something in
me, for the very reason that my existence in time is itself determined by this permanent something. It follows
that the perception of this permanent existence is possible only through a thing without me and not through
the mere representation of a thing without me. Consequently, the determination of my existence in time is
possible only through the existence of real things external to me. Now, consciousness in time is necessarily
connected with the consciousness of the possibility of this determination in time. Hence it follows that
consciousness in time is necessarily connected also with the existence of things without me, inasmuch as the
existence of these things is the condition of determination in time. That is to say, the consciousness of my
own existence is at the same time an immediate consciousness of the existence of other things without me.
Remark I. The reader will observe, that in the foregoing proof the game which idealism plays is retorted upon
itself, and with more justice. It assumed that the only immediate experience is internal and that from this we
can only infer the existence of external things. But, as always happens, when we reason from given effects to
determined causes, idealism bas reasoned with too much haste and uncertainty, for it is quite possible that the
cause of our representations may lie in ourselves, and that we ascribe it falsely to external things. But our
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 97
Page No 102
proof shows that external experience is properly immediate,* that only by virtue of it not, indeed, the
consciousness of our own existence, but certainly the determination of our existence in time, that is, internal
experience is possible. It is true, that the representation "I am," which is the expression of the consciousness
which can accompany all my thoughts, is that which immediately includes the existence of a subject. But in
this representation we cannot find any knowledge of the subject, and therefore also no empirical knowledge,
that is, experience. For experience contains, in addition to the thought of something existing, intuition, and in
this case it must be internal intuition, that is, time, in relation to which the subject must be determined. But
the existence of external things is absolutely requisite for this purpose, so that it follows that internal
experience is itself possible only mediately and through external experience.
*The immediate consciousness of the existence of external things is, in the preceding theorem, not
presupposed, but proved, by the possibility of this consciousness understood by us or not. The question as to
the possibility of it would stand thus: "Have we an internal sense, but no external sense, and is our belief in
external perception a mere delusion?" But it is evident that, in order merely to fancy to ourselves anything as
external, that is, to present it to the sense in intuition we must already possess an external sense, and must
thereby distinguish immediately the mere receptivity of an external intuition from the spontaneity which
characterizes every act of imagination. For merely to imagine also an external sense, would annihilate the
faculty of intuition itself which is to be determined by the imagination.
Remark II. Now with this view all empirical use of our faculty of cognition in the determination of time is in
perfect accordance. Its truth is supported by the fact that it is possible to perceive a determination of time
only by means of a change in external relations (motion) to the permanent in space (for example, we become
aware of the sun's motion by observing the changes of his relation to the objects of this earth). But this is not
all. We find that we possess nothing permanent that can correspond and be submitted to the conception of a
substance as intuition, except matter. This idea of permanence is not itself derived from external experience,
but is an a priori necessary condition of all determination of time, consequently also of the internal sense in
reference to our own existence, and that through the existence of external things. In the representation "I," the
consciousness of myself is not an intuition, but a merely intellectual representation produced by the
spontaneous activity of a thinking subject. It follows, that this "I" has not any predicate of intuition, which, in
its character of permanence, could serve as correlate to the determination of time in the internal sense in the
same way as impenetrability is the correlate of matter as an empirical intuition.
Remark III. From the fact that the existence of external things is a necessary condition of the possibility of a
determined consciousness of ourselves, it does not follow that every intuitive representation of external things
involves the existence of these things, for their representations may very well be the mere products of the
imagination (in dreams as well as in madness); though, indeed, these are themselves created by the
reproduction of previous external perceptions, which, as has been shown, are possible only through the reality
of external objects. The sole aim of our remarks has, however, been to prove that internal experience in
general is possible only through external experience in general. Whether this or that supposed experience be
purely imaginary must be discovered from its particular determinations and by comparing these with the
criteria of all real experience.
Finally, as regards the third postulate, it applies to material necessity in existence, and not to merely formal
and logical necessity in the connection of conceptions. Now as we cannot cognize completely a priori the
existence of any object of sense, though we can do so comparatively a priori, that is, relatively to some other
previously given existence a cognition, however, which can only be of such an existence as must be
contained in the complex of experience, of which the previously given perception is a part the necessity of
existence can never be cognized from conceptions, but always, on the contrary, from its connection with that
which is an object of perception. But the only existence cognized, under the condition of other given
phenomena, as necessary, is the existence of effects from given causes in conformity with the laws of
causality. It is consequently not the necessity of the existence of things (as substances), but the necessity of
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 98
Page No 103
the state of things that we cognize, and that not immediately, but by means of the existence of other states
given in perception, according to empirical laws of causality. Hence it follows that the criterion of necessity
is to be found only in the law of possible experience that everything which happens is determined a priori in
the phenomenon by its cause. Thus we cognize only the necessity of effects in nature, the causes of which are
given us. Moreover, the criterion of necessity in existence possesses no application beyond the field of
possible experience, and even in this it is not valid of the existence of things as substances, because these can
never be considered as empirical effects, or as something that happens and has a beginning. Necessity,
therefore, regards only the relations of phenomena according to the dynamical law of causality, and the
possibility grounded thereon, of reasoning from some given existence (of a cause) a priori to another
existence (of an effect). "Everything that happens is hypothetically necessary," is a principle which subjects
the changes that take place in the world to a law, that is, to a rule of necessary existence, without which
nature herself could not possibly exist. Hence the proposition, "Nothing happens by blind chance (in mundo
non datur casus)," is an a priori law of nature. The case is the same with the proposition, "Necessity in nature
is not blind," that is, it is conditioned, consequently intelligible necessity (non datur fatum). Both laws subject
the play of change to "a nature of things (as phenomena)," or, which is the same thing, to the unity of the
understanding, and through the understanding alone can changes belong to an experience, as the synthetical
unity of phenomena. Both belong to the class of dynamical principles. The former is properly a consequence
of the principle of causality one of the analogies of experience. The latter belongs to the principles of
modality, which to the determination of causality adds the conception of necessity, which is itself, however,
subject to a rule of the understanding. The principle of continuity forbids any leap in the series of phenomena
regarded as changes (in mundo non datur saltus); and likewise, in the complex of all empirical intuitions in
space, any break or hiatus between two phenomena (non datur hiatus) for we can so express the principle,
that experience can admit nothing which proves the existence of a vacuum, or which even admits it as a part
of an empirical synthesis. For, as regards a vacuum or void, which we may cogitate as out and beyond the
field of possible experience (the world), such a question cannot come before the tribunal of mere
understanding, which decides only upon questions that concern the employment of given phenomena for the
construction of empirical cognition. It is rather a problem for ideal reason, which passes beyond the sphere of
a possible experience and aims at forming a judgement of that which surrounds and circumscribes it, and the
proper place for the consideration of it is the transcendental dialectic. These four propositions, "In mundo non
datur hiatus, non datur saltus, non datur casus, non datur fatum," as well as all principles of transcendental
origin, we could very easily exhibit in their proper order, that is, in conformity with the order of the
categories, and assign to each its proper place. But the already practised reader will do this for himself, or
discover the clue to such an arrangement. But the combined result of all is simply this, to admit into the
empirical synthesis nothing which might cause a break in or be foreign to the understanding and the
continuous connection of all phenomena, that is, the unity of the conceptions of the understanding. For in the
understanding alone is the unity of experience, in which all perceptions must have their assigned place,
possible.
Whether the field of possibility be greater than that of reality, and whether the field of the latter be itself
greater than that of necessity, are interesting enough questions, and quite capable of synthetic solution,
questions, however, which come under the jurisdiction of reason alone. For they are tantamount to asking
whether all things as phenomena do without exception belong to the complex and connected whole of a
single experience, of which every given perception is a part which therefore cannot be conjoined with any
other phenomena or, whether my perceptions can belong to more than one possible experience? The
understanding gives to experience, according to the subjective and formal conditions, of sensibility as well as
of apperception, the rules which alone make this experience possible. Other forms of intuition besides those
of space and time, other forms of understanding besides the discursive forms of thought, or of cognition by
means of conceptions, we can neither imagine nor make intelligible to ourselves; and even if we could, they
would still not belong to experience, which is the only mode of cognition by which objects are presented to
us. Whether other perceptions besides those which belong to the total of our possible experience, and
consequently whether some other sphere of matter exists, the understanding has no power to decide, its
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding. 99
Page No 104
proper occupation being with the synthesis of that which is given. Moreover, the poverty of the usual
arguments which go to prove the existence of a vast sphere of possibility, of which all that is real (every
object of experience) is but a small part, is very remarkable. "All real is possible"; from this follows naturally,
according to the logical laws of conversion, the particular proposition: "Some possible is real." Now this
seems to be equivalent to: "Much is possible that is not real." No doubt it does seem as if we ought to
consider the sum of the possible to be greater than that of the real, from the fact that something must be added
to the former to constitute the latter. But this notion of adding to the possible is absurd. For that which is not
in the sum of the possible, and consequently requires to be added to it, is manifestly impossible. In addition to
accordance with the formal conditions of experience, the understanding requires a connection with some
perception; but that which is connected with this perception is real, even although it is not immediately
perceived. But that another series of phenomena, in complete coherence with that which is given in
perception, consequently more than one allembracing experience is possible, is an inference which cannot
be concluded from the data given us by experience, and still less without any data at all. That which is
possible only under conditions which are themselves merely possible, is not possible in any respect. And yet
we can find no more certain ground on which to base the discussion of the question whether the sphere of
possibility is wider than that of experience.
I have merely mentioned these questions, that in treating of the conception of the understanding, there might
be no omission of anything that, in the common opinion, belongs to them. In reality, however, the notion of
absolute possibility (possibility which is valid in every respect) is not a mere conception of the
understanding, which can be employed empirically, but belongs to reason alone, which passes the bounds of
all empirical use of the understanding. We have, therefore, contented ourselves with a merely critical remark,
leaving the subject to be explained in the sequel.
Before concluding this fourth section, and at the same time the system of all principles of the pure
understanding, it seems proper to mention the reasons which induced me to term the principles of modality
postulates. This expression I do not here use in the sense which some more recent philosophers, contrary to
its meaning with mathematicians, to whom the word properly belongs, attach to it that of a proposition,
namely, immediately certain, requiring neither deduction nor proof. For if, in the case of synthetical
propositions, however evident they may be, we accord to them without deduction, and merely on the strength
of their own pretensions, unqualified belief, all critique of the understanding is entirely lost; and, as there is
no want of bold pretensions, which the common belief (though for the philosopher this is no credential) does
not reject, the understanding lies exposed to every delusion and conceit, without the power of refusing its
assent to those assertions, which, though illegitimate, demand acceptance as veritable axioms. When,
therefore, to the conception of a thing an a priori determination is synthetically added, such a proposition
must obtain, if not a proof, at least a deduction of the legitimacy of its assertion.
The principles of modality are, however, not objectively synthetical, for the predicates of possibility, reality,
and necessity do not in the least augment the conception of that of which they are affirmed, inasmuch as they
contribute nothing to the representation of the object. But as they are, nevertheless, always synthetical, they
are so merely subjectively. That is to say, they have a reflective power, and apply to the conception of a
thing, of which, in other respects, they affirm nothing, the faculty of cognition in which the conception
originates and has its seat. So that if the conception merely agree with the formal conditions of experience, its
object is called possible; if it is in connection with perception, and determined thereby, the object is real; if it
is determined according to conceptions by means of the connection of perceptions, the object is called
necessary. The principles of modality therefore predicate of a conception nothing more than the procedure of
the faculty of cognition which generated it. Now a postulate in mathematics is a practical proposition which
contains nothing but the synthesis by which we present an object to ourselves, and produce the conception of
it, for example "With a given line, to describe a circle upon a plane, from a given point"; and such a
proposition does not admit of proof, because the procedure, which it requires, is exactly that by which alone it
is possible to generate the conception of such a figure. With the same right, accordingly, can we postulate the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding.100
Page No 105
principles of modality, because they do not augment* the conception of a thing but merely indicate the
manner in which it is connected with the faculty of cognition.
*When I think the reality of a thing, I do really think more than the possibility, but not in the thing; for that
can never contain more in reality than was contained in its complete possibility. But while the notion of
possibility is merely the notion of a position of thing in relation to the understanding (its empirical use),
reality is the conjunction of the thing with perception.
GENERAL REMARK ON THE SYSTEM OF PRINCIPLES.
It is very remarkable that we cannot perceive the possibility of a thing from the category alone, but must
always have an intuition, by which to make evident the objective reality of the pure conception of the
understanding. Take, for example, the categories of relation. How (1) a thing can exist only as a subject, and
not as a mere determination of other things, that is, can be substance; or how (2), because something exists,
some other thing must exist, consequently how a thing can be a cause; or how (3), when several things exist,
from the fact that one of these things exists, some consequence to the others follows, and reciprocally, and in
this way a community of substances can be possible are questions whose solution cannot be obtained from
mere conceptions. The very same is the case with the other categories; for example, how a thing can be of the
same sort with many others, that is, can be a quantity, and so on. So long as we have not intuition we cannot
know whether we do really think an object by the categories, and where an object can anywhere be found to
cohere with them, and thus the truth is established, that the categories are not in themselves cognitions, but
mere forms of thought for the construction of cognitions from given intuitions. For the same reason is it true
that from categories alone no synthetical proposition can be made. For example: "In every existence there is
substance," that is, something that can exist only as a subject and not as mere predicate; or, "Everything is a
quantity" to construct propositions such as these, we require something to enable us to go out beyond the
given conception and connect another with it. For the same reason the attempt to prove a synthetical
proposition by means of mere conceptions, for example: "Everything that exists contingently has a cause,"
has never succeeded. We could never get further than proving that, without this relation to conceptions, we
could not conceive the existence of the contingent, that is, could not a priori through the understanding
cognize the existence of such a thing; but it does not hence follow that this is also the condition of the
possibility of the thing itself that is said to be contingent. If, accordingly; we look back to our proof of the
principle of causality, we shall find that we were able to prove it as valid only of objects of possible
experience, and, indeed, only as itself the principle of the possibility of experience, Consequently of the
cognition of an object given in empirical intuition, and not from mere conceptions. That, however, the
proposition: "Everything that is contingent must have a cause," is evident to every one merely from
conceptions, is not to be denied. But in this case the conception of the contingent is cogitated as involving not
the category of modality (as that the nonexistence of which can be conceive but that of relation (as that
which can exist only as the consequence of something else), and so it is really an identical proposition: "That
which can exist only as a consequence, has a cause." In fact, when we have to give examples of contingent
existence, we always refer to changes, and not merely to the possibility of conceiving the opposite.* But
change is an event, which, as such, is possible only through a cause, and considered per se its nonexistence
is therefore possible, and we become cognizant of its contingency from the fact that it can exist only as the
effect of a cause. Hence, if a thing is assumed to be contingent, it is an analytical proposition to say, it has a
cause.
*We can easily conceive the nonexistence of matter; but the ancients did not thence infer its contingency.
But even the alternation of the existence and nonexistence of a given state in a thing, in which all change
consists, by no means proves the contingency of that state the ground of proof being the reality of its
opposite. For example, a body is in a state of rest after motion, but we cannot infer the contingency of the
motion from the fact that the former is the opposite of the latter. For this opposite is merely a logical and not
a real opposite to the other. If we wish to demonstrate the contingency of the motion, what we ought to prove
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding.101
Page No 106
is that, instead of the motion which took place in the preceding point of time, it was possible for the body to
have been then in rest, not, that it is afterwards in rest; for in this case, both opposites are perfectly consistent
with each other.
But it is still more remarkable that, to understand the possibility of things according to the categories and thus
to demonstrate the objective reality of the latter, we require not merely intuitions, but external intuitions. If,
for example, we take the pure conceptions of relation, we find that (1) for the purpose of presenting to the
conception of substance something permanent in intuition corresponding thereto and thus of demonstrating
the objective reality of this conception, we require an intuition (of matter) in space, because space alone is
permanent and determines things as such, while time, and with it all that is in the internal sense, is in a state
of continual flow; (2) in order to represent change as the intuition corresponding to the conception of
causality, we require the representation of motion as change in space; in fact, it is through it alone that
changes, the possibility of which no pure understanding can perceive, are capable of being intuited. Change is
the connection of determinations contradictorily opposed to each other in the existence of one and the same
thing. Now, how it is possible that out of a given state one quite opposite to it in the same thing should
follow, reason without an example can not only not conceive, but cannot even make intelligible without
intuition; and this intuition is the motion of a point in space; the existence of which in different spaces (as a
consequence of opposite determinations) alone makes the intuition of change possible. For, in order to make
even internal change cognitable, we require to represent time, as the form of the internal sense, figuratively
by a line, and the internal change by the drawing of that line (motion), and consequently are obliged to
employ external intuition to be able to represent the successive existence of ourselves in different states. The
proper ground of this fact is that all change to be perceived as change presupposes something permanent in
intuition, while in the internal sense no permanent intuition is to be found. Lastly, the objective possibility of
the category of community cannot be conceived by mere reason, and consequently its objective reality cannot
be demonstrated without an intuition, and that external in space. For how can we conceive the possibility of
community, that is, when several substances exist, that some effect on the existence of the one follows from
the existence of the other, and reciprocally, and therefore that, because something exists in the latter,
something else must exist in the former, which could not be understood from its own existence alone? For
this is the very essence of community which is inconceivable as a property of things which are perfectly
isolated. Hence, Leibnitz, in attributing to the substances of the world as cogitated by the understanding
alone a community, required the mediating aid of a divinity; for, from their existence, such a property
seemed to him with justice inconceivable. But we can very easily conceive the possibility of community (of
substances as phenomena) if we represent them to ourselves as in space, consequently in external intuition.
For external intuition contains in itself a priori formal external relations, as the conditions of the possibility of
the real relations of action and reaction, and therefore of the possibility of community. With the same ease
can it be demonstrated, that the possibility of things as quantities, and consequently the objective reality of
the category of quantity, can be grounded only in external intuition, and that by its means alone is the notion
of quantity appropriated by the internal sense. But I must avoid prolixity, and leave the task of illustrating this
by examples to the reader's own reflection.
The above remarks are of the greatest importance, not only for the confirmation of our previous confutation
of idealism, but still more when the subject of selfcognition by mere internal consciousness and the
determination of our own nature without the aid of external empirical intuitions is under discussion, for the
indication of the grounds of the possibility of such a cognition.
The result of the whole of this part of the analytic of principles is, therefore: "All principles of the pure
understanding are nothing more than a priori principles of the possibility of experience, and to experience
alone do all a priori synthetical propositions apply and relate"; indeed, their possibility itself rests entirely on
this relation.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding.102
Page No 107
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into
Phenomena and Noumena.
We have now not only traversed the region of the pure understanding and carefully surveyed every part of it,
but we have also measured it, and assigned to everything therein its proper place. But this land is an island,
and enclosed by nature herself within unchangeable limits. It is the land of truth (an attractive word),
surrounded by a wide and stormy ocean, the region of illusion, where many a fogbank, many an iceberg,
seems to the mariner, on his voyage of discovery, a new country, and, while constantly deluding him with
vain hopes, engages him in dangerous adventures, from which he never can desist, and which yet he never
can bring to a termination. But before venturing upon this sea, in order to explore it in its whole extent, and to
arrive at a certainty whether anything is to be discovered there, it will not be without advantage if we cast our
eyes upon the chart of the land that we are about to leave, and to ask ourselves, firstly, whether we cannot rest
perfectly contented with what it contains, or whether we must not of necessity be contented with it, if we can
find nowhere else a solid foundation to build upon; and, secondly, by what title we possess this land itself,
and how we hold it secure against all hostile claims? Although, in the course of our analytic, we have already
given sufficient answers to these questions, yet a summary recapitulation of these solutions may be useful in
strengthening our conviction, by uniting in one point the momenta of the arguments.
We have seen that everything which the understanding draws from itself, without borrowing from experience,
it nevertheless possesses only for the behoof and use of experience. The principles of the pure understanding,
whether constitutive a priori (as the mathematical principles), or merely regulative (as the dynamical),
contain nothing but the pure schema, as it were, of possible experience. For experience possesses its unity
from the synthetical unity which the understanding, originally and from itself, imparts to the synthesis of the
imagination in relation to apperception, and in a priori relation to and agreement with which phenomena, as
data for a possible cognition, must stand. But although these rules of the understanding are not only a priori
true, but the very source of all truth, that is, of the accordance of our cognition with objects, and on this
ground, that they contain the basis of the possibility of experience, as the ensemble of all cognition, it seems
to us not enough to propound what is true we desire also to be told what we want to know. If, then, we learn
nothing more by this critical examination than what we should have practised in the merely empirical use of
the understanding, without any such subtle inquiry, the presumption is that the advantage we reap from it is
not worth the labour bestowed upon it. It may certainly be answered that no rash curiosity is more prejudicial
to the enlargement of our knowledge than that which must know beforehand the utility of this or that piece of
information which we seek, before we have entered on the needful investigations, and before one could form
the least conception of its utility, even though it were placed before our eyes. But there is one advantage in
such transcendental inquiries which can be made comprehensible to the dullest and most reluctant learner
this, namely, that the understanding which is occupied merely with empirical exercise, and does not reflect on
the sources of its own cognition, may exercise its functions very well and very successfully, but is quite
unable to do one thing, and that of very great importance, to determine, namely, the bounds that limit its
employment, and to know what lies within or without its own sphere. This purpose can be obtained only by
such profound investigations as we have instituted. But if it cannot distinguish whether certain questions lie
within its horizon or not, it can never be sure either as to its claims or possessions, but must lay its account
with many humiliating corrections, when it transgresses, as it unavoidably will, the limits of its own territory,
and loses itself in fanciful opinions and blinding illusions.
That the understanding, therefore, cannot make of its a priori principles, or even of its conceptions, other than
an empirical use, is a proposition which leads to the most important results. A transcendental use is made of a
conception in a fundamental proposition or principle, when it is referred to things in general and considered
as things in themselves; an empirical use, when it is referred merely to phenomena, that is, to objects of a
possible experience. That the latter use of a conception is the only admissible one is evident from the reasons
following. For every conception are requisite, firstly, the logical form of a conception (of thought) general;
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 103
Page No 108
and, secondly, the possibility of presenting to this an object to which it may apply. Failing this latter, it has no
sense, and utterly void of content, although it may contain the logical function for constructing a conception
from certain data. Now, object cannot be given to a conception otherwise than by intuition, and, even if a
pure intuition antecedent to the object is a priori possible, this pure intuition can itself obtain objective
validity only from empirical intuition, of which it is itself but the form. All conceptions, therefore, and with
them all principles, however high the degree of their a priori possibility, relate to empirical intuitions, that is,
to data towards a possible experience. Without this they possess no objective validity, but are mere play of
imagination or of understanding with images or notions. Let us take, for example, the conceptions of
mathematics, and first in its pure intuitions. "Space has three dimensions" "Between two points there can be
only one straight line," etc. Although all these principles, and the representation of the object with which this
science occupies itself, are generated in the mind entirely a priori, they would nevertheless have no
significance if we were not always able to exhibit their significance in and by means of phenomena
(empirical objects). Hence it is requisite that an abstract conception be made sensuous, that is, that an object
corresponding to it in intuition be forthcoming, otherwise the conception remains, as we say, without sense,
that is, without meaning. Mathematics fulfils this requirement by the construction of the figure, which is a
phenomenon evident to the senses. The same science finds support and significance in number; this in its turn
finds it in the fingers, or in counters, or in lines and points. The conception itself is always produced a priori,
together with the synthetical principles or formulas from such conceptions; but the proper employment of
them, and their application to objects, can exist nowhere but in experience, the possibility of which, as
regards its form, they contain a priori.
That this is also the case with all of the categories and the principles based upon them is evident from the fact
that we cannot render intelligible the possibility of an object corresponding to them without having recourse
to the conditions of sensibility, consequently, to the form of phenomena, to which, as their only proper
objects, their use must therefore be confined, inasmuch as, if this condition is removed, all significance, that
is, all relation to an object, disappears, and no example can be found to make it comprehensible what sort of
things we ought to think under such conceptions.
The conception of quantity cannot be explained except by saying that it is the determination of a thing
whereby it can be cogitated how many times one is placed in it. But this "how many times" is based upon
successive repetition, consequently upon time and the synthesis of the homogeneous therein. Reality, in
contradistinction to negation, can be explained only by cogitating a time which is either filled therewith or is
void. If I leave out the notion of permanence (which is existence in all time), there remains in the conception
of substance nothing but the logical notion of subject, a notion of which I endeavour to realize by
representing to myself something that can exist only as a subject. But not only am I perfectly ignorant of any
conditions under which this logical prerogative can belong to a thing, I can make nothing out of the notion,
and draw no inference from it, because no object to which to apply the conception is determined, and we
consequently do not know whether it has any meaning at all. In like manner, if I leave out the notion of time,
in which something follows upon some other thing in conformity with a rule, I can find nothing in the pure
category, except that there is a something of such a sort that from it a conclusion may be drawn as to the
existence of some other thing. But in this case it would not only be impossible to distinguish between a cause
and an effect, but, as this power to draw conclusions requires conditions of which I am quite ignorant, the
conception is not determined as to the mode in which it ought to apply to an object. The socalled principle:
"Everything that is contingent has a cause," comes with a gravity and selfassumed authority that seems to
require no support from without. But, I ask, what is meant by contingent? The answer is that the
nonexistence of which is possible. But I should like very well to know by what means this possibility of
nonexistence is to be cognized, if we do not represent to ourselves a succession in the series of phenomena,
and in this succession an existence which follows a nonexistence, or conversely, consequently, change. For
to say, that the nonexistence of a thing is not selfcontradictory is a lame appeal to a logical condition,
which is no doubt a necessary condition of the existence of the conception, but is far from being sufficient for
the real objective possibility of nonexistence. I can annihilate in thought every existing substance without
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 104
Page No 109
selfcontradiction, but I cannot infer from this their objective contingency in existence, that is to say, the
possibility of their nonexistence in itself. As regards the category of community, it may easily be inferred
that, as the pure categories of substance and causality are incapable of a definition and explanation sufficient
to determine their object without the aid of intuition, the category of reciprocal causality in the relation of
substances to each other (commercium) is just as little susceptible thereof. Possibility, existence, and
necessity nobody has ever yet been able to explain without being guilty of manifest tautology, when the
definition has been drawn entirely from the pure understanding. For the substitution of the logical possibility
of the conception the condition of which is that it be not selfcontradictory, for the transcendental
possibility of things the condition of which is that there be an object corresponding to the conception, is a
trick which can only deceive the inexperienced.*
*In one word, to none of these conceptions belongs a corresponding object, and consequently their real
possibility cannot be demonstrated, if we take away sensuous intuition the only intuition which we possess
and there then remains nothing but the logical possibility, that is, the fact that the conception or thought is
possible which, however, is not the question; what we want to know being, whether it relates to an object
and thus possesses any meaning.
It follows incontestably, that the pure conceptions of the understanding are incapable of transcendental, and
must always be of empirical use alone, and that the principles of the pure understanding relate only to the
general conditions of a possible experience, to objects of the senses, and never to things in general, apart from
the mode in which we intuite them.
Transcendental analytic has accordingly this important result, to wit, that the understanding is competent'
effect nothing a priori, except the anticipation of the form of a possible experience in general, and that, as that
which is not phenomenon cannot be an object of experience, it can never overstep the limits of sensibility,
within which alone objects are presented to us. Its principles are merely principles of the exposition of
phenomena, and the proud name of an ontology, which professes to present synthetical cognitions a priori of
things in general in a systematic doctrine, must give place to the modest title of analytic of the pure
understanding.
Thought is the act of referring a given intuition to an object. If the mode of this intuition is unknown to us,
the object is merely transcendental, and the conception of the understanding is employed only
transcendentally, that is, to produce unity in the thought of a manifold in general. Now a pure category, in
which all conditions of sensuous intuition as the only intuition we possess are abstracted, does not
determine an object, but merely expresses the thought of an object in general, according to different modes.
Now, to employ a conception, the function of judgement is required, by which an object is subsumed under
the conception, consequently the at least formal condition, under which something can be given in intuition.
Failing this condition of judgement (schema), subsumption is impossible; for there is in such a case nothing
given, which may be subsumed under the conception. The merely transcendental use of the categories is
therefore, in fact, no use at all and has no determined, or even, as regards its form, determinable object.
Hence it follows that the pure category is incompetent to establish a synthetical a priori principle, and that the
principles of the pure understanding are only of empirical and never of transcendental use, and that beyond
the sphere of possible experience no synthetical a priori principles are possible.
It may be advisable, therefore, to express ourselves thus. The pure categories, apart from the formal
conditions of sensibility, have a merely transcendental meaning, but are nevertheless not of transcendental
use, because this is in itself impossible, inasmuch as all the conditions of any employment or use of them (in
judgements) are absent, to wit, the formal conditions of the subsumption of an object under these
conceptions. As, therefore, in the character of pure categories, they must be employed empirically, and
cannot be employed transcendentally, they are of no use at all, when separated from sensibility, that is, they
cannot be applied to an object. They are merely the pure form of the employment of the understanding in
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 105
Page No 110
respect of objects in general and of thought, without its being at the same time possible to think or to
determine any object by their means.
But there lurks at the foundation of this subject an illusion which it is very difficult to avoid. The categories
are not based, as regards their origin, upon sensibility, like the forms of intuition, space, and time; they seem,
therefore, to be capable of an application beyond the sphere of sensuous objects. But this is not the case. They
are nothing but mere forms of thought, which contain only the logical faculty of uniting a priori in
consciousness the manifold given in intuition. Apart, then, from the only intuition possible for us, they have
still less meaning than the pure sensuous forms, space and time, for through them an object is at least given,
while a mode of connection of the manifold, when the intuition which alone gives the manifold is wanting,
has no meaning at all. At the same time, when we designate certain objects as phenomena or sensuous
existences, thus distinguishing our mode of intuiting them from their own nature as things in themselves, it is
evident that by this very distinction we as it were place the latter, considered in this their own nature,
although we do not so intuite them, in opposition to the former, or, on the other hand, we do so place other
possible things, which are not objects of our senses, but are cogitated by the understanding alone, and call
them intelligible existences (noumena). Now the question arises whether the pure conceptions of our
understanding do possess significance in respect of these latter, and may possibly be a mode of cognizing
them.
But we are met at the very commencement with an ambiguity, which may easily occasion great
misapprehension. The understanding, when it terms an object in a certain relation phenomenon, at the same
time forms out of this relation a representation or notion of an object in itself, and hence believes that it can
form also conceptions of such objects. Now as the understanding possesses no other fundamental conceptions
besides the categories, it takes for granted that an object considered as a thing in itself must be capable of
being thought by means of these pure conceptions, and is thereby led to hold the perfectly undetermined
conception of an intelligible existence, a something out of the sphere of our sensibility, for a determinate
conception of an existence which we can cognize in some way or other by means of the understanding.
If, by the term noumenon, we understand a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensuous intuition, thus
making abstraction of our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the word. But if we
understand by it an object of a nonsensuous intuition, we in this case assume a peculiar mode of intuition,
an intellectual intuition, to wit, which does not, however, belong to us, of the very possibility of which we
have no notion and this is a noumenon in the positive sense.
The doctrine of sensibility is also the doctrine of noumena in the negative sense, that is, of things which the
understanding is obliged to cogitate apart from any relation to our mode of intuition, consequently not as
mere phenomena, but as things in themselves. But the understanding at the same time comprehends that it
cannot employ its categories for the consideration of things in themselves, because these possess significance
only in relation to the unity of intuitions in space and time, and that they are competent to determine this
unity by means of general a priori connecting conceptions only on account of the pure ideality of space and
time. Where this unity of time is not to be met with, as is the case with noumena, the whole use, indeed the
whole meaning of the categories is entirely lost, for even the possibility of things to correspond to the
categories is in this case incomprehensible. On this point, I need only refer the reader to what I have said at
the commencement of the General Remark appended to the foregoing chapter. Now, the possibility of a thing
can never be proved from the fact that the conception of it is not selfcontradictory, but only by means of an
intuition corresponding to the conception. If, therefore, we wish to apply the categories to objects which
cannot be regarded as phenomena, we must have an intuition different from the sensuous, and in this case the
objects would be a noumena in the positive sense of the word. Now, as such an intuition, that is, an
intellectual intuition, is no part of our faculty of cognition, it is absolutely impossible for the categories to
possess any application beyond the limits of experience. It may be true that there are intelligible existences to
which our faculty of sensuous intuition has no relation, and cannot be applied, but our conceptions of the
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 106
Page No 111
understanding, as mere forms of thought for our sensuous intuition, do not extend to these. What, therefore,
we call noumenon must be understood by us as such in a negative sense.
If I take away from an empirial intuition all thought (by means of the categories), there remains no cognition
of any object; for by means of mere intuition nothing is cogitated, and, from the existence of such or such an
affection of sensibility in me, it does not follow that this affection or representation has any relation to an
object without me. But if I take away all intuition, there still remains the form of thought, that is, the mode of
determining an object for the manifold of a possible intuition. Thus the categories do in some measure really
extend further than sensuous intuition, inasmuch as they think objects in general, without regard to the mode
(of sensibility) in which these objects are given. But they do not for this reason apply to and determine a
wider sphere of objects, because we cannot assume that such can be given, without presupposing the
possibility of another than the sensuous mode of intuition, a supposition we are not justified in making.
I call a conception problematical which contains in itself no contradiction, and which is connected with other
cognitions as a limitation of given conceptions, but whose objective reality cannot be cognized in any
manner. The conception of a noumenon, that is, of a thing which must be cogitated not as an object of sense,
but as a thing in itself (solely through the pure understanding), is not selfcontradictory, for we are not
entitled to maintain that sensibility is the only possible mode of intuition. Nay, further, this conception is
necessary to restrain sensuous intuition within the bounds of phenomena, and thus to limit the objective
validity of sensuous cognition; for things in themselves, which lie beyond its province, are called noumena
for the very purpose of indicating that this cognition does not extend its application to all that the
understanding thinks. But, after all, the possibility of such noumena is quite incomprehensible, and beyond
the sphere of phenomena, all is for us a mere void; that is to say, we possess an understanding whose
province does problematically extend beyond this sphere, but we do not possess an intuition, indeed, not even
the conception of a possible intuition, by means of which objects beyond the region of sensibility could be
given us, and in reference to which the understanding might be employed assertorically. The conception of a
noumenon is therefore merely a limitative conception and therefore only of negative use. But it is not an
arbitrary or fictitious notion, but is connected with the limitation of sensibility, without, however, being
capable of presenting us with any positive datum beyond this sphere.
The division of objects into phenomena and noumena, and of the world into a mundus sensibilis and
intelligibilis is therefore quite inadmissible in a positive sense, although conceptions do certainly admit of
such a division; for the class of noumena have no determinate object corresponding to them, and cannot
therefore possess objective validity. If we abandon the senses, how can it be made conceivable that the
categories (which are the only conceptions that could serve as conceptions for noumena) have any sense or
meaning at all, inasmuch as something more than the mere unity of thought, namely, a possible intuition, is
requisite for their application to an object? The conception of a noumenon, considered as merely
problematical, is, however, not only admissible, but, as a limitative conception of sensibility, absolutely
necessary. But, in this case, a noumenon is not a particular intelligible object for our understanding; on the
contrary, the kind of understanding to which it could belong is itself a problem, for we cannot form the most
distant conception of the possibility of an understanding which should cognize an object, not discursively by
means of categories, but intuitively in a nonsensuous intuition. Our understanding attains in this way a sort
of negative extension. That is to say, it is not limited by, but rather limits, sensibility, by giving the name of
noumena to things, not considered as phenomena, but as things in themselves. But it at the same time
prescribes limits to itself, for it confesses itself unable to cognize these by means of the categories, and hence
is compelled to cogitate them merely as an unknown something.
I find, however, in the writings of modern authors, an entirely different use of the expressions, mundus
sensibilis and intelligibilis, which quite departs from the meaning of the ancients an acceptation in which,
indeed, there is to be found no difficulty, but which at the same time depends on mere verbal quibbling.
According to this meaning, some have chosen to call the complex of phenomena, in so far as it is intuited,
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 107
Page No 112
mundus sensibilis, but in so far as the connection thereof is cogitated according to general laws of thought,
mundus intelligibilis. Astronomy, in so far as we mean by the word the mere observation of the starry heaven,
may represent the former; a system of astronomy, such as the Copernican or Newtonian, the latter. But such
twisting of words is a mere sophistical subterfuge, to avoid a difficult question, by modifying its meaning to
suit our own convenience. To be sure, understanding and reason are employed in the cognition of
phenomena; but the question is, whether these can be applied when the object is not a phenomenon and in
this sense we regard it if it is cogitated as given to the understanding alone, and not to the senses. The
question therefore is whether, over and above the empirical use of the understanding, a transcendental use is
possible, which applies to the noumenon as an object. This question we have answered in the negative.
When therefore we say, the senses represent objects as they appear, the understanding as they are, the latter
statement must not be understood in a transcendental, but only in an empirical signification, that is, as they
must be represented in the complete connection of phenomena, and not according to what they may be, apart
from their relation to possible experience, consequently not as objects of the pure understanding. For this
must ever remain unknown to us. Nay, it is also quite unknown to us whether any such transcendental or
extraordinary cognition is possible under any circumstances, at least, whether it is possible by means of our
categories. Understanding and sensibility, with us, can determine objects only in conjunction. If we separate
them, we have intuitions without conceptions, or conceptions without intuitions; in both cases,
representations, which we cannot apply to any determinate object.
If, after all our inquiries and explanations, any one still hesitates to abandon the mere transcendental use of
the categories, let him attempt to construct with them a synthetical proposition. It would, of course, be
unnecessary for this purpose to construct an analytical proposition, for that does not extend the sphere of the
understanding, but, being concerned only about what is cogitated in the conception itself, it leaves it quite
undecided whether the conception has any relation to objects, or merely indicates the unity of thought
complete abstraction being made of the modi in which an object may be given: in such a proposition, it is
sufficient for the understanding to know what lies in the conception to what it applies is to it indifferent. The
attempt must therefore be made with a synthetical and socalled transcendental principle, for example:
"Everything that exists, exists as substance," or, "Everything that is contingent exists as an effect of some
other thing, viz., of its cause." Now I ask, whence can the understanding draw these synthetical propositions,
when the conceptions contained therein do not relate to possible experience but to things in themselves
(noumena)? Where is to be found the third term, which is always requisite PURE site in a synthetical
proposition, which may connect in the same proposition conceptions which have no logical (analytical)
connection with each other? The proposition never will be demonstrated, nay, more, the possibility of any
such pure assertion never can be shown, without making reference to the empirical use of the understanding,
and thus, ipso facto, completely renouncing pure and nonsensuous judgement. Thus the conception of pure
and merely intelligible objects is completely void of all principles of its application, because we cannot
imagine any mode in which they might be given, and the problematical thought which leaves a place open for
them serves only, like a void space, to limit the use of empirical principles, without containing at the same
time any other object of cognition beyond their sphere. APPENDIX
APPENDIX.
Of the Equivocal Nature or Amphiboly of the Conceptions of
Reflection from the Confusion of the Transcendental with
the Empirical use of the Understanding.
Reflection (reflexio) is not occupied about objects themselves, for the purpose of directly obtaining
conceptions of them, but is that state of the mind in which we set ourselves to discover the subjective
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 108
Page No 113
conditions under which we obtain conceptions. It is the consciousness of the relation of given representations
to the different sources or faculties of cognition, by which alone their relation to each other can be rightly
determined. The first question which occurs in considering our representations is to what faculty of cognition
do they belong? To the understanding or to the senses? Many judgements are admitted to be true from mere
habit or inclination; but, because reflection neither precedes nor follows, it is held to be a judgement that has
its origin in the understanding. All judgements do not require examination, that is, investigation into the
grounds of their truth. For, when they are immediately certain (for example: "Between two points there can
be only one straight line"), no better or less mediate test of their truth can be found than that which they
themselves contain and express. But all judgement, nay, all comparisons require reflection, that is, a
distinction of the faculty of cognition to which the given conceptions belong. The act whereby I compare my
representations with the faculty of cognition which originates them, and whereby I distinguish whether they
are compared with each other as belonging to the pure understanding or to sensuous intuition, I term
transcendental reflection. Now, the relations in which conceptions can stand to each other are those of
identity and difference, agreement and opposition, of the internal and external, finally, of the determinable
and the determining (matter and form). The proper determination of these relations rests on the question, to
what faculty of cognition they subjectively belong, whether to sensibility or understanding? For, on the
manner in which we solve this question depends the manner in which we must cogitate these relations.
Before constructing any objective judgement, we compare the conceptions that are to be placed in the
judgement, and observe whether there exists identity (of many representations in one conception), if a general
judgement is to be constructed, or difference, if a particular; whether there is agreement when affirmative;
and opposition when negative judgements are to be constructed, and so on. For this reason we ought to call
these conceptions, conceptions of comparison (conceptus comparationis). But as, when the question is not as
to the logical form, but as to the content of conceptions, that is to say, whether the things themselves are
identical or different, in agreement or opposition, and so on, the things can have a twofold relation to our
faculty of cognition, to wit, a relation either to sensibility or to the understanding, and as on this relation
depends their relation to each other, transcendental reflection, that is, the relation of given representations to
one or the other faculty of cognition, can alone determine this latter relation. Thus we shall not be able to
discover whether the things are identical or different, in agreement or opposition, etc., from the mere
conception of the things by means of comparison (comparatio), but only by distinguishing the mode of
cognition to which they belong, in other words, by means of transcendental reflection. We may, therefore,
with justice say, that logical reflection is mere comparison, for in it no account is taken of the faculty of
cognition to which the given conceptions belong, and they are consequently, as far as regards their origin, to
be treated as homogeneous; while transcendental reflection (which applies to the objects themselves) contains
the ground of the possibility of objective comparison of representations with each other, and is therefore very
different from the former, because the faculties of cognition to which they belong are not even the same.
Transcendental reflection is a duty which no one can neglect who wishes to establish an a priori judgement
upon things. We shall now proceed to fulfil this duty, and thereby throw not a little light on the question as to
the determination of the proper business of the understanding.
1. Identity and Difference. When an object is presented to us several times, but always with the same internal
determinations (qualitas et quantitas), it, if an object of pure understanding, is always the same, not several
things, but only one thing (numerica identitas); but if a phenomenon, we do not concern ourselves with
comparing the conception of the thing with the conception of some other, but, although they may be in this
respect perfectly the same, the difference of place at the same time is a sufficient ground for asserting the
numerical difference of these objects (of sense). Thus, in the case of two drops of water, we may make
complete abstraction of all internal difference (quality and quantity), and, the fact that they are intuited at the
same time in different places, is sufficient to justify us in holding them to be numerically different. Leibnitz
regarded phenomena as things in themselves, consequently as intelligibilia, that is, objects of pure
understanding (although, on account of the confused nature of their representations, he gave them the name
of phenomena), and in this case his principle of the indiscernible (principium identatis indiscernibilium) is
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 109
Page No 114
not to be impugned. But, as phenomena are objects of sensibility, and, as the understanding, in respect of
them, must be employed empirically and not purely or transcendentally, plurality and numerical difference
are given by space itself as the condition of external phenomena. For one part of space, although it may be
perfectly similar and equal to another part, is still without it, and for this reason alone is different from the
latter, which is added to it in order to make up a greater space. It follows that this must hold good of all things
that are in the different parts of space at the same time, however similar and equal one may be to another.
2. Agreement and Opposition. When reality is represented by the pure understanding (realitas noumenon),
opposition between realities is incogitable such a relation, that is, that when these realities are connected in
one subject, they annihilate the effects of each other and may be represented in the formula 3 3 = 0. On the
other hand, the real in a phenomenon (realitas phaenomenon) may very well be in mutual opposition, and,
when united in the same subject, the one may completely or in part annihilate the effect or consequence of the
other; as in the case of two moving forces in the same straight line drawing or impelling a point in opposite
directions, or in the case of a pleasure counterbalancing a certain amount of pain.
3. The Internal and External. In an object of the pure understanding, only that is internal which has no
relation (as regards its existence) to anything different from itself. On the other hand, the internal
determinations of a substantia phaenomenon in space are nothing but relations, and it is itself nothing more
than a complex of mere relations. Substance in space we are cognizant of only through forces operative in it,
either drawing others towards itself (attraction), or preventing others from forcing into itself (repulsion and
impenetrability). We know no other properties that make up the conception of substance phenomenal in
space, and which we term matter. On the other hand, as an object of the pure understanding, every substance
must have internal determination and forces. But what other internal attributes of such an object can I think
than those which my internal sense presents to me? That, to wit, which in either itself thought, or something
analogous to it. Hence Leibnitz, who looked upon things as noumena, after denying them everything like
external relation, and therefore also composition or combination, declared that all substances, even the
component parts of matter, were simple substances with powers of representation, in one word, monads.
4. Matter and Form. These two conceptions lie at the foundation of all other reflection, so inseparably are
they connected with every mode of exercising the understanding. The former denotes the determinable in
general, the second its determination, both in a transcendental sense, abstraction being made of every
difference in that which is given, and of the mode in which it is determined. Logicians formerly termed the
universal, matter, the specific difference of this or that part of the universal, form. In a judgement one may
call the given conceptions logical matter (for the judgement), the relation of these to each other (by means of
the copula), the form of the judgement. In an object, the composite parts thereof (essentialia) are the matter;
the mode in which they are connected in the object, the form. In respect to things in general, unlimited reality
was regarded as the matter of all possibility, the limitation thereof (negation) as the form, by which one thing
is distinguished from another according to transcendental conceptions. The understanding demands that
something be given (at least in the conception), in order to be able to determine it in a certain manner. Hence,
in a conception of the pure understanding, the matter precedes the form, and for this reason Leibnitz first
assumed the existence of things (monads) and of an internal power of representation in them, in order to
found upon this their external relation and the community their state (that is, of their representations). Hence,
with him, space and time were possible the former through the relation of substances, the latter through the
connection of their determinations with each other, as causes and effects. And so would it really be, if the
pure understanding were capable of an immediate application to objects, and if space and time were
determinations of things in themselves. But being merely sensuous intuitions, in which we determine all
objects solely as phenomena, the form of intuition (as a subjective property of sensibility) must antecede all
matter (sensations), consequently space and time must antecede all phenomena and all data of experience,
and rather make experience itself possible. But the intellectual philosopher could not endure that the form
should precede the things themselves and determine their possibility; an objection perfectly correct, if we
assume that we intuite things as they are, although with confused representation. But as sensuous intuition is
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 110
Page No 115
a peculiar subjective condition, which is a priori at the foundation of all perception, and the form of which is
primitive, the form must be given per se, and so far from matter (or the things themselves which appear) lying
at the foundation of experience (as we must conclude, if we judge by mere conceptions), the very possibility
of itself presupposes, on the contrary, a given formal intuition (space and time).
REMARK ON THE AMPHIBOLY OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF REFLECTION.
Let me be allowed to term the position which we assign to a conception either in the sensibility or in the pure
understanding, the transcendental place. In this manner, the appointment of the position which must be taken
by each conception according to the difference in its use, and the directions for determining this place to all
conceptions according to rules, would be a transcendental topic, a doctrine which would thoroughly shield us
from the surreptitious devices of the pure understanding and the delusions which thence arise, as it would
always distinguish to what faculty of cognition each conception properly belonged. Every conception, every
title, under which many cognitions rank together, may be called a logical place. Upon this is based the logical
topic of Aristotle, of which teachers and rhetoricians could avail themselves, in order, under certain titles of
thought, to observe what would best suit the matter they had to treat, and thus enable themselves to quibble
and talk with fluency and an appearance of profundity.
Transcendental topic, on the contrary, contains nothing more than the abovementioned four titles of all
comparison and distinction, which differ from categories in this respect, that they do not represent the object
according to that which constitutes its conception (quantity, reality), but set forth merely the comparison of
representations, which precedes our conceptions of things. But this comparison requires a previous reflection,
that is, a determination of the place to which the representations of the things which are compared belong,
whether, to wit, they are cogitated by the pure understanding, or given by sensibility.
Conceptions may be logically compared without the trouble of inquiring to what faculty their objects belong,
whether as noumena, to the understanding, or as phenomena, to sensibility. If, however, we wish to employ
these conceptions in respect of objects, previous transcendental reflection is necessary. Without this reflection
I should make a very unsafe use of these conceptions, and construct pretended synthetical propositions which
critical reason cannot acknowledge and which are based solely upon a transcendental amphiboly, that is, upon
a substitution of an object of pure understanding for a phenomenon.
For want of this doctrine of transcendental topic, and consequently deceived by the amphiboly of the
conceptions of reflection, the celebrated Leibnitz constructed an intellectual system of the world, or rather,
believed himself competent to cognize the internal nature of things, by comparing all objects merely with the
understanding and the abstract formal conceptions of thought. Our table of the conceptions of reflection gives
us the unexpected advantage of being able to exhibit the distinctive peculiarities of his system in all its parts,
and at the same time of exposing the fundamental principle of this peculiar mode of thought, which rested
upon naught but a misconception. He compared all things with each other merely by means of conceptions,
and naturally found no other differences than those by which the understanding distinguishes its pure
conceptions one from another. The conditions of sensuous intuition, which contain in themselves their own
means of distinction, he did not look upon as primitive, because sensibility was to him but a confused mode
of representation and not any particular source of representations. A phenomenon was for him the
representation of the thing in itself, although distinguished from cognition by the understanding only in
respect of the logical form the former with its usual want of analysis containing, according to him, a certain
mixture of collateral representations in its conception of a thing, which it is the duty of the understanding to
separate and distinguish. In one word, Leibnitz intellectualized phenomena, just as Locke, in his system of
noogony (if I may be allowed to make use of such expressions), sensualized the conceptions of the
understanding, that is to say, declared them to be nothing more than empirical or abstract conceptions of
reflection. Instead of seeking in the understanding and sensibility two different sources of representations,
which, however, can present us with objective judgements of things only in conjunction, each of these great
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 111
Page No 116
men recognized but one of these faculties, which, in their opinion, applied immediately to things in
themselves, the other having no duty but that of confusing or arranging the representations of the former.
Accordingly, the objects of sense were compared by Leibnitz as things in general merely in the
understanding.
1st. He compares them in regard to their identity or difference as judged by the understanding. As,
therefore, he considered merely the conceptions of objects, and not their position in intuition, in which alone
objects can be given, and left quite out of sight the transcendental locale of these conceptions whether, that
is, their object ought to be classed among phenomena, or among things in themselves, it was to be expected
that he should extend the application of the principle of indiscernibles, which is valid solely of conceptions of
things in general, to objects of sense (mundus phaenomenon), and that he should believe that he had thereby
contributed in no small degree to extend our knowledge of nature. In truth, if I cognize in all its inner
determinations a drop of water as a thing in itself, I cannot look upon one drop as different from another, if
the conception of the one is completely identical with that of the other. But if it is a phenomenon in space, it
has a place not merely in the understanding (among conceptions), but also in sensuous external intuition (in
space), and in this case, the physical locale is a matter of indifference in regard to the internal determinations
of things, and one place, B, may contain a thing which is perfectly similar and equal to another in a place, A,
just as well as if the two things were in every respect different from each other. Difference of place without
any other conditions, makes the plurality and distinction of objects as phenomena, not only possible in itself,
but even necessary. Consequently, the above socalled law is not a law of nature. It is merely an analytical
rule for the comparison of things by means of mere conceptions.
2nd. The principle: "Realities (as simple affirmations) never logically contradict each other," is a proposition
perfectly true respecting the relation of conceptions, but, whether as regards nature, or things in themselves
(of which we have not the slightest conception), is without any the least meaning. For real opposition, in
which A B is = 0, exists everywhere, an opposition, that is, in which one reality united with another in the
same subject annihilates the effects of the other a fact which is constantly brought before our eyes by the
different antagonistic actions and operations in nature, which, nevertheless, as depending on real forces, must
be called realitates phaenomena. General mechanics can even present us with the empirical condition of this
opposition in an a priori rule, as it directs its attention to the opposition in the direction of forces a condition
of which the transcendental conception of reality can tell us nothing. Although M. Leibnitz did not announce
this proposition with precisely the pomp of a new principle, he yet employed it for the establishment of new
propositions, and his followers introduced it into their LeibnitzioWolfian system of philosophy. According
to this principle, for example, all evils are but consequences of the limited nature of created beings, that is,
negations, because these are the only opposite of reality. (In the mere conception of a thing in general this is
really the case, but not in things as phenomena.) In like manner, the upholders of this system deem it not only
possible, but natural also, to connect and unite all reality in one being, because they acknowledge no other
sort of opposition than that of contradiction (by which the conception itself of a thing is annihilated), and find
themselves unable to conceive an opposition of reciprocal destruction, so to speak, in which one real cause
destroys the effect of another, and the conditions of whose representation we meet with only in sensibility.
3rd. The Leibnitzian monadology has really no better foundation than on this philosopher's mode of falsely
representing the difference of the internal and external solely in relation to the understanding. Substances, in
general, must have something inward, which is therefore free from external relations, consequently from that
of composition also. The simple that which can be represented by a unit is therefore the foundation of that
which is internal in things in themselves. The internal state of substances cannot therefore consist in place,
shape, contact, or motion, determinations which are all external relations, and we can ascribe to them no other
than that whereby we internally determine our faculty of sense itself, that is to say, the state of representation.
Thus, then, were constructed the monads, which were to form the elements of the universe, the active force of
which consists in representation, the effects of this force being thus entirely confined to themselves.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 112
Page No 117
For the same reason, his view of the possible community of substances could not represent it but as a
predetermined harmony, and by no means as a physical influence. For inasmuch as everything is occupied
only internally, that is, with its own representations, the state of the representations of one substance could
not stand in active and living connection with that of another, but some third cause operating on all without
exception was necessary to make the different states correspond with one another. And this did not happen by
means of assistance applied in each particular case (systema assistentiae), but through the unity of the idea of
a cause occupied and connected with all substances, in which they necessarily receive, according to the
Leibnitzian school, their existence and permanence, consequently also reciprocal correspondence, according
to universal laws.
4th. This philosopher's celebrated doctrine of space and time, in which he intellectualized these forms of
sensibility, originated in the same delusion of transcendental reflection. If I attempt to represent by the mere
understanding, the external relations of things, I can do so only by employing the conception of their
reciprocal action, and if I wish to connect one state of the same thing with another state, I must avail myself
of the notion of the order of cause and effect. And thus Leibnitz regarded space as a certain order in the
community of substances, and time as the dynamical sequence of their states. That which space and time
possess proper to themselves and independent of things, he ascribed to a necessary confusion in our
conceptions of them, whereby that which is a mere form of dynamical relations is held to be a selfexistent
intuition, antecedent even to things themselves. Thus space and time were the intelligible form of the
connection of things (substances and their states) in themselves. But things were intelligible substances
(substantiae noumena). At the same time, he made these conceptions valid of phenomena, because he did not
allow to sensibility a peculiar mode of intuition, but sought all, even the empirical representation of objects,
in the understanding, and left to sense naught but the despicable task of confusing and disarranging the
representations of the former.
But even if we could frame any synthetical proposition concerning things in themselves by means of the pure
understanding (which is impossible), it could not apply to phenomena, which do not represent things in
themselves. In such a case I should be obliged in transcendental reflection to compare my conceptions only
under the conditions of sensibility, and so space and time would not be determinations of things in
themselves, but of phenomena. What things may be in themselves, I know not and need not know, because a
thing is never presented to me otherwise than as a phenomenon.
I must adopt the same mode of procedure with the other conceptions of reflection. Matter is substantia
phaenomenon. That in it which is internal I seek to discover in all parts of space which it occupies, and in all
the functions and operations it performs, and which are indeed never anything but phenomena of the external
sense. I cannot therefore find anything that is absolutely, but only what is comparatively internal, and which
itself consists of external relations. The absolutely internal in matter, and as it should be according to the pure
understanding, is a mere chimera, for matter is not an object for the pure understanding. But the
transcendental object, which is the foundation of the phenomenon which we call matter, is a mere nescio
quid, the nature of which we could not understand, even though someone were found able to tell us. For we
can understand nothing that does not bring with it something in intuition corresponding to the expressions
employed. If, by the complaint of being unable to perceive the internal nature of things, it is meant that we do
not comprehend by the pure understanding what the things which appear to us may be in themselves, it is a
silly and unreasonable complaint; for those who talk thus really desire that we should be able to cognize,
consequently to intuite, things without senses, and therefore wish that we possessed a faculty of cognition
perfectly different from the human faculty, not merely in degree, but even as regards intuition and the mode
thereof, so that thus we should not be men, but belong to a class of beings, the possibility of whose existence,
much less their nature and constitution, we have no means of cognizing. By observation and analysis of
phenomena we penetrate into the interior of nature, and no one can say what progress this knowledge may
make in time. But those transcendental questions which pass beyond the limits of nature, we could never
answer, even although all nature were laid open to us, because we have not the power of observing our own
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 113
Page No 118
mind with any other intuition than that of our internal sense. For herein lies the mystery of the origin and
source of our faculty of sensibility. Its application to an object, and the transcendental ground of this unity of
subjective and objective, lie too deeply concealed for us, who cognize ourselves only through the internal
sense, consequently as phenomena, to be able to discover in our existence anything but phenomena, the
nonsensuous cause of which we at the same time earnestly desire to penetrate to.
The great utility of this critique of conclusions arrived at by the processes of mere reflection consists in its
clear demonstration of the nullity of all conclusions respecting objects which are compared with each other in
the understanding alone, while it at the same time confirms what we particularly insisted on, namely, that,
although phenomena are not included as things in themselves among the objects of the pure understanding,
they are nevertheless the only things by which our cognition can possess objective reality, that is to say,
which give us intuitions to correspond with our conceptions.
When we reflect in a purely logical manner, we do nothing more than compare conceptions in our
understanding, to discover whether both have the same content, whether they are selfcontradictory or not,
whether anything is contained in either conception, which of the two is given, and which is merely a mode of
thinking that given. But if I apply these conceptions to an object in general (in the transcendental sense),
without first determining whether it is an object of sensuous or intellectual intuition, certain limitations
present themselves, which forbid us to pass beyond the conceptions and render all empirical use of them
impossible. And thus these limitations prove that the representation of an object as a thing in general is not
only insufficient, but, without sensuous determination and independently of empirical conditions,
selfcontradictory; that we must therefore make abstraction of all objects, as in logic, or, admitting them,
must think them under conditions of sensuous intuition; that, consequently, the intelligible requires an
altogether peculiar intuition, which we do not possess, and in the absence of which it is for us nothing; while,
on the other hand phenomena cannot be objects in themselves. For, when I merely think things in general, the
difference in their external relations cannot constitute a difference in the things themselves; on the contrary,
the former presupposes the latter, and if the conception of one of two things is not internally different from
that of the other, I am merely thinking the same thing in different relations. Further, by the addition of one
affirmation (reality) to the other, the positive therein is really augmented, and nothing is abstracted or
withdrawn from it; hence the real in things cannot be in contradiction with or opposition to itself and so on.
The true use of the conceptions of reflection in the employment of the understanding has, as we have shown,
been so misconceived by Leibnitz, one of the most acute philosophers of either ancient or modern times, that
he has been misled into the construction of a baseless system of intellectual cognition, which professes to
determine its objects without the intervention of the senses. For this reason, the exposition of the cause of the
amphiboly of these conceptions, as the origin of these false principles, is of great utility in determining with
certainty the proper limits of the understanding.
It is right to say whatever is affirmed or denied of the whole of a conception can be affirmed or denied of any
part of it (dictum de omni et nullo); but it would be absurd so to alter this logical proposition as to say
whatever is not contained in a general conception is likewise not contained in the particular conceptions
which rank under it; for the latter are particular conceptions, for the very reason that their content is greater
than that which is cogitated in the general conception. And yet the whole intellectual system of Leibnitz is
based upon this false principle, and with it must necessarily fall to the ground, together with all the
ambiguous principles in reference to the employment of the understanding which have thence originated.
Leibnitz's principle of the identity of indiscernibles or indistinguishables is really based on the presupposition
that, if in the conception of a thing a certain distinction is not to be found, it is also not to be met with in
things themselves; that, consequently, all things are completely identical (numero eadem) which are not
distinguishable from each other (as to quality or quantity) in our conceptions of them. But, as in the mere
conception of anything abstraction has been made of many necessary conditions of intuition, that of which
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 114
Page No 119
abstraction has been made is rashly held to be nonexistent, and nothing is attributed to the thing but what is
contained in its conception.
The conception of a cubic foot of space, however I may think it, is in itself completely identical. But two
cubic feet in space are nevertheless distinct from each other from the sole fact of their being in different
places (they are numero diversa); and these places are conditions of intuition, wherein the object of this
conception is given, and which do not belong to the conception, but to the faculty of sensibility. In like
manner, there is in the conception of a thing no contradiction when a negative is not connected with an
affirmative; and merely affirmative conceptions cannot, in conjunction, produce any negation. But in
sensuous intuition, wherein reality (take for example, motion) is given, we find conditions (opposite
directions) of which abstraction has been made in the conception of motion in general which render
possible a contradiction or opposition (not indeed of a logical kind) and which from pure positives produce
zero = 0. We are therefore not justified in saying that all reality is in perfect agreement and harmony, because
no contradiction is discoverable among its conceptions.* According to mere conceptions, that which is
internal is the substratum of all relations or external determinations. When, therefore, I abstract all conditions
of intuition, and confine myself solely to the conception of a thing in general, I can make abstraction of all
external relations, and there must nevertheless remain a conception of that which indicates no relation, but
merely internal determinations. Now it seems to follow that in everything (substance) there is something
which is absolutely internal and which antecedes all external determinations, inasmuch as it renders them
possible; and that therefore this substratum is something which does not contain any external relations and is
consequently simple (for corporeal things are never anything but relations, at least of their parts external to
each other); and, inasmuch as we know of no other absolutely internal determinations than those of the
internal sense, this substratum is not only simple, but also, analogously with our internal sense, determined
through representations, that is to say, all things are properly monads, or simple beings endowed with the
power of representation. Now all this would be perfectly correct, if the conception of a thing were the only
necessary condition of the presentation of objects of external intuition. It is, on the contrary, manifest that a
permanent phenomenon in space (impenetrable extension) can contain mere relations, and nothing that is
absolutely internal, and yet be the primary substratum of all external perception. By mere conceptions I
cannot think anything external, without, at the same time, thinking something internal, for the reason that
conceptions of relations presuppose given things, and without these are impossible. But, as an intuition there
is something (that is, space, which, with all it contains, consists of purely formal, or, indeed, real relations)
which is not found in the mere conception of a thing in general, and this presents to us the substratum which
could not be cognized through conceptions alone, I cannot say: because a thing cannot be represented by
mere conceptions without something absolutely internal, there is also, in the things themselves which are
contained under these conceptions, and in their intuition nothing external to which something absolutely
internal does not serve as the foundation. For, when we have made abstraction of all the conditions of
intuition, there certainly remains in the mere conception nothing but the internal in general, through which
alone the external is possible. But this necessity, which is grounded upon abstraction alone, does not obtain in
the case of things themselves, in so far as they are given in intuition with such determinations as express mere
relations, without having anything internal as their foundation; for they are not things of a thing of which we
can neither for they are not things in themselves, but only phenomena. What we cognize in matter is nothing
but relations (what we call its internal determinations are but comparatively internal). But there are some
selfsubsistent and permanent, through which a determined object is given. That I, when abstraction is made
of these relations, have nothing more to think, does not destroy the conception of a thing as phenomenon, nor
the conception of an object in abstracto, but it does away with the possibility of an object that is determinable
according to mere conceptions, that is, of a noumenon. It is certainly startling to hear that a thing consists
solely of relations; but this thing is simply a phenomenon, and cannot be cogitated by means of the mere
categories: it does itself consist in the mere relation of something in general to the senses. In the same way,
we cannot cogitate relations of things in abstracto, if we commence with conceptions alone, in any other
manner than that one is the cause of determinations in the other; for that is itself the conception of the
understanding or category of relation. But, as in this case we make abstraction of all intuition, we lose
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 115
Page No 120
altogether the mode in which the manifold determines to each of its parts its place, that is, the form of
sensibility (space); and yet this mode antecedes all empirical causality.
*If any one wishes here to have recourse to the usual subterfuge, and to say, that at least realitates noumena
cannot be in opposition to each other, it will be requisite for him to adduce an example of this pure and
nonsensuous reality, that it may be understood whether the notion represents something or nothing. But an
example cannot be found except in experience, which never presents to us anything more than phenomena;
and thus the proposition means nothing more than that the conception which contains only affirmatives does
not contain anything negative a proposition nobody ever doubted.
If by intelligible objects we understand things which can be thought by means of the pure categories, without
the need of the schemata of sensibility, such objects are impossible. For the condition of the objective use of
all our conceptions of understanding is the mode of our sensuous intuition, whereby objects are given; and, if
we make abstraction of the latter, the former can have no relation to an object. And even if we should
suppose a different kind of intuition from our own, still our functions of thought would have no use or
signification in respect thereof. But if we understand by the term, objects of a nonsensuous intuition, in
respect of which our categories are not valid, and of which we can accordingly have no knowledge (neither
intuition nor conception), in this merely negative sense noumena must be admitted. For this is no more than
saying that our mode of intuition is not applicable to all things, but only to objects of our senses, that
consequently its objective validity is limited, and that room is therefore left for another kind of intuition, and
thus also for things that may be objects of it. But in this sense the conception of a noumenon is problematical,
that is to say, it is the notion of that it that it is possible, nor that it is impossible, inasmuch as we do not know
of any mode of intuition besides the sensuous, or of any other sort of conceptions than the categories a mode
of intuition and a kind of conception neither of which is applicable to a nonsensuous object. We are on this
account incompetent to extend the sphere of our objects of thought beyond the conditions of our sensibility,
and to assume the existence of objects of pure thought, that is, of noumena, inasmuch as these have no true
positive signification. For it must be confessed of the categories that they are not of themselves sufficient for
the cognition of things in themselves and, without the data of sensibility, are mere subjective forms of the
unity of the understanding. Thought is certainly not a product of the senses, and in so far is not limited by
them, but it does not therefore follow that it may be employed purely and without the intervention of
sensibility, for it would then be without reference to an object. And we cannot call a noumenon an object of
pure thought; for the representation thereof is but the problematical conception of an object for a perfectly
different intuition and a perfectly different understanding from ours, both of which are consequently
themselves problematical. The conception of a noumenon is therefore not the conception of an object, but
merely a problematical conception inseparably connected with the limitation of our sensibility. That is to say,
this conception contains the answer to the question: "Are there objects quite unconnected with, and
independent of, our intuition?" a question to which only an indeterminate answer can be given. That answer
is: "Inasmuch as sensuous intuition does not apply to all things without distinction, there remains room for
other and different objects." The existence of these problematical objects is therefore not absolutely denied,
in the absence of a determinate conception of them, but, as no category is valid in respect of them, neither
must they be admitted as objects for our understanding.
Understanding accordingly limits sensibility, without at the same time enlarging its own field. While,
moreover, it forbids sensibility to apply its forms and modes to things in themselves and restricts it to the
sphere of phenomena, it cogitates an object in itself, only, however, as a transcendental object, which is the
cause of a phenomenon (consequently not itself a phenomenon), and which cannot be thought either as a
quantity or as reality, or as substance (because these conceptions always require sensuous forms in which to
determine an object) an object, therefore, of which we are quite unable to say whether it can be met with in
ourselves or out of us, whether it would be annihilated together with sensibility, or, if this were taken away,
would continue to exist. If we wish to call this object a noumenon, because the representation of it is
nonsensuous, we are at liberty to do so. But as we can apply to it none of the conceptions of our
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 116
Page No 121
understanding, the representation is for us quite void, and is available only for the indication of the limits of
our sensuous intuition, thereby leaving at the same time an empty space, which we are competent to fill by
the aid neither of possible experience, nor of the pure understanding.
The critique of the pure understanding, accordingly, does not permit us to create for ourselves a new field of
objects beyond those which are presented to us as phenomena, and to stray into intelligible worlds; nay, it
does not even allow us to endeavour to form so much as a conception of them. The specious error which
leads to this and which is a perfectly excusable one lies in the fact that the employment of the
understanding, contrary to its proper purpose and destination, is made transcendental, and objects, that is,
possible intuitions, are made to regulate themselves according to conceptions, instead of the conceptions
arranging themselves according to the intuitions, on which alone their own objective validity rests. Now the
reason of this again is that apperception, and with it thought, antecedes all possible determinate arrangement
of representations. Accordingly we think something in general and determine it on the one hand sensuously,
but, on the other, distinguish the general and in abstracto represented object from this particular mode of
intuiting it. In this case there remains a mode of determining the object by mere thought, which is really but a
logical form without content, which, however, seems to us to be a mode of the existence of the object in itself
(noumenon), without regard to intuition which is limited to our senses.
Before ending this transcendental analytic, we must make an addition, which, although in itself of no
particular importance, seems to be necessary to the completeness of the system. The highest conception, with
which a transcendental philosophy commonly begins, is the division into possible and impossible. But as all
division presupposes a divided conception, a still higher one must exist, and this is the conception of an
object in general problematically understood and without its being decided whether it is something or
nothing. As the categories are the only conceptions which apply to objects in general, the distinguishing of an
object, whether it is something or nothing, must proceed according to the order and direction of the
categories.
1. To the categories of quantity, that is, the conceptions of all, many, and one, the conception which
annihilates all, that is, the conception of none, is opposed. And thus the object of a conception, to which no
intuition can be found to correspond, is = nothing. That is, it is a conception without an object (ens rationis),
like noumena, which cannot be considered possible in the sphere of reality, though they must not therefore be
held to be impossible or like certain new fundamental forces in matter, the existence of which is cogitable
without contradiction, though, as examples from experience are not forthcoming, they must not be regarded
as possible.
2. Reality is something; negation is nothing, that is, a conception of the absence of an object, as cold, a
shadow (nihil privativum).
3. The mere form of intuition, without substance, is in itself no object, but the merely formal condition of an
object (as phenomenon), as pure space and pure time. These are certainly something, as forms of intuition,
but are not themselves objects which are intuited (ens imaginarium).
4. The object of a conception which is selfcontradictory, is nothing, because the conception is nothing is
impossible, as a figure composed of two straight lines (nihil negativum).
The table of this division of the conception of nothing (the corresponding division of the conception of
something does not require special description) must therefore be arranged as follows:
NOTHING
AS
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena. 117
Page No 122
1
As Empty Conception
without object,
ens rationis
2 3
Empty object of Empty intuition
a conception, without object,
nihil privativum ens imaginarium
4
Empty object
without conception,
nihil negativum
We see that the ens rationis is distinguished from the nihil negativum or pure nothing by the consideration
that the former must not be reckoned among possibilities, because it is a mere fiction though not
selfcontradictory, while the latter is completely opposed to all possibility, inasmuch as the conception
annihilates itself. Both, however, are empty conceptions. On the other hand, the nihil privativum and ens
imaginarium are empty data for conceptions. If light be not given to the senses, we cannot represent to
ourselves darkness, and if extended objects are not perceived, we cannot represent space. Neither the
negation, nor the mere form of intuition can, without something real, be an object.
TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC. SECOND DIVISION.
TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. INTRODUCTION.
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance.
We termed dialectic in general a logic of appearance. This does not signify a doctrine of probability; for
probability is truth, only cognized upon insufficient grounds, and though the information it gives us is
imperfect, it is not therefore deceitful. Hence it must not be separated from the analytical part of logic. Still
less must phenomenon and appearance be held to be identical. For truth or illusory appearance does not
reside in the object, in so far as it is intuited, but in the judgement upon the object, in so far as it is thought. It
is, therefore, quite correct to say that the senses do not err, not because they always judge correctly, but
because they do not judge at all. Hence truth and error, consequently also, illusory appearance as the cause of
error, are only to be found in a judgement, that is, in the relation of an object to our understanding. In a
cognition which completely harmonizes with the laws of the understanding, no error can exist. In a
representation of the senses as not containing any judgement there is also no error. But no power of nature
can of itself deviate from its own laws. Hence neither the understanding per se (without the influence of
another cause), nor the senses per se, would fall into error; the former could not, because, if it acts only
according to its own laws, the effect (the judgement) must necessarily accord with these laws. But in
The Critique of Pure Reason
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. 118
Page No 123
accordance with the laws of the understanding consists the formal element in all truth. In the senses there is
no judgement neither a true nor a false one. But, as we have no source of cognition besides these two, it
follows that error is caused solely by the unobserved influence of the sensibility upon the understanding. And
thus it happens that the subjective grounds of a judgement and are confounded with the objective, and cause
them to deviate from their proper determination,* just as a body in motion would always of itself proceed in a
straight line, but if another impetus gives to it a different direction, it will then start off into a curvilinear line
of motion. To distinguish the peculiar action of the understanding from the power which mingles with it, it is
necessary to consider an erroneous judgement as the diagonal between two forces, that determine the
judgement in two different directions, which, as it were, form an angle, and to resolve this composite
operation into the simple ones of the understanding and the sensibility. In pure a priori judgements this must
be done by means of transcendental reflection, whereby, as has been already shown, each representation has
its place appointed in the corresponding faculty of cognition, and consequently the influence of the one
faculty upon the other is made apparent.
*Sensibility, subjected to the understanding, as the object upon which the understanding employs its
functions, is the source of real cognitions. But, in so far as it exercises an influence upon the action of the
understanding and determines it to judgement, sensibility is itself the cause of error.
It is not at present our business to treat of empirical illusory appearance (for example, optical illusion), which
occurs in the empirical application of otherwise correct rules of the understanding, and in which the
judgement is misled by the influence of imagination. Our purpose is to speak of transcendental illusory
appearance, which influences principles that are not even applied to experience, for in this case we should
possess a sure test of their correctness but which leads us, in disregard of all the warnings of criticism,
completely beyond the empirical employment of the categories and deludes us with the chimera of an
extension of the sphere of the pure understanding. We shall term those principles the application of which is
confined entirely within the limits of possible experience, immanent; those, on the other hand, which
transgress these limits, we shall call transcendent principles. But by these latter I do not understand principles
of the transcendental use or misuse of the categories, which is in reality a mere fault of the judgement when
not under due restraint from criticism, and therefore not paying sufficient attention to the limits of the sphere
in which the pure understanding is allowed to exercise its functions; but real principles which exhort us to
break down all those barriers, and to lay claim to a perfectly new field of cognition, which recognizes no line
of demarcation. Thus transcendental and transcendent are not identical terms. The principles of the pure
understanding, which we have already propounded, ought to be of empirical and not of transcendental use,
that is, they are not applicable to any object beyond the sphere of experience. A principle which removes
these limits, nay, which authorizes us to overstep them, is called transcendent. If our criticism can succeed in
exposing the illusion in these pretended principles, those which are limited in their employment to the sphere
of experience may be called, in opposition to the others, immanent principles of the pure understanding.
Logical illusion, which consists merely in the imitation of the form of reason (the illusion in sophistical
syllogisms), arises entirely from a want of due attention to logical rules. So soon as the attention is awakened
to the case before us, this illusion totally disappears. Transcendental illusion, on the contrary, does not cease
to exist, even after it has been exposed, and its nothingness clearly perceived by means of transcendental
criticism. Take, for example, the illusion in the proposition: "The world must have a beginning in time." The
cause of this is as follows. In our reason, subjectively considered as a faculty of human cognition, there exist
fundamental rules and maxims of its exercise, which have completely the appearance of objective principles.
Now from this cause it happens that the subjective necessity of a certain connection of our conceptions, is
regarded as an objective necessity of the determination of things in themselves. This illusion it is impossible
to avoid, just as we cannot avoid perceiving that the sea appears to be higher at a distance than it is near the
shore, because we see the former by means of higher rays than the latter, or, which is a still stronger case, as
even the astronomer cannot prevent himself from seeing the moon larger at its rising than some time
afterwards, although he is not deceived by this illusion.
The Critique of Pure Reason
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. 119
Page No 124
Transcendental dialectic will therefore content itself with exposing the illusory appearance in transcendental
judgements, and guarding us against it; but to make it, as in the case of logical illusion, entirely disappear and
cease to be illusion is utterly beyond its power. For we have here to do with a natural and unavoidable
illusion, which rests upon subjective principles and imposes these upon us as objective, while logical
dialectic, in the detection of sophisms, has to do merely with an error in the logical consequence of the
propositions, or with an artificially constructed illusion, in imitation of the natural error. There is, therefore, a
natural and unavoidable dialectic of pure reason not that in which the bungler, from want of the requisite
knowledge, involves himself, nor that which the sophist devises for the purpose of misleading, but that which
is an inseparable adjunct of human reason, and which, even after its illusions have been exposed, does not
cease to deceive, and continually to lead reason into momentary errors, which it becomes necessary
continually to remove.
II. Of Pure Reason as the Seat of Transcendental Illusory
Appearance.
A. OF REASON IN GENERAL.
All our knowledge begins with sense, proceeds thence to understanding, and ends with reason, beyond which
nothing higher can be discovered in the human mind for elaborating the matter of intuition and subjecting it
to the highest unity of thought. At this stage of our inquiry it is my duty to give an explanation of this, the
highest faculty of cognition, and I confess I find myself here in some difficulty. Of reason, as of the
understanding, there is a merely formal, that is, logical use, in which it makes abstraction of all content of
cognition; but there is also a real use, inasmuch as it contains in itself the source of certain conceptions and
principles, which it does not borrow either from the senses or the understanding. The former faculty has been
long defined by logicians as the faculty of mediate conclusion in contradistinction to immediate conclusions
(consequentiae immediatae); but the nature of the latter, which itself generates conceptions, is not to be
understood from this definition. Now as a division of reason into a logical and a transcendental faculty
presents itself here, it becomes necessary to seek for a higher conception of this source of cognition which
shall comprehend both conceptions. In this we may expect, according to the analogy of the conceptions of the
understanding, that the logical conception will give us the key to the transcendental, and that the table of the
functions of the former will present us with the clue to the conceptions of reason.
In the former part of our transcendental logic, we defined the understanding to be the faculty of rules; reason
may be distinguished from understanding as the faculty of principles.
The term principle is ambiguous, and commonly signifies merely a cognition that may be employed as a
principle, although it is not in itself, and as regards its proper origin, entitled to the distinction. Every general
proposition, even if derived from experience by the process of induction, may serve as the major in a
syllogism; but it is not for that reason a principle. Mathematical axioms (for example, there can be only one
straight line between two points) are general a priori cognitions, and are therefore rightly denominated
principles, relatively to the cases which can be subsumed under them. But I cannot for this reason say that I
cognize this property of a straight line from principles I cognize it only in pure intuition.
Cognition from principles, then, is that cognition in which I cognize the particular in the general by means of
conceptions. Thus every syllogism is a form of the deduction of a cognition from a principle. For the major
always gives a conception, through which everything that is subsumed under the condition thereof is
cognized according to a principle. Now as every general cognition may serve as the major in a syllogism, and
the understanding presents us with such general a priori propositions, they may be termed principles, in
respect of their possible use.
The Critique of Pure Reason
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. 120
Page No 125
But if we consider these principles of the pure understanding in relation to their origin, we shall find them to
be anything rather than cognitions from conceptions. For they would not even be possible a priori, if we
could not rely on the assistance of pure intuition (in mathematics), or on that of the conditions of a possible
experience. That everything that happens has a cause, cannot be concluded from the general conception of
that which happens; on the contrary the principle of causality instructs us as to the mode of obtaining from
that which happens a determinate empirical conception.
Synthetical cognitions from conceptions the understanding cannot supply, and they alone are entitled to be
called principles. At the same time, all general propositions may be termed comparative principles.
It has been a longcherished wish that (who knows how late), may one day, be happily accomplished that
the principles of the endless variety of civil laws should be investigated and exposed; for in this way alone
can we find the secret of simplifying legislation. But in this case, laws are nothing more than limitations of
our freedom upon conditions under which it subsists in perfect harmony with itself; they consequently have
for their object that which is completely our own work, and of which we ourselves may be the cause by
means of these conceptions. But how objects as things in themselves how the nature of things is
subordinated to principles and is to be determined. according to conceptions, is a question which it seems
well nigh impossible to answer. Be this, however, as it may for on this point our investigation is yet to be
made it is at least manifest from what we have said that cognition from principles is something very
different from cognition by means of the understanding, which may indeed precede other cognitions in the
form of a principle, but in itself in so far as it is synthetical is neither based upon mere thought, nor
contains a general proposition drawn from conceptions alone shall comprehend
The understanding may be a faculty for the production of unity of phenomena by virtue of rules; the reason is
a faculty for the production of unity of rules (of the understanding) under principles. Reason, therefore, never
applies directly to experience, or to any sensuous object; its object is, on the contrary, the understanding, to
the manifold cognition of which it gives a unity a priori by means of conceptions a unity which may be
called rational unity, and which is of a nature very different from that of the unity produced by the
understanding.
The above is the general conception of the faculty of reason, in so far as it has been possible to make it
comprehensible in the absence of examples. These will be given in the sequel.
B. OF THE LOGICAL USE OF REASON.
A distinction is commonly made between that which is immediately cognized and that which is inferred or
concluded. That in a figure which is bounded by three straight lines there are three angles, is an immediate
cognition; but that these angles are together equal to two right angles, is an inference or conclusion. Now, as
we are constantly employing this mode of thought and have thus become quite accustomed to it, we no longer
remark the above distinction, and, as in the case of the socalled deceptions of sense, consider as
immediately perceived, what has really been inferred. In every reasoning or syllogism, there is a fundamental
proposition, afterwards a second drawn from it, and finally the conclusion, which connects the truth in the
first with the truth in the second and that infallibly. If the judgement concluded is so contained in the first
proposition that it can be deduced from it without the meditation of a third notion, the conclusion is called
immediate (consequentia immediata); I prefer the term conclusion of the understanding. But if, in addition to
the fundamental cognition, a second judgement is necessary for the production of the conclusion, it is called a
conclusion of the reason. In the proposition: All men are mortal, are contained the propositions: Some men
are mortal, Nothing that is not mortal is a man, and these are therefore immediate conclusions from the first.
On the other hand, the proposition: all the learned are mortal, is not contained in the main proposition (for the
conception of a learned man does not occur in it), and it can be deduced from the main proposition only by
means of a mediating judgement.
The Critique of Pure Reason
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. 121
Page No 126
In every syllogism I first cogitate a rule (the major) by means of the understanding. In the next place I
subsume a cognition under the condition of the rule (and this is the minor) by means of the judgement. And
finally I determine my cognition by means of the predicate of the rule (this is the conclusio), consequently, I
determine it a priori by means of the reason. The relations, therefore, which the major proposition, as the rule,
represents between a cognition and its condition, constitute the different kinds of syllogisms. These are just
threefold analogously with all judgements, in so far as they differ in the mode of expressing the relation of a
cognition in the understanding namely, categorical, hypothetical, and disjunctive.
When as often happens, the conclusion is a judgement which may follow from other given judgements,
through which a perfectly different object is cogitated, I endeavour to discover in the understanding whether
the assertion in this conclusion does not stand under certain conditions according to a general rule. If I find
such a condition, and if the object mentioned in the conclusion can be subsumed under the given condition,
then this conclusion follows from a rule which is also valid for other objects of cognition. From this we see
that reason endeavours to subject the great variety of the cognitions of the understanding to the smallest
possible number of principles (general conditions), and thus to produce in it the highest unity.
C. OF THE PURE USE OF REASON.
Can we isolate reason, and, if so, is it in this case a peculiar source of conceptions and judgements which
spring from it alone, and through which it can be applied to objects; or is it merely a subordinate faculty,
whose duty it is to give a certain form to given cognitions a form which is called logical, and through which
the cognitions of the understanding are subordinated to each other, and lower rules to higher (those, to wit,
whose condition comprises in its sphere the condition of the others), in so far as this can be done by
comparison? This is the question which we have at present to answer. Manifold variety of rules and unity of
principles is a requirement of reason, for the purpose of bringing the understanding into complete accordance
with itself, just as understanding subjects the manifold content of intuition to conceptions, and thereby
introduces connection into it. But this principle prescribes no law to objects, and does not contain any ground
of the possibility of cognizing or of determining them as such, but is merely a subjective law for the proper
arrangement of the content of the understanding. The purpose of this law is, by a comparison of the
conceptions of the understanding, to reduce them to the smallest possible number, although, at the same time,
it does not justify us in demanding from objects themselves such a uniformity as might contribute to the
convenience and the enlargement of the sphere of the understanding, or in expecting that it will itself thus
receive from them objective validity. In one word, the question is: "does reason in itself, that is, does pure
reason contain a priori synthetical principles and rules, and what are those principles?"
The formal and logical procedure of reason in syllogisms gives us sufficient information in regard to the
ground on which the transcendental principle of reason in its pure synthetical cognition will rest.
1. Reason, as observed in the syllogistic process, is not applicable to intuitions, for the purpose of subjecting
them to rules for this is the province of the understanding with its categories but to conceptions and
judgements. If pure reason does apply to objects and the intuition of them, it does so not immediately, but
mediately through the understanding and its judgements, which have a direct relation to the senses and their
intuition, for the purpose of determining their objects. The unity of reason is therefore not the unity of a
possible experience, but is essentially different from this unity, which is that of the understanding. That
everything which happens has a cause, is not a principle cognized and prescribed by reason. This principle
makes the unity of experience possible and borrows nothing from reason, which, without a reference to
possible experience, could never have produced by means of mere conceptions any such synthetical unity.
2. Reason, in its logical use, endeavours to discover the general condition of its judgement (the conclusion),
and a syllogism is itself nothing but a judgement by means of the subsumption of its condition under a
general rule (the major). Now as this rule may itself be subjected to the same process of reason, and thus the
The Critique of Pure Reason
I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance. 122
Page No 127
condition of the condition be sought (by means of a prosyllogism) as long as the process can be continued, it
is very manifest that the peculiar principle of reason in its logical use is to find for the conditioned cognition
of the understanding the unconditioned whereby the unity of the former is completed.
But this logical maxim cannot be a principle of pure reason, unless we admit that, if the conditioned is given,
the whole series of conditions subordinated to one another a series which is consequently itself
unconditioned is also given, that is, contained in the object and its connection.
But this principle of pure reason is evidently synthetical; for, analytically, the conditioned certainly relates to
some condition, but not to the unconditioned. From this principle also there must originate different
synthetical propositions, of which the pure understanding is perfectly ignorant, for it has to do only with
objects of a possible experience, the cognition and synthesis of which is always conditioned. The
unconditioned, if it does really exist, must be especially considered in regard to the determinations which
distinguish it from whatever is conditioned, and will thus afford us material for many a priori synthetical
propositions.
The principles resulting from this highest principle of pure reason will, however, be transcendent in relation
to phenomena, that is to say, it will be impossible to make any adequate empirical use of this principle. It is
therefore completely different from all principles of the understanding, the use made of which is entirely
immanent, their object and purpose being merely the possibility of experience. Now our duty in the
transcendental dialectic is as follows. To discover whether the principle that the series of conditions (in the
synthesis of phenomena, or of thought in general) extends to the unconditioned is objectively true, or not;
what consequences result therefrom affecting the empirical use of the understanding, or rather whether there
exists any such objectively valid proposition of reason, and whether it is not, on the contrary, a merely logical
precept which directs us to ascend perpetually to still higher conditions, to approach completeness in the
series of them, and thus to introduce into our cognition the highest possible unity of reason. We must
ascertain, I say, whether this requirement of reason has not been regarded, by a misunderstanding, as a
transcendental principle of pure reason, which postulates a thorough completeness in the series of conditions
in objects themselves. We must show, moreover, the misconceptions and illusions that intrude into
syllogisms, the major proposition of which pure reason has supplied a proposition which has perhaps more
of the character of a petitio than of a postulatum and that proceed from experience upwards to its conditions.
The solution of these problems is our task in transcendental dialectic, which we are about to expose even at
its source, that lies deep in human reason. We shall divide it into two parts, the first of which will treat of the
transcendent conceptions of pure reason, the second of transcendent and dialectical syllogisms.
BOOK I. OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON.
The conceptions of pure reason we do not here speak of the possibility of them are not obtained by
reflection, but by inference or conclusion. The conceptions of understanding are also cogitated a priori
antecedently to experience, and render it possible; but they contain nothing but the unity of reflection upon
phenomena, in so far as these must necessarily belong to a possible empirical consciousness. Through them
alone are cognition and the determination of an object possible. It is from them, accordingly, that we receive
material for reasoning, and antecedently to them we possess no a priori conceptions of objects from which
they might be deduced, On the other hand, the sole basis of their objective reality consists in the necessity
imposed on them, as containing the intellectual form of all experience, of restricting their application and
influence to the sphere of experience.
But the term, conception of reason, or rational conception, itself indicates that it does not confine itself within
the limits of experience, because its objectmatter is a cognition, of which every empirical cognition is but a
part nay, the whole of possible experience may be itself but a part of it a cognition to which no actual
experience ever fully attains, although it does always pertain to it. The aim of rational conceptions is the
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK I. OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON. 123
Page No 128
comprehension, as that of the conceptions of understanding is the understanding of perceptions. If they
contain the unconditioned, they relate to that to which all experience is subordinate, but which is never itself
an object of experience that towards which reason tends in all its conclusions from experience, and by the
standard of which it estimates the degree of their empirical use, but which is never itself an element in an
empirical synthesis. If, notwithstanding, such conceptions possess objective validity, they may be called
conceptus ratiocinati (conceptions legitimately concluded); in cases where they do not, they have been
admitted on account of having the appearance of being correctly concluded, and may be called conceptus
ratiocinantes (sophistical conceptions). But as this can only be sufficiently demonstrated in that part of our
treatise which relates to the dialectical conclusions of reason, we shall omit any consideration of it in this
place. As we called the pure conceptions of the understanding categories, we shall also distinguish those of
pure reason by a new name and call them transcendental ideas. These terms, however, we must in the first
place explain and justify.
SECTION I Of Ideas in General.
Despite the great wealth of words which European languages possess, the thinker finds himself often at a loss
for an expression exactly suited to his conception, for want of which he is unable to make himself intelligible
either to others or to himself. To coin new words is a pretension to legislation in language which is seldom
successful; and, before recourse is taken to so desperate an expedient, it is advisable to examine the dead and
learned languages, with the hope and the probability that we may there meet with some adequate expression
of the notion we have in our minds. In this case, even if the original meaning of the word has become
somewhat uncertain, from carelessness or want of caution on the part of the authors of it, it is always better to
adhere to and confirm its proper meaning even although it may be doubtful whether it was formerly used in
exactly this sense than to make our labour vain by want of sufficient care to render ourselves intelligible.
For this reason, when it happens that there exists only a single word to express a certain conception, and this
word, in its usual acceptation, is thoroughly adequate to the conception, the accurate distinction of which
from related conceptions is of great importance, we ought not to employ the expression improvidently, or, for
the sake of variety and elegance of style, use it as a synonym for other cognate words. It is our duty, on the
contrary, carefully to preserve its peculiar signification, as otherwise it easily happens that when the attention
of the reader is no longer particularly attracted to the expression, and it is lost amid the multitude of other
words of very different import, the thought which it conveyed, and which it alone conveyed, is lost with it.
Plato employed the expression idea in a way that plainly showed he meant by it something which is never
derived from the senses, but which far transcends even the conceptions of the understanding (with which
Aristotle occupied himself), inasmuch as in experience nothing perfectly corresponding to them could be
found. Ideas are, according to him, archetypes of things themselves, and not merely keys to possible
experiences, like the categories. In his view they flow from the highest reason, by which they have been
imparted to human reason, which, however, exists no longer in its original state, but is obliged with great
labour to recall by reminiscence which is called philosophy the old but now sadly obscured ideas. I will
not here enter upon any literary investigation of the sense which this sublime philosopher attached to this
expression. I shall content myself with remarking that it is nothing unusual, in common conversation as well
as in written works, by comparing the thoughts which an author has delivered upon a subject, to understand
him better than he understood himself inasmuch as he may not have sufficiently determined his conception,
and thus have sometimes spoken, nay even thought, in opposition to his own opinions.
Plato perceived very clearly that our faculty of cognition has the feeling of a much higher vocation than that
of merely spelling out phenomena according to synthetical unity, for the purpose of being able to read them
as experience, and that our reason naturally raises itself to cognitions far too elevated to admit of the
possibility of an object given by experience corresponding to them cognitions which are nevertheless real,
and are not mere phantoms of the brain.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I Of Ideas in General. 124
Page No 129
This philosopher found his ideas especially in all that is practical,* that is, which rests upon freedom, which
in its turn ranks under cognitions that are the peculiar product of reason. He who would derive from
experience the conceptions of virtue, who would make (as many have really done) that, which at best can but
serve as an imperfectly illustrative example, a model for or the formation of a perfectly adequate idea on the
subject, would in fact transform virtue into a nonentity changeable according to time and circumstance and
utterly incapable of being employed as a rule. On the contrary, every one is conscious that, when any one is
held up to him as a model of virtue, he compares this socalled model with the true original which he
possesses in his own mind and values him according to this standard. But this standard is the idea of virtue, in
relation to which all possible objects of experience are indeed serviceable as examples proofs of the
practicability in a certain degree of that which the conception of virtue demands but certainly not as
archetypes. That the actions of man will never be in perfect accordance with all the requirements of the pure
ideas of reason, does not prove the thought to be chimerical. For only through this idea are all judgements as
to moral merit or demerit possible; it consequently lies at the foundation of every approach to moral
perfection, however far removed from it the obstacles in human nature indeterminable as to degree may
keep us.
*He certainly extended the application of his conception to speculative cognitions also, provided they were
given pure and completely a priori, nay, even to mathematics, although this science cannot possess an object
otherwhere than in Possible experience. I cannot follow him in this, and as little can I follow him in his
mystical deduction of these ideas, or in his hypostatization of them; although, in truth, the elevated and
exaggerated language which he employed in describing them is quite capable of an interpretation more
subdued and more in accordance with fact and the nature of things.
The Platonic Republic has become proverbial as an example and a striking one of imaginary perfection,
such as can exist only in the brain of the idle thinker; and Brucker ridicules the philosopher for maintaining
that a prince can never govern well, unless he is participant in the ideas. But we should do better to follow up
this thought and, where this admirable thinker leaves us without assistance, employ new efforts to place it in
clearer light, rather than carelessly fling it aside as useless, under the very miserable and pernicious pretext of
impracticability. A constitution of the greatest possible human freedom according to laws, by which the
liberty of every individual can consist with the liberty of every other (not of the greatest possible happiness,
for this follows necessarily from the former), is, to say the least, a necessary idea, which must be placed at the
foundation not only of the first plan of the constitution of a state, but of all its laws. And, in this, it not
necessary at the outset to take account of the obstacles which lie in our way obstacles which perhaps do not
necessarily arise from the character of human nature, but rather from the previous neglect of true ideas in
legislation. For there is nothing more pernicious and more unworthy of a philosopher, than the vulgar appeal
to a socalled adverse experience, which indeed would not have existed, if those institutions had been
established at the proper time and in accordance with ideas; while, instead of this, conceptions, crude for the
very reason that they have been drawn from experience, have marred and frustrated all our better views and
intentions. The more legislation and government are in harmony with this idea, the more rare do punishments
become and thus it is quite reasonable to maintain, as Plato did, that in a perfect state no punishments at all
would be necessary. Now although a perfect state may never exist, the idea is not on that account the less just,
which holds up this maximum as the archetype or standard of a constitution, in order to bring legislative
government always nearer and nearer to the greatest possible perfection. For at what precise degree human
nature must stop in its progress, and how wide must be the chasm which must necessarily exist between the
idea and its realization, are problems which no one can or ought to determine and for this reason, that it is
the destination of freedom to overstep all assigned limits between itself and the idea.
But not only in that wherein human reason is a real causal agent and where ideas are operative causes (of
actions and their objects), that is to say, in the region of ethics, but also in regard to nature herself, Plato saw
clear proofs of an origin from ideas. A plant, and animal, the regular order of nature probably also the
disposition of the whole universe give manifest evidence that they are possible only by means of and
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I Of Ideas in General. 125
Page No 130
according to ideas; that, indeed, no one creature, under the individual conditions of its existence, perfectly
harmonizes with the idea of the most perfect of its kind just as little as man with the idea of humanity,
which nevertheless he bears in his soul as the archetypal standard of his actions; that, notwithstanding, these
ideas are in the highest sense individually, unchangeably, and completely determined, and are the original
causes of things; and that the totality of connected objects in the universe is alone fully adequate to that idea.
Setting aside the exaggerations of expression in the writings of this philosopher, the mental power exhibited
in this ascent from the ectypal mode of regarding the physical world to the architectonic connection thereof
according to ends, that is, ideas, is an effort which deserves imitation and claims respect. But as regards the
principles of ethics, of legislation, and of religion, spheres in which ideas alone render experience possible,
although they never attain to full expression therein, he has vindicated for himself a position of peculiar
merit, which is not appreciated only because it is judged by the very empirical rules, the validity of which as
principles is destroyed by ideas. For as regards nature, experience presents us with rules and is the source of
truth, but in relation to ethical laws experience is the parent of illusion, and it is in the highest degree
reprehensible to limit or to deduce the laws which dictate what I ought to do, from what is done.
We must, however, omit the consideration of these important subjects, the development of which is in reality
the peculiar duty and dignity of philosophy, and confine ourselves for the present to the more humble but not
less useful task of preparing a firm foundation for those majestic edifices of moral science. For this
foundation has been hitherto insecure from the many subterranean passages which reason in its confident but
vain search for treasures has made in all directions. Our present duty is to make ourselves perfectly
acquainted with the transcendental use made of pure reason, its principles and ideas, that we may be able
properly to determine and value its influence and real worth. But before bringing these introductory remarks
to a close, I beg those who really have philosophy at heart and their number is but small if they shall find
themselves convinced by the considerations following as well as by those above, to exert themselves to
preserve to the expression idea its original signification, and to take care that it be not lost among those other
expressions by which all sorts of representations are loosely designated that the interests of science may not
thereby suffer. We are in no want of words to denominate adequately every mode of representation, without
the necessity of encroaching upon terms which are proper to others. The following is a graduated list of them.
The genus is representation in general (representation. Under it stands representation with consciousness
(perceptio). A perception which relates solely to the subject as a modification of its state, is a sensation
(sensatio), an objective perception is a cognition (cognitio). A cognition is either an intuition or a conception
(intuitus vel conceptus). The former has an immediate relation to the object and is singular and individual; the
latter has but a mediate relation, by means of a characteristic mark which may be common to several things.
A conception is either empirical or pure. A pure conception, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding
alone, and is not the conception of a pure sensuous image, is called notio. A conception formed from notions,
which transcends the possibility of experience, is an idea, or a conception of reason. To one who has
accustomed himself to these distinctions, it must be quite intolerable to hear the representation of the colour
red called an idea. It ought not even to be called a notion or conception of understanding.
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas.
Transcendental analytic showed us how the mere logical form of our cognition can contain the origin of pure
conceptions a priori, conceptions which represent objects antecedently to all experience, or rather, indicate
the synthetical unity which alone renders possible an empirical cognition of objects. The form of
judgements converted into a conception of the synthesis of intuitions produced the categories which direct
the employment of the understanding in experience. This consideration warrants us to expect that the form of
syllogisms, when applied to synthetical unity of intuitions, following the rule of the categories, will contain
the origin of particular a priori conceptions, which we may call pure conceptions of reason or transcendental
ideas, and which will determine the use of the understanding in the totality of experience according to
principles.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas. 126
Page No 131
The function of reason in arguments consists in the universality of a cognition according to conceptions, and
the syllogism itself is a judgement which is determined a priori in the whole extent of its condition. The
proposition: "Caius is mortal," is one which may be obtained from experience by the aid of the understanding
alone; but my wish is to find a conception which contains the condition under which the predicate of this
judgement is given in this case, the conception of man and after subsuming under this condition, taken in
its whole extent (all men are mortal), I determine according to it the cognition of the object thought, and say:
"Caius is mortal."
Hence, in the conclusion of a syllogism we restrict a predicate to a certain object, after having thought it in
the major in its whole extent under a certain condition. This complete quantity of the extent in relation to
such a condition is called universality (universalitas). To this corresponds totality (universitas) of conditions
in the synthesis of intuitions. The transcendental conception of reason is therefore nothing else than the
conception of the totality of the conditions of a given conditioned. Now as the unconditioned alone renders
possible totality of conditions, and, conversely, the totality of conditions is itself always unconditioned; a
pure rational conception in general can be defined and explained by means of the conception of the
unconditioned, in so far as it contains a basis for the synthesis of the conditioned.
To the number of modes of relation which the understanding cogitates by means of the categories, the
number of pure rational conceptions will correspond. We must therefore seek for, first, an unconditioned of
the categorical synthesis in a subject; secondly, of the hypothetical synthesis of the members of a series;
thirdly, of the disjunctive synthesis of parts in a system.
There are exactly the same number of modes of syllogisms, each of which proceeds through prosyllogisms to
the unconditioned one to the subject which cannot be employed as predicate, another to the presupposition
which supposes nothing higher than itself, and the third to an aggregate of the members of the complete
division of a conception. Hence the pure rational conceptions of totality in the synthesis of conditions have a
necessary foundation in the nature of human reason at least as modes of elevating the unity of the
understanding to the unconditioned. They may have no valid application, corresponding to their
transcendental employment, in concreto, and be thus of no greater utility than to direct the understanding
how, while extending them as widely as possible, to maintain its exercise and application in perfect
consistence and harmony.
But, while speaking here of the totality of conditions and of the unconditioned as the common title of all
conceptions of reason, we again light upon an expression which we find it impossible to dispense with, and
which nevertheless, owing to the ambiguity attaching to it from long abuse, we cannot employ with safety.
The word absolute is one of the few words which, in its original signification, was perfectly adequate to the
conception it was intended to convey a conception which no other word in the same language exactly suits,
and the loss or, which is the same thing, the incautious and loose employment of which must be followed
by the loss of the conception itself. And, as it is a conception which occupies much of the attention of reason,
its loss would be greatly to the detriment of all transcendental philosophy. The word absolute is at present
frequently used to denote that something can be predicated of a thing considered in itself and intrinsically. In
this sense absolutely possible would signify that which is possible in itself (interne) which is, in fact, the
least that one can predicate of an object. On the other hand, it is sometimes employed to indicate that a thing
is valid in all respects for example, absolute sovereignty. Absolutely possible would in this sense signify
that which is possible in all relations and in every respect; and this is the most that can be predicated of the
possibility of a thing. Now these significations do in truth frequently coincide. Thus, for example, that which
is intrinsically impossible, is also impossible in all relations, that is, absolutely impossible. But in most cases
they differ from each other toto caelo, and I can by no means conclude that, because a thing is in itself
possible, it is also possible in all relations, and therefore absolutely. Nay, more, I shall in the sequel show that
absolute necessity does not by any means depend on internal necessity, and that, therefore, it must not be
considered as synonymous with it. Of an opposite which is intrinsically impossible, we may affirm that it is
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas. 127
Page No 132
in all respects impossible, and that, consequently, the thing itself, of which this is the opposite, is absolutely
necessary; but I cannot reason conversely and say, the opposite of that which is absolutely necessary is
intrinsically impossible, that is, that the absolute necessity of things is an internal necessity. For this internal
necessity is in certain cases a mere empty word with which the least conception cannot be connected, while
the conception of the necessity of a thing in all relations possesses very peculiar determinations. Now as the
loss of a conception of great utility in speculative science cannot be a matter of indifference to the
philosopher, I trust that the proper determination and careful preservation of the expression on which the
conception depends will likewise be not indifferent to him.
In this enlarged signification, then, shall I employ the word absolute, in opposition to that which is valid only
in some particular respect; for the latter is restricted by conditions, the former is valid without any restriction
whatever.
Now the transcendental conception of reason has for its object nothing else than absolute totality in the
synthesis of conditions and does not rest satisfied till it has attained to the absolutely, that is, in all respects
and relations, unconditioned. For pure reason leaves to the understanding everything that immediately relates
to the object of intuition or rather to their synthesis in imagination. The former restricts itself to the absolute
totality in the employment of the conceptions of the understanding and aims at carrying out the synthetical
unity which is cogitated in the category, even to the unconditioned. This unity may hence be called the
rational unity of phenomena, as the other, which the category expresses, may be termed the unity of the
understanding. Reason, therefore, has an immediate relation to the use of the understanding, not indeed in so
far as the latter contains the ground of possible experience (for the conception of the absolute totality of
conditions is not a conception that can be employed in experience, because no experience is unconditioned),
but solely for the purpose of directing it to a certain unity, of which the understanding has no conception, and
the aim of which is to collect into an absolute whole all acts of the understanding. Hence the objective
employment of the pure conceptions of reason is always transcendent, while that of the pure conceptions of
the understanding must, according to their nature, be always immanent, inasmuch as they are limited to
possible experience.
I understand by idea a necessary conception of reason, to which no corresponding object can be discovered in
the world of sense. Accordingly, the pure conceptions of reason at present under consideration are
transcendental ideas. They are conceptions of pure reason, for they regard all empirical cognition as
determined by means of an absolute totality of conditions. They are not mere fictions, but natural and
necessary products of reason, and have hence a necessary relation to the whole sphere of the exercise of the
understanding. And, finally, they are transcendent, and overstep the limits of all experiences, in which,
consequently, no object can ever be presented that would be perfectly adequate to a transcendental idea.
When we use the word idea, we say, as regards its object (an object of the pure understanding), a great deal,
but as regards its subject (that is, in respect of its reality under conditions of experience), exceedingly little,
because the idea, as the conception of a maximum, can never be completely and adequately presented in
concreto. Now, as in the merely speculative employment of reason the latter is properly the sole aim, and as
in this case the approximation to a conception, which is never attained in practice, is the same thing as if the
conception were nonexistent it is commonly said of the conception of this kind, "it is only an idea." So we
might very well say, "the absolute totality of all phenomena is only an idea," for, as we never can present an
adequate representation of it, it remains for us a problem incapable of solution. On the other hand, as in the
practical use of the understanding we have only to do with action and practice according to rules, an idea of
pure reason can always be given really in concreto, although only partially, nay, it is the indispensable
condition of all practical employment of reason. The practice or execution of the idea is always limited and
defective, but nevertheless within indeterminable boundaries, consequently always under the influence of the
conception of an absolute perfection. And thus the practical idea is always in the highest degree fruitful, and
in relation to real actions indispensably necessary. In the idea, pure reason possesses even causality and the
power of producing that which its conception contains. Hence we cannot say of wisdom, in a disparaging
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas. 128
Page No 133
way, "it is only an idea." For, for the very reason that it is the idea of the necessary unity of all possible aims,
it must be for all practical exertions and endeavours the primitive condition and rule a rule which, if not
constitutive, is at least limitative.
Now, although we must say of the transcendental conceptions of reason, "they are only ideas," we must not,
on this account, look upon them as superfluous and nugatory. For, although no object can be determined by
them, they can be of great utility, unobserved and at the basis of the edifice of the understanding, as the canon
for its extended and selfconsistent exercise a canon which, indeed, does not enable it to cognize more in an
object than it would cognize by the help of its own conceptions, but which guides it more securely in its
cognition. Not to mention that they perhaps render possible a transition from our conceptions of nature and
the nonego to the practical conceptions, and thus produce for even ethical ideas keeping, so to speak, and
connection with the speculative cognitions of reason. The explication of all this must be looked for in the
sequel.
But setting aside, in conformity with our original purpose, the consideration of the practical ideas, we proceed
to contemplate reason in its speculative use alone, nay, in a still more restricted sphere, to wit, in the
transcendental use; and here must strike into the same path which we followed in our deduction of the
categories. That is to say, we shall consider the logical form of the cognition of reason, that we may see
whether reason may not be thereby a source of conceptions which enables us to regard objects in themselves
as determined synthetically a priori, in relation to one or other of the functions of reason.
Reason, considered as the faculty of a certain logical form of cognition, is the faculty of conclusion, that is, of
mediate judgement by means of the subsumption of the condition of a possible judgement under the
condition of a given judgement. The given judgement is the general rule (major). The subsumption of the
condition of another possible judgement under the condition of the rule is the minor. The actual judgement,
which enounces the assertion of the rule in the subsumed case, is the conclusion (conclusio). The rule
predicates something generally under a certain condition. The condition of the rule is satisfied in some
particular case. It follows that what was valid in general under that condition must also be considered as valid
in the particular case which satisfies this condition. It is very plain that reason attains to a cognition, by
means of acts of the understanding which constitute a series of conditions. When I arrive at the proposition,
"All bodies are changeable," by beginning with the more remote cognition (in which the conception of body
does not appear, but which nevertheless contains the condition of that conception), "All compound is
changeable," by proceeding from this to a less remote cognition, which stands under the condition of the
former, "Bodies are compound," and hence to a third, which at length connects for me the remote cognition
(changeable) with the one before me, "Consequently, bodies are changeable" I have arrived at a cognition
(conclusion) through a series of conditions (premisses). Now every series, whose exponent (of the categorical
or hypothetical judgement) is given, can be continued; consequently the same procedure of reason conducts
us to the ratiocinatio polysyllogistica, which is a series of syllogisms, that can be continued either on the side
of the conditions (per prosyllogismos) or of the conditioned (per episyllogismos) to an indefinite extent.
But we very soon perceive that the chain or series of prosyllogisms, that is, of deduced cognitions on the side
of the grounds or conditions of a given cognition, in other words, the ascending series of syllogisms must
have a very different relation to the faculty of reason from that of the descending series, that is, the
progressive procedure of reason on the side of the conditioned by means of episyllogisms. For, as in the
former case the cognition (conclusio) is given only as conditioned, reason can attain to this cognition only
under the presupposition that all the members of the series on the side of the conditions are given (totality in
the series of premisses), because only under this supposition is the judgement we may be considering
possible a priori; while on the side of the conditioned or the inferences, only an incomplete and becoming,
and not a presupposed or given series, consequently only a potential progression, is cogitated. Hence, when a
cognition is contemplated as conditioned, reason is compelled to consider the series of conditions in an
ascending line as completed and given in their totality. But if the very same condition is considered at the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas. 129
Page No 134
same time as the condition of other cognitions, which together constitute a series of inferences or
consequences in a descending line, reason may preserve a perfect indifference, as to how far this progression
may extend a parte posteriori, and whether the totality of this series is possible, because it stands in no need
of such a series for the purpose of arriving at the conclusion before it, inasmuch as this conclusion is
sufficiently guaranteed and determined on grounds a parte priori. It may be the case, that upon the side of the
conditions the series of premisses has a first or highest condition, or it may not possess this, and so be a parte
priori unlimited; but it must, nevertheless, contain totality of conditions, even admitting that we never could
succeed in completely apprehending it; and the whole series must be unconditionally true, if the conditioned,
which is considered as an inference resulting from it, is to be held as true. This is a requirement of reason,
which announces its cognition as determined a priori and as necessary, either in itself and in this case it
needs no grounds to rest upon or, if it is deduced, as a member of a series of grounds, which is itself
unconditionally true.
SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas.
We are not at present engaged with a logical dialectic, which makes complete abstraction of the content of
cognition and aims only at unveiling the illusory appearance in the form of syllogisms. Our subject is
transcendental dialectic, which must contain, completely a priori, the origin of certain cognitions drawn from
pure reason, and the origin of certain deduced conceptions, the object of which cannot be given empirically
and which therefore lie beyond the sphere of the faculty of understanding. We have observed, from the
natural relation which the transcendental use of our cognition, in syllogisms as well as in judgements, must
have to the logical, that there are three kinds of dialectical arguments, corresponding to the three modes of
conclusion, by which reason attains to cognitions on principles; and that in all it is the business of reason to
ascend from the conditioned synthesis, beyond which the understanding never proceeds, to the unconditioned
which the understanding never can reach.
Now the most general relations which can exist in our representations are: 1st, the relation to the subject; 2nd,
the relation to objects, either as phenomena, or as objects of thought in general. If we connect this subdivision
with the main division, all the relations of our representations, of which we can form either a conception or an
idea, are threefold: 1. The relation to the subject; 2. The relation to the manifold of the object as a
phenomenon; 3. The relation to all things in general.
Now all pure conceptions have to do in general with the synthetical unity of representations; conceptions of
pure reason (transcendental ideas), on the other hand, with the unconditional synthetical unity of all
conditions. It follows that all transcendental ideas arrange themselves in three classes, the first of which
contains the absolute (unconditioned) unity of the thinking subject, the second the absolute unity of the series
of the conditions of a phenomenon, the third the absolute unity of the condition of all objects of thought in
general.
The thinking subject is the objectmatter of Psychology; the sum total of all phenomena (the world) is the
objectmatter of Cosmology; and the thing which contains the highest condition of the possibility of all that
is cogitable (the being of all beings) is the objectmatter of all Theology. Thus pure reason presents us with
the idea of a transcendental doctrine of the soul (psychologia rationalis), of a transcendental science of the
world (cosmologia rationalis), and finally of a transcendental doctrine of God (theologia transcendentalis).
Understanding cannot originate even the outline of any of these sciences, even when connected with the
highest logical use of reason, that is, all cogitable syllogisms for the purpose of proceeding from one object
(phenomenon) to all others, even to the utmost limits of the empirical synthesis. They are, on the contrary,
pure and genuine products, or problems, of pure reason.
What modi of the pure conceptions of reason these transcendental ideas are will be fully exposed in the
following chapter. They follow the guiding thread of the categories. For pure reason never relates
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas. 130
Page No 135
immediately to objects, but to the conceptions of these contained in the understanding. In like manner, it will
be made manifest in the detailed explanation of these ideas how reason, merely through the synthetical use
of the same function which it employs in a categorical syllogism, necessarily attains to the conception of the
absolute unity of the thinking subject how the logical procedure in hypothetical ideas necessarily produces
the idea of the absolutely unconditioned in a series of given conditions, and finally how the mere form of
the disjunctive syllogism involves the highest conception of a being of all beings: a thought which at first
sight seems in the highest degree paradoxical.
An objective deduction, such as we were able to present in the case of the categories, is impossible as regards
these transcendental ideas. For they have, in truth, no relation to any object, in experience, for the very reason
that they are only ideas. But a subjective deduction of them from the nature of our reason is possible, and has
been given in the present chapter.
It is easy to perceive that the sole aim of pure reason is the absolute totality of the synthesis on the side of the
conditions, and that it does not concern itself with the absolute completeness on the Part of the conditioned.
For of the former alone does she stand in need, in order to preposit the whole series of conditions, and thus
present them to the understanding a priori. But if we once have a completely (and unconditionally) given
condition, there is no further necessity, in proceeding with the series, for a conception of reason; for the
understanding takes of itself every step downward, from the condition to the conditioned. Thus the
transcendental ideas are available only for ascending in the series of conditions, till we reach the
unconditioned, that is, principles. As regards descending to the conditioned, on the other hand, we find that
there is a widely extensive logical use which reason makes of the laws of the understanding, but that a
transcendental use thereof is impossible; and that when we form an idea of the absolute totality of such a
synthesis, for example, of the whole series of all future changes in the world, this idea is a mere ens rationis,
an arbitrary fiction of thought, and not a necessary presupposition of reason. For the possibility of the
conditioned presupposes the totality of its conditions, but not of its consequences. Consequently, this
conception is not a transcendental idea and it is with these alone that we are at present occupied.
Finally, it is obvious that there exists among the transcendental ideas a certain connection and unity, and that
pure reason, by means of them, collects all its cognitions into one system. From the cognition of self to the
cognition of the world, and through these to the supreme being, the progression is so natural, that it seems to
resemble the logical march of reason from the premisses to the conclusion.* Now whether there lies
unobserved at the foundation of these ideas an analogy of the same kind as exists between the logical and
transcendental procedure of reason, is another of those questions, the answer to which we must not expect till
we arrive at a more advanced stage in our inquiries. In this cursory and preliminary view, we have,
meanwhile, reached our aim. For we have dispelled the ambiguity which attached to the transcendental
conceptions of reason, from their being commonly mixed up with other conceptions in the systems of
philosophers, and not properly distinguished from the conceptions of the understanding; we have exposed
their origin and, thereby, at the same time their determinate number, and presented them in a systematic
connection, and have thus marked out and enclosed a definite sphere for pure reason.
*The science of Metaphysics has for the proper object of its inquiries only three grand ideas: GOD,
FREEDOM, and IMMORTALITY, and it aims at showing, that the second conception, conjoined with the
first, must lead to the third, as a necessary conclusion. All the other subjects with which it occupies itself, are
merely means for the attainment and realization of these ideas. It does not require these ideas for the
construction of a science of nature, but, on the contrary, for the purpose of passing beyond the sphere of
nature. A complete insight into and comprehension of them would render Theology, Ethics, and, through the
conjunction of both, Religion, solely dependent on the speculative faculty of reason. In a systematic
representation of these ideas the abovementioned arrangement the synthetical one would be the most
suitable; but in the investigation which must necessarily precede it, the analytical, which reverses this
arrangement, would be better adapted to our purpose, as in it we should proceed from that which experience
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas. 131
Page No 136
immediately presents to us psychology, to cosmology, and thence to theology.
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON.
It may be said that the object of a merely transcendental idea is something of which we have no conception,
although the idea may be a necessary product of reason according to its original laws. For, in fact, a
conception of an object that is adequate to the idea given by reason, is impossible. For such an object must be
capable of being presented and intuited in a Possible experience. But we should express our meaning better,
and with less risk of being misunderstood, if we said that we can have no knowledge of an object, which
perfectly corresponds to an idea, although we may possess a problematical conception thereof.
Now the transcendental (subjective) reality at least of the pure conceptions of reason rests upon the fact that
we are led to such ideas by a necessary procedure of reason. There must therefore be syllogisms which
contain no empirical premisses, and by means of which we conclude from something that we do know, to
something of which we do not even possess a conception, to which we, nevertheless, by an unavoidable
illusion, ascribe objective reality. Such arguments are, as regards their result, rather to be termed sophisms
than syllogisms, although indeed, as regards their origin, they are very well entitled to the latter name,
inasmuch as they are not fictions or accidental products of reason, but are necessitated by its very nature.
They are sophisms, not of men, but of pure reason herself, from which the Wisest cannot free himself. After
long labour he may be able to guard against the error, but he can never be thoroughly rid of the illusion which
continually mocks and misleads him.
Of these dialectical arguments there are three kinds, corresponding to the number of the ideas which their
conclusions present. In the argument or syllogism of the first class, I conclude, from the transcendental
conception of the subject contains no manifold, the absolute unity of the subject itself, of which I cannot in
this manner attain to a conception. This dialectical argument I shall call the transcendental paralogism. The
second class of sophistical arguments is occupied with the transcendental conception of the absolute totality
of the series of conditions for a given phenomenon, and I conclude, from the fact that I have always a
selfcontradictory conception of the unconditioned synthetical unity of the series upon one side, the truth of
the opposite unity, of which I have nevertheless no conception. The condition of reason in these dialectical
arguments, I shall term the antinomy of pure reason. Finally, according to the third kind of sophistical
argument, I conclude, from the totality of the conditions of thinking objects in general, in so far as they can
be given, the absolute synthetical unity of all conditions of the possibility of things in general; that is, from
things which I do not know in their mere transcendental conception, I conclude a being of all beings which I
know still less by means of a transcendental conception, and of whose unconditioned necessity I can form no
conception whatever. This dialectical argument I shall call the ideal of pure reason.
CHAPTER I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason.
The logical paralogism consists in the falsity of an argument in respect of its form, be the content what it
may. But a transcendental paralogism has a transcendental foundation, and concludes falsely, while the form
is correct and unexceptionable. In this manner the paralogism has its foundation in the nature of human
reason, and is the parent of an unavoidable, though not insoluble, mental illusion.
We now come to a conception which was not inserted in the general list of transcendental conceptions. and
yet must be reckoned with them, but at the same time without in the least altering, or indicating a deficiency
in that table. This is the conception, or, if the term is preferred, the judgement, "I think." But it is readily
perceived that this thought is as it were the vehicle of all conceptions in general, and consequently of
transcendental conceptions also, and that it is therefore regarded as a transcendental conception, although it
can have no peculiar claim to be so ranked, inasmuch as its only use is to indicate that all thought is
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 132
Page No 137
accompanied by consciousness. At the same time, pure as this conception is from empirical content
(impressions of the senses), it enables us to distinguish two different kinds of objects. "I," as thinking, am an
object of the internal sense, and am called soul. That which is an object of the external senses is called body.
Thus the expression, "I," as a thinking being, designates the objectmatter of psychology, which may be
called "the rational doctrine of the soul," inasmuch as in this science I desire to know nothing of the soul but
what, independently of all experience (which determines me in concreto), may be concluded from this
conception "I," in so far as it appears in all thought.
Now, the rational doctrine of the soul is really an undertaking of this kind. For if the smallest empirical
element of thought, if any particular perception of my internal state, were to be introduced among the grounds
of cognition of this science, it would not be a rational, but an empirical doctrine of the soul. We have thus
before us a pretended science, raised upon the single proposition, "I think," whose foundation or want of
foundation we may very properly, and agreeably with the nature of a transcendental philosophy, here
examine. It ought not to be objected that in this proposition, which expresses the perception of one's self, an
internal experience is asserted, and that consequently the rational doctrine of the soul which is founded upon
it, is not pure, but partly founded upon an empirical principle. For this internal perception is nothing more
than the mere apperception, "I think," which in fact renders all transcendental conceptions possible, in which
we say, "I think substance, cause, etc." For internal experience in general and its possibility, or perception in
general, and its relation to other perceptions, unless some particular distinction or determination thereof is
empirically given, cannot be regarded as empirical cognition, but as cognition of the empirical, and belongs
to the investigation of the possibility of every experience, which is certainly transcendental. The smallest
object of experience (for example, only pleasure or pain), that should be included in the general
representation of selfconsciousness, would immediately change the rational into an empirical psychology.
"I think" is therefore the only text of rational psychology, from which it must develop its whole system. It is
manifest that this thought, when applied to an object (myself), can contain nothing but transcendental
predicates thereof; because the least empirical predicate would destroy the purity of the science and its
independence of all experience.
But we shall have to follow here the guidance of the categories only, as in the present case a thing, "I," as
thinking being, is at first given, we shall not indeed change the order of the categories as it stands in the
table but begin at the category of substance, by which at the a thing a thing is represented and proceeds
backwards through the series. The topic of the rational doctrine of the soul, from which everything else it
may contain must be deduced, is accordingly as follows:
1 2
The Soul is SUBSTANCE As regards its quality
it is SIMPLE
3
As regards the different
times in which it exists,
it is numerically identical,
that is UNITY, not Plurality.
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 133
Page No 138
4
It is in relation to possible objects in space*
*The reader, who may not so easily perceive the psychological sense of these expressions, taken here in their
transcendental abstraction, and cannot guess why the latter attribute of the soul belongs to the category of
existence, will find the expressions sufficiently explained and justified in the sequel. I have, moreover, to
apologize for the Latin terms which have been employed,instead of their German synonyms, contrary to the
rules of correct writing. But I judged it better to sacrifice elegance to perspicuity.
From these elements originate all the conceptions of pure psychology, by combination alone, without the aid
of any other principle. This substance, merely as an object of the internal sense, gives the conception of
Immateriality; as simple substance, that of Incorruptibility; its identity, as intellectual substance, gives the
conception of Personality; all these three together, Spirituality. Its relation to objects in space gives us the
conception of connection (commercium) with bodies. Thus it represents thinking substance as the principle of
life in matter, that is, as a soul (anima), and as the ground of Animality; and this, limited and determined by
the conception of spirituality, gives us that of Immortality.
Now to these conceptions relate four paralogisms of a transcendental psychology, which is falsely held to be
a science of pure reason. touching the nature of our thinking being. We can, however, lay at the foundation of
this science nothing but the simple and in itself perfectly contentless representation "I which cannot even be
called a conception, but merely a consciousness which accompanies all conceptions. By this "I," or "He," or
"It," who or which thinks, nothing more is represented than a transcendental subject of thought = x, which is
cognized only by means of the thoughts that are its predicates, and of which, apart from these, we cannot
form the least conception. Hence in a perpetual circle, inasmuch as we must always employ it, in order to
frame any judgement respecting it. And this inconvenience we find it impossible to rid ourselves of, because
consciousness in itself is not so much a representation distinguishing a particular object, as a form of
representation in general, in so far as it may be termed cognition; for in and by cognition alone do I think
anything.
It must, however, appear extraordinary at first sight that the condition under which I think, and which is
consequently a property of my subject, should be held to be likewise valid for every existence which thinks,
and that we can presume to base upon a seemingly empirical proposition a judgement which is apodeictic and
universal, to wit, that everything which thinks is constituted as the voice of my consciousness declares it to
be, that is, as a selfconscious being. The cause of this belief is to be found in the fact that we necessarily
attribute to things a priori all the properties which constitute conditions under which alone we can cogitate
them. Now I cannot obtain the least representation of a thinking being by means of external experience, but
solely through selfconsciousness. Such objects are consequently nothing more than the transference of this
consciousness of mine to other things which can only thus be represented as thinking beings. The proposition,
"I think," is, in the present case, understood in a problematical sense, not in so far as it contains a perception
of an existence (like the Cartesian "Cogito, ergo sum"),* but in regard to its mere possibility for the purpose
of discovering what properties may be inferred from so simple a proposition and predicated of the subject of
it.
*["I think, therefore I am."]
If at the foundation of our pure rational cognition of thinking beings there lay more than the mere Cogito if
we could likewise call in aid observations on the play of our thoughts, and the thence derived natural laws of
the thinking self, there would arise an empirical psychology which would be a kind of physiology of the
internal sense and might possibly be capable of explaining the phenomena of that sense. But it could never be
available for discovering those properties which do not belong to possible experience (such as the quality of
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 134
Page No 139
simplicity), nor could it make any apodeictic enunciation on the nature of thinking beings: it would therefore
not be a rational psychology.
Now, as the proposition "I think" (in the problematical sense) contains the form of every judgement in
general and is the constant accompaniment of all the categories, it is manifest that conclusions are drawn
from it only by a transcendental employment of the understanding. This use of the understanding excludes all
empirical elements; and we cannot, as has been shown above, have any favourable conception beforehand of
its procedure. We shall therefore follow with a critical eye this proposition through all the predicaments of
pure psychology; but we shall, for brevity's sake, allow this examination to proceed in an uninterrupted
connection.
Before entering on this task, however, the following general remark may help to quicken our attention to this
mode of argument. It is not merely through my thinking that I cognize an object, but only through my
determining a given intuition in relation to the unity of consciousness in which all thinking consists. It
follows that I cognize myself, not through my being conscious of myself as thinking, but only when I am
conscious of the intuition of myself as determined in relation to the function of thought. All the modi of
selfconsciousness in thought are hence not conceptions of objects (conceptions of the understanding
categories); they are mere logical functions, which do not present to thought an object to be cognized, and
cannot therefore present my Self as an object. Not the consciousness of the determining, but only that of the
determinable self, that is, of my internal intuition (in so far as the manifold contained in it can be connected
conformably with the general condition of the unity of apperception in thought), is the object.
1. In all judgements I am the determining subject of that relation which constitutes a judgement. But that the I
which thinks, must be considered as in thought always a subject, and as a thing which cannot be a predicate
to thought, is an apodeictic and identical proposition. But this proposition does not signify that I, as an object,
am, for myself, a selfsubsistent being or substance. This latter statement an ambitious one requires to be
supported by data which are not to be discovered in thought; and are perhaps (in so far as I consider the
thinking self merely as such) not to be discovered in the thinking self at all.
2. That the I or Ego of apperception, and consequently in all thought, is singular or simple, an;3 cannot be
resolved into a plurality of subjects, and therefore indicates a logically simple subject this is selfevident
from the very conception of an Ego, and is consequently an analytical proposition. But this is not tantamount
to declaring that the thinking Ego is a simple substance for this would be a synthetical proposition. The
conception of substance always relates to intuitions, which with me cannot be other than sensuous, and which
consequently lie completely out of the sphere of the understanding and its thought: but to this sphere belongs
the affirmation that the Ego is simple in thought. It would indeed be surprising, if the conception of
"substance," which in other cases requires so much labour to distinguish from the other elements presented by
intuition so much trouble, too, to discover whether it can be simple (as in the case of the parts of matter)
should be presented immediately to me, as if by revelation, in the poorest mental representation of all.
3. The proposition of the identity of my Self amidst all the manifold representations of which I am conscious,
is likewise a proposition lying in the conceptions themselves, and is consequently analytical. But this identity
of the subject, of which I am conscious in all its representations, does not relate to or concern the intuition of
the subject, by which it is given as an object. This proposition cannot therefore enounce the identity of the
person, by which is understood the consciousness of the identity of its own substance as a thinking being in
all change and variation of circumstances. To prove this, we should require not a mere analysis of the
proposition, but synthetical judgements based upon a given intuition.
4. I distinguish my own existence, as that of a thinking being, from that of other things external to me
among which my body also is reckoned. This is also an analytical proposition, for other things are exactly
those which I think as different or distinguished from myself. But whether this consciousness of myself is
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 135
Page No 140
possible without things external to me; and whether therefore I can exist merely as a thinking being (without
being man) cannot be known or inferred from this proposition.
Thus we have gained nothing as regards the cognition of myself as object, by the analysis of the
consciousness of my Self in thought. The logical exposition of thought in general is mistaken for a
metaphysical determination of the object.
Our Critique would be an investigation utterly superfluous, if there existed a possibility of proving a priori,
that all thinking beings are in themselves simple substances, as such, therefore, possess the inseparable
attribute of personality, and are conscious of their existence apart from and unconnected with matter. For we
should thus have taken a step beyond the world of sense, and have penetrated into the sphere of noumena;
and in this case the right could not be denied us of extending our knowledge in this sphere, of establishing
ourselves, and, under a favouring star, appropriating to ourselves possessions in it. For the proposition:
"Every thinking being, as such, is simple substance," is an a priori synthetical proposition; because in the first
place it goes beyond the conception which is the subject of it, and adds to the mere notion of a thinking being
the mode of its existence, and in the second place annexes a predicate (that of simplicity) to the latter
conception a predicate which it could not have discovered in the sphere of experience. It would follow that a
priori synthetical propositions are possible and legitimate, not only, as we have maintained, in relation to
objects of possible experience, and as principles of the possibility of this experience itself, but are applicable
to things in themselves an inference which makes an end of the whole of this Critique, and obliges us to fall
back on the old mode of metaphysical procedure. But indeed the danger is not so great, if we look a little
closer into the question.
There lurks in the procedure of rational Psychology a paralogism, which is represented in the following
syllogism:
That which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subject, does not exist otherwise than as subject, and is
therefore substance.
A thinking being, considered merely as such, cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subject.
Therefore it exists also as such, that is, as substance.
In the major we speak of a being that can be cogitated generally and in every relation, consequently as it may
be given in intuition. But in the minor we speak of the same being only in so far as it regards itself as subject,
relatively to thought and the unity of consciousness, but not in relation to intuition, by which it is presented as
an object to thought. Thus the conclusion is here arrived at by a Sophisma figurae dictionis.*
*Thought is taken in the two premisses in two totally different senses. In the major it is considered as relating
and applying to objects in general, consequently to objects of intuition also. In the minor, we understand it as
relating merely to selfconsciousness. In this sense, we do not cogitate an object, but merely the relation to
the selfconsciousness of the subject, as the form of thought. In the former premiss we speak of things which
cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subjects. In the second, we do not speak of things, but of thought all
objects being abstracted), in which the Ego is always the subject of consciousness. Hence the conclusion
cannot be, "I cannot exist otherwise than as subject"; but only "I can, in cogitating my existence, employ my
Ego only as the subject of the judgement." But this is an identical proposition, and throws no light on the
mode of my existence.
That this famous argument is a mere paralogism, will be plain to any one who will consider the general
remark which precedes our exposition of the principles of the pure understanding, and the section on
noumena. For it was there proved that the conception of a thing, which can exist per se only as a subject and
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 136
Page No 141
never as a predicate, possesses no objective reality; that is to say, we can never know whether there exists any
object to correspond to the conception; consequently, the conception is nothing more than a conception, and
from it we derive no proper knowledge. If this conception is to indicate by the term substance, an object that
can be given, if it is to become a cognition, we must have at the foundation of the cognition a permanent
intuition, as the indispensable condition of its objective reality. For through intuition alone can an object be
given. But in internal intuition there is nothing permanent, for the Ego is but the consciousness of my
thought. If then, we appeal merely to thought, we cannot discover the necessary condition of the application
of the conception of substance that is, of a subject existing per se to the subject as a thinking being. And
thus the conception of the simple nature of substance, which is connected with the objective reality of this
conception, is shown to be also invalid, and to be, in fact, nothing more than the logical qualitative unity of
selfconsciousness in thought; whilst we remain perfectly ignorant whether the subject is composite or not.
Refutation of the Argument of Mendelssohn for the
Substantiality or Permanence of the Soul.
This acute philosopher easily perceived the insufficiency of the common argument which attempts to prove
that the soul it being granted that it is a simple being cannot perish by dissolution or decomposition; he
saw it is not impossible for it to cease to be by extinction, or disappearance. He endeavoured to prove in his
Phaedo, that the soul cannot be annihilated, by showing that a simple being cannot cease to exist. Inasmuch
as, be said, a simple existence cannot diminish, nor gradually lose portions of its being, and thus be by
degrees reduced to nothing (for it possesses no parts, and therefore no multiplicity), between the moment in
which it is, and the moment in which it is not, no time can be discovered which is impossible. But this
philosopher did not consider that, granting the soul to possess this simple nature, which contains no parts
external to each other and consequently no extensive quantity, we cannot refuse to it any less than to any
other being, intensive quantity, that is, a degree of reality in regard to all its faculties, nay, to all that
constitutes its existence. But this degree of reality can become less and less through an infinite series of
smaller degrees. It follows, therefore, that this supposed substance this thing, the permanence of which is
not assured in any other way, may, if not by decomposition, by gradual loss (remissio) of its powers
(consequently by elanguescence, if I may employ this expression), be changed into nothing. For
consciousness itself has always a degree, which may be lessened.* Consequently the faculty of being
conscious may be diminished; and so with all other faculties. The permanence of the soul, therefore, as an
object of the internal sense, remains undemonstrated, nay, even indemonstrable. Its permanence in life is
evident, per se, inasmuch as the thinking being (as man) is to itself, at the same time, an object of the external
senses. But this does not authorize the rational psychologist to affirm, from mere conceptions, its permanence
beyond life.*[2]
*Clearness is not, as logicians maintain, the consciousness of a representation. For a certain degree of
consciousness, which may not, however, be sufficient for recollection, is to be met with in many dim
representations. For without any consciousness at all, we should not be able to recognize any difference in the
obscure representations we connect; as we really can do with many conceptions, such as those of right and
justice, and those of the musician, who strikes at once several notes in improvising a piece of music. But a
representation is clear, in which our consciousness is sufficient for the consciousness of the difference of this
representation from others. If we are only conscious that there is a difference, but are not conscious of the
difference that is, what the difference is the representation must be termed obscure. There is, consequently,
an infinite series of degrees of consciousness down to its entire disappearance.
*[2] There are some who think they have done enough to establish a new possibility in the mode of the
existence of souls, when they have shown that there is no contradiction in their hypotheses on this subject.
Such are those who affirm the possibility of thought of which they have no other knowledge than what they
derive from its use in connecting empirical intuitions presented in this our human life after this life bas
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 137
Page No 142
ceased. But it is very easy to embarrass them by the introduction of counterpossibilities, which rest upon
quite as good a foundation. Such, for example, is the possibility of the division of a simple substance into
several substances; and conversely, of the coalition of several into one simple substance. For, although
divisibility presupposes composition, it does not necessarily require a composition of substances, but only of
the degrees (of the several faculties) of one and the same substance. Now we can cogitate all the powers and
faculties of the soul even that of consciousness as diminished by one half, the substance still remaining. In
the same way we can represent to ourselves without contradiction, this obliterated half as preserved, not in
the soul, but without it; and we can believe that, as in this case every. thing that is real in the soul, and has a
degree consequently its entire existence has been halved, a particular substance would arise out of the soul.
For the multiplicity, which has been divided, formerly existed, but not as a multiplicity of substances, but of
every reality as the quantum of existence in it; and the unity of substance was merely a mode of existence,
which by this division alone has been transformed into a plurality of subsistence. In the same manner several
simple substances might coalesce into one, without anything being lost except the plurality of subsistence,
inasmuch as the one substance would contain the degree of reality of all the former substances. Perhaps,
indeed, the simple substances, which appear under the form of matter, might (not indeed by a mechanical or
chemical influence upon each other, but by an unknown influence, of which the former would be but the
phenomenal appearance), by means of such a dynamical division of the parentsouls, as intensive quantities,
produce other souls, while the former repaired the loss thus sustained with new matter of the same sort. I am
far from allowing any value to such chimeras; and the principles of our analytic have clearly proved that no
other than an empirical use of the categories that of substance, for example is possible. But if the
rationalist is bold enough to construct, on the mere authority of the faculty of thought without any intuition,
whereby an object is given a selfsubsistent being, merely because the unity of apperception in thought
cannot allow him to believe it a composite being, instead of declaring, as he ought to do, that he is unable to
explain the possibility of a thinking nature; what ought to hinder the materialist, with as complete an
independence of experience, to employ the principle of the rationalist in a directly opposite manner still
preserving the formal unity required by his opponent?
If, now, we take the above propositions as they must be accepted as valid for all thinking beings in the
system of rational psychology in synthetical connection, and proceed, from the category of relation, with the
proposition: "All thinking beings are, as such, substances," backwards through the series, till the circle is
completed; we come at last to their existence, of which, in this system of rational psychology, substances are
held to be conscious, independently of external things; nay, it is asserted that, in relation to the permanence
which is a necessary characteristic of substance, they can of themselves determine external things. It follows
that idealism at least problematical idealism, is perfectly unavoidable in this rationalistic system. And, if the
existence of outward things is not held to be requisite to the determination of the existence of a substance in
time, the existence of these outward things at all, is a gratuitous assumption which remains without the
possibility of a proof.
But if we proceed analytically the "I think" as a proposition containing in itself an existence as given,
consequently modality being the principle and dissect this proposition, in order to ascertain its content, and
discover whether and how this Ego determines its existence in time and space without the aid of anything
external; the propositions of rationalistic psychology would not begin with the conception of a thinking
being, but with a reality, and the properties of a thinking being in general would be deduced from the mode in
which this reality is cogitated, after everything empirical had been abstracted; as is shown in the following
table:
1
I think,
2 3
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 138
Page No 143
as Subject, as simple Subject,
4
as identical Subject,
in every state of my thought.
Now, inasmuch as it is not determined in this second proposition, whether I can exist and be cogitated only as
subject, and not also as a predicate of another being, the conception of a subject is here taken in a merely
logical sense; and it remains undetermined, whether substance is to be cogitated under the conception or not.
But in the third proposition, the absolute unity of apperception the simple Ego in the representation to which
all connection and separation, which constitute thought, relate, is of itself important; even although it presents
us with no information about the constitution or subsistence of the subject. Apperception is something real,
and the simplicity of its nature is given in the very fact of its possibility. Now in space there is nothing real
that is at the same time simple; for points, which are the only simple things in space, are merely limits, but
not constituent parts of space. From this follows the impossibility of a definition on the basis of materialism
of the constitution of my Ego as a merely thinking subject. But, because my existence is considered in the
first proposition as given, for it does not mean, "Every thinking being exists" (for this would be predicating of
them absolute necessity), but only, "I exist thinking"; the proposition is quite empirical, and contains the
determinability of my existence merely in relation to my representations in time. But as I require for this
purpose something that is permanent, such as is not given in internal intuition; the mode of my existence,
whether as substance or as accident, cannot be determined by means of this simple selfconsciousness. Thus,
if materialism is inadequate to explain the mode in which I exist, spiritualism is likewise as insufficient; and
the conclusion is that we are utterly unable to attain to any knowledge of the constitution of the soul, in so far
as relates to the possibility of its existence apart from external objects.
And, indeed, how should it be possible, merely by the aid of the unity of consciousness which we cognize
only for the reason that it is indispensable to the possibility of experience to pass the bounds of experience
(our existence in this life); and to extend our cognition to the nature of all thinking beings by means of the
empirical but in relation to every sort of intuition, perfectly undetermined proposition, "I think"?
There does not then exist any rational psychology as a doctrine furnishing any addition to our knowledge of
ourselves. It is nothing more than a discipline, which sets impassable limits to speculative reason in this
region of thought, to prevent it, on the one hand, from throwing itself into the arms of a soulless materialism,
and, on the other, from losing itself in the mazes of a baseless spiritualism. It teaches us to consider this
refusal of our reason to give any satisfactory answer to questions which reach beyond the limits of this our
human life, as a hint to abandon fruitless speculation; and to direct, to a practical use, our knowledge of
ourselves which, although applicable only to objects of experience, receives its principles from a higher
source, and regulates its procedure as if our destiny reached far beyond the boundaries of experience and life.
From all this it is evident that rational psychology has its origin in a mere misunderstanding. The unity of
consciousness, which lies at the basis of the categories, is considered to be an intuition of the subject as an
object; and the category of substance is applied to the intuition. But this unity is nothing more than the unity
in thought, by which no object is given; to which therefore the category of substance which always
presupposes a given intuition cannot be applied. Consequently, the subject cannot be cognized. The subject
of the categories cannot, therefore, for the very reason that it cogitates these, frame any conception of itself as
an object of the categories; for, to cogitate these, it must lay at the foundation its own pure
selfconsciousness the very thing that it wishes to explain and describe. In like manner, the subject, in
which the representation of time has its basis, cannot determine, for this very reason, its own existence in
time. Now, if the latter is impossible, the former, as an attempt to determine itself by means of the categories
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 139
Page No 144
as a thinking being in general, is no less so.*
*The "I think" is, as has been already stated, an empirical proposition, and contains the proposition, "I exist."
But I cannot say, "Everything, which thinks, exists"; for in this case the property of thought would constitute
all beings possessing it, necessary being Hence my existence cannot be considered as an inference from the
proposition, "I think," as Descartes maintained because in this case the major premiss, "Everything, which
thinks, exists," must precede but the two propositions are identical. The proposition, "I think," expresses an
undetermined empirical intuition, that perception (proving consequently that sensation, which must belong to
sensibility, lies at the foundation of this proposition); but it precedes experience, whose province it is to
determine an object of perception by means of the categories in relation to time; and existence in this
proposition is not a category, as it does not apply to an undetermined given object, but only to one of which
we have a conception, and about which we wish to know whether it does or does not exist, out of, and apart
from this conception. An undetermined perception signifies here merely something real that has been given,
only, however, to thought in general but not as a phenomenon, nor as a thing in itself (noumenon), but only
as something that really exists, and is designated as such in the proposition, "I think." For it must be remarked
that, when I call the proposition, "I think," an empirical proposition, I do not thereby mean that the Ego in the
proposition is an empirical representation; on the contrary, it is purely intellectual, because it belongs to
thought in general. But without some empirical representation, which presents to the mind material for
thought, the mental act, "I think," would not take place; and the empirical is only the condition of the
application or employment of the pure intellectual faculty.
Thus, then, appears the vanity of the hope of establishing a cognition which is to extend its rule beyond the
limits of experience a cognition which is one of the highest interests of humanity; and thus is proved the
futility of the attempt of speculative philosophy in this region of thought. But, in this interest of thought, the
severity of criticism has rendered to reason a not unimportant service, by the demonstration of the
impossibility of making any dogmatical affirmation concerning an object of experience beyond the
boundaries of experience. She has thus fortified reason against all affirmations of the contrary. Now, this can
be accomplished in only two ways. Either our proposition must be proved apodeictically; or, if this is
unsuccessful, the sources of this inability must be sought for, and, if these are discovered to exist in the
natural and necessary limitation of our reason, our opponents must submit to the same law of renunciation
and refrain from advancing claims to dogmatic assertion.
But the right, say rather the necessity to admit a future life, upon principles of the practical conjoined with the
speculative use of reason, has lost nothing by this renunciation; for the merely speculative proof has never
had any influence upon the common reason of men. It stands upon the point of a hair, so that even the schools
have been able to preserve it from falling only by incessantly discussing it and spinning it like a top; and even
in their eyes it has never been able to present any safe foundation for the erection of a theory. The proofs
which have been current among men, preserve their value undiminished; nay, rather gain in clearness and
unsophisticated power, by the rejection of the dogmatical assumptions of speculative reason. For reason is
thus confined within her own peculiar province the arrangement of ends or aims, which is at the same time
the arrangement of nature; and, as a practical faculty, without limiting itself to the latter, it is justified in
extending the former, and with it our own existence, beyond the boundaries of experience and life. If we turn
our attention to the analogy of the nature of living beings in this world, in the consideration of which reason
is obliged to accept as a principle that no organ, no faculty, no appetite is useless, and that nothing is
superfluous, nothing disproportionate to its use, nothing unsuited to its end; but that, on the contrary,
everything is perfectly conformed to its destination in life we shall find that man, who alone is the final end
and aim of this order, is still the only animal that seems to be excepted from it. For his natural gifts not
merely as regards the talents and motives that may incite him to employ them, but especially the moral law in
him stretch so far beyond all mere earthly utility and advantage, that he feels himself bound to prize the
mere consciousness of probity, apart from all advantageous consequences even the shadowy gift of
posthumous fame above everything; and he is conscious of an inward call to constitute himself, by his
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 140
Page No 145
conduct in this world without regard to mere sublunary interests the citizen of a better. This mighty,
irresistible proof accompanied by an everincreasing knowledge of the conformability to a purpose in
everything we see around us, by the conviction of the boundless immensity of creation, by the consciousness
of a certain illimitableness in the possible extension of our knowledge, and by a desire commensurate
therewith remains to humanity, even after the theoretical cognition of ourselves bas failed to establish the
necessity of an existence after death.
Conclusion of the Solution of the
Psychological Paralogism.
The dialectical illusion in rational psychology arises from our confounding an idea of reason (of a pure
intelligence) with the conception in every respect undetermined of a thinking being in general. I cogitate
myself in behalf of a possible experience, at the same time making abstraction of all actual experience; and
infer therefrom that I can be conscious of myself apart from experience and its empirical conditions. I
consequently confound the possible abstraction of my empirically determined existence with the supposed
consciousness of a possible separate existence of my thinking self; and I believe that I cognize what is
substantial in myself as a transcendental subject, when I have nothing more in thought than the unity of
consciousness, which lies at the basis of all determination of cognition.
The task of explaining the community of the soul with the body does not properly belong to the psychology
of which we are here speaking; because it proposes to prove the personality of the soul apart from this
communion (after death), and is therefore transcendent in the proper sense of the word, although occupying
itself with an object of experience only in so far, however, as it ceases to be an object of experience. But a
sufficient answer may be found to the question in our system. The difficulty which lies in the execution of
this task consists, as is well known, in the presupposed heterogeneity of the object of the internal sense (the
soul) and the objects of the external senses; inasmuch as the formal condition of the intuition of the one is
time, and of that of the other space also. But if we consider that both kinds of objects do not differ internally,
but only in so far as the one appears externally to the other consequently, that what lies at the basis of
phenomena, as a thing in itself, may not be heterogeneous; this difficulty disappears. There then remains no
other difficulty than is to be found in the question how a community of substances is possible; a question
which lies out of the region of psychology, and which the reader, after what in our analytic has been said of
primitive forces and faculties, will easily judge to be also beyond the region of human cognition.
GENERAL REMARK
On the Transition from Rational Psychology to Cosmology.
The proposition, "I think," or, "I exist thinking," is an empirical proposition. But such a proposition must be
based on empirical intuition, and the object cogitated as a phenomenon; and thus our theory appears to
maintain that the soul, even in thought, is merely a phenomenon; and in this way our consciousness itself, in
fact, abuts upon nothing.
Thought, per se, is merely the purely spontaneous logical function which operates to connect the manifold of
a possible intuition; and it does not represent the subject of consciousness as a phenomenon for this reason
alone, that it pays no attention to the question whether the mode of intuiting it is sensuous or intellectual. I
therefore do not represent myself in thought either as I am, or as I appear to myself; I merely cogitate myself
as an object in general, of the mode of intuiting which I make abstraction. When I represent myself as the
subject of thought, or as the ground of thought, these modes of representation are not related to the categories
of substance or of cause; for these are functions of thought applicable only to our sensuous intuition. The
application of these categories to the Ego would, however, be necessary, if I wished to make myself an object
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON. 141
Page No 146
of knowledge. But I wish to be conscious of myself only as thinking; in what mode my Self is given in
intuition, I do not consider, and it may be that I, who think, am a phenomenon although not in so far as I am
a thinking being; but in the consciousness of myself in mere thought I am a being, though this consciousness
does not present to me any property of this being as material for thought.
But the proposition, "I think," in so far as it declares, "I exist thinking," is not the mere representation of a
logical function. It determines the subject (which is in this case an object also) in relation to existence; and it
cannot be given without the aid of the internal sense, whose intuition presents to us an object, not as a thing
in itself, but always as a phenomenon. In this proposition there is therefore something more to be found than
the mere spontaneity of thought; there is also the receptivity of intuition, that is, my thought of myself applied
to the empirical intuition of myself. Now, in this intuition the thinking self must seek the conditions of the
employment of its logical functions as categories of substance, cause, and so forth; not merely for the purpose
of distinguishing itself as an object in itself by means of the representation "I," but also for the purpose of
determining the mode of its existence, that is, of cognizing itself as noumenon. But this is impossible, for the
internal empirical intuition is sensuous, and presents us with nothing but phenomenal data, which do not
assist the object of pure consciousness in its attempt to cognize itself as a separate existence, but are useful
only as contributions to experience.
But, let it be granted that we could discover, not in experience, but in certain firmlyestablished a priori laws
of the use of pure reason laws relating to our existence, authority to consider ourselves as legislating a priori
in relation to our own existence and as determining this existence; we should, on this supposition, find
ourselves possessed of a spontaneity, by which our actual existence would be determinable, without the aid of
the conditions of empirical intuition. We should also become aware that in the consciousness of our existence
there was an a priori content, which would serve to determine our own existence an existence only
sensuously determinable relatively, however, to a certain internal faculty in relation to an intelligible world.
But this would not give the least help to the attempts of rational psychology. For this wonderful faculty,
which the consciousness of the moral law in me reveals, would present me with a principle of the
determination of my own existence which is purely intellectual but by what predicates? By none other than
those which are given in sensuous intuition. Thus I should find myself in the same position in rational
psychology which I formerly occupied, that is to say, I should find myself still in need of sensuous intuitions,
in order to give significance to my conceptions of substance and cause, by means of which alone I can
possess a knowledge of myself: but these intuitions can never raise me above the sphere of experience. I
should be justified, however, in applying these conceptions, in regard to their practical use, which is always
directed to objects of experience in conformity with their analogical significance when employed
theoretically to freedom and its subject. At the same time, I should understand by them merely the logical
functions of subject and predicate, of principle and consequence, in conformity with which all actions are so
determined, that they are capable of being explained along with the laws of nature, conformably to the
categories of substance and cause, although they originate from a very different principle. We have made
these observations for the purpose of guarding against misunderstanding, to which the doctrine of our
intuition of self as a phenomenon is exposed. We shall have occasion to perceive their utility in the sequel.
CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason.
We showed in the introduction to this part of our work, that all transcendental illusion of pure reason arose
from dialectical arguments, the schema of which logic gives us in its three formal species of syllogisms just
as the categories find their logical schema in the four functions of all judgements. The first kind of these
sophistical arguments related to the unconditioned unity of the subjective conditions of all representations in
general (of the subject or soul), in correspondence with the categorical syllogisms, the major of which, as the
principle, enounces the relation of a predicate to a subject. The second kind of dialectical argument will
therefore be concerned, following the analogy with hypothetical syllogisms, with the unconditioned unity of
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason. 142
Page No 147
the objective conditions in the phenomenon; and, in this way, the theme of the third kind to be treated of in
the following chapter will be the unconditioned unity of the objective conditions of the possibility of objects
in general.
But it is worthy of remark that the transcendental paralogism produced in the mind only a onethird illusion,
in regard to the idea of the subject of our thought; and the conceptions of reason gave no ground to maintain
the contrary proposition. The advantage is completely on the side of Pneumatism; although this theory itself
passes into naught, in the crucible of pure reason.
Very different is the case when we apply reason to the objective synthesis of phenomena. Here, certainly,
reason establishes, with much plausibility, its principle of unconditioned unity; but it very soon falls into such
contradictions that it is compelled, in relation to cosmology, to renounce its pretensions.
For here a new phenomenon of human reason meets us a perfectly natural antithetic, which does not require
to be sought for by subtle sophistry, but into which reason of itself unavoidably falls. It is thereby preserved,
to be sure, from the slumber of a fancied conviction which a merely onesided illusion produces; but it is at
the same time compelled, either, on the one hand, to abandon itself to a despairing scepticism, or, on the
other, to assume a dogmatical confidence and obstinate persistence in certain assertions, without granting a
fair hearing to the other side of the question. Either is the death of a sound philosophy, although the former
might perhaps deserve the title of the euthanasia of pure reason.
Before entering this region of discord and confusion, which the conflict of the laws of pure reason (antinomy)
produces, we shall present the reader with some considerations, in explanation and justification of the method
we intend to follow in our treatment of this subject. I term all transcendental ideas, in so far as they relate to
the absolute totality in the synthesis of phenomena, cosmical conceptions; partly on account of this
unconditioned totality, on which the conception of the worldwhole is based a conception, which is itself an
idea partly because they relate solely to the synthesis of phenomena the empirical synthesis; while, on the
other hand, the absolute totality in the synthesis of the conditions of all possible things gives rise to an ideal
of pure reason, which is quite distinct from the cosmical conception, although it stands in relation with it.
Hence, as the paralogisms of pure reason laid the foundation for a dialectical psychology, the antinomy of
pure reason will present us with the transcendental principles of a pretended pure (rational) cosmology not,
however, to declare it valid and to appropriate it, but as the very term of a conflict of reason sufficiently
indicates, to present it as an idea which cannot be reconciled with phenomena and experience.
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas.
That We may be able to enumerate with systematic precision these ideas according to a principle, we must
remark, in the first place, that it is from the understanding alone that pure and transcendental conceptions take
their origin; that the reason does not properly give birth to any conception, but only frees the conception of
the understanding from the unavoidable limitation of a possible experience, and thus endeavours to raise it
above the empirical, though it must still be in connection with it. This happens from the fact that, for a given
conditioned, reason demands absolute totality on the side of the conditions (to which the understanding
submits all phenomena), and thus makes of the category a transcendental idea. This it does that it may be able
to give absolute completeness to the empirical synthesis, by continuing it to the unconditioned (which is not
to be found in experience, but only in the idea). Reason requires this according to the principle: If the
conditioned is given the whole of the conditions, and consequently the absolutely unconditioned, is also
given, whereby alone the former was possible. First, then, the transcendental ideas are properly nothing but
categories elevated to the unconditioned; and they may be arranged in a table according to the titles of the
latter. But, secondly, all the categories are not available for this purpose, but only those in which the synthesis
constitutes a series of conditions subordinated to, not coordinated with, each other. Absolute totality is
required of reason only in so far as concerns the ascending series of the conditions of a conditioned; not,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas. 143
Page No 148
consequently, when the question relates to the descending series of consequences, or to the aggregate of the
coordinated conditions of these consequences. For, in relation to a given conditioned, conditions are
presupposed and considered to be given along with it. On the other hand, as the consequences do not render
possible their conditions, but rather presuppose them in the consideration of the procession of consequences
(or in the descent from the given condition to the conditioned), we may be quite unconcerned whether the
series ceases or not; and their totality is not a necessary demand of reason.
Thus we cogitate and necessarily a given time completely elapsed up to a given moment, although that
time is not determinable by us. But as regards time future, which is not the condition of arriving at the
present, in order to conceive it; it is quite indifferent whether we consider future time as ceasing at some
point, or as prolonging itself to infinity. Take, for example, the series m, n, o, in which n is given as
conditioned in relation to m, but at the same time as the condition of o, and let the series proceed upwards
from the conditioned n to m (l, k, i, etc.), and also downwards from the condition n to the conditioned o (p, q,
r, etc.) I must presuppose the former series, to be able to consider n as given, and n is according to reason
(the totality of conditions) possible only by means of that series. But its possibility does not rest on the
following series o, p, q, r, which for this reason cannot be regarded as given, but only as capable of being
given (dabilis).
I shall term the synthesis of the series on the side of the conditions from that nearest to the given
phenomenon up to the more remote regressive; that which proceeds on the side of the conditioned, from the
immediate consequence to the more remote, I shall call the progressive synthesis. The former proceeds in
antecedentia, the latter in consequentia. The cosmological ideas are therefore occupied with the totality of the
regressive synthesis, and proceed in antecedentia, not in consequentia. When the latter takes place, it is an
arbitrary and not a necessary problem of pure reason; for we require, for the complete understanding of what
is given in a phenomenon, not the consequences which succeed, but the grounds or principles which precede.
In order to construct the table of ideas in correspondence with the table of categories, we take first the two
primitive quanta of all our intuitions, time and space. Time is in itself a series (and the formal condition of all
series), and hence, in relation to a given present, we must distinguish a priori in it the antecedentia as
conditions (time past) from the consequentia (time future). Consequently, the transcendental idea of the
absolute totality of the series of the conditions of a given conditioned, relates merely to all past time.
According to the idea of reason, the whole past time, as the condition of the given moment, is necessarily
cogitated as given. But, as regards space, there exists in it no distinction between progressus and regressus;
for it is an aggregate and not a series its parts existing together at the same time. I can consider a given point
of time in relation to past time only as conditioned, because this given moment comes into existence only
through the past time rather through the passing of the preceding time. But as the parts of space are not
subordinated, but coordinated to each other, one part cannot be the condition of the possibility of the other;
and space is not in itself, like time, a series. But the synthesis of the manifold parts of space (the syntheses
whereby we apprehend space) is nevertheless successive; it takes place, therefore, in time, and contains a
series. And as in this series of aggregated spaces (for example, the feet in a rood), beginning with a given
portion of space, those which continue to be annexed form the condition of the limits of the former the
measurement of a space must also be regarded as a synthesis of the series of the conditions of a given
conditioned. It differs, however, in this respect from that of time, that the side of the conditioned is not in
itself distinguishable from the side of the condition; and, consequently, regressus and progressus in space
seem to be identical. But, inasmuch as one part of space is not given, but only limited, by and through
another, we must also consider every limited space as conditioned, in so far as it presupposes some other
space as the condition of its limitation, and so on. As regards limitation, therefore, our procedure in space is
also a regressus, and the transcendental idea of the absolute totality of the synthesis in a series of conditions
applies to space also; and I am entitled to demand the absolute totality of the phenomenal synthesis in space
as well as in time. Whether my demand can be satisfied is a question to be answered in the sequel.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas. 144
Page No 149
Secondly, the real in space that is, matter is conditioned. Its internal conditions are its parts, and the parts
of parts its remote conditions; so that in this case we find a regressive synthesis, the absolute totality of which
is a demand of reason. But this cannot be obtained otherwise than by a complete division of parts, whereby
the real in matter becomes either nothing or that which is not matter, that is to say, the simple. Consequently
we find here also a series of conditions and a progress to the unconditioned.
Thirdly, as regards the categories of a real relation between phenomena, the category of substance and its
accidents is not suitable for the formation of a transcendental idea; that is to say, reason has no ground, in
regard to it, to proceed regressively with conditions. For accidents (in so far as they inhere in a substance) are
coordinated with each other, and do not constitute a series. And, in relation to substance, they are not
properly subordinated to it, but are the mode of existence of the substance itself. The conception of the
substantial might nevertheless seem to be an idea of the transcendental reason. But, as this signifies nothing
more than the conception of an object in general, which subsists in so far as we cogitate in it merely a
transcendental subject without any predicates; and as the question here is of an unconditioned in the series of
phenomena it is clear that the substantial can form no member thereof. The same holds good of substances
in community, which are mere aggregates and do not form a series. For they are not subordinated to each
other as conditions of the possibility of each other; which, however, may be affirmed of spaces, the limits of
which are never determined in themselves, but always by some other space. It is, therefore, only in the
category of causality that we can find a series of causes to a given effect, and in which we ascend from the
latter, as the conditioned, to the former as the conditions, and thus answer the question of reason.
Fourthly, the conceptions of the possible, the actual, and the necessary do not conduct us to any series
excepting only in so far as the contingent in existence must always be regarded as conditioned, and as
indicating, according to a law of the understanding, a condition, under which it is necessary to rise to a
higher, till in the totality of the series, reason arrives at unconditioned necessity.
There are, accordingly, only four cosmological ideas, corresponding with the four titles of the categories. For
we can select only such as necessarily furnish us with a series in the synthesis of the manifold.
1
The absolute Completeness
of the
COMPOSITION
of the given totality of all phenomena.
2
The absolute Completeness
of the
DIVISION
of given totality in a phenomenon.
3
The absolute Completeness
of the
ORIGINATION
of a phenomenon.
4
The absolute Completeness
of the DEPENDENCE of the EXISTENCE
of what is changeable in a phenomenon.
We must here remark, in the first place, that the idea of absolute totality relates to nothing but the exposition
of phenomena, and therefore not to the pure conception of a totality of things. Phenomena are here, therefore,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas. 145
Page No 150
regarded as given, and reason requires the absolute completeness of the conditions of their possibility, in so
far as these conditions constitute a series consequently an absolutely (that is, in every respect) complete
synthesis, whereby a phenomenon can be explained according to the laws of the understanding.
Secondly, it is properly the unconditioned alone that reason seeks in this serially and regressively conducted
synthesis of conditions. It wishes, to speak in another way, to attain to completeness in the series of
premisses, so as to render it unnecessary to presuppose others. This unconditioned is always contained in the
absolute totality of the series, when we endeavour to form a representation of it in thought. But this
absolutely complete synthesis is itself but an idea; for it is impossible, at least before hand, to know whether
any such synthesis is possible in the case of phenomena. When we represent all existence in thought by
means of pure conceptions of the understanding, without any conditions of sensuous intuition, we may say
with justice that for a given conditioned the whole series of conditions subordinated to each other is also
given; for the former is only given through the latter. But we find in the case of phenomena a particular
limitation of the mode in which conditions are given, that is, through the successive synthesis of the manifold
of intuition, which must be complete in the regress. Now whether this completeness is sensuously possible, is
a problem. But the idea of it lies in the reason be it possible or impossible to connect with the idea adequate
empirical conceptions. Therefore, as in the absolute totality of the regressive synthesis of the manifold in a
phenomenon (following the guidance of the categories, which represent it as a series of conditions to a given
conditioned) the unconditioned is necessarily contained it being still left unascertained whether and how this
totality exists; reason sets out from the idea of totality, although its proper and final aim is the
unconditioned of the whole series, or of a part thereof.
This unconditioned may be cogitated either as existing only in the entire series, all the members of which
therefore would be without exception conditioned and only the totality absolutely unconditioned and in this
case the regressus is called infinite; or the absolutely unconditioned is only a part of the series, to which the
other members are subordinated, but which Is not itself submitted to any other condition.* In the former case
the series is a parte priori unlimited (without beginning), that is, infinite, and nevertheless completely given.
But the regress in it is never completed, and can only be called potentially infinite. In the second case there
exists a first in the series. This first is called, in relation to past time, the beginning of the world; in relation to
space, the limit of the world; in relation to the parts of a given limited whole, the simple; in relation to causes,
absolute spontaneity (liberty); and in relation to the existence of changeable things, absolute physical
necessity.
*The absolute totality of the series of conditions to a given conditioned is always unconditioned; because
beyond it there exist no other conditions, on which it might depend. But the absolute totality of such a series
is only an idea, or rather a problematical conception, the possibility of which must be investigated
particularly in relation to the mode in which the unconditioned, as the transcendental idea which is the real
subject of inquiry, may be contained therein.
We possess two expressions, world and nature, which are generally interchanged. The first denotes the
mathematical total of all phenomena and the totality of their synthesis in its progress by means of
composition, as well as by division. And the world is termed nature,* when it is regarded as a dynamical
whole when our attention is not directed to the aggregation in space and time, for the purpose of cogitating
it as a quantity, but to the unity in the existence of phenomena. In this case the condition of that which
happens is called a cause; the unconditioned causality of the cause in a phenomenon is termed liberty; the
conditioned cause is called in a more limited sense a natural cause. The conditioned in existence is termed
contingent, and the unconditioned necessary. The unconditioned necessity of phenomena may be called
natural necessity.
*Nature, understood adjective (formaliter), signifies the complex of the determinations of a thing, connected
according to an internal principle of causality. On the other hand, we understand by nature, substantive
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas. 146
Page No 151
(materialiter), the sum total of phenomena, in so far as they, by virtue of an internal principle of causality, are
connected with each other throughout. In the former sense we speak of the nature of liquid matter, of fire,
etc., and employ the word only adjective; while, if speaking of the objects of nature, we have in our minds the
idea of a subsisting whole.
The ideas which we are at present engaged in discussing I have called cosmological ideas; partly because by
the term world is understood the entire content of all phenomena, and our ideas are directed solely to the
unconditioned among phenomena; partly also, because world, in the transcendental sense, signifies the
absolute totality of the content of existing things, and we are directing our attention only to the completeness
of the synthesis although, properly, only in regression. In regard to the fact that these ideas are all
transcendent. and, although they do not transcend phenomena as regards their mode, but are concerned solely
with the world of sense (and not with noumena), nevertheless carry their synthesis to a degree far above all
possible experience it still seems to me that we can, with perfect propriety, designate them cosmical
conceptions. As regards the distinction between the mathematically and the dynamically unconditioned which
is the aim of the regression of the synthesis, I should call the two former, in a more limited signification,
cosmical conceptions, the remaining two transcendent physical conceptions. This distinction does not at
present seem to be of particular importance, but we shall afterwards find it to be of some value.
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason.
Thetic is the term applied to every collection of dogmatical propositions. By antithetic I do not understand
dogmatical assertions of the opposite, but the selfcontradiction of seemingly dogmatical cognitions (thesis
cum antithesis, in none of which we can discover any decided superiority. Antithetic is not, therefore,
occupied with onesided statements, but is engaged in considering the contradictory nature of the general
cognitions of reason and its causes. Transcendental antithetic is an investigation into the antinomy of pure
reason, its causes and result. If we employ our reason not merely in the application of the principles of the
understanding to objects of experience, but venture with it beyond these boundaries, there arise certain
sophistical propositions or theorems. These assertions have the following peculiarities: They can find neither
confirmation nor confutation in experience; and each is in itself not only selfconsistent, but possesses
conditions of its necessity in the very nature of reason only that, unluckily, there exist just as valid and
necessary grounds for maintaining the contrary proposition.
The questions which naturally arise in the consideration of this dialectic of pure reason, are therefore: 1st. In
what propositions is pure reason unavoidably subject to an antinomy? 2nd. What are the causes of this
antinomy? 3rd. Whether and in what way can reason free itself from this selfcontradiction?
A dialectical proposition or theorem of pure reason must, according to what has been said, be distinguishable
from all sophistical propositions, by the fact that it is not an answer to an arbitrary question, which may be
raised at the mere pleasure of any person, but to one which human reason must necessarily encounter in its
progress. In the second place, a dialectical proposition, with its opposite, does not carry the appearance of a
merely artificial illusion, which disappears as soon as it is investigated, but a natural and unavoidable
illusion, which, even when we are no longer deceived by it, continues to mock us and, although rendered
harmless, can never be completely removed.
This dialectical doctrine will not relate to the unity of understanding in empirical conceptions, but to the unity
of reason in pure ideas. The conditions of this doctrine are inasmuch as it must, as a synthesis according to
rules, be conformable to the understanding, and at the same time as the absolute unity of the synthesis, to the
reason that, if it is adequate to the unity of reason, it is too great for the understanding, if according with the
understanding, it is too small for the reason. Hence arises a mutual opposition, which cannot be avoided, do
what we will.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 147
Page No 152
These sophistical assertions of dialectic open, as it were, a battlefield, where that side obtains the victory
which has been permitted to make the attack, and he is compelled to yield who has been unfortunately
obliged to stand on the defensive. And hence, champions of ability, whether on the right or on the wrong side,
are certain to carry away the crown of victory, if they only take care to have the right to make the last attack,
and are not obliged to sustain another onset from their opponent. We can easily believe that this arena has
been often trampled by the feet of combatants, that many victories have been obtained on both sides, but that
the last victory, decisive of the affair between the contending parties, was won by him who fought for the
right, only if his adversary was forbidden to continue the tourney. As impartial umpires, we must lay aside
entirely the consideration whether the combatants are fighting for the right or for the wrong side, for the true
or for the false, and allow the combat to be first decided. Perhaps, after they have wearied more than injured
each other, they will discover the nothingness of their cause of quarrel and part good friends.
This method of watching, or rather of originating, a conflict of assertions, not for the purpose of finally
deciding in favour of either side, but to discover whether the object of the struggle is not a mere illusion,
which each strives in vain to reach, but which would be no gain even when reached this procedure, I say,
may be termed the sceptical method. It is thoroughly distinct from scepticism the principle of a technical
and scientific ignorance, which undermines the foundations of all knowledge, in order, if possible, to destroy
our belief and confidence therein. For the sceptical method aims at certainty, by endeavouring to discover in a
conflict of this kind, conducted honestly and intelligently on both sides, the point of misunderstanding; just as
wise legislators derive, from the embarrassment of judges in lawsuits, information in regard to the defective
and illdefined parts of their statutes. The antinomy which reveals itself in the application of laws, is for our
limited wisdom the best criterion of legislation. For the attention of reason, which in abstract speculation does
not easily become conscious of its errors, is thus roused to the momenta in the determination of its principles.
But this sceptical method is essentially peculiar to transcendental philosophy, and can perhaps be dispensed
with in every other field of investigation. In mathematics its use would be absurd; because in it no false
assertions can long remain hidden, inasmuch as its demonstrations must always proceed under the guidance
of pure intuition, and by means of an always evident synthesis. In experimental philosophy, doubt and delay
may be very useful; but no misunderstanding is possible, which cannot be easily removed; and in experience
means of solving the difficulty and putting an end to the dissension must at last be found, whether sooner or
later. Moral philosophy can always exhibit its principles, with their practical consequences, in concreto at
least in possible experiences, and thus escape the mistakes and ambiguities of abstraction. But transcendental
propositions, which lay claim to insight beyond the region of possible experience, cannot, on the one hand,
exhibit their abstract synthesis in any a priori intuition, nor, on the other, expose a lurking error by the help of
experience. Transcendental reason, therefore, presents us with no other criterion than that of an attempt to
reconcile such assertions, and for this purpose to permit a free and unrestrained conflict between them. And
this we now proceed to arrange.*
*The antinomies stand in the order of the four transcendental ideas above detailed.
FIRST CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
THESIS.
The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited in regard to space.
PROOF.
Granted that the world has no beginning in time; up to every given moment of time, an eternity must have
elapsed, and therewith passed away an infinite series of successive conditions or states of things in the world.
Now the infinity of a series consists in the fact that it never can be completed by means of a successive
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 148
Page No 153
synthesis. It follows that an infinite series already elapsed is impossible and that, consequently, a beginning
of the world is a necessary condition of its existence. And this was the first thing to be proved.
As regards the second, let us take the opposite for granted. In this case, the world must be an infinite given
total of coexistent things. Now we cannot cogitate the dimensions of a quantity, which is not given within
certain limits of an intuition,* in any other way than by means of the synthesis of its parts, and the total of
such a quantity only by means of a completed synthesis, or the repeated addition of unity to itself.
Accordingly, to cogitate the world, which fills all spaces, as a whole, the successive synthesis of the parts of
an infinite world must be looked upon as completed, that is to say, an infinite time must be regarded as
having elapsed in the enumeration of all coexisting things; which is impossible. For this reason an infinite
aggregate of actual things cannot be considered as a given whole, consequently, not as a contemporaneously
given whole. The world is consequently, as regards extension in space, not infinite, but enclosed in limits.
And this was the second thing to be proved.
*We may consider an undetermined quantity as a whole, when it is enclosed within limits, although we
cannot construct or ascertain its totality by measurement, that is, by the successive synthesis of its parts. For
its limits of themselves determine its completeness as a whole.
ANTITHESIS.
The world has no beginning, and no limits in space, but is, in relation both to time and space, infinite.
PROOF.
For let it be granted that it has a beginning. A beginning is an existence which is preceded by a time in which
the thing does not exist. On the above supposition, it follows that there must have been a time in which the
world did not exist, that is, a void time. But in a void time the origination of a thing is impossible; because no
part of any such time contains a distinctive condition of being, in preference to that of nonbeing (whether
the supposed thing originate of itself, or by means of some other cause). Consequently, many series of things
may have a beginning in the world, but the world itself cannot have a beginning, and is, therefore, in relation
to past time, infinite.
As regards the second statement, let us first take the opposite for granted that the world is finite and limited
in space; it follows that it must exist in a void space, which is not limited. We should therefore meet not only
with a relation of things in space, but also a relation of things to space. Now, as the world is an absolute
whole, out of and beyond which no object of intuition, and consequently no correlate to which can be
discovered, this relation of the world to a void space is merely a relation to no object. But such a relation, and
consequently the limitation of the world by void space, is nothing. Consequently, the world, as regards space,
is not limited, that is, it is infinite in regard to extension.*
*Space is merely the form of external intuition (formal intuition), and not a real object which can be
externally perceived. Space, prior to all things which determine it (fill or limit it), or, rather, which present an
empirical intuition conformable to it, is, under the title of absolute space, nothing but the mere possibility of
external phenomena, in so far as they either exist in themselves, or can annex themselves to given intuitions.
Empirical intuition is therefore not a composition of phenomena and space (of perception and empty
intuition). The one is not the correlate of the other in a synthesis, but they are vitally connected in the same
empirical intuition, as matter and form. If we wish to set one of these two apart from the other space from
phenomena there arise all sorts of empty determinations of external intuition, which are very far from being
possible perceptions. For example, motion or rest of the world in an infinite empty space, or a determination
of the mutual relation of both, cannot possibly be perceived, and is therefore merely the predicate of a
notional entity.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 149
Page No 154
OBSERVATIONS ON THE FIRST ANTINOMY.
ON THE THESIS.
In bringing forward these conflicting arguments, I have not been on the search for sophisms, for the purpose
of availing myself of special pleading, which takes advantage of the carelessness of the opposite party,
appeals to a misunderstood statute, and erects its unrighteous claims upon an unfair interpretation. Both
proofs originate fairly from the nature of the case, and the advantage presented by the mistakes of the
dogmatists of both parties has been completely set aside.
The thesis might also have been unfairly demonstrated, by the introduction of an erroneous conception of the
infinity of a given quantity. A quantity is infinite, if a greater than itself cannot possibly exist. The quantity is
measured by the number of given units which are taken as a standard contained in it. Now no number can
be the greatest, because one or more units can always be added. It follows that an infinite given quantity,
consequently an infinite world (both as regards time and extension) is impossible. It is, therefore, limited in
both respects. In this manner I might have conducted my proof; but the conception given in it does not agree
with the true conception of an infinite whole. In this there is no representation of its quantity, it is not said
how large it is; consequently its conception is not the conception of a maximum. We cogitate in it merely its
relation to an arbitrarily assumed unit, in relation to which it is greater than any number. Now, just as the unit
which is taken is greater or smaller, the infinite will be greater or smaller; but the infinity, which consists
merely in the relation to this given unit, must remain always the same, although the absolute quantity of the
whole is not thereby cognized.
The true (transcendental) conception of infinity is: that the successive synthesis of unity in the measurement
of a given quantum can never be completed.* Hence it follows, without possibility of mistake, that an eternity
of actual successive states up to a given (the present) moment cannot have elapsed, and that the world must
therefore have a beginning.
*The quantum in this sense contains a congeries of given units, which is greater than any number and this is
the mathematical conception of the infinite.
In regard to the second part of the thesis, the difficulty as to an infinite and yet elapsed series disappears; for
the manifold of a world infinite in extension is contemporaneously given. But, in order to cogitate the total of
this manifold, as we cannot have the aid of limits constituting by themselves this total in intuition, we are
obliged to give some account of our conception, which in this case cannot proceed from the whole to the
determined quantity of the parts, but must demonstrate the possibility of a whole by means of a successive
synthesis of the parts. But as this synthesis must constitute a series that cannot be completed, it is impossible
for us to cogitate prior to it, and consequently not by means of it, a totality. For the conception of totality
itself is in the present case the representation of a completed synthesis of the parts; and this completion, and
consequently its conception, is impossible.
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
The proof in favour of the infinity of the cosmical succession and the cosmical content is based upon the
consideration that, in the opposite case, a void time and a void space must constitute the limits of the world.
Now I am not unaware, that there are some ways of escaping this conclusion. It may, for example, be alleged,
that a limit to the world, as regards both space and time, is quite possible, without at the same time holding
the existence of an absolute time before the beginning of the world, or an absolute space extending beyond
the actual world which is impossible. I am quite well satisfied with the latter part of this opinion of the
philosophers of the Leibnitzian school. Space is merely the form of external intuition, but not a real object
which can itself be externally intuited; it is not a correlate of phenomena, it is the form of phenomena itself.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 150
Page No 155
Space, therefore, cannot be regarded as absolutely and in itself something determinative of the existence of
things, because it is not itself an object, but only the form of possible objects. Consequently, things, as
phenomena, determine space; that is to say, they render it possible that, of all the possible predicates of space
(size and relation), certain may belong to reality. But we cannot affirm the converse, that space, as something
selfsubsistent, can determine real things in regard to size or shape, for it is in itself not a real thing. Space
(filled or void)* may therefore be limited by phenomena, but phenomena cannot be limited by an empty
space without them. This is true of time also. All this being granted, it is nevertheless indisputable, that we
must assume these two nonentities, void space without and void time before the world, if we assume the
existence of cosmical limits, relatively to space or time.
*It is evident that what is meant here is, that empty space, in so far as it is limited by phenomena space, that
is, within the world does not at least contradict transcendental principles, and may therefore, as regards
them, be admitted, although its possibility cannot on that account be affirmed.
For, as regards the subterfuge adopted by those who endeavour to evade the consequence that, if the world
is limited as to space and time, the infinite void must determine the existence of actual things in regard to
their dimensions it arises solely from the fact that instead of a sensuous world, an intelligible world of
which nothing is known is cogitated; instead of a real beginning (an existence, which is preceded by a
period in which nothing exists), an existence which presupposes no other condition than that of time; and,
instead of limits of extension, boundaries of the universe. But the question relates to the mundus
phaenomenon, and its quantity; and in this case we cannot make abstraction of the conditions of sensibility,
without doing away with the essential reality of this world itself. The world of sense, if it is limited, must
necessarily lie in the infinite void. If this, and with it space as the a priori condition of the possibility of
phenomena, is left out of view, the whole world of sense disappears. In our problem is this alone considered
as given. The mundus intelligibilis is nothing but the general conception of a world, in which abstraction has
been made of all conditions of intuition, and in relation to which no synthetical proposition either
affirmative or negative is possible.
SECOND CONFLICT OF TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
THESIS.
Every composite substance in the world consists of simple parts; and there exists nothing that is not either
itself simple, or composed of simple parts.
PROOF.
For, grant that composite substances do not consist of simple parts; in this case, if all combination or
composition were annihilated in thought, no composite part, and (as, by the supposition, there do not exist
simple parts) no simple part would exist. Consequently, no substance; consequently, nothing would exist.
Either, then, it is impossible to annihilate composition in thought; or, after such annihilation, there must
remain something that subsists without composition, that is, something that is simple. But in the former case
the composite could not itself consist of substances, because with substances composition is merely a
contingent relation, apart from which they must still exist as selfsubsistent beings. Now, as this case
contradicts the supposition, the second must contain the truth that the substantial composite in the world
consists of simple parts.
It follows, as an immediate inference, that the things in the world are all, without exception, simple beings
that composition is merely an external condition pertaining to them and that, although we never can separate
and isolate the elementary substances from the state of composition, reason must cogitate these as the primary
subjects of all composition, and consequently, as prior thereto and as simple substances.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 151
Page No 156
ANTITHESIS.
No composite thing in the world consists of simple parts; and there does not exist in the world any simple
substance.
PROOF.
Let it be supposed that a composite thing (as substance) consists of simple parts. Inasmuch as all external
relation, consequently all composition of substances, is possible only in space; the space, occupied by that
which is composite, must consist of the same number of parts as is contained in the composite. But space
does not consist of simple parts, but of spaces. Therefore, every part of the composite must occupy a space.
But the absolutely primary parts of what is composite are simple. It follows that what is simple occupies a
space. Now, as everything real that occupies a space, contains a manifold the parts of which are external to
each other, and is consequently composite and a real composite, not of accidents (for these cannot exist
external to each other apart from substance), but of substances it follows that the simple must be a
substantial composite, which is selfcontradictory.
The second proposition of the antithesis that there exists in the world nothing that is simple is here
equivalent to the following: The existence of the absolutely simple cannot be demonstrated from any
experience or perception either external or internal; and the absolutely simple is a mere idea, the objective
reality of which cannot be demonstrated in any possible experience; it is consequently, in the exposition of
phenomena, without application and object. For, let us take for granted that an object may be found in
experience for this transcendental idea; the empirical intuition of such an object must then be recognized to
contain absolutely no manifold with its parts external to each other, and connected into unity. Now, as we
cannot reason from the nonconsciousness of such a manifold to the impossibility of its existence in the
intuition of an object, and as the proof of this impossibility is necessary for the establishment and proof of
absolute simplicity; it follows that this simplicity cannot be inferred from any perception whatever. As,
therefore, an absolutely simple object cannot be given in any experience, and the world of sense must be
considered as the sum total of all possible experiences: nothing simple exists in the world.
This second proposition in the antithesis has a more extended aim than the first. The first merely banishes the
simple from the intuition of the composite; while the second drives it entirely out of nature. Hence we were
unable to demonstrate it from the conception of a given object of external intuition (of the composite), but we
were obliged to prove it from the relation of a given object to a possible experience in general.
OBSERVATIONS ON THE SECOND ANTINOMY.
THESIS.
When I speak of a whole, which necessarily consists of simple parts, I understand thereby only a substantial
whole, as the true composite; that is to say, I understand that contingent unity of the manifold which is given
as perfectly isolated (at least in thought), placed in reciprocal connection, and thus constituted a unity. Space
ought not to be called a compositum but a totum, for its parts are possible in the whole, and not the whole by
means of the parts. It might perhaps be called a compositum ideale, but not a compositum reale. But this is of
no importance. As space is not a composite of substances (and not even of real accidents), if I abstract all
composition therein nothing, not even a point, remains; for a point is possible only as the limit of a space
consequently of a composite. Space and time, therefore, do not consist of simple parts. That which belongs
only to the condition or state of a substance, even although it possesses a quantity (motion or change, for
example), likewise does not consist of simple parts. That is to say, a certain degree of change does not
originate from the addition of many simple changes. Our inference of the simple from the composite is valid
only of selfsubsisting things. But the accidents of a state are not selfsubsistent. The proof, then, for the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 152
Page No 157
necessity of the simple, as the component part of all that is substantial and composite, may prove a failure,
and the whole case of this thesis be lost, if we carry the proposition too far, and wish to make it valid of
everything that is composite without distinction as indeed has really now and then happened. Besides, I am
here speaking only of the simple, in so far as it is necessarily given in the composite the latter being capable
of solution into the former as its component parts. The proper signification of the word monas (as employed
by Leibnitz) ought to relate to the simple, given immediately as simple substance (for example, in
consciousness), and not as an element of the composite. As an clement, the term atomus would be more
appropriate. And as I wish to prove the existence of simple substances, only in relation to, and as the
elements of, the composite, I might term the antithesis of the second Antinomy, transcendental Atomistic.
But as this word has long been employed to designate a particular theory of corporeal phenomena
(moleculae), and thus presupposes a basis of empirical conceptions, I prefer calling it the dialectical principle
of Monadology.
ANTITHESIS.
Against the assertion of the infinite subdivisibility of matter whose ground of proof is purely mathematical,
objections have been alleged by the Monadists. These objections lay themselves open, at first sight, to
suspicion, from the fact that they do not recognize the clearest mathematical proofs as propositions relating to
the constitution of space, in so far as it is really the formal condition of the possibility of all matter, but regard
them merely as inferences from abstract but arbitrary conceptions, which cannot have any application to real
things. just as if it were possible to imagine another mode of intuition than that given in the primitive
intuition of space; and just as if its a priori determinations did not apply to everything, the existence of which
is possible, from the fact alone of its filling space. If we listen to them, we shall find ourselves required to
cogitate, in addition to the mathematical point, which is simple not, however, a part, but a mere limit of
space physical points, which are indeed likewise simple, but possess the peculiar property, as parts of space,
of filling it merely by their aggregation. I shall not repeat here the common and clear refutations of this
absurdity, which are to be found everywhere in numbers: every one knows that it is impossible to undermine
the evidence of mathematics by mere discursive conceptions; I shall only remark that, if in this case
philosophy endeavours to gain an advantage over mathematics by sophistical artifices, it is because it forgets
that the discussion relates solely to Phenomena and their conditions. It is not sufficient to find the conception
of the simple for the pure conception of the composite, but we must discover for the intuition of the
composite (matter), the intuition of the simple. Now this, according to the laws of sensibility, and
consequently in the case of objects of sense, is utterly impossible. In the case of a whole composed of
substances, which is cogitated solely by the pure understanding, it may be necessary to be in possession of
the simple before composition is possible. But this does not hold good of the Totum substantiale
phaenomenon, which, as an empirical intuition in space, possesses the necessary property of containing no
simple part, for the very reason that no part of space is simple. Meanwhile, the Monadists have been subtle
enough to escape from this difficulty, by presupposing intuition and the dynamical relation of substances as
the condition of the possibility of space, instead of regarding space as the condition of the possibility of the
objects of external intuition, that is, of bodies. Now we have a conception of bodies only as phenomena, and,
as such, they necessarily presuppose space as the condition of all external phenomena. The evasion is
therefore in vain; as, indeed, we have sufficiently shown in our Aesthetic. If bodies were things in
themselves, the proof of the Monadists would be unexceptionable.
The second dialectical assertion possesses the peculiarity of having opposed to it a dogmatical proposition,
which, among all such sophistical statements, is the only one that undertakes to prove in the case of an object
of experience, that which is properly a transcendental idea the absolute simplicity of substance. The
proposition is that the object of the internal sense, the thinking Ego, is an absolute simple substance. Without
at present entering upon this subject as it has been considered at length in a former chapter I shall merely
remark that, if something is cogitated merely as an object, without the addition of any synthetical
determination of its intuition as happens in the case of the bare representation, I it is certain that no
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 153
Page No 158
manifold and no composition can be perceived in such a representation. As, moreover, the predicates
whereby I cogitate this object are merely intuitions of the internal sense, there cannot be discovered in them
anything to prove the existence of a manifold whose parts are external to each other, and, consequently,
nothing to prove the existence of real composition. Consciousness, therefore, is so constituted that, inasmuch
as the thinking subject is at the same time its own object, it cannot divide itself although it can divide its
inhering determinations. For every object in relation to itself is absolute unity. Nevertheless, if the subject is
regarded externally, as an object of intuition, it must, in its character of phenomenon, possess the property of
composition. And it must always be regarded in this manner, if we wish to know whether there is or is not
contained in it a manifold whose parts are external to each other.
THIRD CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
THESIS.
Causality according to the laws of nature, is not the only causality operating to originate the phenomena of
the world. A causality of freedom is also necessary to account fully for these phenomena.
PROOF.
Let it be supposed, that there is no other kind of causality than that according to the laws of nature.
Consequently, everything that happens presupposes a previous condition, which it follows with absolute
certainty, in conformity with a rule. But this previous condition must itself be something that has happened
(that has arisen in time, as it did not exist before), for, if it has always been in existence, its consequence or
effect would not thus originate for the first time, but would likewise have always existed. The causality,
therefore, of a cause, whereby something happens, is itself a thing that has happened. Now this again
presupposes, in conformity with the law of nature, a previous condition and its causality, and this another
anterior to the former, and so on. If, then, everything happens solely in accordance with the laws of nature,
there cannot be any real first beginning of things, but only a subaltern or comparative beginning. There
cannot, therefore, be a completeness of series on the side of the causes which originate the one from the
other. But the law of nature is that nothing can happen without a sufficient a priori determined cause. The
proposition therefore if all causality is possible only in accordance with the laws of nature is, when stated
in this unlimited and general manner, selfcontradictory. It follows that this cannot be the only kind of
causality.
From what has been said, it follows that a causality must be admitted, by means of which something happens,
without its cause being determined according to necessary laws by some other cause preceding. That is to
say, there must exist an absolute spontaneity of cause, which of itself originates a series of phenomena which
proceeds according to natural laws consequently transcendental freedom, without which even in the course
of nature the succession of phenomena on the side of causes is never complete.
ANTITHESIS.
There is no such thing as freedom, but everything in the world happens solely according to the laws of nature.
PROOF.
Granted, that there does exist freedom in the transcendental sense, as a peculiar kind of causality, operating to
produce events in the world a faculty, that is to say, of originating a state, and consequently a series of
consequences from that state. In this case, not only the series originated by this spontaneity, but the
determination of this spontaneity itself to the production of the series, that is to say, the causality itself must
have an absolute commencement, such that nothing can precede to determine this action according to
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 154
Page No 159
unvarying laws. But every beginning of action presupposes in the acting cause a state of inaction; and a
dynamically primal beginning of action presupposes a state, which has no connection as regards causality
with the preceding state of the cause which does not, that is, in any wise result from it. Transcendental
freedom is therefore opposed to the natural law of cause and effect, and such a conjunction of successive
states in effective causes is destructive of the possibility of unity in experience and for that reason not to be
found in experience is consequently a mere fiction of thought.
We have, therefore, nothing but nature to which we must look for connection and order in cosmical events.
Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also a
relinquishing of the guidance of law and rule. For it cannot be alleged that, instead of the laws of nature, laws
of freedom may be introduced into the causality of the course of nature. For, if freedom were determined
according to laws, it would be no longer freedom, but merely nature. Nature, therefore, and transcendental
freedom are distinguishable as conformity to law and lawlessness. The former imposes upon understanding
the difficulty of seeking the origin of events ever higher and higher in the series of causes, inasmuch as
causality is always conditioned thereby; while it compensates this labour by the guarantee of a unity complete
and in conformity with law. The latter, on the contrary, holds out to the understanding the promise of a point
of rest in the chain of causes, by conducting it to an unconditioned causality, which professes to have the
power of spontaneous origination, but which, in its own utter blindness, deprives it of the guidance of rules,
by which alone a completely connected experience is possible.
OBSERVATIONS ON THE THIRD ANTINOMY.
ON THE THESIS.
The transcendental idea of freedom is far from constituting the entire content of the psychological conception
so termed, which is for the most part empirical. It merely presents us with the conception of spontaneity of
action, as the proper ground for imputing freedom to the cause of a certain class of objects. It is, however, the
true stumblingstone to philosophy, which meets with unconquerable difficulties in the way of its admitting
this kind of unconditioned causality. That element in the question of the freedom of the will, which bas for so
long a time placed speculative reason in such perplexity, is properly only transcendental, and concerns the
question, whether there must be held to exist a faculty of spontaneous origination of a series of successive
things or states. How such a faculty is possible is not a necessary inquiry; for in the case of natural causality
itself, we are obliged to content ourselves with the a priori knowledge that such a causality must be
presupposed, although we are quite incapable of comprehending how the being of one thing is possible
through the being of another, but must for this information look entirely to experience. Now we have
demonstrated this necessity of a free first beginning of a series of phenomena, only in so far as it is required
for the comprehension of an origin of the world, all following states being regarded as a succession according
to laws of nature alone. But, as there has thus been proved the existence of a faculty which can of itself
originate a series in time although we are unable to explain how it can exist we feel ourselves authorized to
admit, even in the midst of the natural course of events, a beginning, as regards causality, of different
successions of phenomena, and at the same time to attribute to all substances a faculty of free action. But we
ought in this case not to allow ourselves to fall into a common misunderstanding, and to suppose that,
because a successive series in the world can only have a comparatively first beginning another state or
condition of things always preceding an absolutely first beginning of a series in the course of nature is
impossible. For we are not speaking here of an absolutely first beginning in relation to time, but as regards
causality alone. When, for example, I, completely of my own free will, and independently of the necessarily
determinative influence of natural causes, rise from my chair, there commences with this event, including its
material consequences in infinitum, an absolutely new series; although, in relation to time, this event is
merely the continuation of a preceding series. For this resolution and act of mine do not form part of the
succession of effects in nature, and are not mere continuations of it; on the contrary, the determining causes
of nature cease to operate in reference to this event, which certainly succeeds the acts of nature, but does not
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 155
Page No 160
proceed from them. For these reasons, the action of a free agent must be termed, in regard to causality, if not
in relation to time, an absolutely primal beginning of a series of phenomena.
The justification of this need of reason to rest upon a free act as the first beginning of the series of natural
causes is evident from the fact, that all philosophers of antiquity (with the exception of the Epicurean school)
felt themselves obliged, when constructing a theory of the motions of the universe, to accept a prime mover,
that is, a freely acting cause, which spontaneously and prior to all other causes evolved this series of states.
They always felt the need of going beyond mere nature, for the purpose of making a first beginning
comprehensible.
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
The assertor of the allsufficiency of nature in regard to causality (transcendental Physiocracy), in opposition
to the doctrine of freedom, would defend his view of the question somewhat in the following manner. He
would say, in answer to the sophistical arguments of the opposite party: If you do not accept a mathematical
first, in relation to time, you have no need to seek a dynamical first, in regard to causality. Who compelled
you to imagine an absolutely primal condition of the world, and therewith an absolute beginning of the
gradually progressing successions of phenomena and, as some foundation for this fancy of yours, to set
bounds to unlimited nature? Inasmuch as the substances in the world have always existed at least the unity
of experience renders such a supposition quite necessary there is no difficulty in believing also, that the
changes in the conditions of these substances have always existed; and, consequently, that a first beginning,
mathematical or dynamical, is by no means required. The possibility of such an infinite derivation, without
any initial member from which all the others result, is certainly quite incomprehensible. But, if you are rash
enough to deny the enigmatical secrets of nature for this reason, you will find yourselves obliged to deny also
the existence of many fundamental properties of natural objects (such as fundamental forces), which you can
just as little comprehend; and even the possibility of so simple a conception as that of change must present to
you insuperable difficulties. For if experience did not teach you that it was real, you never could conceive a
priori the possibility of this ceaseless sequence of being and nonbeing.
But if the existence of a transcendental faculty of freedom is granted a faculty of originating changes in the
world this faculty must at least exist out of and apart from the world; although it is certainly a bold
assumption, that, over and above the complete content of all possible intuitions, there still exists an object
which cannot be presented in any possible perception. But, to attribute to substances in the world itself such a
faculty, is quite inadmissible; for, in this case; the connection of phenomena reciprocally determining and
determined according to general laws, which is termed nature, and along with it the criteria of empirical truth,
which enable us to distinguish experience from mere visionary dreaming, would almost entirely disappear. In
proximity with such a lawless faculty of freedom, a system of nature is hardly cogitable; for the laws of the
latter would be continually subject to the intrusive influences of the former, and the course of phenomena,
which would otherwise proceed regularly and uniformly, would become thereby confused and disconnected.
FOURTH CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.
THESIS.
There exists either in, or in connection with the world either as a part of it, or as the cause of itan
absolutely necessary being.
PROOF.
The world of sense, as the sum total of all phenomena, contains a series of changes. For, without such a
series, the mental representation of the series of time itself, as the condition of the possibility of the sensuous
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 156
Page No 161
world, could not be presented to us.* But every change stands under its condition, which precedes it in time
and renders it necessary. Now the existence of a given condition presupposes a complete series of conditions
up to the absolutely unconditioned, which alone is absolutely necessary. It follows that something that is
absolutely necessary must exist, if change exists as its consequence. But this necessary thing itself belongs to
the sensuous world. For suppose it to exist out of and apart from it, the series of cosmical changes would
receive from it a beginning, and yet this necessary cause would not itself belong to the world of sense. But
this is impossible. For, as the beginning of a series in time is determined only by that which precedes it in
time, the supreme condition of the beginning of a series of changes must exist in the time in which this series
itself did not exist; for a beginning supposes a time preceding, in which the thing that begins to be was not in
existence. The causality of the necessary cause of changes, and consequently the cause itself, must for these
reasons belong to time and to phenomena, time being possible only as the form of phenomena.
Consequently, it cannot be cogitated as separated from the world of sense the sum total of all phenomena.
There is, therefore, contained in the world, something that is absolutely necessary whether it be the whole
cosmical series itself, or only a part of it.
*Objectively, time, as the formal condition of the possibility of change, precedes all changes; but
subjectively, and in consciousness, the representation of time, like every other, is given solely by occasion of
perception.
ANTITHESIS.
An absolutely necessary being does not exist, either in the world, or out of it as its cause.
PROOF.
Grant that either the world itself is necessary, or that there is contained in it a necessary existence. Two cases
are possible. First, there must either be in the series of cosmical changes a beginning, which is
unconditionally necessary, and therefore uncaused which is at variance with the dynamical law of the
determination of all phenomena in time; or, secondly, the series itself is without beginning, and, although
contingent and conditioned in all its parts, is nevertheless absolutely necessary and unconditioned as a
whole which is selfcontradictory. For the existence of an aggregate cannot be necessary, if no single part
of it possesses necessary existence.
Grant, on the other band, that an absolutely necessary cause exists out of and apart from the world. This
cause, as the highest member in the series of the causes of cosmical changes, must originate or begin* the
existence of the latter and their series. In this case it must also begin to act, and its causality would therefore
belong to time, and consequently to the sum total of phenomena, that is, to the world. It follows that the cause
cannot be out of the world; which is contradictory to the hypothesis. Therefore, neither in the world, nor out
of it (but in causal connection with it), does there exist any absolutely necessary being.
*The word begin is taken in two senses. The first is active the cause being regarded as beginning a series of
conditions as its effect (infit). The second is passive the causality in the cause itself beginning to operate
(fit). I reason here from the first to the second.
OBSERVATIONS ON THE FOURTH ANTINOMY.
ON THE THESIS.
To demonstrate the existence of a necessary being, I cannot be permitted in this place to employ any other
than the cosmological argument, which ascends from the conditioned in phenomena to the unconditioned in
conception the unconditioned being considered the necessary condition of the absolute totality of the series.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 157
Page No 162
The proof, from the mere idea of a supreme being, belongs to another principle of reason and requires
separate discussion.
The pure cosmological proof demonstrates the existence of a necessary being, but at the same time leaves it
quite unsettled, whether this being is the world itself, or quite distinct from it. To establish the truth of the
latter view, principles are requisite, which are not cosmological and do not proceed in the series of
phenomena. We should require to introduce into our proof conceptions of contingent beings regarded
merely as objects of the understanding, and also a principle which enables us to connect these, by means of
mere conceptions, with a necessary being. But the proper place for all such arguments is a transcendent
philosophy, which has unhappily not yet been established.
But, if we begin our proof cosmologically, by laying at the foundation of it the series of phenomena, and the
regress in it according to empirical laws of causality, we are not at liberty to break off from this mode of
demonstration and to pass over to something which is not itself a member of the series. The condition must
be taken in exactly the same signification as the relation of the conditioned to its condition in the series has
been taken, for the series must conduct us in an unbroken regress to this supreme condition. But if this
relation is sensuous, and belongs to the possible empirical employment of understanding, the supreme
condition or cause must close the regressive series according to the laws of sensibility and consequently, must
belong to the series of time. It follows that this necessary existence must be regarded as the highest member
of the cosmical series.
Certain philosophers have, nevertheless, allowed themselves the liberty of making such a saltus (metabasis
eis allo gonos). From the changes in the world they have concluded their empirical contingency, that is, their
dependence on empiricallydetermined causes, and they thus admitted an ascending series of empirical
conditions: and in this they are quite right. But as they could not find in this series any primal beginning or
any highest member, they passed suddenly from the empirical conception of contingency to the pure
category, which presents us with a series not sensuous, but intellectual whose completeness does certainly
rest upon the existence of an absolutely necessary cause. Nay, more, this intellectual series is not tied to any
sensuous conditions; and is therefore free from the condition of time, which requires it spontaneously to
begin its causality in time. But such a procedure is perfectly inadmissible, as will be made plain from what
follows.
In the pure sense of the categories, that is contingent the contradictory opposite of which is possible. Now we
cannot reason from empirical contingency to intellectual. The opposite of that which is changed the opposite
of its state is actual at another time, and is therefore possible. Consequently, it is not the contradictory
opposite of the former state. To be that, it is necessary that, in the same time in which the preceding state
existed, its opposite could have existed in its place; but such a cognition is not given us in the mere
phenomenon of change. A body that was in motion = A, comes into a state of rest = nonA. Now it cannot be
concluded from the fact that a state opposite to the state A follows it, that the contradictory opposite of A is
possible; and that A is therefore contingent. To prove this, we should require to know that the state of rest
could have existed in the very same time in which the motion took place. Now we know nothing more than
that the state of rest was actual in the time that followed the state of motion; consequently, that it was also
possible. But motion at one time, and rest at another time, are not contradictorily opposed to each other. It
follows from what has been said that the succession of opposite determinations, that is, change, does not
demonstrate the fact of contingency as represented in the conceptions of the pure understanding; and that it
cannot, therefore, conduct us to the fact of the existence of a necessary being. Change proves merely
empirical contingency, that is to say, that the new state could not have existed without a cause, which belongs
to the preceding time. This cause even although it is regarded as absolutely necessary must be presented to
us in time, and must belong to the series of phenomena.
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason. 158
Page No 163
The difficulties which meet us, in our attempt to rise through the series of phenomena to the existence of an
absolutely necessary supreme cause, must not originate from our inability to establish the truth of our mere
conceptions of the necessary existence of a thing. That is to say, our objections not be ontological, but must
be directed against the causal connection with a series of phenomena of a condition which is itself
unconditioned. In one word, they must be cosmological and relate to empirical laws. We must show that the
regress in the series of causes (in the world of sense) cannot conclude with an empirically unconditioned
condition, and that the cosmological argument from the contingency of the cosmical state a contingency
alleged to arise from change does not justify us in accepting a first cause, that is, a prime originator of the
cosmical series.
The reader will observe in this antinomy a very remarkable contrast. The very same grounds of proof which
established in the thesis the existence of a supreme being, demonstrated in the antithesis and with equal
strictness the nonexistence of such a being. We found, first, that a necessary being exists, because the
whole time past contains the series of all conditions, and with it, therefore, the unconditioned (the necessary);
secondly, that there does not exist any necessary being, for the same reason, that the whole time past contains
the series of all conditions which are themselves, therefore, in the aggregate, conditioned. The cause of this
seeming incongruity is as follows. We attend, in the first argument, solely to the absolute totality of the series
of conditions, the one of which determines the other in time, and thus arrive at a necessary unconditioned. In
the second, we consider, on the contrary, the contingency of everything that is determined in the series of
time for every event is preceded by a time, in which the condition itself must be determined as conditioned
and thus everything that is unconditioned or absolutely necessary disappears. In both, the mode of proof is
quite in accordance with the common procedure of human reason, which often falls into discord with itself,
from considering an object from two different points of view. Herr von Mairan regarded the controversy
between two celebrated astronomers, which arose from a similar difficulty as to the choice of a proper
standpoint, as a phenomenon of sufficient importance to warrant a separate treatise on the subject. The one
concluded: the moon revolves on its own axis, because it constantly presents the same side to the earth; the
other declared that the moon does not revolve on its own axis, for the same reason. Both conclusions were
perfectly correct, according to the point of view from which the motions of the moon were considered.
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions.
We have thus completely before us the dialectical procedure of the cosmological ideas. No possible
experience can present us with an object adequate to them in extent. Nay, more, reason itself cannot cogitate
them as according with the general laws of experience. And yet they are not arbitrary fictions of thought. On
the contrary, reason, in its uninterrupted progress in the empirical synthesis, is necessarily conducted to them,
when it endeavours to free from all conditions and to comprehend in its unconditioned totality that which can
only be determined conditionally in accordance with the laws of experience. These dialectical propositions
are so many attempts to solve four natural and unavoidable problems of reason. There are neither more, nor
can there be less, than this number, because there are no other series of synthetical hypotheses, limiting a
priori the empirical synthesis.
The brilliant claims of reason striving to extend its dominion beyond the limits of experience, have been
represented above only in dry formulae, which contain merely the grounds of its pretensions. They have,
besides, in conformity with the character of a transcendental philosophy, been freed from every empirical
element; although the full splendour of the promises they hold out, and the anticipations they excite,
manifests itself only when in connection with empirical cognitions. In the application of them, however, and
in the advancing enlargement of the employment of reason, while struggling to rise from the region of
experience and to soar to those sublime ideas, philosophy discovers a value and a dignity, which, if it could
but make good its assertions, would raise it far above all other departments of human knowledge professing,
as it does, to present a sure foundation for our highest hopes and the ultimate aims of all the exertions of
reason. The questions: whether the world has a beginning and a limit to its extension in space; whether there
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions. 159
Page No 164
exists anywhere, or perhaps, in my own thinking Self, an indivisible and indestructible unity or whether
nothing but what is divisible and transitory exists; whether I am a free agent, or, like other beings, am bound
in the chains of nature and fate; whether, finally, there is a supreme cause of the world, or all our thought and
speculation must end with nature and the order of external things are questions for the solution of which the
mathematician would willingly exchange his whole science; for in it there is no satisfaction for the highest
aspirations and most ardent desires of humanity. Nay, it may even be said that the true value of mathematics
that pride of human reason consists in this: that she guides reason to the knowledge of nature in her greater
as well as in her less manifestations in her beautiful order and regularity guides her, moreover, to an
insight into the wonderful unity of the moving forces in the operations of nature, far beyond the expectations
of a philosophy building only on experience; and that she thus encourages philosophy to extend the province
of reason beyond all experience, and at the same time provides it with the most excellent materials for
supporting its investigations, in so far as their nature admits, by adequate and accordant intuitions.
Unfortunately for speculation but perhaps fortunately for the practical interests of humanity reason, in the
midst of her highest anticipations, finds herself hemmed in by a press of opposite and contradictory
conclusions, from which neither her honour nor her safety will permit her to draw back. Nor can she regard
these conflicting trains of reasoning with indifference as mere passages at arms, still less can she command
peace; for in the subject of the conflict she has a deep interest. There is no other course left open to her than
to reflect with herself upon the origin of this disunion in reason whether it may not arise from a mere
misunderstanding. After such an inquiry, arrogant claims would have to be given up on both sides; but the
sovereignty of reason over understanding and sense would be based upon a sure foundation.
We shall at present defer this radical inquiry and, in the meantime, consider for a little what side in the
controversy we should most willingly take, if we were obliged to become partisans at all. As, in this case, we
leave out of sight altogether the logical criterion of truth, and merely consult our own interest in reference to
the question, these considerations, although inadequate to settle the question of right in either party, will
enable us to comprehend how those who have taken part in the struggle, adopt the one view rather than the
other no special insight into the subject, however, having influenced their choice. They will, at the same
time, explain to us many other things by the way for example, the fiery zeal on the one side and the cold
maintenance of their cause on the other; why the one party has met with the warmest approbations, and the
other has always been repulsed by irreconcilable prejudices.
There is one thing, however, that determines the proper point of view, from which alone this preliminary
inquiry can be instituted and carried on with the proper completeness and that is the comparison of the
principles from which both sides, thesis and antithesis, proceed. My readers would remark in the propositions
of the antithesis a complete uniformity in the mode of thought and a perfect unity of principle. Its principle
was that of pure empiricism, not only in the explication of the phenomena in the world, but also in the
solution of the transcendental ideas, even of that of the universe itself. The affirmations of the thesis, on the
contrary, were based, in addition to the empirical mode of explanation employed in the series of phenomena,
on intellectual propositions; and its principles were in so far not simple. I shall term the thesis, in view of its
essential characteristic, the dogmatism of pure reason.
On the side of Dogmatism, or of the thesis, therefore, in the determination of the cosmological ideas, we find:
1. A practical interest, which must be very dear to every rightthinking man. That the word has a beginning
that the nature of my thinking self is simple, and therefore indestructible that I am a free agent, and raised
above the compulsion of nature and her laws and, finally, that the entire order of things, which form the
world, is dependent upon a Supreme Being, from whom the whole receives unity and connection these are
so many foundationstones of morality and religion. The antithesis deprives us of all these supports or, at
least, seems so to deprive us.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions. 160
Page No 165
2. A speculative interest of reason manifests itself on this side. For, if we take the transcendental ideas and
employ them in the manner which the thesis directs, we can exhibit completely a priori the entire chain of
conditions, and understand the derivation of the conditioned beginning from the unconditioned. This the
antithesis does not do; and for this reason does not meet with so welcome a reception. For it can give no
answer to our question respecting the conditions of its synthesis except such as must be supplemented by
another question, and so on to infinity. According to it, we must rise from a given beginning to one still
higher; every part conducts us to a still smaller one; every event is preceded by another event which is its
cause; and the conditions of existence rest always upon other and still higher conditions, and find neither end
nor basis in some selfsubsistent thing as the primal being.
3. This side has also the advantage of popularity; and this constitutes no small part of its claim to favour. The
common understanding does not find the least difficulty in the idea of the unconditioned beginning of all
synthesis accustomed, as it is, rather to follow our consequences than to seek for a proper basis for
cognition. In the conception of an absolute first, moreover the possibility of which it does not inquire into
it is highly gratified to find a firmlyestablished point of departure for its attempts at theory; while in the
restless and continuous ascent from the conditioned to the condition, always with one foot in the air, it can
find no satisfaction.
On the side of the antithesis, or Empiricism, in the determination of the cosmological ideas:
1. We cannot discover any such practical interest arising from pure principles of reason as morality and
religion present. On the contrary, pure empiricism seems to empty them of all their power and influence. If
there does not exist a Supreme Being distinct from the world if the world is without beginning,
consequently without a Creator if our wills are not free, and the soul is divisible and subject to corruption
just like matter the ideas and principles of morality lose all validity and fall with the transcendental ideas
which constituted their theoretical support.
2. But empiricism, in compensation, holds out to reason, in its speculative interests, certain important
advantages, far exceeding any that the dogmatist can promise us. For, when employed by the empiricist,
understanding is always upon its proper ground of investigation the field of possible experience, the laws of
which it can explore, and thus extend its cognition securely and with clear intelligence without being stopped
by limits in any direction. Here can it and ought it to find and present to intuition its proper object not only
in itself, but in all its relations; or, if it employ conceptions, upon this ground it can always present the
corresponding images in clear and unmistakable intuitions. It is quite unnecessary for it to renounce the
guidance of nature, to attach itself to ideas, the objects of which it cannot know; because, as mere intellectual
entities, they cannot be presented in any intuition. On the contrary, it is not even permitted to abandon its
proper occupation, under the pretence that it has been brought to a conclusion (for it never can be), and to
pass into the region of idealizing reason and transcendent conceptions, which it is not required to observe and
explore the laws of nature, but merely to think and to imagine secure from being contradicted by facts,
because they have not been called as witnesses, but passed by, or perhaps subordinated to the socalled
higher interests and considerations of pure reason.
Hence the empiricist will never allow himself to accept any epoch of nature for the first the absolutely
primal state; he will not believe that there can be limits to his outlook into her wide domains, nor pass from
the objects of nature, which he can satisfactorily explain by means of observation and mathematical thought
which he can determine synthetically in intuition, to those which neither sense nor imagination can ever
present in concreto; he will not concede the existence of a faculty in nature, operating independently of the
laws of nature a concession which would introduce uncertainty into the procedure of the understanding,
which is guided by necessary laws to the observation of phenomena; nor, finally, will he permit himself to
seek a cause beyond nature, inasmuch as we know nothing but it, and from it alone receive an objective basis
for all our conceptions and instruction in the unvarying laws of things.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions. 161
Page No 166
In truth, if the empirical philosopher had no other purpose in the establishment of his antithesis than to check
the presumption of a reason which mistakes its true destination, which boasts of its insight and its knowledge,
just where all insight and knowledge cease to exist, and regards that which is valid only in relation to a
practical interest, as an advancement of the speculative interests of the mind (in order, when it is convenient
for itself, to break the thread of our physical investigations, and, under pretence of extending our cognition,
connect them with transcendental ideas, by means of which we really know only that we know nothing) if, I
say, the empiricist rested satisfied with this benefit, the principle advanced by him would be a maxim
recommending moderation in the pretensions of reason and modesty in its affirmations, and at the same time
would direct us to the right mode of extending the province of the understanding, by the help of the only true
teacher, experience. In obedience to this advice, intellectual hypotheses and faith would not be called in aid
of our practical interests; nor should we introduce them under the pompous titles of science and insight. For
speculative cognition cannot find an objective basis any other where than in experience; and, when we
overstep its limits our synthesis, which requires ever new cognitions independent of experience, has no
substratum of intuition upon which to build.
But if as often happens empiricism, in relation to ideas, becomes itself dogmatic and boldly denies that
which is above the sphere of its phenomenal cognition, it falls itself into the error of intemperance an error
which is here all the more reprehensible, as thereby the practical interest of reason receives an irreparable
injury.
And this constitutes the opposition between Epicureanism* and Platonism.
*It is, however, still a matter of doubt whether Epicurus ever propounded these principles as directions for the
objective employment of the understanding. If, indeed, they were nothing more than maxims for the
speculative exercise of reason, he gives evidence therein a more genuine philosophic spirit than any of the
philosophers of antiquity. That, in the explanation of phenomena, we must proceed as if the field of inquiry
had neither limits in space nor commencement in time; that we must be satisfied with the teaching of
experience in reference to the material of which the world is posed; that we must not look for any other mode
of the origination of events than that which is determined by the unalterable laws of nature; and finally, that
we not employ the hypothesis of a cause distinct from the world to account for a phenomenon or for the
world itself are principles for the extension of speculative philosophy, and the discovery of the true sources
of the principles of morals, which, however little conformed to in the present day, are undoubtedly correct. At
the same time, any one desirous of ignoring, in mere speculation, these dogmatical propositions, need not for
that reason be accused of denying them.
Both Epicurus and Plato assert more in their systems than they know. The former encourages and advances
science although to the prejudice of the practical; the latter presents us with excellent principles for the
investigation of the practical, but, in relation to everything regarding which we can attain to speculative
cognition, permits reason to append idealistic explanations of natural phenomena, to the great injury of
physical investigation.
3. In regard to the third motive for the preliminary choice of a party in this war of assertions, it seems very
extraordinary that empiricism should be utterly unpopular. We should be inclined to believe that the common
understanding would receive it with pleasure promising as it does to satisfy it without passing the bounds of
experience and its connected order; while transcendental dogmatism obliges it to rise to conceptions which
far surpass the intelligence and ability of the most practised thinkers. But in this, in truth, is to be found its
real motive. For the common understanding thus finds itself in a situation where not even the most learned
can have the advantage of it. If it understands little or nothing about these transcendental conceptions, no one
can boast of understanding any more; and although it may not express itself in so scholastically correct a
manner as others, it can busy itself with reasoning and arguments without end, wandering among mere ideas,
about which one can always be very eloquent, because we know nothing about them; while, in the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Selfcontradictions. 162
Page No 167
observation and investigation of nature, it would be forced to remain dumb and to confess its utter ignorance.
Thus indolence and vanity form of themselves strong recommendations of these principles. Besides, although
it is a hard thing for a philosopher to assume a principle, of which he can give to himself no reasonable
account, and still more to employ conceptions, the objective reality of which cannot be established, nothing is
more usual with the common understanding. It wants something which will allow it to go to work with
confidence. The difficulty of even comprehending a supposition does not disquiet it, because not knowing
what comprehending means it never even thinks of the supposition it may be adopting as a principle; and
regards as known that with which it has become familiar from constant use. And, at last, all speculative
interests disappear before the practical interests which it holds dear; and it fancies that it understands and
knows what its necessities and hopes incite it to assume or to believe. Thus the empiricism of
transcendentally idealizing reason is robbed of all popularity; and, however prejudicial it may be to the
highest practical principles, there is no fear that it will ever pass the limits of the schools, or acquire any
favour or influence in society or with the multitude a
Human reason is by nature architectonic. That is to say, it regards all cognitions as parts of a possible system,
and hence accepts only such principles as at least do not incapacitate a cognition to which we may have
attained from being placed along with others in a general system. But the propositions of the antithesis are of
a character which renders the completion of an edifice of cognitions impossible. According to these, beyond
one state or epoch of the world there is always to be found one more ancient; in every part always other parts
themselves divisible; preceding every event another, the origin of which must itself be sought still higher; and
everything in existence is conditioned, and still not dependent on an unconditioned and primal existence. As,
therefore, the antithesis will not concede the existence of a first beginning which might be available as a
foundation, a complete edifice of cognition, in the presence of such hypothesis, is utterly impossible. Thus
the architectonic interest of reason, which requires a unity not empirical, but a priori and rational forms a
natural recommendation for the assertions of the thesis in our antinomy.
But if any one could free himself entirely from all considerations of interest, and weigh without partiality the
assertions of reason, attending only to their content, irrespective of the consequences which follow from
them; such a person, on the supposition that he knew no other way out of the confusion than to settle the truth
of one or other of the conflicting doctrines, would live in a state of continual hesitation. Today, he would feel
convinced that the human will is free; tomorrow, considering the indissoluble chain of nature, he would
look on freedom as a mere illusion and declare nature to be allinall. But, if he were called to action, the
play of the merely speculative reason would disappear like the shapes of a dream, and practical interest would
dictate his choice of principles. But, as it well befits a reflective and inquiring being to devote certain periods
of time to the examination of its own reason to divest itself of all partiality, and frankly to communicate its
observations for the judgement and opinion of others; so no one can be blamed for, much less prevented
from, placing both parties on their trial, with permission to end themselves, free from intimidation, before
intimidation, before a sworn jury of equal condition with themselves the condition of weak and fallible men.
SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting
a Solution of its Transcendental Problems.
To avow an ability to solve all problems and to answer all questions would be a profession certain to convict
any philosopher of extravagant boasting and selfconceit, and at once to destroy the confidence that might
otherwise have been reposed in him. There are, however, sciences so constituted that every question arising
within their sphere must necessarily be capable of receiving an answer from the knowledge already
possessed, for the answer must be received from the same sources whence the question arose. In such
sciences it is not allowable to excuse ourselves on the plea of necessary and unavoidable ignorance; a
solution is absolutely requisite. The rule of right and wrong must help us to the knowledge of what is right or
wrong in all possible cases; otherwise, the idea of obligation or duty would be utterly null, for we cannot have
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental Problems. 163
Page No 168
any obligation to that which we cannot know. On the other hand, in our investigations of the phenomena of
nature, much must remain uncertain, and many questions continue insoluble; because what we know of
nature is far from being sufficient to explain all the phenomena that are presented to our observation. Now the
question is: "Whether there is in transcendental philosophy any question, relating to an object presented to
pure reason, which is unanswerable by this reason; and whether we must regard the subject of the question as
quite uncertain, so far as our knowledge extends, and must give it a place among those subjects, of which we
have just so much conception as is sufficient to enable us to raise a question faculty or materials failing us,
however, when we attempt an answer. the world
Now I maintain that, among all speculative cognition, the peculiarity of transcendental philosophy is that
there is no question, relating to an object presented to pure reason, which is insoluble by this reason; and that
the profession of unavoidable ignorance the problem being alleged to be beyond the reach of our faculties
cannot free us from the obligation to present a complete and satisfactory answer. For the very conception
which enables us to raise the question must give us the power of answering it; inasmuch as the object, as in
the case of right and wrong, is not to be discovered out of the conception.
But, in transcendental philosophy, it is only the cosmological questions to which we can demand a
satisfactory answer in relation to the constitution of their object; and the philosopher is not permitted to avail
himself of the pretext of necessary ignorance and impenetrable obscurity. These questions relate solely to the
cosmological ideas. For the object must be given in experience, and the question relates to the adequateness
of the object to an idea. If the object is transcendental and therefore itself unknown; if the question, for
example, is whether the object the something, the phenomenon of which (internal in ourselves) is thought
that is to say, the soul, is in itself a simple being; or whether there is a cause of all things, which is absolutely
necessary in such cases we are seeking for our idea an object, of which we may confess that it is unknown
to us, though we must not on that account assert that it is impossible.* The cosmological ideas alone posses
the peculiarity that we can presuppose the object of them and the empirical synthesis requisite for the
conception of that object to be given; and the question, which arises from these ideas, relates merely to the
progress of this synthesis, in so far as it must contain absolute totality which, however, is not empirical, as it
cannot be given in any experience. Now, as the question here is solely in regard to a thing as the object of a
possible experience and not as a thing in itself, the answer to the transcendental cosmological question need
not be sought out of the idea, for the question does not regard an object in itself. The question in relation to a
possible experience is not, "What can be given in an experience in concreto" but "what is contained in the
idea, to which the empirical synthesis must approximate." The question must therefore be capable of solution
from the idea alone. For the idea is a creation of reason itself, which therefore cannot disclaim the obligation
to answer or refer us to the unknown object.
*The question, "What is the constitution of a transcendental object?" is unanswerable we are unable to say
what it is; but we can perceive that the question itself is nothing; because it does not relate to any object that
can be presented to us. For this reason, we must consider all the questions raised in transcendental
psychology as answerable and as really answered; for they relate to the transcendental subject of all internal
phenomena, which is not itself phenomenon and consequently not given as an object, in which, moreover,
none of the categories and it is to them that the question is properly directed find any conditions of its
application. Here, therefore, is a case where no answer is the only proper answer. For a question regarding the
constitution of a something which cannot be cogitated by any determined predicate, being completely beyond
the sphere of objects and experience, is perfectly null and void.
It is not so extraordinary, as it at first sight appears, that a science should demand and expect satisfactory
answers to all the questions that may arise within its own sphere (questiones domesticae), although, up to a
certain time, these answers may not have been discovered. There are, in addition to transcendental
philosophy, only two pure sciences of reason; the one with a speculative, the other with a practical content
pure mathematics and pure ethics. Has any one ever heard it alleged that, from our complete and necessary
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental Problems. 164
Page No 169
ignorance of the conditions, it is uncertain what exact relation the diameter of a circle bears to the circle in
rational or irrational numbers? By the former the sum cannot be given exactly, by the latter only
approximately; and therefore we decide that the impossibility of a solution of the question is evident.
Lambert presented us with a demonstration of this. In the general principles of morals there can be nothing
uncertain, for the propositions are either utterly without meaning, or must originate solely in our rational
conceptions. On the other hand, there must be in physical science an infinite number of conjectures, which
can never become certainties; because the phenomena of nature are not given as objects dependent on our
conceptions. The key to the solution of such questions cannot, therefore, be found in our conceptions, or in
pure thought, but must lie without us and for that reason is in many cases not to be discovered; and
consequently a satisfactory explanation cannot be expected. The questions of transcendental analytic, which
relate to the deduction of our pure cognition, are not to be regarded as of the same kind as those mentioned
above; for we are not at present treating of the certainty of judgements in relation to the origin of our
conceptions, but only of that certainty in relation to objects.
We cannot, therefore, escape the responsibility of at least a critical solution of the questions of reason, by
complaints of the limited nature of our faculties, and the seemingly humble confession that it is beyond the
power of our reason to decide, whether the world has existed from all eternity or had a beginning whether it
is infinitely extended, or enclosed within certain limits whether anything in the world is simple, or whether
everything must be capable of infinite divisibility whether freedom can originate phenomena, or whether
everything is absolutely dependent on the laws and order of nature and, finally, whether there exists a being
that is completely unconditioned and necessary, or whether the existence of everything is conditioned and
consequently dependent on something external to itself, and therefore in its own nature contingent. For all
these questions relate to an object, which can be given nowhere else than in thought. This object is the
absolutely unconditioned totality of the synthesis of phenomena. If the conceptions in our minds do not assist
us to some certain result in regard to these problems, we must not defend ourselves on the plea that the object
itself remains hidden from and unknown to us. For no such thing or object can be given it is not to be found
out of the idea in our minds. We must seek the cause of our failure in our idea itself, which is an insoluble
problem and in regard to which we obstinately assume that there exists a real object corresponding and
adequate to it. A clear explanation of the dialectic which lies in our conception, will very soon enable us to
come to a satisfactory decision in regard to such a question.
The pretext that we are unable to arrive at certainty in regard to these problems may be met with this
question, which requires at least a plain answer: "From what source do the ideas originate, the solution of
which involves you in such difficulties? Are you seeking for an explanation of certain phenomena; and do
you expect these ideas to give you the principles or the rules of this explanation?" Let it be granted, that all
nature was laid open before you; that nothing was hid from your senses and your consciousness. Still, you
could not cognize in concreto the object of your ideas in any experience. For what is demanded is not only
this full and complete intuition, but also a complete synthesis and the consciousness of its absolute totality;
and this is not possible by means of any empirical cognition. It follows that your question your idea is by
no means necessary for the explanation of any phenomenon; and the idea cannot have been in any sense
given by the object itself. For such an object can never be presented to us, because it cannot be given by any
possible experience. Whatever perceptions you may attain to, you are still surrounded by conditions in
space, or in time and you cannot discover anything unconditioned; nor can you decide whether this
unconditioned is to be placed in an absolute beginning of the synthesis, or in an absolute totality of the series
without beginning. A whole, in the empirical signification of the term, is always merely comparative. The
absolute whole of quantity (the universe), of division, of derivation, of the condition of existence, with the
question whether it is to be produced by finite or infinite synthesis, no possible experience can instruct us
concerning. You will not, for example, be able to explain the phenomena of a body in the least degree better,
whether you believe it to consist of simple, or of composite parts; for a simple phenomenon and just as little
an infinite series of composition can never be presented to your perception. Phenomena require and admit of
explanation, only in so far as the conditions of that explanation are given in perception; but the sum total of
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental Problems. 165
Page No 170
that which is given in phenomena, considered as an absolute whole, is itself a perception and we cannot
therefore seek for explanations of this whole beyond itself, in other perceptions. The explanation of this
whole is the proper object of the transcendental problems of pure reason.
Although, therefore, the solution of these problems is unattainable through experience, we must not permit
ourselves to say that it is uncertain how the object of our inquiries is constituted. For the object is in our own
mind and cannot be discovered in experience; and we have only to take care that our thoughts are consistent
with each other, and to avoid falling into the amphiboly of regarding our idea as a representation of an object
empirically given, and therefore to be cognized according to the laws of experience. A dogmatical solution is
therefore not only unsatisfactory but impossible. The critical solution, which may be a perfectly certain one,
does not consider the question objectively, but proceeds by inquiring into the basis of the cognition upon
which the question rests.
SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems
presented in the four Transcendental Ideas.
We should be quite willing to desist from the demand of a dogmatical answer to our questions, if we
understood beforehand that, be the answer what it may, it would only serve to increase our ignorance, to
throw us from one incomprehensibility into another, from one obscurity into another still greater, and perhaps
lead us into irreconcilable contradictions. If a dogmatical affirmative or negative answer is demanded, is it at
all prudent to set aside the probable grounds of a solution which lie before us and to take into consideration
what advantage we shall gain, if the answer is to favour the one side or the other? If it happens that in both
cases the answer is mere nonsense, we have in this an irresistible summons to institute a critical investigation
of the question, for the purpose of discovering whether it is based on a groundless presupposition and relates
to an idea, the falsity of which would be more easily exposed in its application and consequences than in the
mere representation of its content. This is the great utility of the sceptical mode of treating the questions
addressed by pure reason to itself. By this method we easily rid ourselves of the confusions of dogmatism,
and establish in its place a temperate criticism, which, as a genuine cathartic, will successfully remove the
presumptuous notions of philosophy and their consequence the vain pretension to universal science.
If, then, I could understand the nature of a cosmological idea and perceive, before I entered on the discussion
of the subject at all, that, whatever side of the question regarding the unconditioned of the regressive
synthesis of phenomena it favoured it must either be too great or too small for every conception of the
understanding I would be able to comprehend how the idea, which relates to an object of experience an
experience which must be adequate to and in accordance with a possible conception of the understanding
must be completely void and without significance, inasmuch as its object is inadequate, consider it as we
may. And this is actually the case with all cosmological conceptions, which, for the reason above mentioned,
involve reason, so long as it remains attached to them, in an unavoidable antinomy. For suppose:
First, that the world has no beginning in this case it is too large for our conception; for this conception,
which consists in a successive regress, cannot overtake the whole eternity that has elapsed. Grant that it has a
beginning, it is then too small for the conception of the understanding. For, as a beginning presupposes a time
preceding, it cannot be unconditioned; and the law of the empirical employment of the understanding
imposes the necessity of looking for a higher condition of time; and the world is, therefore, evidently too
small for this law.
The same is the case with the double answer to the question regarding the extent, in space, of the world. For,
if it is infinite and unlimited, it must be too large for every possible empirical conception. If it is finite and
limited, we have a right to ask: "What determines these limits?" Void space is not a selfsubsistent correlate
of things, and cannot be a final condition and still less an empirical condition, forming a part of a possible
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems presented in the four Transcendental Ideas. 166
Page No 171
experience. For how can we have any experience or perception of an absolute void? But the absolute totality
of the empirical synthesis requires that the unconditioned be an empirical conception. Consequently, a finite
world is too small for our conception.
Secondly, if every phenomenon (matter) in space consists of an infinite number of parts, the regress of the
division is always too great for our conception; and if the division of space must cease with some member of
the division (the simple), it is too small for the idea of the unconditioned. For the member at which we have
discontinued our division still admits a regress to many more parts contained in the object.
Thirdly, suppose that every event in the world happens in accordance with the laws of nature; the causality of
a cause must itself be an event and necessitates a regress to a still higher cause, and consequently the
unceasing prolongation of the series of conditions a parte priori. Operative nature is therefore too large for
every conception we can form in the synthesis of cosmical events.
If we admit the existence of spontaneously produced events, that is, of free agency, we are driven, in our
search for sufficient reasons, on an unavoidable law of nature and are compelled to appeal to the empirical
law of causality, and we find that any such totality of connection in our synthesis is too small for our
necessary empirical conception.
Fourthly, if we assume the existence of an absolutely necessary being whether it be the world or something
in the world, or the cause of the world we must place it in a time at an infinite distance from any given
moment; for, otherwise, it must be dependent on some other and higher existence. Such an existence is, in
this case, too large for our empirical conception, and unattainable by the continued regress of any synthesis.
But if we believe that everything in the world be it condition or conditioned is contingent; every given
existence is too small for our conception. For in this case we are compelled to seek for some other existence
upon which the former depends.
We have said that in all these cases the cosmological idea is either too great or too small for the empirical
regress in a synthesis, and consequently for every possible conception of the understanding. Why did we not
express ourselves in a manner exactly the reverse of this and, instead of accusing the cosmological idea of
over stepping or of falling short of its true aim, possible experience, say that, in the first case, the empirical
conception is always too small for the idea, and in the second too great, and thus attach the blame of these
contradictions to the empirical regress? The reason is this. Possible experience can alone give reality to our
conceptions; without it a conception is merely an idea, without truth or relation to an object. Hence a possible
empirical conception must be the standard by which we are to judge whether an idea is anything more than an
idea and fiction of thought, or whether it relates to an object in the world. If we say of a thing that in relation
to some other thing it is too large or too small, the former is considered as existing for the sake of the latter,
and requiring to be adapted to it. Among the trivial subjects of discussion in the old schools of dialectics was
this question: "If a ball cannot pass through a hole, shall we say that the ball is too large or the hole too
small?" In this case it is indifferent what expression we employ; for we do not know which exists for the sake
of the other. On the other hand, we cannot say: "The man is too long for his coat"; but: "The coat is too short
for the man."
We are thus led to the wellfounded suspicion that the cosmological ideas, and all the conflicting sophistical
assertions connected with them, are based upon a false and fictitious conception of the mode in which the
object of these ideas is presented to us; and this suspicion will probably direct us how to expose the illusion
that has so long led us astray from the truth.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems presented in the four Transcendental Ideas. 167
Page No 172
SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Pure
Cosmological Dialectic.
In the transcendental aesthetic we proved that everything intuited in space and time, all objects of a possible
experience, are nothing but phenomena, that is, mere representations; and that these, as presented to us as
extended bodies, or as series of changes have no selfsubsistent existence apart from human thought. This
doctrine I call Transcendental Idealism.* The realist in the transcendental sense regards these modifications
of our sensibility, these mere representations, as things subsisting in themselves.
*I have elsewhere termed this theory formal idealism, to distinguish it from material idealism, which doubts
or denies the existence of external things. To avoid ambiguity, it seems advisable in many cases to employ
this term instead of that mentioned in the text.
It would be unjust to accuse us of holding the longdecried theory of empirical idealism, which, while
admitting the reality of space, denies, or at least doubts, the existence of bodies extended in it, and thus leaves
us without a sufficient criterion of reality and illusion. The supporters of this theory find no difficulty in
admitting the reality of the phenomena of the internal sense in time; nay, they go the length of maintaining
that this internal experience is of itself a sufficient proof of the real existence of its object as a thing in itself.
Transcendental idealism allows that the objects of external intuition as intuited in space, and all changes in
time as represented by the internal sense, are real. For, as space is the form of that intuition which we call
external, and, without objects in space, no empirical representation could be given us, we can and ought to
regard extended bodies in it as real. The case is the same with representations in time. But time and space,
with all phenomena therein, are not in themselves things. They are nothing but representations and cannot
exist out of and apart from the mind. Nay, the sensuous internal intuition of the mind (as the object of
consciousness), the determination of which is represented by the succession of different states in time, is not
the real, proper self, as it exists in itself not the transcendental subject but only a phenomenon, which is
presented to the sensibility of this, to us, unknown being. This internal phenomenon cannot be admitted to be
a selfsubsisting thing; for its condition is time, and time cannot be the condition of a thing in itself. But the
empirical truth of phenomena in space and time is guaranteed beyond the possibility of doubt, and
sufficiently distinguished from the illusion of dreams or fancy although both have a proper and thorough
connection in an experience according to empirical laws. The objects of experience then are not things in
themselves, but are given only in experience, and have no existence apart from and independently of
experience. That there may be inhabitants in the moon, although no one has ever observed them, must
certainly be admitted; but this assertion means only, that we may in the possible progress of experience
discover them at some future time. For that which stands in connection with a perception according to the
laws of the progress of experience is real. They are therefore really existent, if they stand in empirical
connection with my actual or real consciousness, although they are not in themselves real, that is, apart from
the progress of experience.
There is nothing actually given we can be conscious of nothing as real, except a perception and the
empirical progression from it to other possible perceptions. For phenomena, as mere representations, are real
only in perception; and perception is, in fact, nothing but the reality of an empirical representation, that is, a
phenomenon. To call a phenomenon a real thing prior to perception means either that we must meet with this
phenomenon in the progress of experience, or it means nothing at all. For I can say only of a thing in itself
that it exists without relation to the senses and experience. But we are speaking here merely of phenomena in
space and time, both of which are determinations of sensibility, and not of things in themselves. It follows
that phenomena are not things in themselves, but are mere representations, which if not given in us in
perception are nonexistent.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Pure Cosmological Dialectic. 168
Page No 173
The faculty of sensuous intuition is properly a receptivity a capacity of being affected in a certain manner by
representations, the relation of which to each other is a pure intuition of space and time the pure forms of
sensibility. These representations, in so far as they are connected and determinable in this relation (in space
and time) according to laws of the unity of experience, are called objects. The nonsensuous cause of these
representations is completely unknown to us and hence cannot be intuited as an object. For such an object
could not be represented either in space or in time; and without these conditions intuition or representation is
impossible. We may, at the same time, term the nonsensuous cause of phenomena the transcendental
object but merely as a mental correlate to sensibility, considered as a receptivity. To this transcendental
object we may attribute the whole connection and extent of our possible perceptions, and say that it is given
and exists in itself prior to all experience. But the phenomena, corresponding to it, are not given as things in
themselves, but in experience alone. For they are mere representations, receiving from perceptions alone
significance and relation to a real object, under the condition that this or that perception indicating an
object is in complete connection with all others in accordance with the rules of the unity of experience. Thus
we can say: "The things that really existed in past time are given in the transcendental object of experience."
But these are to me real objects, only in so far as I can represent to my own mind, that a regressive series of
possible perceptions following the indications of history, or the footsteps of cause and effect in accordance
with empirical laws that, in one word, the course of the world conducts us to an elapsed series of time as the
condition of the present time. This series in past time is represented as real, not in itself, but only in
connection with a possible experience. Thus, when I say that certain events occurred in past time, I merely
assert the possibility of prolonging the chain of experience, from the present perception, upwards to the
conditions that determine it according to time.
If I represent to myself all objects existing in all space and time, I do not thereby place these in space and
time prior to all experience; on the contrary, such a representation is nothing more than the notion of a
possible experience, in its absolute completeness. In experience alone are those objects, which are nothing
but representations, given. But, when I say they existed prior to my experience, this means only that I must
begin with the perception present to me and follow the track indicated until I discover them in some part or
region of experience. The cause of the empirical condition of this progression and consequently at what
member therein I must stop, and at what point in the regress I am to find this member is transcendental, and
hence necessarily incognizable. But with this we have not to do; our concern is only with the law of
progression in experience, in which objects, that is, phenomena, are given. It is a matter of indifference,
whether I say, "I may in the progress of experience discover stars, at a hundred times greater distance than the
most distant of those now visible," or, "Stars at this distance may be met in space, although no one has, or
ever will discover them." For, if they are given as things in themselves, without any relation to possible
experience, they are for me nonexistent, consequently, are not objects, for they are not contained in the
regressive series of experience. But, if these phenomena must be employed in the construction or support of
the cosmological idea of an absolute whole, and when we are discussing a question that oversteps the limits
of possible experience, the proper distinction of the different theories of the reality of sensuous objects is of
great importance, in order to avoid the illusion which must necessarily arise from the misinterpretation of our
empirical conceptions.
SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem.
The antinomy of pure reason is based upon the following dialectical argument: "If that which is conditioned
is given, the whole series of its conditions is also given; but sensuous objects are given as conditioned;
consequently..." This syllogism, the major of which seems so natural and evident, introduces as many
cosmological ideas as there are different kinds of conditions in the synthesis of phenomena, in so far as these
conditions constitute a series. These ideas require absolute totality in the series, and thus place reason in
inextricable embarrassment. Before proceeding to expose the fallacy in this dialectical argument, it will be
necessary to have a correct understanding of certain conceptions that appear in it.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem. 169
Page No 174
In the first place, the following proposition is evident, and indubitably certain: "If the conditioned is given, a
regress in the series of all its conditions is thereby imperatively required." For the very conception of a
conditioned is a conception of something related to a condition, and, if this condition is itself conditioned, to
another condition and so on through all the members of the series. This proposition is, therefore, analytical
and has nothing to fear from transcendental criticism. It is a logical postulate of reason: to pursue, as far as
possible, the connection of a conception with its conditions.
If, in the second place, both the conditioned and the condition are things in themselves, and if the former is
given, not only is the regress to the latter requisite, but the latter is really given with the former. Now, as this
is true of all the members of the series, the entire series of conditions, and with them the unconditioned, is at
the same time given in the very fact of the conditioned, the existence of which is possible only in and through
that series, being given. In this case, the synthesis of the conditioned with its condition, is a synthesis of the
understanding merely, which represents things as they are, without regarding whether and how we can
cognize them. But if I have to do with phenomena, which, in their character of mere representations, are not
given, if I do not attain to a cognition of them (in other words, to themselves, for they are nothing more than
empirical cognitions), I am not entitled to say: "If the conditioned is given, all its conditions (as phenomena)
are also given." I cannot, therefore, from the fact of a conditioned being given, infer the absolute totality of
the series of its conditions. For phenomena are nothing but an empirical synthesis in apprehension or
perception, and are therefore given only in it. Now, in speaking of phenomena it does not follow that, if the
conditioned is given, the synthesis which constitutes its empirical condition is also thereby given and
presupposed; such a synthesis can be established only by an actual regress in the series of conditions. But we
are entitled to say in this case that a regress to the conditions of a conditioned, in other words, that a
continuous empirical synthesis is enjoined; that, if the conditions are not given, they are at least required; and
that we are certain to discover the conditions in this regress.
We can now see that the major, in the above cosmological syllogism, takes the conditioned in the
transcendental signification which it has in the pure category, while the minor speaks of it in the empirical
signification which it has in the category as applied to phenomena. There is, therefore, a dialectical fallacy in
the syllogism a sophisma figurae dictionis. But this fallacy is not a consciously devised one, but a perfectly
natural illusion of the common reason of man. For, when a thing is given as conditioned, we presuppose in
the major its conditions and their series, unperceived, as it were, and unseen; because this is nothing more
than the logical requirement of complete and satisfactory premisses for a given conclusion. In this case, time
is altogether left out in the connection of the conditioned with the condition; they are supposed to be given in
themselves, and contemporaneously. It is, moreover, just as natural to regard phenomena (in the minor) as
things in themselves and as objects presented to the pure understanding, as in the major, in which complete
abstraction was made of all conditions of intuition. But it is under these conditions alone that objects are
given. Now we overlooked a remarkable distinction between the conceptions. The synthesis of the
conditioned with its condition, and the complete series of the latter (in the major) are not limited by time, and
do not contain the conception of succession. On the contrary, the empirical synthesis and the series of
conditions in the phenomenal world subsumed in the minor are necessarily successive and given in time
alone. It follows that I cannot presuppose in the minor, as I did in the major, the absolute totality of the
synthesis and of the series therein represented; for in the major all the members of the series are given as
things in themselves without any limitations or conditions of time, while in the minor they are possible only
in and through a successive regress, which cannot exist, except it be actually carried into execution in the
world of phenomena.
After this proof of the viciousness of the argument commonly employed in maintaining cosmological
assertions, both parties may now be justly dismissed, as advancing claims without grounds or title. But the
process has not been ended by convincing them that one or both were in the wrong and had maintained an
assertion which was without valid grounds of proof. Nothing seems to be clearer than that, if one maintains:
"The world has a beginning," and another: "The world has no beginning," one of the two must be right. But it
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem. 170
Page No 175
is likewise clear that, if the evidence on both sides is equal, it is impossible to discover on what side the truth
lies; and the controversy continues, although the parties have been recommended to peace before the tribunal
of reason. There remains, then, no other means of settling the question than to convince the parties, who
refute each other with such conclusiveness and ability, that they are disputing about nothing, and that a
transcendental illusion has been mocking them with visions of reality where there is none. The mode of
adjusting a dispute which cannot be decided upon its own merits, we shall now proceed to lay before our
readers.
Zeno of Elea, a subtle dialectician, was severely reprimanded by Plato as a sophist, who, merely from the
base motive of exhibiting his skill in discussion, maintained and subverted the same proposition by
arguments as powerful and convincing on the one side as on the other. He maintained, for example, that God
(who was probably nothing more, in his view, than the world) is neither finite nor infinite, neither in motion
nor in rest, neither similar nor dissimilar to any other thing. It seemed to those philosophers who criticized his
mode of discussion that his purpose was to deny completely both of two selfcontradictory propositions
which is absurd. But I cannot believe that there is any justice in this accusation. The first of these
propositions I shall presently consider in a more detailed manner. With regard to the others, if by the word of
God he understood merely the Universe, his meaning must have been that it cannot be permanently present
in one place that is, at rest nor be capable of changing its place that is, of moving because all places are
in the universe, and the universe itself is, therefore, in no place. Again, if the universe contains in itself
everything that exists, it cannot be similar or dissimilar to any other thing, because there is, in fact, no other
thing with which it can be compared. If two opposite judgements presuppose a contingent impossible, or
arbitrary condition, both in spite of their opposition (which is, however, not properly or really a
contradiction) fall away; because the condition, which ensured the validity of both, has itself disappeared.
If we say: "Everybody has either a good or a bad smell," we have omitted a third possible judgement it has
no smell at all; and thus both conflicting statements may be false. If we say: "It is either goodsmelling or not
goodsmelling (vel suaveolens vel nonsuaveolens)," both judgements are contradictorily opposed; and the
contradictory opposite of the former judgement some bodies are not goodsmelling embraces also those
bodies which have no smell at all. In the preceding pair of opposed judgements (per disparata), the contingent
condition of the conception of body (smell) attached to both conflicting statements, instead of having been
omitted in the latter, which is consequently not the contradictory opposite of the former.
If, accordingly, we say: "The world is either infinite in extension, or it is not infinite (non est infinitus)"; and
if the former proposition is false, its contradictory opposite the world is not infinite must be true. And thus
I should deny the existence of an infinite, without, however affirming the existence of a finite world. But if
we construct our proposition thus: "The world is either infinite or finite (noninfinite)," both statements may
be false. For, in this case, we consider the world as per se determined in regard to quantity, and while, in the
one judgement, we deny its infinite and consequently, perhaps, its independent existence; in the other, we
append to the world, regarded as a thing in itself, a certain determination that of finitude; and the latter may
be false as well as the former, if the world is not given as a thing in itself, and thus neither as finite nor as
infinite in quantity. This kind of opposition I may be allowed to term dialectical; that of contradictories may
be called analytical opposition. Thus then, of two dialectically opposed judgements both may be false, from
the fact, that the one is not a mere contradictory of the other, but actually enounces more than is requisite for
a full and complete contradiction.
When we regard the two propositions "The world is infinite in quantity," and, "The world is finite in
quantity," as contradictory opposites, we are assuming that the world the complete series of phenomena is
a thing in itself. For it remains as a permanent quantity, whether I deny the infinite or the finite regress in the
series of its phenomena. But if we dismiss this assumption this transcendental illusion and deny that it is a
thing in itself, the contradictory opposition is metamorphosed into a merely dialectical one; and the world, as
not existing in itself independently of the regressive series of my representations exists in like manner
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem. 171
Page No 176
neither as a whole which is infinite nor as a whole which is finite in itself. The universe exists for me only in
the empirical regress of the series of phenomena and not per se. If, then, it is always conditioned, it is never
completely or as a whole; and it is, therefore, not an unconditioned whole and does not exist as such, either
with an infinite, or with a finite quantity.
What we have here said of the first cosmological idea that of the absolute totality of quantity in
phenomena applies also to the others. The series of conditions is discoverable only in the regressive
synthesis itself, and not in the phenomenon considered as a thing in itself given prior to all regress. Hence I
am compelled to say: "The aggregate of parts in a given phenomenon is in itself neither finite nor infinite;
and these parts are given only in the regressive synthesis of decomposition a synthesis which is never given
in absolute completeness, either as finite, or as infinite." The same is the case with the series of subordinated
causes, or of the conditioned up to the unconditioned and necessary existence, which can never be regarded
as in itself, ind in its totality, either as finite or as infinite; because, as a series of subordinate representations,
it subsists only in the dynamical regress and cannot be regarded as existing previously to this regress, or as a
selfsubsistent series of things.
Thus the antinomy of pure reason in its cosmological ideas disappears. For the above demonstration has
established the fact that it is merely the product of a dialectical and illusory opposition, which arises from the
application of the idea of absolute totality admissible only as a condition of things in themselves to
phenomena, which exist only in our representations, and when constituting a series in a successive regress.
This antinomy of reason may, however, be really profitable to our speculative interests, not in the way of
contributing any dogmatical addition, but as presenting to us another material support in our critical
investigations. For it furnishes us with an indirect proof of the transcendental ideality of phenomena, if our
minds were not completely satisfied with the direct proof set forth in the Trancendental Aesthetic. The proof
would proceed in the following dilemma. If the world is a whole existing in itself, it must be either finite or
infinite. But it is neither finite nor infinite as has been shown, on the one side, by the thesis, on the other, by
the antithesis. Therefore the world the content of all phenomena is not a whole existing in itself. It follows
that phenomena are nothing, apart from our representations. And this is what we mean by transcendental
ideality.
This remark is of some importance. It enables us to see that the proofs of the fourfold antinomy are not mere
sophistries are not fallacious, but grounded on the nature of reason, and valid under the supposition that
phenomena are things in themselves. The opposition of the judgements which follow makes it evident that a
fallacy lay in the initial supposition, and thus helps us to discover the true constitution of objects of sense.
This transcendental dialectic does not favour scepticism, although it presents us with a triumphant
demonstration of the advantages of the sceptical method, the great utility of which is apparent in the
antinomy, where the arguments of reason were allowed to confront each other in undiminished force. And
although the result of these conflicts of reason is not what we expected although we have obtained no
positive dogmatical addition to metaphysical science we have still reaped a great advantage in the correction
of our judgements on these subjects of thought.
SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the
Cosmological Ideas.
The cosmological principle of totality could not give us any certain knowledge in regard to the maximum in
the series of conditions in the world of sense, considered as a thing in itself. The actual regress in the series is
the only means of approaching this maximum. This principle of pure reason, therefore, may still be
considered as valid not as an axiom enabling us to cogitate totality in the object as actual, but as a problem
for the understanding, which requires it to institute and to continue, in conformity with the idea of totality in
the mind, the regress in the series of the conditions of a given conditioned. For in the world of sense, that is,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the Cosmological Ideas. 172
Page No 177
in space and time, every condition which we discover in our investigation of phenomena is itself conditioned;
because sensuous objects are not things in themselves (in which case an absolutely unconditioned might be
reached in the progress of cognition), but are merely empirical representations the conditions of which must
always be found in intuition. The principle of reason is therefore properly a mere rule prescribing a regress
in the series of conditions for given phenomena, and prohibiting any pause or rest on an absolutely
unconditioned. It is, therefore, not a principle of the possibility of experience or of the empirical cognition of
sensuous objects consequently not a principle of the understanding; for every experience is confined within
certain proper limits determined by the given intuition. Still less is it a constitutive principle of reason
authorizing us to extend our conception of the sensuous world beyond all possible experience. It is merely a
principle for the enlargement and extension of experience as far as is possible for human faculties. It forbids
us to consider any empirical limits as absolute. It is, hence, a principle of reason, which, as a rule, dictates
how we ought to proceed in our empirical regress, but is unable to anticipate or indicate prior to the empirical
regress what is given in the object itself. I have termed it for this reason a regulative principle of reason;
while the principle of the absolute totality of the series of conditions, as existing in itself and given in the
object, is a constitutive cosmological principle. This distinction will at once demonstrate the falsehood of the
constitutive principle, and prevent us from attributing (by a transcendental subreptio) objective reality to an
idea, which is valid only as a rule.
In order to understand the proper meaning of this rule of pure reason, we must notice first that it cannot tell us
what the object is, but only how the empirical regress is to be proceeded with in order to attain to the
complete conception of the object. If it gave us any information in respect to the former statement, it would
be a constitutive principle a principle impossible from the nature of pure reason. It will not therefore enable
us to establish any such conclusions as: "The series of conditions for a given conditioned is in itself finite."
or, "It is infinite." For, in this case, we should be cogitating in the mere idea of absolute totality, an object
which is not and cannot be given in experience; inasmuch as we should be attributing a reality objective and
independent of the empirical synthesis, to a series of phenomena. This idea of reason cannot then be regarded
as valid except as a rule for the regressive synthesis in the series of conditions, according to which we must
proceed from the conditioned, through all intermediate and subordinate conditions, up to the unconditioned;
although this goal is unattained and unattainable. For the absolutely unconditioned cannot be discovered in
the sphere of experience.
We now proceed to determine clearly our notion of a synthesis which can never be complete. There are two
terms commonly employed for this purpose. These terms are regarded as expressions of different and
distinguishable notions, although the ground of the distinction has never been clearly exposed. The term
employed by the mathematicians is progressus in infinitum. The philosophers prefer the expression
progressus in indefinitum. Without detaining the reader with an examination of the reasons for such a
distinction, or with remarks on the right or wrong use of the terms, I shall endeavour clearly to determine
these conceptions, so far as is necessary for the purpose in this Critique.
We may, with propriety, say of a straight line, that it may be produced to infinity. In this case the distinction
between a progressus in infinitum and a progressus in indefinitum is a mere piece of subtlety. For, although
when we say, "Produce a straight line," it is more correct to say in indefinitum than in infinitum; because the
former means, "Produce it as far as you please," the second, "You must not cease to produce it"; the
expression in infinitum is, when we are speaking of the power to do it, perfectly correct, for we can always
make it longer if we please on to infinity. And this remark holds good in all cases, when we speak of a
progressus, that is, an advancement from the condition to the conditioned; this possible advancement always
proceeds to infinity. We may proceed from a given pair in the descending line of generation from father to
son, and cogitate a neverending line of descendants from it. For in such a case reason does not demand
absolute totality in the series, because it does not presuppose it as a condition and as given (datum), but
merely as conditioned, and as capable of being given (dabile).
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the Cosmological Ideas. 173
Page No 178
Very different is the case with the problem: "How far the regress, which ascends from the given conditioned
to the conditions, must extend"; whether I can say: "It is a regress in infinitum," or only "in indefinitum"; and
whether, for example, setting out from the human beings at present alive in the world, I may ascend in the
series of their ancestors, in infinitum mr whether all that can be said is, that so far as I have proceeded, I
have discovered no empirical ground for considering the series limited, so that I am justified, and indeed,
compelled to search for ancestors still further back, although I am not obliged by the idea of reason to
presuppose them.
My answer to this question is: "If the series is given in empirical intuition as a whole, the regress in the series
of its internal conditions proceeds in infinitum; but, if only one member of the series is given, from which the
regress is to proceed to absolute totality, the regress is possible only in indefinitum." For example, the
division of a portion of matter given within certain limits of a body, that is proceeds in infinitum. For, as
the condition of this whole is its part, and the condition of the part a part of the part, and so on, and as in this
regress of decomposition an unconditioned indivisible member of the series of conditions is not to be found;
there are no reasons or grounds in experience for stopping in the division, but, on the contrary, the more
remote members of the division are actually and empirically given prior to this division. That is to say, the
division proceeds to infinity. On the other hand, the series of ancestors of any given human being is not
given, in its absolute totality, in any experience, and yet the regress proceeds from every genealogical
member of this series to one still higher, and does not meet with any empirical limit presenting an absolutely
unconditioned member of the series. But as the members of such a series are not contained in the empirical
intuition of the whole, prior to the regress, this regress does not proceed to infinity, but only in indefinitum,
that is, we are called upon to discover other and higher members, which are themselves always conditioned.
In neither case the regressus in infinitum, nor the regressus in indefinitum, is the series of conditions to be
considered as actually infinite in the object itself. This might be true of things in themselves, but it cannot be
asserted of phenomena, which, as conditions of each other, are only given in the empirical regress itself.
Hence, the question no longer is, "What is the quantity of this series of conditions in itself is it finite or
infinite?" for it is nothing in itself; but, "How is the empirical regress to be commenced, and how far ought
we to proceed with it?" And here a signal distinction in the application of this rule becomes apparent. If the
whole is given empirically, it is possible to recede in the series of its internal conditions to infinity. But if the
whole is not given, and can only be given by and through the empirical regress, I can only say: "It is possible
to infinity, to proceed to still higher conditions in the series." In the first case, I am justified in asserting that
more members are empirically given in the object than I attain to in the regress (of decomposition). In the
second case, I am justified only in saying, that I can always proceed further in the regress, because no
member of the series. is given as absolutely conditioned, and thus a higher member is possible, and an
inquiry with regard to it is necessary. In the one case it is necessary to find other members of the series, in the
other it is necessary to inquire for others, inasmuch as experience presents no absolute limitation of the
regress. For, either you do not possess a perception which absolutely limits your empirical regress, and in this
case the regress cannot be regarded as complete; or, you do possess such a limitative perception, in which
case it is not a part of your series (for that which limits must be distinct from that which is limited by it), and
it is incumbent you to continue your regress up to this condition, and so on.
These remarks will be placed in their proper light by their application in the following section.
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason
with regard to the Cosmological Ideas.
We have shown that no transcendental use can be made either of the conceptions of reason or of
understanding. We have shown, likewise, that the demand of absolute totality in the series of conditions in
the world of sense arises from a transcendental employment of reason, resting on the opinion that phenomena
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 174
Page No 179
are to be regarded as things in themselves. It follows that we are not required to answer the question
respecting the absolute quantity of a series whether it is in itself limited or unlimited. We are only called
upon to determine how far we must proceed in the empirical regress from condition to condition, in order to
discover, in conformity with the rule of reason, a full and correct answer to the questions proposed by reason
itself.
This principle of reason is hence valid only as a rule for the extension of a possible experience its invalidity
as a principle constitutive of phenomena in themselves having been sufficiently demonstrated. And thus, too,
the antinomial conflict of reason with itself is completely put an end to; inasmuch as we have not only
presented a critical solution of the fallacy lurking in the opposite statements of reason, but have shown the
true meaning of the ideas which gave rise to these statements. The dialectical principle of reason has,
therefore, been changed into a doctrinal principle. But in fact, if this principle, in the subjective signification
which we have shown to be its only true sense, may be guaranteed as a principle of the unceasing extension
of the employment of our understanding, its influence and value are just as great as if it were an axiom for the
a priori determination of objects. For such an axiom could not exert a stronger influence on the extension and
rectification of our knowledge, otherwise than by procuring for the principles of the understanding the most
widely expanded employment in the field of experience.
I. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the
Composition of Phenomena in the Universe.
Here, as well as in the case of the other cosmological problems, the ground of the regulative principle of
reason is the proposition that in our empirical regress no experience of an absolute limit, and consequently no
experience of a condition, which is itself absolutely unconditioned, is discoverable. And the truth of this
proposition itself rests upon the consideration that such an experience must represent to us phenomena as
limited by nothing or the mere void, on which our continued regress by means of perception must abut
which is impossible.
Now this proposition, which declares that every condition attained in the empirical regress must itself be
considered empirically conditioned, contains the rule in terminis, which requires me, to whatever extent I
may have proceeded in the ascending series, always to look for some higher member in the series whether
this member is to become known to me through experience, or not.
Nothing further is necessary, then, for the solution of the first cosmological problem, than to decide, whether,
in the regress to the unconditioned quantity of the universe (as regards space and time), this never limited
ascent ought to be called a regressus in infinitum or indefinitum.
The general representation which we form in our minds of the series of all past states or conditions of the
world, or of all the things which at present exist in it, is itself nothing more than a possible empirical regress,
which is cogitated although in an undetermined manner in the mind, and which gives rise to the conception
of a series of conditions for a given object.* Now I have a conception of the universe, but not an intuition
that is, not an intuition of it as a whole. Thus I cannot infer the magnitude of the regress from the quantity or
magnitude of the world, and determine the former by means of the latter; on the contrary, I must first of all
form a conception of the quantity or magnitude of the world from the magnitude of the empirical regress. But
of this regress I know nothing more than that I ought to proceed from every given member of the series of
conditions to one still higher. But the quantity of the universe is not thereby determined, and we cannot
affirm that this regress proceeds in infinitum. Such an affirmation would anticipate the members of the series
which have not yet been reached, and represent the number of them as beyond the grasp of any empirical
synthesis; it would consequently determine the cosmical quantity prior to the regress (although only in a
negative manner) which is impossible. For the world is not given in its totality in any intuition:
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 175
Page No 180
consequently, its quantity cannot be given prior to the regress. It follows that we are unable to make any
declaration respecting the cosmical quantity in itself not even that the regress in it is a regress in infinitum;
we must only endeavour to attain to a conception of the quantity of the universe, in conformity with the rule
which determines the empirical regress in it. But this rule merely requires us never to admit an absolute limit
to our series how far soever we may have proceeded in it, but always, on the contrary, to subordinate every
phenomenon to some other as its condition, and consequently to proceed to this higher phenomenon. Such a
regress is, therefore, the regressus in indefinitum, which, as not determining a quantity in the object, is clearly
distinguishable from the regressus in infinitum.
*The cosmical series can neither be greater nor smaller than the possible empirical regress, upon which its
conception is based. And as this regress cannot be a determinate infinite regress, still less a determinate finite
(absolutely limited), it is evident that we cannot regard the world as either finite or infinite, because the
regress, which gives us the representation of the world, is neither finite nor infinite.
It follows from what we have said that we are not justified in declaring the world to be infinite in space, or as
regards past time. For this conception of an infinite given quantity is empirical; but we cannot apply the
conception of an infinite quantity to the world as an object of the senses. I cannot say, "The regress from a
given perception to everything limited either in space or time, proceeds in infinitum," for this presupposes an
infinite cosmical quantity; neither can I say, "It is finite," for an absolute limit is likewise impossible in
experience. It follows that I am not entitled to make any assertion at all respecting the whole object of
experience the world of sense; I must limit my declarations to the rule according to which experience or
empirical knowledge is to be attained.
To the question, therefore, respecting the cosmical quantity, the first and negative answer is: "The world has
no beginning in time, and no absolute limit in space."
For, in the contrary case, it would be limited by a void time on the one hand, and by a void space on the
other. Now, since the world, as a phenomenon, cannot be thus limited in itself for a phenomenon is not a
thing in itself; it must be possible for us to have a perception of this limitation by a void time and a void
space. But such a perception such an experience is impossible; because it has no content. Consequently, an
absolute cosmical limit is empirically, and therefore absolutely, impossible.*
*The reader will remark that the proof presented above is very different from the dogmatical demonstration
given in the antithesis of the first antinomy. In that demonstration, it was taken for granted that the world is a
thing in itself given in its totality prior to all regress, and a determined position in space and time was
denied to it if it was not considered as occupying all time and all space. Hence our conclusion differed from
that given above; for we inferred in the antithesis the actual infinity of the world.
From this follows the affirmative answer: "The regress in the series of phenomena as a determination of the
cosmical quantity, proceeds in indefinitum." This is equivalent to saying: "The world of sense has no absolute
quantity, but the empirical regress (through which alone the world of sense is presented to us on the side of its
conditions) rests upon a rule, which requires it to proceed from every member of the series, as conditioned, to
one still more remote (whether through personal experience, or by means of history, or the chain of cause and
effect), and not to cease at any point in this extension of the possible empirical employment of the
understanding." And this is the proper and only use which reason can make of its principles.
The above rule does not prescribe an unceasing regress in one kind of phenomena. It does not, for example,
forbid us, in our ascent from an individual human being through the line of his ancestors, to expect that we
shall discover at some point of the regress a primeval pair, or to admit, in the series of heavenly bodies, a sun
at the farthest possible distance from some centre. All that it demands is a perpetual progress from
phenomena to phenomena, even although an actual perception is not presented by them (as in the case of our
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 176
Page No 181
perceptions being so weak as that we are unable to become conscious of them), since they, nevertheless,
belong to possible experience.
Every beginning is in time, and all limits to extension are in space. But space and time are in the world of
sense. Consequently phenomena in the world are conditionally limited, but the world itself is not limited,
either conditionally or unconditionally.
For this reason, and because neither the world nor the cosmical series of conditions to a given conditioned
can be completely given, our conception of the cosmical quantity is given only in and through the regress and
not prior to it in a collective intuition. But the regress itself is really nothing more than the determining of
the cosmical quantity, and cannot therefore give us any determined conception of it still less a conception of
a quantity which is, in relation to a certain standard, infinite. The regress does not, therefore, proceed to
infinity (an infinity given), but only to an indefinite extent, for or the of presenting to us a quantity realized
only in and through the regress itself.
II. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of
the Division of a Whole given in Intuition.
When I divide a whole which is given in intuition, I proceed from a conditioned to its conditions. The
division of the parts of the whole (subdivisio or decompositio) is a regress in the series of these conditions.
The absolute totality of this series would be actually attained and given to the mind, if the regress could arrive
at simple parts. But if all the parts in a continuous decomposition are themselves divisible, the division, that
is to say, the regress, proceeds from the conditioned to its conditions in infinitum; because the conditions (the
parts) are themselves contained in the conditioned, and, as the latter is given in a limited intuition, the former
are all given along with it. This regress cannot, therefore, be called a regressus in indefinitum, as happened in
the case of the preceding cosmological idea, the regress in which proceeded from the conditioned to the
conditions not given contemporaneously and along with it, but discoverable only through the empirical
regress. We are not, however, entitled to affirm of a whole of this kind, which is divisible in infinitum, that it
consists of an infinite number of parts. For, although all the parts are contained in the intuition of the whole,
the whole division is not contained therein. The division is contained only in the progressing decomposition
in the regress itself, which is the condition of the possibility and actuality of the series. Now, as this regress is
infinite, all the members (parts) to which it attains must be contained in the given whole as an aggregate. But
the complete series of division is not contained therein. For this series, being infinite in succession and
always incomplete, cannot represent an infinite number of members, and still less a composition of these
members into a whole.
To apply this remark to space. Every limited part of space presented to intuition is a whole, the parts of which
are always spaces to whatever extent subdivided. Every limited space is hence divisible to infinity.
Let us again apply the remark to an external phenomenon enclosed in limits, that is, a body. The divisibility
of a body rests upon the divisibility of space, which is the condition of the possibility of the body as an
extended whole. A body is consequently divisible to infinity, though it does not, for that reason, consist of an
infinite number of parts.
It certainly seems that, as a body must be cogitated as substance in space, the law of divisibility would not be
applicable to it as substance. For we may and ought to grant, in the case of space, that division or
decomposition, to any extent, never can utterly annihilate composition (that is to say, the smallest part of
space must still consist of spaces); otherwise space would entirely cease to exist which is impossible. But,
the assertion on the other band that when all composition in matter is annihilated in thought, nothing remains,
does not seem to harmonize with the conception of substance, which must be properly the subject of all
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 177
Page No 182
composition and must remain, even after the conjunction of its attributes in space which constituted a body
is annihilated in thought. But this is not the case with substance in the phenomenal world, which is not a thing
in itself cogitated by the pure category. Phenomenal substance is not an absolute subject; it is merely a
permanent sensuous image, and nothing more than an intuition, in which the unconditioned is not to be
found.
But, although this rule of progress to infinity is legitimate and applicable to the subdivision of a phenomenon,
as a mere occupation or filling of space, it is not applicable to a whole consisting of a number of distinct parts
and constituting a quantum discretum that is to say, an organized body. It cannot be admitted that every part
in an organized whole is itself organized, and that, in analysing it to infinity, we must always meet with
organized parts; although we may allow that the parts of the matter which we decompose in infinitum, may
be organized. For the infinity of the division of a phenomenon in space rests altogether on the fact that the
divisibility of a phenomenon is given only in and through this infinity, that is, an undetermined number of
parts is given, while the parts themselves are given and determined only in and through the subdivision; in a
word, the infinity of the division necessarily presupposes that the whole is not already divided in se. Hence
our division determines a number of parts in the whole a number which extends just as far as the actual
regress in the division; while, on the other hand, the very notion of a body organized to infinity represents the
whole as already and in itself divided. We expect, therefore, to find in it a determinate, but at the same time,
infinite, number of parts which is selfcontradictory. For we should thus have a whole containing a series of
members which could not be completed in any regress which is infinite, and at the same time complete in an
organized composite. Infinite divisibility is applicable only to a quantum continuum, and is based entirely on
the infinite divisibility of space, But in a quantum discretum the multitude of parts or units is always
determined, and hence always equal to some number. To what extent a body may be organized, experience
alone can inform us; and although, so far as our experience of this or that body has extended, we may not
have discovered any inorganic part, such parts must exist in possible experience. But how far the
transcendental division of a phenomenon must extend, we cannot know from experience it is a question
which experience cannot answer; it is answered only by the principle of reason which forbids us to consider
the empirical regress, in the analysis of extended body, as ever absolutely complete.
Concluding Remark on the Solution of the Transcendental
Mathematical Ideas and Introductory to the
Solution of the Dynamical Ideas.
We presented the antinomy of pure reason in a tabular form, and we endeavoured to show the ground of this
selfcontradiction on the part of reason, and the only means of bringing it to a conclusion znamely, by
declaring both contradictory statements to be false. We represented in these antinomies the conditions of
phenomena as belonging to the conditioned according to relations of space and time which is the usual
supposition of the common understanding. In this respect, all dialectical representations of totality, in the
series of conditions to a given conditioned, were perfectly homogeneous. The condition was always a
member of the series along with the conditioned, and thus the homogeneity of the whole series was assured.
In this case the regress could never be cogitated as complete; or, if this was the case, a member really
conditioned was falsely regarded as a primal member, consequently as unconditioned. In such an antinomy,
therefore, we did not consider the object, that is, the conditioned, but the series of conditions belonging to the
object, and the magnitude of that series. And thus arose the difficulty a difficulty not to be settled by any
decision regarding the claims of the two parties, but simply by cutting the knot by declaring the series
proposed by reason to be either too long or too short for the understanding, which could in neither case make
its conceptions adequate with the ideas.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 178
Page No 183
But we have overlooked, up to this point, an essential difference existing between the conceptions of the
understanding which reason endeavours to raise to the rank of ideas two of these indicating a mathematical,
and two a dynamical synthesis of phenomena. Hitherto, it was necessary to signalize this distinction; for, just
as in our general representation of all transcendental ideas, we considered them under phenomenal
conditions, so, in the two mathematical ideas, our discussion is concerned solely with an object in the world
of phenomena. But as we are now about to proceed to the consideration of the dynamical conceptions of the
understanding, and their adequateness with ideas, we must not lose sight of this distinction. We shall find that
it opens up to us an entirely new view of the conflict in which reason is involved. For, while in the first two
antinomies, both parties were dismissed, on the ground of having advanced statements based upon false
hypothesis; in the present case the hope appears of discovering a hypothesis which may be consistent with the
demands of reason, and, the judge completing the statement of the grounds of claim, which both parties had
left in an unsatisfactory state, the question may be settled on its own merits, not by dismissing the claimants,
but by a comparison of the arguments on both sides. If we consider merely their extension, and whether they
are adequate with ideas, the series of conditions may be regarded as all homogeneous. But the conception of
the understanding which lies at the basis of these ideas, contains either a synthesis of the homogeneous
(presupposed in every quantity in its composition as well as in its division) or of the heterogeneous, which
is the case in the dynamical synthesis of cause and effect, as well as of the necessary and the contingent.
Thus it happens that in the mathematical series of phenomena no other than a sensuous condition is
admissible a condition which is itself a member of the series; while the dynamical series of sensuous
conditions admits a heterogeneous condition, which is not a member of the series, but, as purely intelligible,
lies out of and beyond it. And thus reason is satisfied, and an unconditioned placed at the head of the series of
phenomena, without introducing confusion into or discontinuing it, contrary to the principles of the
understanding.
Now, from the fact that the dynamical ideas admit a condition of phenomena which does not form a part of
the series of phenomena, arises a result which we should not have expected from an antinomy. In former
cases, the result was that both contradictory dialectical statements were declared to be false. In the present
case, we find the conditioned in the dynamical series connected with an empirically unconditioned, but
nonsensuous condition; and thus satisfaction is done to the understanding on the one hand and to the reason
on the other.* While, moreover, the dialectical arguments for unconditioned totality in mere phenomena fall
to the ground, both propositions of reason may be shown to be true in their proper signification. This could
not happen in the case of the cosmological ideas which demanded a mathematically unconditioned unity; for
no condition could be placed at the head of the series of phenomena, except one which was itself a
phenomenon and consequently a member of the series.
*For the understanding cannot admit among phenomena a condition which is itself empirically
unconditioned. But if it is possible to cogitate an intelligible condition one which is not a member of the
series of phenomena for a conditioned phenomenon, without breaking the series of empirical conditions,
such a condition may be admissible as empirically unconditioned, and the empirical regress continue regular,
unceasing, and intact.
III. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of
the Deduction of Cosmical Events from their Causes.
There are only two modes of causality cogitable the causality of nature or of freedom. The first is the
conjunction of a particular state with another preceding it in the world of sense, the former following the
latter by virtue of a law. Now, as the causality of phenomena is subject to conditions of time, and the
preceding state, if it had always existed, could not have produced an effect which would make its first
appearance at a particular time, the causality of a cause must itself be an effect must itself have begun to be,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 179
Page No 184
and therefore, according to the principle of the understanding, itself requires a cause.
We must understand, on the contrary, by the term freedom, in the cosmological sense, a faculty of the
spontaneous origination of a state; the causality of which, therefore, is not subordinated to another cause
determining it in time. Freedom is in this sense a pure transcendental idea, which, in the first place, contains
no empirical element; the object of which, in the second place, cannot be given or determined in any
experience, because it is a universal law of the very possibility of experience, that everything which happens
must have a cause, that consequently the causality of a cause, being itself something that has happened, must
also have a cause. In this view of the case, the whole field of experience, how far soever it may extend,
contains nothing that is not subject to the laws of nature. But, as we cannot by this means attain to an absolute
totality of conditions in reference to the series of causes and effects, reason creates the idea of a spontaneity,
which can begin to act of itself, and without any external cause determining it to action, according to the
natural law of causality.
It is especially remarkable that the practical conception of freedom is based upon the transcendental idea, and
that the question of the possibility of the former is difficult only as it involves the consideration of the truth of
the latter. Freedom, in the practical sense, is the independence of the will of coercion by sensuous impulses.
A will is sensuous, in so far as it is pathologically affected (by sensuous impulses); it is termed animal
(arbitrium brutum), when it is pathologically necessitated. The human will is certainly an arbitrium
sensitivum, not brutum, but liberum; because sensuousness does not necessitate its action, a faculty existing
in man of selfdetermination, independently of all sensuous coercion.
It is plain that, if all causality in the world of sense were natural and natural only every event would be
determined by another according to necessary laws, and that, consequently, phenomena, in so far as they
determine the will, must necessitate every action as a natural effect from themselves; and thus all practical
freedom would fall to the ground with the transcendental idea. For the latter presupposes that although a
certain thing has not happened, it ought to have happened, and that, consequently, its phenomenal cause was
not so powerful and determinative as to exclude the causality of our will a causality capable of producing
effects independently of and even in opposition to the power of natural causes, and capable, consequently, of
spontaneously originating a series of events.
Here, too, we find it to be the case, as we generally found in the selfcontradictions and perplexities of a
reason which strives to pass the bounds of possible experience, that the problem is properly not physiological,
but transcendental. The question of the possibility of freedom does indeed concern psychology; but, as it rests
upon dialectical arguments of pure reason, its solution must engage the attention of transcendental
philosophy. Before attempting this solution, a task which transcendental philosophy cannot decline, it will be
advisable to make a remark with regard to its procedure in the settlement of the question.
If phenomena were things in themselves, and time and space forms of the existence of things, condition and
conditioned would always be members of the same series; and thus would arise in the present case the
antinomy common to all transcendental ideas that their series is either too great or too small for the
understanding. The dynamical ideas, which we are about to discuss in this and the following section, possess
the peculiarity of relating to an object, not considered as a quantity, but as an existence; and thus, in the
discussion of the present question, we may make abstraction of the quantity of the series of conditions, and
consider merely the dynamical relation of the condition to the conditioned. The question, then, suggests itself,
whether freedom is possible; and, if it is, whether it can consist with the universality of the natural law of
causality; and, consequently, whether we enounce a proper disjunctive proposition when we say: "Every
effect must have its origin either in nature or in freedom," or whether both cannot exist together in the same
event in different relations. The principle of an unbroken connection between all events in the phenomenal
world, in accordance with the unchangeable laws of nature, is a wellestablished principle of transcendental
analytic which admits of no exception. The question, therefore, is: "Whether an effect, determined according
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 180
Page No 185
to the laws of nature, can at the same time be produced by a free agent, or whether freedom and nature
mutually exclude each other?" And here, the common but fallacious hypothesis of the absolute reality of
phenomena manifests its injurious influence in embarrassing the procedure of reason. For if phenomena are
things in themselves, freedom is impossible. In this case, nature is the complete and allsufficient cause of
every event; and condition and conditioned, cause and effect are contained in the same series, and
necessitated by the same law. If, on the contrary, phenomena are held to be, as they are in fact, nothing more
than mere representations, connected with each other in accordance with empirical laws, they must have a
ground which is not phenomenal. But the causality of such an intelligible cause is not determined or
determinable by phenomena; although its effects, as phenomena, must be determined by other phenomenal
existences. This cause and its causality exist therefore out of and apart from the series of phenomena; while
its effects do exist and are discoverable in the series of empirical conditions. Such an effect may therefore be
considered to be free in relation to its intelligible cause, and necessary in relation to the phenomena from
which it is a necessary consequence a distinction which, stated in this perfectly general and abstract manner,
must appear in the highest degree subtle and obscure. The sequel will explain. It is sufficient, at present, to
remark that, as the complete and unbroken connection of phenomena is an unalterable law of nature, freedom
is impossible on the supposition that phenomena are absolutely real. Hence those philosophers who adhere
to the common opinion on this subject can never succeed in reconciling the ideas of nature and freedom.
Possibility of Freedom in Harmony with the Universal Law
of Natural Necessity.
That element in a sensuous object which is not itself sensuous, I may be allowed to term intelligible. If,
accordingly, an object which must be regarded as a sensuous phenomenon possesses a faculty which is not an
object of sensuous intuition, but by means of which it is capable of being the cause of phenomena, the
causality of an object or existence of this kind may be regarded from two different points of view. It may be
considered to be intelligible, as regards its action the action of a thing which is a thing in itself, and
sensuous, as regards its effects the effects of a phenomenon belonging to the sensuous world. We should
accordingly, have to form both an empirical and an intellectual conception of the causality of such a faculty
or power both, however, having reference to the same effect. This twofold manner of cogitating a power
residing in a sensuous object does not run counter to any of the conceptions which we ought to form of the
world of phenomena or of a possible experience. Phenomena not being things in themselves must have a
transcendental object as a foundation, which determines them as mere representations; and there seems to be
no reason why we should not ascribe to this transcendental object, in addition to the property of
selfphenomenization, a causality whose effects are to be met with in the world of phenomena, although it is
not itself a phenomenon. But every effective cause must possess a character, that is to say, a law of its
causality, without which it would cease to be a cause. In the above case, then, every sensuous object would
possess an empirical character, which guaranteed that its actions, as phenomena, stand in complete and
harmonious connection, conformably to unvarying natural laws, with all other phenomena, and can be
deduced from these, as conditions, and that they do thus, in connection with these, constitute a series in the
order of nature. This sensuous object must, in the second place, possess an intelligible character, which
guarantees it to be the cause of those actions, as phenomena, although it is not itself a phenomenon nor
subordinate to the conditions of the world of sense. The former may be termed the character of the thing as a
phenomenon, the latter the character of the thing as a thing in itself.
Now this active subject would, in its character of intelligible subject, be subordinate to no conditions of time,
for time is only a condition of phenomena, and not of things in themselves. No action would begin or cease to
be in this subject; it would consequently be free from the law of all determination of time the law of change,
namely, that everything which happens must have a cause in the phenomena of a preceding state. In one
word, the causality of the subject, in so far as it is intelligible, would not form part of the series of empirical
conditions which determine and necessitate an event in the world of sense. Again, this intelligible character
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 181
Page No 186
of a thing cannot be immediately cognized, because we can perceive nothing but phenomena, but it must be
capable of being cogitated in harmony with the empirical character; for we always find ourselves compelled
to place, in thought, a transcendental object at the basis of phenomena although we can never know what this
object is in itself.
In virtue of its empirical character, this subject would at the same time be subordinate to all the empirical
laws of causality, and, as a phenomenon and member of the sensuous world, its effects would have to be
accounted for by a reference to preceding phenomena. Eternal phenomena must be capable of influencing it;
and its actions, in accordance with natural laws, must explain to us how its empirical character, that is, the
law of its causality, is to be cognized in and by means of experience. In a word, all requisites for a complete
and necessary determination of these actions must be presented to us by experience.
In virtue of its intelligible character, on the other hand (although we possess only a general conception of this
character), the subject must be regarded as free from all sensuous influences, and from all phenomenal
determination. Moreover, as nothing happens in this subject for it is a noumenon, and there does not
consequently exist in it any change, demanding the dynamical determination of time, and for the same reason
no connection with phenomena as causes this active existence must in its actions be free from and
independent of natural necessity, for or necessity exists only in the world of phenomena. It would be quite
correct to say that it originates or begins its effects in the world of sense from itself, although the action
productive of these effects does not begin in itself. We should not be in this case affirming that these
sensuous effects began to exist of themselves, because they are always determined by prior empirical
conditions by virtue of the empirical character, which is the phenomenon of the intelligible character and
are possible only as constituting a continuation of the series of natural causes. And thus nature and freedom,
each in the complete and absolute signification of these terms, can exist, without contradiction or
disagreement, in the same action to
Exposition of the Cosmological Idea of Freedom in Harmony
with the Universal Law of Natural Necessity.
I have thought it advisable to lay before the reader at first merely a sketch of the solution of this
transcendental problem, in order to enable him to form with greater ease a clear conception of the course
which reason must adopt in the solution. I shall now proceed to exhibit the several momenta of this solution,
and to consider them in their order.
The natural law that everything which happens must have a cause, that the causality of this cause, that is, the
action of the cause (which cannot always have existed, but must be itself an event, for it precedes in time
some effect which it has originated), must have itself a phenomenal cause, by which it is determined and,
and, consequently, all events are empirically determined in an order of nature this law, I say, which lies at
the foundation of the possibility of experience, and of a connected system of phenomena or nature is a law of
the understanding, from which no departure, and to which no exception, can be admitted. For to except even
a single phenomenon from its operation is to exclude it from the sphere of possible experience and thus to
admit it to be a mere fiction of thought or phantom of the brain.
Thus we are obliged to acknowledge the existence of a chain of causes, in which, however, absolute totality
cannot be found. But we need not detain ourselves with this question, for it has already been sufficiently
answered in our discussion of the antinomies into which reason falls, when it attempts to reach the
unconditioned in the series of phenomena. If we permit ourselves to be deceived by the illusion of
transcendental idealism, we shall find that neither nature nor freedom exists. Now the question is: "Whether,
admitting the existence of natural necessity in the world of phenomena, it is possible to consider an effect as
at the same time an effect of nature and an effect of freedom or, whether these two modes of causality are
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 182
Page No 187
contradictory and incompatible?"
No phenomenal cause can absolutely and of itself begin a series. Every action, in so far as it is productive of
an event, is itself an event or occurrence, and presupposes another preceding state, in which its cause existed.
Thus everything that happens is but a continuation of a series, and an absolute beginning is impossible in the
sensuous world. The actions of natural causes are, accordingly, themselves effects, and presuppose causes
preceding them in time. A primal action which forms an absolute beginning, is beyond the causal power of
phenomena.
Now, is it absolutely necessary that, granting that all effects are phenomena, the causality of the cause of
these effects must also be a phenomenon and belong to the empirical world? Is it not rather possible that,
although every effect in the phenomenal world must be connected with an empirical cause, according to the
universal law of nature, this empirical causality may be itself the effect of a nonempirical and intelligible
causality its connection with natural causes remaining nevertheless intact? Such a causality would be
considered, in reference to phenomena, as the primal action of a cause, which is in so far, therefore, not
phenomenal, but, by reason of this faculty or power, intelligible; although it must, at the same time, as a link
in the chain of nature, be regarded as belonging to the sensuous world.
A belief in the reciprocal causality of phenomena is necessary, if we are required to look for and to present
the natural conditions of natural events, that is to say, their causes. This being admitted as unexceptionably
valid, the requirements of the understanding, which recognizes nothing but nature in the region of
phenomena, are satisfied, and our physical explanations of physical phenomena may proceed in their regular
course, without hindrance and without opposition. But it is no stumblingblock in the way, even assuming
the idea to be a pure fiction, to admit that there are some natural causes in the possession of a faculty which is
not empirical, but intelligible, inasmuch as it is not determined to action by empirical conditions, but purely
and solely upon grounds brought forward by the understanding this action being still, when the cause is
phenomenized, in perfect accordance with the laws of empirical causality. Thus the acting subject, as a causal
phenomenon, would continue to preserve a complete connection with nature and natural conditions; and the
phenomenon only of the subject (with all its phenomenal causality) would contain certain conditions, which,
if we ascend from the empirical to the transcendental object, must necessarily be regarded as intelligible. For,
if we attend, in our inquiries with regard to causes in the world of phenomena, to the directions of nature
alone, we need not trouble ourselves about the relation in which the transcendental subject, which is
completely unknown to us, stands to these phenomena and their connection in nature. The intelligible ground
of phenomena in this subject does not concern empirical questions. It has to do only with pure thought; and,
although the effects of this thought and action of the pure understanding are discoverable in phenomena,
these phenomena must nevertheless be capable of a full and complete explanation, upon purely physical
grounds and in accordance with natural laws. And in this case we attend solely to their empirical and omit all
consideration of their intelligible character (which is the transcendental cause of the former) as completely
unknown, except in so far as it is exhibited by the latter as its empirical symbol. Now let us apply this to
experience. Man is a phenomenon of the sensuous world and, at the same time, therefore, a natural cause, the
causality of which must be regulated by empirical laws. As such, he must possess an empirical character, like
all other natural phenomena. We remark this empirical character in his actions, which reveal the presence of
certain powers and faculties. If we consider inanimate or merely animal nature, we can discover no reason for
ascribing to ourselves any other than a faculty which is determined in a purely sensuous manner. But man, to
whom nature reveals herself only through sense, cognizes himself not only by his senses, but also through
pure apperception; and this in actions and internal determinations, which he cannot regard as sensuous
impressions. He is thus to himself, on the one hand, a phenomenon, but on the other hand, in respect of
certain faculties, a purely intelligible object intelligible, because its action cannot be ascribed to sensuous
receptivity. These faculties are understanding and reason. The latter, especially, is in a peculiar manner
distinct from all empiricallyconditioned faculties, for it employs ideas alone in the consideration of its
objects, and by means of these determines the understanding, which then proceeds to make an empirical use
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 183
Page No 188
of its own conceptions, which, like the ideas of reason, are pure and nonempirical.
That reason possesses the faculty of causality, or that at least we are compelled so to represent it, is evident
from the imperatives, which in the sphere of the practical we impose on many of our executive powers. The
words I ought express a species of necessity, and imply a connection with grounds which nature does not and
cannot present to the mind of man. Understanding knows nothing in nature but that which is, or has been, or
will be. It would be absurd to say that anything in nature ought to be other than it is in the relations of time in
which it stands; indeed, the ought, when we consider merely the course of nature, bas neither application nor
meaning. The question, "What ought to happen in the sphere of nature?" is just as absurd as the question,
"What ought to be the properties of a circle?" All that we are entitled to ask is, "What takes place in nature?"
or, in the latter case, "What are the properties of a circle?"
But the idea of an ought or of duty indicates a possible action, the ground of which is a pure conception;
while the ground of a merely natural action is, on the contrary, always a phenomenon. This action must
certainly be possible under physical conditions, if it is prescribed by the moral imperative ought; but these
physical or natural conditions do not concern the determination of the will itself, they relate to its effects
alone, and the consequences of the effect in the world of phenomena. Whatever number of motives nature
may present to my will, whatever sensuous impulses the moral ought it is beyond their power to produce.
They may produce a volition, which, so far from being necessary, is always conditioned a volition to which
the ought enunciated by reason, sets an aim and a standard, gives permission or prohibition. Be the object
what it may, purely sensuous as pleasure, or presented by pure reason as good, reason will not yield to
grounds which have an empirical origin. Reason will not follow the order of things presented by experience,
but, with perfect spontaneity, rearranges them according to ideas, with which it compels empirical conditions
to agree. It declares, in the name of these ideas, certain actions to be necessary which nevertheless have not
taken place and which perhaps never will take place; and yet presupposes that it possesses the faculty of
causality in relation to these actions. For, in the absence of this supposition, it could not expect its ideas to
produce certain effects in the world of experience.
Now, let us stop here and admit it to be at least possible that reason does stand in a really causal relation to
phenomena. In this case it must pure reason as it is exhibit an empirical character. For every cause
supposes a rule, according to which certain phenomena follow as effects from the cause, and every rule
requires uniformity in these effects; and this is the proper ground of the conception of a cause as a faculty or
power. Now this conception (of a cause) may be termed the empirical character of reason; and this character
is a permanent one, while the effects produced appear, in conformity with the various conditions which
accompany and partly limit them, in various forms.
Thus the volition of every man has an empirical character, which is nothing more than the causality of his
reason, in so far as its effects in the phenomenal world manifest the presence of a rule, according to which we
are enabled to examine, in their several kinds and degrees, the actions of this causality and the rational
grounds for these actions, and in this way to decide upon the subjective principles of the volition. Now we
learn what this empirical character is only from phenomenal effects, and from the rule of these which is
presented by experience; and for this reason all the actions of man in the world of phenomena are determined
by his empirical character, and the cooperative causes of nature. If, then, we could investigate all the
phenomena of human volition to their lowest foundation in the mind, there would be no action which we
could not anticipate with certainty, and recognize to be absolutely necessary from its preceding conditions. So
far as relates to this empirical character, therefore, there can be no freedom; and it is only in the light of this
character that we can consider the human will, when we confine ourselves to simple observation and, as is the
case in anthropology, institute a physiological investigation of the motive causes of human actions.
But when we consider the same actions in relation to reason not for the purpose of explaining their origin,
that is, in relation to speculative reason, but to practical reason, as the producing cause of these actions we
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 184
Page No 189
shall discover a rule and an order very different from those of nature and experience. For the declaration of
this mental faculty may be that what has and could not but take place in the course of nature, ought not to
have taken place. Sometimes, too, we discover, or believe that we discover, that the ideas of reason did
actually stand in a causal relation to certain actions of man; and that these actions have taken place because
they were determined, not by empirical causes, but by the act of the will upon grounds of reason.
Now, granting that reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena; can an action of reason be called free,
when we know that, sensuously, in its empirical character, it is completely determined and absolutely
necessary? But this empirical character is itself determined by the intelligible character. The latter we cannot
cognize; we can only indicate it by means of phenomena, which enable us to have an immediate cognition
only of the empirical character.* An action, then, in so far as it is to be ascribed to an intelligible cause, does
not result from it in accordance with empirical laws. That is to say, not the conditions of pure reason, but only
their effects in the internal sense, precede the act. Pure reason, as a purely intelligible faculty, is not subject to
the conditions of time. The causality of reason in its intelligible character does not begin to be; it does not
make its appearance at a certain time, for the purpose of producing an effect. If this were not the case, the
causality of reason would be subservient to the natural law of phenomena, which determines them according
to time, and as a series of causes and effects in time; it would consequently cease to be freedom and become a
part of nature. We are therefore justified in saying: "If reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena, it is a
faculty which originates the sensuous condition of an empirical series of effects." For the condition, which
resides in the reason, is nonsensuous, and therefore cannot be originated, or begin to be. And thus we find
what we could not discover in any empirical series a condition of a successive series of events itself
empirically unconditioned. For, in the present case, the condition stands out of and beyond the series of
phenomena it is intelligible, and it consequently cannot be subjected to any sensuous condition, or to any
timedetermination by a preceding cause.
*The real morality of actions their merit or demerit, and even that of our own conduct, is completely
unknown to us. Our estimates can relate only to their empirical character. How much is the result of the
action of free will, how much is to be ascribed to nature and to blameless error, or to a happy constitution of
temperament (merito fortunae), no one can discover, nor, for this reason, determine with perfect justice.
But, in another respect, the same cause belongs also to the series of phenomena. Man is himself a
phenomenon. His will has an empirical character, which is the empirical cause of all his actions. There is no
condition determining man and his volition in conformity with this character which does not itself form
part of the series of effects in nature, and is subject to their law the law according to which an empirically
undetermined cause of an event in time cannot exist. For this reason no given action can have an absolute and
spontaneous origination, all actions being phenomena, and belonging to the world of experience. But it
cannot be said of reason, that the state in which it determines the will is always preceded by some other state
determining it. For reason is not a phenomenon, and therefore not subject to sensuous conditions; and,
consequently, even in relation to its causality, the sequence or conditions of time do not influence reason, nor
can the dynamical law of nature, which determines the sequence of time according to certain rules, be applied
to it.
Reason is consequently the permanent condition of all actions of the human will. Each of these is determined
in the empirical character of the man, even before it has taken place. The intelligible character, of which the
former is but the sensuous schema, knows no before or after; and every action, irrespective of the
timerelation in which it stands with other phenomena, is the immediate effect of the intelligible character of
pure reason, which, consequently, enjoys freedom of action, and is not dynamically determined either by
internal or external preceding conditions. This freedom must not be described, in a merely negative manner,
as independence of empirical conditions, for in this case the faculty of reason would cease to be a cause of
phenomena; but it must be regarded, positively, as a faculty which can spontaneously originate a series of
events. At the same time, it must not be supposed that any beginning can take place in reason; on the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 185
Page No 190
contrary, reason, as the unconditioned condition of all action of the will, admits of no timeconditions,
although its effect does really begin in a series of phenomena a beginning which is not, however, absolutely
primal.
I shall illustrate this regulative principle of reason by an example, from its employment in the world of
experience; proved it cannot be by any amount of experience, or by any number of facts, for such arguments
cannot establish the truth of transcendental propositions. Let us take a voluntary action for example, a
falsehood by means of which a man has introduced a certain degree of confusion into the social life of
humanity, which is judged according to the motives from which it originated, and the blame of which and of
the evil consequences arising from it, is imputed to the offender. We at first proceed to examine the empirical
character of the offence, and for this purpose we endeavour to penetrate to the sources of that character, such
as a defective education, bad company, a shameless and wicked disposition, frivolity, and want of reflection
not forgetting also the occasioning causes which prevailed at the moment of the transgression. In this the
procedure is exactly the same as that pursued in the investigation of the series of causes which determine a
given physical effect. Now, although we believe the action to have been determined by all these
circumstances, we do not the less blame the offender. We do not blame him for his unhappy disposition, nor
for the circumstances which influenced him, nay, not even for his former course of life; for we presuppose
that all these considerations may be set aside, that the series of preceding conditions may be regarded as
having never existed, and that the action may be considered as completely unconditioned in relation to any
state preceding, just as if the agent commenced with it an entirely new series of effects. Our blame of the
offender is grounded upon a law of reason, which requires us to regard this faculty as a cause, which could
have and ought to have otherwise determined the behaviour of the culprit, independently of all empirical
conditions. This causality of reason we do not regard as a cooperating agency, but as complete in itself. It
matters not whether the sensuous impulses favoured or opposed the action of this causality, the offence is
estimated according to its intelligible character the offender is decidedly worthy of blame, the moment he
utters a falsehood. It follows that we regard reason, in spite of the empirical conditions of the act, as
completely free, and therefore, therefore, as in the present case, culpable.
The above judgement is complete evidence that we are accustomed to think that reason is not affected by
sensuous conditions, that in it no change takes place although its phenomena, in other words, the mode in
which it appears in its effects, are subject to change that in it no preceding state determines the following,
and, consequently, that it does not form a member of the series of sensuous conditions which necessitate
phenomena according to natural laws. Reason is present and the same in all human actions and at all times;
but it does not itself exist in time, and therefore does not enter upon any state in which it did not formerly
exist. It is, relatively to new states or conditions, determining, but not determinable. Hence we cannot ask:
"Why did not reason determine itself in a different manner?" The question ought to be thus stated: "Why did
not reason employ its power of causality to determine certain phenomena in a different manner?" "But this is
a question which admits of no answer. For a different intelligible character would have exhibited a different
empirical character; and, when we say that, in spite of the course which his whole former life has taken, the
offender could have refrained from uttering the falsehood, this means merely that the act was subject to the
power and authority permissive or prohibitive of reason. Now, reason is not subject in its causality to any
conditions of phenomena or of time; and a difference in time may produce a difference in the relation of
phenomena to each other for these are not things and therefore not causes in themselves but it cannot
produce any difference in the relation in which the action stands to the faculty of reason.
Thus, then, in our investigation into free actions and the causal power which produced them, we arrive at an
intelligible cause, beyond which, however, we cannot go; although we can recognize that it is free, that is,
independent of all sensuous conditions, and that, in this way, it may be the sensuously unconditioned
condition of phenomena. But for what reason the intelligible character generates such and such phenomena
and exhibits such and such an empirical character under certain circumstances, it is beyond the power of our
reason to decide. The question is as much above the power and the sphere of reason as the following would
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 186
Page No 191
be: "Why does the transcendental object of our external sensuous intuition allow of no other form than that of
intuition in space?" But the problem, which we were called upon to solve, does not require us to entertain any
such questions. The problem was merely this whether freedom and natural necessity can exist without
opposition in the same action. To this question we have given a sufficient answer; for we have shown that, as
the former stands in a relation to a different kind of condition from those of the latter, the law of the one does
not affect the law of the other and that, consequently, both can exist together in independence of and without
interference with each other.
The reader must be careful to remark that my intention in the above remarks has not been to prove the actual
existence of freedom, as a faculty in which resides the cause of certain sensuous phenomena. For, not to
mention that such an argument would not have a transcendental character, nor have been limited to the
discussion of pure conceptions all attempts at inferring from experience what cannot be cogitated in
accordance with its laws, must ever be unsuccessful. Nay, more, I have not even aimed at demonstrating the
possibility of freedom; for this too would have been a vain endeavour, inasmuch as it is beyond the power of
the mind to cognize the possibility of a reality or of a causal power by the aid of mere a priori conceptions.
Freedom has been considered in the foregoing remarks only as a transcendental idea, by means of which
reason aims at originating a series of conditions in the world of phenomena with the help of that which is
sensuously unconditioned, involving itself, however, in an antinomy with the laws which itself prescribes for
the conduct of the understanding. That this antinomy is based upon a mere illusion, and that nature and
freedom are at least not opposed this was the only thing in our power to prove, and the question which it
was our task to solve.
IV. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of
the Dependence of Phenomenal Existences.
In the preceding remarks, we considered the changes in the world of sense as constituting a dynamical series,
in which each member is subordinated to another as its cause. Our present purpose is to avail ourselves of
this series of states or conditions as a guide to an existence which may be the highest condition of all
changeable phenomena, that is, to a necessary being. Our endeavour to reach, not the unconditioned
causality, but the unconditioned existence, of substance. The series before us is therefore a series of
conceptions, and not of intuitions (in which the one intuition is the condition of the other).
But it is evident that, as all phenomena are subject to change and conditioned in their existence, the series of
dependent existences cannot embrace an unconditioned member, the existence of which would be absolutely
necessary. It follows that, if phenomena were things in themselves, and as an immediate consequence from
this supposition condition and conditioned belonged to the same series of phenomena, the existence of a
necessary being, as the condition of the existence of sensuous phenomena, would be perfectly impossible.
An important distinction, however, exists between the dynamical and the mathematical regress. The latter is
engaged solely with the combination of parts into a whole, or with the division of a whole into its parts; and
therefore are the conditions of its series parts of the series, and to be consequently regarded as homogeneous,
and for this reason, as consisting, without exception, of phenomena. If the former regress, on the contrary, the
aim of which is not to establish the possibility of an unconditioned whole consisting of given parts, or of an
unconditioned part of a given whole, but to demonstrate the possibility of the deduction of a certain state
from its cause, or of the contingent existence of substance from that which exists necessarily, it is not
requisite that the condition should form part of an empirical series along with the conditioned.
In the case of the apparent antinomy with which we are at present dealing, there exists a way of escape from
the difficulty; for it is not impossible that both of the contradictory statements may be true in different
relations. All sensuous phenomena may be contingent, and consequently possess only an empirically
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 187
Page No 192
conditioned existence, and yet there may also exist a nonempirical condition of the whole series, or, in other
words, a necessary being. For this necessary being, as an intelligible condition, would not form a member
not even the highest member of the series; the whole world of sense would be left in its empirically
determined existence uninterfered with and uninfluenced. This would also form a ground of distinction
between the modes of solution employed for the third and fourth antinomies. For, while in the consideration
of freedom in the former antinomy, the thing itself the cause (substantia phaenomenon) was regarded as
belonging to the series of conditions, and only its causality to the intelligible world we are obliged in the
present case to cogitate this necessary being as purely intelligible and as existing entirely apart from the
world of sense (as an ens extramundanum); for otherwise it would be subject to the phenomenal law of
contingency and dependence.
In relation to the present problem, therefore, the regulative principle of reason is that everything in the
sensuous world possesses an empirically conditioned existence that no property of the sensuous world
possesses unconditioned necessity that we are bound to expect, and, so far as is possible, to seek for the
empirical condition of every member in the series of conditions and that there is no sufficient reason to
justify us in deducing any existence from a condition which lies out of and beyond the empirical series, or in
regarding any existence as independent and selfsubsistent; although this should not prevent us from
recognizing the possibility of the whole series being based upon a being which is intelligible, and for this
reason free from all empirical conditions.
But it has been far from my intention, in these remarks, to prove the existence of this unconditioned and
necessary being, or even to evidence the possibility of a purely intelligible condition of the existence or all
sensuous phenomena. As bounds were set to reason, to prevent it from leaving the guiding thread of empirical
conditions and losing itself in transcendent theories which are incapable of concrete presentation; so it was
my purpose, on the other band, to set bounds to the law of the purely empirical understanding, and to protest
against any attempts on its part at deciding on the possibility of things, or declaring the existence of the
intelligible to be impossible, merely on the ground that it is not available for the explanation and exposition
of phenomena. It has been shown, at the same time, that the contingency of all the phenomena of nature and
their empirical conditions is quite consistent with the arbitrary hypothesis of a necessary, although purely
intelligible condition, that no real contradiction exists between them and that, consequently, both may be true.
The existence of such an absolutely necessary being may be impossible; but this can never be demonstrated
from the universal contingency and dependence of sensuous phenomena, nor from the principle which forbids
us to discontinue the series at some member of it, or to seek for its cause in some sphere of existence beyond
the world of nature. Reason goes its way in the empirical world, and follows, too, its peculiar path in the
sphere of the transcendental.
The sensuous world contains nothing but phenomena, which are mere representations, and always sensuously
conditioned; things in themselves are not, and cannot be, objects to us. It is not to be wondered at, therefore,
that we are not justified in leaping from some member of an empirical series beyond the world of sense, as if
empirical representations were things in themselves, existing apart from their transcendental ground in the
human mind, and the cause of whose existence may be sought out of the empirical series. This would
certainly be the case with contingent things; but it cannot be with mere representations of things, the
contingency of which is itself merely a phenomenon and can relate to no other regress than that which
determines phenomena, that is, the empirical. But to cogitate an intelligible ground of phenomena, as free,
moreover, from the contingency of the latter, conflicts neither with the unlimited nature of the empirical
regress, nor with the complete contingency of phenomena. And the demonstration of this was the only thing
necessary for the solution of this apparent antinomy. For if the condition of every conditioned as regards its
existence is sensuous, and for this reason a part of the same series, it must be itself conditioned, as was
shown in the antithesis of the fourth antinomy. The embarrassments into which a reason, which postulates the
unconditioned, necessarily falls, must, therefore, continue to exist; or the unconditioned must be placed in the
sphere of the intelligible. In this way, its necessity does not require, nor does it even permit, the presence of
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas. 188
Page No 193
an empirical condition: and it is, consequently, unconditionally necessary.
The empirical employment of reason is not affected by the assumption of a purely intelligible being; it
continues its operations on the principle of the contingency of all phenomena, proceeding from empirical
conditions to still higher and higher conditions, themselves empirical. just as little does this regulative
principle exclude the assumption of an intelligible cause, when the question regards merely the pure
employment of reason in relation to ends or aims. For, in this case, an intelligible cause signifies merely the
transcendental and to us unknown ground of the possibility of sensuous phenomena, and its existence,
necessary and independent of all sensuous conditions, is not inconsistent with the contingency of phenomena,
or with the unlimited possibility of regress which exists in the series of empirical conditions.
Concluding Remarks on the Antinomy of Pure Reason.
So long as the object of our rational conceptions is the totality of conditions in the world of phenomena, and
the satisfaction, from this source, of the requirements of reason, so long are our ideas transcendental and
cosmological. But when we set the unconditioned which is the aim of all our inquiries in a sphere which
lies out of the world of sense and possible experience, our ideas become transcendent. They are then not
merely serviceable towards the completion of the exercise of reason (which remains an idea, never executed,
but always to be pursued); they detach themselves completely from experience and construct for themselves
objects, the material of which has not been presented by experience, and the objective reality of which is not
based upon the completion of the empirical series, but upon pure a priori conceptions. The intelligible object
of these transcendent ideas may be conceded, as a transcendental object. But we cannot cogitate it as a thing
determinable by certain distinct predicates relating to its internal nature, for it has no connection with
empirical conceptions; nor are we justified in affirming the existence of any such object. It is, consequently, a
mere product of the mind alone. Of all the cosmological ideas, however, it is that occasioning the fourth
antinomy which compels us to venture upon this step. For the existence of phenomena, always conditioned
and never selfsubsistent, requires us to look for an object different from phenomena an intelligible object,
with which all contingency must cease. But, as we have allowed ourselves to assume the existence of a
selfsubsistent reality out of the field of experience, and are therefore obliged to regard phenomena as merely
a contingent mode of representing intelligible objects employed by beings which are themselves
intelligences no other course remains for us than to follow an alogy and employ the same mode in forming
some conception of intelligible things, of which we have not the least knowledge, which nature taught us to
use in the formation of empirical conceptions. Experience made us acquainted with the contingent. But we
are at present engaged in the discussion of things which are not objects of experience; and must, therefore,
deduce our knowledge of them from that which is necessary absolutely and in itself, that is, from pure
conceptions. Hence the first step which we take out of the world of sense obliges us to begin our system of
new cognition with the investigation of a necessary being, and to deduce from our conceptions of it all our
conceptions of intelligible things. This we propose to attempt in the following chapter.
CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason.
SECTION I. Of the Ideal in General.
We have seen that pure conceptions do not present objects to the mind, except under sensuous conditions;
because the conditions of objective reality do not exist in these conceptions, which contain, in fact, nothing
but the mere form of thought. They may, however, when applied to phenomena, be presented in concreto; for
it is phenomena that present to them the materials for the formation of empirical conceptions, which are
nothing more than concrete forms of the conceptions of the understanding. But ideas are still further removed
from objective reality than categories; for no phenomenon can ever present them to the human mind in
concreto. They contain a certain perfection, attainable by no possible empirical cognition; and they give to
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason. 189
Page No 194
reason a systematic unity, to which the unity of experience attempts to approximate, but can never completely
attain.
But still further removed than the idea from objective reality is the Ideal, by which term I understand the idea,
not in concreto, but in individuo as an individual thing, determinable or determined by the idea alone. The
idea of humanity in its complete perfection supposes not only the advancement of all the powers and
faculties, which constitute our conception of human nature, to a complete attainment of their final aims, but
also everything which is requisite for the complete determination of the idea; for of all contradictory
predicates, only one can conform with the idea of the perfect man. What I have termed an ideal was in Plato's
philosophy an idea of the divine mind an individual object present to its pure intuition, the most perfect of
every kind of possible beings, and the archetype of all phenomenal existences.
Without rising to these speculative heights, we are bound to confess that human reason contains not only
ideas, but ideals, which possess, not, like those of Plato, creative, but certainly practical power as regulative
principles, and form the basis of the perfectibility of certain actions. Moral conceptions are not perfectly pure
conceptions of reason, because an empirical element of pleasure or pain lies at the foundation of them. In
relation, however, to the principle, whereby reason sets bounds to a freedom which is in itself without law,
and consequently when we attend merely to their form, they may be considered as pure conceptions of
reason. Virtue and wisdom in their perfect purity are ideas. But the wise man of the Stoics is an ideal, that is
to say, a human being existing only in thought and in complete conformity with the idea of wisdom. As the
idea provides a rule, so the ideal serves as an archetype for the perfect and complete determination of the
copy. Thus the conduct of this wise and divine man serves us as a standard of action, with which we may
compare and judge ourselves, which may help us to reform ourselves, although the perfection it demands can
never be attained by us. Although we cannot concede objective reality to these ideals, they are not to be
considered as chimeras; on the contrary, they provide reason with a standard, which enables it to estimate, by
comparison, the degree of incompleteness in the objects presented to it. But to aim at realizing the ideal in an
example in the world of experience to describe, for instance, the character of the perfectly wise man in a
romance is impracticable. Nay more, there is something absurd in the attempt; and the result must be little
edifying, as the natural limitations, which are continually breaking in upon the perfection and completeness
of the idea, destroy the illusion in the story and throw an air of suspicion even on what is good in the idea,
which hence appears fictitious and unreal.
Such is the constitution of the ideal of reason, which is always based upon determinate conceptions, and
serves as a rule and a model for limitation or of criticism. Very different is the nature of the ideals of the
imagination. Of these it is impossible to present an intelligible conception; they are a kind of monogram,
drawn according to no determinate rule, and forming rather a vague picture the production of many diverse
experiences than a determinate image. Such are the ideals which painters and physiognomists profess to
have in their minds, and which can serve neither as a model for production nor as a standard for appreciation.
They may be termed, though improperly, sensuous ideals, as they are declared to be models of certain
possible empirical intuitions. They cannot, however, furnish rules or standards for explanation or examination
with
In its ideals, reason aims at complete and perfect determination according to a priori rules; and hence it
cogitates an object, which must be completely determinable in conformity with principles, although all
empirical conditions are absent, and the conception of the object is on this account transcendent.
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale).
Every conception is, in relation to that which is not contained in it, undetermined and subject to the principle
of determinability. This principle is that, of every two contradictorily opposed predicates, only one can
belong to a conception. It is a purely logical principle, itself based upon the principle of contradiction;
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale). 190
Page No 195
inasmuch as it makes complete abstraction of the content and attends merely to the logical form of the
cognition.
But again, everything, as regards its possibility, is also subject to the principle of complete determination,
according to which one of all the possible contradictory predicates of things must belong to it. This principle
is not based merely upon that of contradiction; for, in addition to the relation between two contradictory
predicates, it regards everything as standing in a relation to the sum of possibilities, as the sum total of all
predicates of things, and, while presupposing this sum as an a priori condition, presents to the mind
everything as receiving the possibility of its individual existence from the relation it bears to, and the share it
possesses in, the aforesaid sum of possibilities.* The principle of complete determination relates the content
and not to the logical form. It is the principle of the synthesis of all the predicates which are required to
constitute the complete conception of a thing, and not a mere principle analytical representation, which
enounces that one of two contradictory predicates must belong to a conception. It contains, moreover, a
transcendental presupposition that, namely, of the material for all possibility, which must contain a priori
the data for this or that particular possibility.
*Thus this principle declares everything to possess a relation to a common correlate the sumtotal of
possibility, which, if discovered to exist in the idea of one individual thing, would establish the affinity of all
possible things, from the identity of the ground of their complete determination. The determinability of every
conception is subordinate to the universality (Allgemeinheit, universalitas) of the principle of excluded
middle; the determination of a thing to the totality (Allheit, universitas) of all possible predicates.
The proposition, Everything which exists is completely determined, means not only that one of every pair of
given contradictory attributes, but that one of all possible attributes, is always predicable of the thing; in it the
predicates are not merely compared logically with each other, but the thing itself is transcendentally
compared with the sumtotal of all possible predicates. The proposition is equivalent to saying: "To attain to
a complete knowledge of a thing, it is necessary to possess a knowledge of everything that is possible, and to
determine it thereby in a positive or negative manner." The conception of complete determination is
consequently a conception which cannot be presented in its totality in concreto, and is therefore based upon
an idea, which has its seat in the reason the faculty which prescribes to the understanding the laws of its
harmonious and perfect exercise relates
Now, although this idea of the sumtotal of all possibility, in so far as it forms the condition of the complete
determination of everything, is itself undetermined in relation to the predicates which may constitute this
sumtotal, and we cogitate in it merely the sumtotal of all possible predicates we nevertheless find, upon
closer examination, that this idea, as a primitive conception of the mind, excludes a large number of
predicates those deduced and those irreconcilable with others, and that it is evolved as a conception
completely determined a priori. Thus it becomes the conception of an individual object, which is completely
determined by and through the mere idea, and must consequently be termed an ideal of pure reason.
When we consider all possible predicates, not merely logically, but transcendentally, that is to say, with
reference to the content which may be cogitated as existing in them a priori, we shall find that some indicate a
being, others merely a nonbeing. The logical negation expressed in the word not does not properly belong to
a conception, but only to the relation of one conception to another in a judgement, and is consequently quite
insufficient to present to the mind the content of a conception. The expression not mortal does not indicate
that a nonbeing is cogitated in the object; it does not concern the content at all. A transcendental negation,
on the contrary, indicates nonbeing in itself, and is opposed to transcendental affirmation, the conception of
which of itself expresses a being. Hence this affirmation indicates a reality, because in and through it objects
are considered to be something to be things; while the opposite negation, on the other band, indicates a mere
want, or privation, or absence, and, where such negations alone are attached to a representation, the
nonexistence of anything corresponding to the representation.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale). 191
Page No 196
Now a negation cannot be cogitated as determined, without cogitating at the same time the opposite
affirmation. The man born blind has not the least notion of darkness, because he has none of light; the
vagabond knows nothing of poverty, because he has never known what it is to be in comfort;* the ignorant
man has no conception of his ignorance, because he has no conception of knowledge. All conceptions of
negatives are accordingly derived or deduced conceptions; and realities contain the data, and, so to speak, the
material or transcendental content of the possibility and complete determination of all things.
*The investigations and calculations of astronomers have taught us much that is wonderful; but the most
important lesson we have received from them is the discovery of the abyss of our ignorance in relation to the
universe an ignorance the magnitude of which reason, without the information thus derived, could never
have conceived. This discovery of our deficiencies must produce a great change in the determination of the
aims of human reason.
If, therefore, a transcendental substratum lies at the foundation of the complete determination of things a
substratum which is to form the fund from which all possible predicates of things are to be supplied, this
substratum cannot be anything else than the idea of a sumtotal of reality (omnitudo realitatis). In this view,
negations are nothing but limitations a term which could not, with propriety, be applied to them, if the
unlimited (the all) did not form the true basis of our conception.
This conception of a sumtotal of reality is the conception of a thing in itself, regarded as completely
determined; and the conception of an ens realissimum is the conception of an individual being, inasmuch as it
is determined by that predicate of all possible contradictory predicates, which indicates and belongs to being.
It is, therefore, a transcendental ideal which forms the basis of the complete determination of everything that
exists, and is the highest material condition of its possibility a condition on which must rest the cogitation of
all objects with respect to their content. Nay, more, this ideal is the only proper ideal of which the human
mind is capable; because in this case alone a general conception of a thing is completely determined by and
through itself, and cognized as the representation of an individuum.
The logical determination of a conception is based upon a disjunctive syllogism, the major of which contains
the logical division of the extent of a general conception, the minor limits this extent to a certain part, while
the conclusion determines the conception by this part. The general conception of a reality cannot be divided a
priori, because, without the aid of experience, we cannot know any determinate kinds of reality, standing
under the former as the genus. The transcendental principle of the complete determination of all things is
therefore merely the representation of the sumtotal of all reality; it is not a conception which is the genus of
all predicates under itself, but one which comprehends them all within itself. The complete determination of a
thing is consequently based upon the limitation of this total of reality, so much being predicated of the thing,
while all that remains over is excluded a procedure which is in exact agreement with that of the disjunctive
syllogism and the determination of the objects in the conclusion by one of the members of the division. It
follows that reason, in laying the transcendental ideal at the foundation of its determination of all possible
things, takes a course in exact analogy with that which it pursues in disjunctive syllogisms a proposition
which formed the basis of the systematic division of all transcendental ideas, according to which they are
produced in complete parallelism with the three modes of syllogistic reasoning employed by the human mind.
It is selfevident that reason, in cogitating the necessary complete determination of things, does not
presuppose the existence of a being corresponding to its ideal, but merely the idea of the ideal for the
purpose of deducing from the unconditional totality of complete determination, The ideal is therefore the
prototype of all things, which, as defective copies (ectypa), receive from it the material of their possibility,
and approximate to it more or less, though it is impossible that they can ever attain to its perfection.
The possibility of things must therefore be regarded as derived except that of the thing which contains in
itself all reality, which must be considered to be primitive and original. For all negations and they are the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale). 192
Page No 197
only predicates by means of which all other things can be distinguished from the ens realissimum are mere
limitations of a greater and a higher nay, the highest reality; and they consequently presuppose this reality,
and are, as regards their content, derived from it. The manifold nature of things is only an infinitely various
mode of limiting the conception of the highest reality, which is their common substratum; just as all figures
are possible only as different modes of limiting infinite space. The object of the ideal of reason an object
existing only in reason itself is also termed the primal being (ens originarium); as having no existence
superior to him, the supreme being (ens summum); and as being the condition of all other beings, which rank
under it, the being of all beings (ens entium). But none of these terms indicate the objective relation of an
actually existing object to other things, but merely that of an idea to conceptions; and all our investigations
into this subject still leave us in perfect uncertainty with regard to the existence of this being.
A primal being cannot be said to consist of many other beings with an existence which is derivative, for the
latter presuppose the former, and therefore cannot be constitutive parts of it. It follows that the ideal of the
primal being must be cogitated as simple.
The deduction of the possibility of all other things from this primal being cannot, strictly speaking, be
considered as a limitation, or as a kind of division of its reality; for this would be regarding the primal being
as a mere aggregate which has been shown to be impossible, although it was so represented in our first
rough sketch. The highest reality must be regarded rather as the ground than as the sumtotal of the
possibility of all things, and the manifold nature of things be based, not upon the limitation of the primal
being itself, but upon the complete series of effects which flow from it. And thus all our powers of sense, as
well as all phenomenal reality, phenomenal reality, may be with propriety regarded as belonging to this series
of effects, while they could not have formed parts of the idea, considered as an aggregate. Pursuing this track,
and hypostatizing this idea, we shall find ourselves authorized to determine our notion of the Supreme Being
by means of the mere conception of a highest reality, as one, simple, allsufficient, eternal, and so on in one
word, to determine it in its unconditioned completeness by the aid of every possible predicate. The
conception of such a being is the conception of God in its transcendental sense, and thus the ideal of pure
reason is the objectmatter of a transcendental theology.
But, by such an employment of the transcendental idea, we should be over stepping the limits of its validity
and purpose. For reason placed it, as the conception of all reality, at the basis of the complete determination
of things, without requiring that this conception be regarded as the conception of an objective existence. Such
an existence would be purely fictitious, and the hypostatizing of the content of the idea into an ideal, as an
individual being, is a step perfectly unauthorized. Nay, more, we are not even called upon to assume the
possibility of such an hypothesis, as none of the deductions drawn from such an ideal would affect the
complete determination of things in general for the sake of which alone is the idea necessary.
It is not sufficient to circumscribe the procedure and the dialectic of reason; we must also endeavour to
discover the sources of this dialectic, that we may have it in our power to give a rational explanation of this
illusion, as a phenomenon of the human mind. For the ideal, of which we are at present speaking, is based,
not upon an arbitrary, but upon a natural, idea. The question hence arises: How happens it that reason regards
the possibility of all things as deduced from a single possibility, that, to wit, of the highest reality, and
presupposes this as existing in an individual and primal being?
The answer is ready; it is at once presented by the procedure of transcendental analytic. The possibility of
sensuous objects is a relation of these objects to thought, in which something (the empirical form) may be
cogitated a priori; while that which constitutes the matter the reality of the phenomenon (that element which
corresponds to sensation) must be given from without, as otherwise it could not even be cogitated by, nor
could its possibility be presentable to the mind. Now, a sensuous object is completely determined, when it has
been compared with all phenomenal predicates, and represented by means of these either positively or
negatively. But, as that which constitutes the thing itself the real in a phenomenon, must be given, and that,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale). 193
Page No 198
in which the real of all phenomena is given, is experience, one, sole, and allembracing the material of the
possibility of all sensuous objects must be presupposed as given in a whole, and it is upon the limitation of
this whole that the possibility of all empirical objects, their distinction from each other and their complete
determination, are based. Now, no other objects are presented to us besides sensuous objects, and these can
be given only in connection with a possible experience; it follows that a thing is not an object to us, unless it
presupposes the whole or sumtotal of empirical reality as the condition of its possibility. Now, a natural
illusion leads us to consider this principle, which is valid only of sensuous objects, as valid with regard to
things in general. And thus we are induced to hold the empirical principle of our conceptions of the
possibility of things, as phenomena, by leaving out this limitative condition, to be a transcendental principle
of the possibility of things in general.
We proceed afterwards to hypostatize this idea of the sumtotal of all reality, by changing the distributive
unity of the empirical exercise of the understanding into the collective unity of an empirical whole a
dialectical illusion, and by cogitating this whole or sum of experience as an individual thing, containing in
itself all empirical reality. This individual thing or being is then, by means of the abovementioned
transcendental subreption, substituted for our notion of a thing which stands at the head of the possibility of
all things, the real conditions of whose complete determination it presents.*
*This ideal of the ens realissimum although merely a mental representation is first objectivized, that is, has
an objective existence attributed to it, then hypostatized, and finally, by the natural progress of reason to the
completion of unity, personified, as we shall show presently. For the regulative unity of experience is not
based upon phenomena themselves, but upon the connection of the variety of phenomena by the
understanding in a consciousness, and thus the unity of the supreme reality and the complete determinability
of all things, seem to reside in a supreme understanding, and, consequently, in a conscious intelligence.
SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in
Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being.
Notwithstanding the pressing necessity which reason feels, to form some presupposition that shall serve the
understanding as a proper basis for the complete determination of its conceptions, the idealistic and factitious
nature of such a presupposition is too evident to allow reason for a moment to persuade itself into a belief of
the objective existence of a mere creation of its own thought. But there are other considerations which
compel reason to seek out some resting place in the regress from the conditioned to the unconditioned, which
is not given as an actual existence from the mere conception of it, although it alone can give completeness to
the series of conditions. And this is the natural course of every human reason, even of the most uneducated,
although the path at first entered it does not always continue to follow. It does not begin from conceptions,
but from common experience, and requires a basis in actual existence. But this basis is insecure, unless it
rests upon the immovable rock of the absolutely necessary. And this foundation is itself unworthy of trust, if
it leave under and above it empty space, if it do not fill all, and leave no room for a why or a wherefore, if it
be not, in one word, infinite in its reality.
If we admit the existence of some one thing, whatever it may be, we must also admit that there is something
which exists necessarily. For what is contingent exists only under the condition of some other thing, which is
its cause; and from this we must go on to conclude the existence of a cause which is not contingent, and
which consequently exists necessarily and unconditionally. Such is the argument by which reason justifies its
advances towards a primal being.
Now reason looks round for the conception of a being that may be admitted, without inconsistency, to be
worthy of the attribute of absolute necessity, not for the purpose of inferring a priori, from the conception of
such a being, its objective existence (for if reason allowed itself to take this course, it would not require a
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being. 194
Page No 199
basis in given and actual existence, but merely the support of pure conceptions), but for the purpose of
discovering, among all our conceptions of possible things, that conception which possesses no element
inconsistent with the idea of absolute necessity. For that there must be some absolutely necessary existence, it
regards as a truth already established. Now, if it can remove every existence incapable of supporting the
attribute of absolute necessity, excepting one this must be the absolutely necessary being, whether its
necessity is comprehensible by us, that is, deducible from the conception of it alone, or not.
Now that, the conception of which contains a therefore to every wherefore, which is not defective in any
respect whatever, which is allsufficient as a condition, seems to be the being of which we can justly
predicate absolute necessity for this reason, that, possessing the conditions of all that is possible, it does not
and cannot itself require any condition. And thus it satisfies, in one respect at least, the requirements of the
conception of absolute necessity. In this view, it is superior to all other conceptions, which, as deficient and
incomplete, do not possess the characteristic of independence of all higher conditions. It is true that we
cannot infer from this that what does not contain in itself the supreme and complete condition the condition
of all other things must possess only a conditioned existence; but as little can we assert the contrary, for this
supposed being does not possess the only characteristic which can enable reason to cognize by means of an a
priori conception the unconditioned and necessary nature of its existence.
The conception of an ens realissimum is that which best agrees with the conception of an unconditioned and
necessary being. The former conception does not satisfy all the requirements of the latter; but we have no
choice, we are obliged to adhere to it, for we find that we cannot do without the existence of a necessary
being; and even although we admit it, we find it out of our power to discover in the whole sphere of
possibility any being that can advance wellgrounded claims to such a distinction.
The following is, therefore, the natural course of human reason. It begins by persuading itself of the existence
of some necessary being. In this being it recognizes the characteristics of unconditioned existence. It then
seeks the conception of that which is independent of all conditions, and finds it in that which is itself the
sufficient condition of all other things in other words, in that which contains all reality. But the unlimited all
is an absolute unity, and is conceived by the mind as a being one and supreme; and thus reason concludes that
the Supreme Being, as the primal basis of all things, possesses an existence which is absolutely necessary.
This conception must be regarded as in some degree satisfactory, if we admit the existence of a necessary
being, and consider that there exists a necessity for a definite and final answer to these questions. In such a
case, we cannot make a better choice, or rather we have no choice at all, but feel ourselves obliged to declare
in favour of the absolute unity of complete reality, as the highest source of the possibility of things. But if
there exists no motive for coming to a definite conclusion, and we may leave the question unanswered till we
have fully weighed both sides in other words, when we are merely called upon to decide how much we
happen to know about the question, and how much we merely flatter ourselves that we know the above
conclusion does not appear to be so great advantage, but, on the contrary, seems defective in the grounds
upon which it is supported.
For, admitting the truth of all that has been said, that, namely, the inference from a given existence (my own,
for example) to the existence of an unconditioned and necessary being is valid and unassailable; that, in the
second place, we must consider a being which contains all reality, and consequently all the conditions of
other things, to be absolutely unconditioned; and admitting too, that we have thus discovered the conception
of a thing to which may be attributed, without inconsistency, absolute necessity it does not follow from all
this that the conception of a limited being, in which the supreme reality does not reside, is therefore
incompatible with the idea of absolute necessity. For, although I do not discover the element of the
unconditioned in the conception of such a being an element which is manifestly existent in the sumtotal of
all conditions I am not entitled to conclude that its existence is therefore conditioned; just as I am not
entitled to affirm, in a hypothetical syllogism, that where a certain condition does not exist (in the present,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being. 195
Page No 200
completeness, as far as pure conceptions are concerned), the conditioned does not exist either. On the
contrary, we are free to consider all limited beings as likewise unconditionally necessary, although we are
unable to infer this from the general conception which we have of them. Thus conducted, this argument is
incapable of giving us the least notion of the properties of a necessary being, and must be in every respect
without result.
This argument continues, however, to possess a weight and an authority, which, in spite of its objective
insufficiency, it has never been divested of. For, granting that certain responsibilities lie upon us, which, as
based on the ideas of reason, deserve to be respected and submitted to, although they are incapable of a real
or practical application to our nature, or, in other words, would be responsibilities without motives, except
upon the supposition of a Supreme Being to give effect and influence to the practical laws: in such a case we
should be bound to obey our conceptions, which, although objectively insufficient, do, according to the
standard of reason, preponderate over and are superior to any claims that may be advanced from any other
quarter. The equilibrium of doubt would in this case be destroyed by a practical addition; indeed, Reason
would be compelled to condemn herself, if she refused to comply with the demands of the judgement, no
superior to which we know however defective her understanding of the grounds of these demands might be.
This argument, although in fact transcendental, inasmuch as it rests upon the intrinsic insufficiency of the
contingent, is so simple and natural, that the commonest understanding can appreciate its value. We see
things around us change, arise, and pass away; they, or their condition, must therefore have a cause. The same
demand must again be made of the cause itself as a datum of experience. Now it is natural that we should
place the highest causality just where we place supreme causality, in that being, which contains the
conditions of all possible effects, and the conception of which is so simple as that of an allembracing reality.
This highest cause, then, we regard as absolutely necessary, because we find it absolutely necessary to rise to
it, and do not discover any reason for proceeding beyond it. Thus, among all nations, through the darkest
polytheism glimmer some faint sparks of monotheism, to which these idolaters have been led, not from
reflection and profound thought, but by the study and natural progress of the common understanding.
There are only three modes of proving the existence of a Deity, on the grounds of speculative reason.
All the paths conducting to this end begin either from determinate experience and the peculiar constitution of
the world of sense, and rise, according to the laws of causality, from it to the highest cause existing apart
from the world or from a purely indeterminate experience, that is, some empirical existence or abstraction
is made of all experience, and the existence of a supreme cause is concluded from a priori conceptions alone.
The first is the physicotheological argument, the second the cosmological, the third the ontological. More
there are not, and more there cannot be.
I shall show it is as unsuccessful on the one path the empirical as on the other the transcendental and
that it stretches its wings in vain, to soar beyond the world of sense by the mere might of speculative thought.
As regards the order in which we must discuss those arguments, it will be exactly the reverse of that in which
reason, in the progress of its development, attains to them the order in which they are placed above. For it
will be made manifest to the reader that, although experience presents the occasion and the startingpoint, it
is the transcendental idea of reason which guides it in its pilgrimage and is the goal of all its struggles. I shall
therefore begin with an examination of the transcendental argument, and afterwards inquire what additional
strength has accrued to this mode of proof from the addition of the empirical element.
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the
Existence of God.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God. 196
Page No 201
It is evident from what has been said that the conception of an absolutely necessary being is a mere idea, the
objective reality of which is far from being established by the mere fact that it is a need of reason. On the
contrary, this idea serves merely to indicate a certain unattainable perfection, and rather limits the operations
than, by the presentation of new objects, extends the sphere of the understanding. But a strange anomaly
meets us at the very threshold; for the inference from a given existence in general to an absolutely necessary
existence seems to be correct and unavoidable, while the conditions of the understanding refuse to aid us in
forming any conception of such a being.
Philosophers have always talked of an absolutely necessary being, and have nevertheless declined to take the
trouble of conceiving whether and how a being of this nature is even cogitable, not to mention that its
existence is actually demonstrable. A verbal definition of the conception is certainly easy enough: it is
something the nonexistence of which is impossible. But does this definition throw any light upon the
conditions which render it impossible to cogitate the nonexistence of a thing conditions which we wish to
ascertain, that we may discover whether we think anything in the conception of such a being or not? For the
mere fact that I throw away, by means of the word unconditioned, all the conditions which the understanding
habitually requires in order to regard anything as necessary, is very far from making clear whether by means
of the conception of the unconditionally necessary I think of something, or really of nothing at all.
Nay, more, this chanceconception, now become so current, many have endeavoured to explain by examples
which seemed to render any inquiries regarding its intelligibility quite needless. Every geometrical
proposition a triangle has three angles it was said, is absolutely necessary; and thus people talked of an
object which lay out of the sphere of our understanding as if it were perfectly plain what the conception of
such a being meant.
All the examples adduced have been drawn, without exception, from judgements, and not from things. But
the unconditioned necessity of a judgement does not form the absolute necessity of a thing. On the contrary,
the absolute necessity of a judgement is only a conditioned necessity of a thing, or of the predicate in a
judgement. The proposition abovementioned does not enounce that three angles necessarily exist, but, upon
condition that a triangle exists, three angles must necessarily exist in it. And thus this logical necessity has
been the source of the greatest delusions. Having formed an a priori conception of a thing, the content of
which was made to embrace existence, we believed ourselves safe in concluding that, because existence
belongs necessarily to the object of the conception (that is, under the condition of my positing this thing as
given), the existence of the thing is also posited necessarily, and that it is therefore absolutely necessary
merely because its existence has been cogitated in the conception.
If, in an identical judgement, I annihilate the predicate in thought, and retain the subject, a contradiction is the
result; and hence I say, the former belongs necessarily to the latter. But if I suppress both subject and
predicate in thought, no contradiction arises; for there is nothing at all, and therefore no means of forming a
contradiction. To suppose the existence of a triangle and not that of its three angles, is selfcontradictory; but
to suppose the nonexistence of both triangle and angles is perfectly admissible. And so is it with the
conception of an absolutely necessary being. Annihilate its existence in thought, and you annihilate the thing
itself with all its predicates; how then can there be any room for contradiction? Externally, there is nothing to
give rise to a contradiction, for a thing cannot be necessary externally; nor internally, for, by the annihilation
or suppression of the thing itself, its internal properties are also annihilated. God is omnipotent that is a
necessary judgement. His omnipotence cannot be denied, if the existence of a Deity is posited the existence,
that is, of an infinite being, the two conceptions being identical. But when you say, God does not exist,
neither omnipotence nor any other predicate is affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject, and in this
judgement there cannot exist the least selfcontradiction.
You have thus seen that when the predicate of a judgement is annihilated in thought along with the subject,
no internal contradiction can arise, be the predicate what it may. There is no possibility of evading the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God. 197
Page No 202
conclusion you find yourselves compelled to declare: There are certain subjects which cannot be annihilated
in thought. But this is nothing more than saying: There exist subjects which are absolutely necessary the
very hypothesis which you are called upon to establish. For I find myself unable to form the slightest
conception of a thing which when annihilated in thought with all its predicates, leaves behind a contradiction;
and contradiction is the only criterion of impossibility in the sphere of pure a priori conceptions.
Against these general considerations, the justice of which no one can dispute, one argument is adduced,
which is regarded as furnishing a satisfactory demonstration from the fact. It is affirmed that there is one and
only one conception, in which the nonbeing or annihilation of the object is selfcontradictory, and this is the
conception of an ens realissimum. It possesses, you say, all reality, and you feel yourselves justified in
admitting the possibility of such a being. (This I am willing to grant for the present, although the existence of
a conception which is not selfcontradictory is far from being sufficient to prove the possibility of an
object.)* Now the notion of all reality embraces in it that of existence; the notion of existence lies, therefore,
in the conception of this possible thing. If this thing is annihilated in thought, the internal possibility of the
thing is also annihilated, which is selfcontradictory.
*A conception is always possible, if it is not selfcontradictory. This is the logical criterion of possibility,
distinguishing the object of such a conception from the nihil negativum. But it may be, notwithstanding, an
empty conception, unless the objective reality of this synthesis, but which it is generated, is demonstrated;
and a proof of this kind must be based upon principles of possible experience, and not upon the principle of
analysis or contradiction. This remark may be serviceable as a warning against concluding, from the
possibility of a conception which is logical the possibility of a thing which is real.
I answer: It is absurd to introduce under whatever term disguised into the conception of a thing, which is to
be cogitated solely in reference to its possibility, the conception of its existence. If this is admitted, you will
have apparently gained the day, but in reality have enounced nothing but a mere tautology. I ask, is the
proposition, this or that thing (which I am admitting to be possible) exists, an analytical or a synthetical
proposition? If the former, there is no addition made to the subject of your thought by the affirmation of its
existence; but then the conception in your minds is identical with the thing itself, or you have supposed the
existence of a thing to be possible, and then inferred its existence from its internal possibility which is but a
miserable tautology. The word reality in the conception of the thing, and the word existence in the conception
of the predicate, will not help you out of the difficulty. For, supposing you were to term all positing of a thing
reality, you have thereby posited the thing with all its predicates in the conception of the subject and assumed
its actual existence, and this you merely repeat in the predicate. But if you confess, as every reasonable
person must, that every existential proposition is synthetical, how can it be maintained that the predicate of
existence cannot be denied without contradiction? a property which is the characteristic of analytical
propositions, alone.
I should have a reasonable hope of putting an end for ever to this sophistical mode of argumentation, by a
strict definition of the conception of existence, did not my own experience teach me that the illusion arising
from our confounding a logical with a real predicate (a predicate which aids in the determination of a thing)
resists almost all the endeavours of explanation and illustration. A logical predicate may be what you please,
even the subject may be predicated of itself; for logic pays no regard to the content of a judgement. But the
determination of a conception is a predicate, which adds to and enlarges the conception. It must not,
therefore, be contained in the conception.
Being is evidently not a real predicate, that is, a conception of something which is added to the conception of
some other thing. It is merely the positing of a thing, or of certain determinations in it. Logically, it is merely
the copula of a judgement. The proposition, God is omnipotent, contains two conceptions, which have a
certain object or content; the word is, is no additional predicate it merely indicates the relation of the
predicate to the subject. Now, if I take the subject (God) with all its predicates (omnipotence being one), and
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God. 198
Page No 203
say: God is, or, There is a God, I add no new predicate to the conception of God, I merely posit or affirm the
existence of the subject with all its predicates I posit the object in relation to my conception. The content of
both is the same; and there is no addition made to the conception, which expresses merely the possibility of
the object, by my cogitating the object in the expression, it is as absolutely given or existing. Thus the real
contains no more than the possible. A hundred real dollars contain no more than a hundred possible dollars.
For, as the latter indicate the conception, and the former the object, on the supposition that the content of the
former was greater than that of the latter, my conception would not be an expression of the whole object, and
would consequently be an inadequate conception of it. But in reckoning my wealth there may be said to be
more in a hundred real dollars than in a hundred possible dollars that is, in the mere conception of them. For
the real object the dollars is not analytically contained in my conception, but forms a synthetical addition
to my conception (which is merely a determination of my mental state), although this objective reality this
existence apart from my conceptions, does not in the least degree increase the aforesaid hundred dollars.
By whatever and by whatever number of predicates even to the complete determination of it I may cogitate
a thing, I do not in the least augment the object of my conception by the addition of the statement: This thing
exists. Otherwise, not exactly the same, but something more than what was cogitated in my conception,
would exist, and I could not affirm that the exact object of my conception had real existence. If I cogitate a
thing as containing all modes of reality except one, the mode of reality which is absent is not added to the
conception of the thing by the affirmation that the thing exists; on the contrary, the thing exists if it exist at
all with the same defect as that cogitated in its conception; otherwise not that which was cogitated, but
something different, exists. Now, if I cogitate a being as the highest reality, without defect or imperfection,
the question still remains whether this being exists or not? For, although no element is wanting in the
possible real content of my conception, there is a defect in its relation to my mental state, that is, I am
ignorant whether the cognition of the object indicated by the conception is possible a posteriori. And here the
cause of the present difficulty becomes apparent. If the question regarded an object of sense merely, it would
be impossible for me to confound the conception with the existence of a thing. For the conception merely
enables me to cogitate an object as according with the general conditions of experience; while the existence
of the object permits me to cogitate it as contained in the sphere of actual experience. At the same time, this
connection with the world of experience does not in the least augment the conception, although a possible
perception has been added to the experience of the mind. But if we cogitate existence by the pure category
alone, it is not to be wondered at, that we should find ourselves unable to present any criterion sufficient to
distinguish it from mere possibility.
Whatever be the content of our conception of an object, it is necessary to go beyond it, if we wish to predicate
existence of the object. In the case of sensuous objects, this is attained by their connection according to
empirical laws with some one of my perceptions; but there is no means of cognizing the existence of objects
of pure thought, because it must be cognized completely a priori. But all our knowledge of existence (be it
immediately by perception, or by inferences connecting some object with a perception) belongs entirely to
the sphere of experience which is in perfect unity with itself; and although an existence out of this sphere
cannot be absolutely declared to be impossible, it is a hypothesis the truth of which we have no means of
ascertaining.
The notion of a Supreme Being is in many respects a highly useful idea; but for the very reason that it is an
idea, it is incapable of enlarging our cognition with regard to the existence of things. It is not even sufficient
to instruct us as to the possibility of a being which we do not know to exist. The analytical criterion of
possibility, which consists in the absence of contradiction in propositions, cannot be denied it. But the
connection of real properties in a thing is a synthesis of the possibility of which an a priori judgement cannot
be formed, because these realities are not presented to us specifically; and even if this were to happen, a
judgement would still be impossible, because the criterion of the possibility of synthetical cognitions must be
sought for in the world of experience, to which the object of an idea cannot belong. And thus the celebrated
Leibnitz has utterly failed in his attempt to establish upon a priori grounds the possibility of this sublime ideal
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God. 199
Page No 204
being.
The celebrated ontological or Cartesian argument for the existence of a Supreme Being is therefore
insufficient; and we may as well hope to increase our stock of knowledge by the aid of mere ideas, as the
merchant to augment his wealth by the addition of noughts to his cash account.
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the
Existence of God.
It was by no means a natural course of proceeding, but, on the contrary, an invention entirely due to the
subtlety of the schools, to attempt to draw from a mere idea a proof of the existence of an object
corresponding to it. Such a course would never have been pursued, were it not for that need of reason which
requires it to suppose the existence of a necessary being as a basis for the empirical regress, and that, as this
necessity must be unconditioned and a priori, reason is bound to discover a conception which shall satisfy, if
possible, this requirement, and enable us to attain to the a priori cognition of such a being. This conception
was thought to be found in the idea of an ens realissimum, and thus this idea was employed for the attainment
of a better defined knowledge of a necessary being, of the existence of which we were convinced, or
persuaded, on other grounds. Thus reason was seduced from her natural courage; and, instead of concluding
with the conception of an ens realissimum, an attempt was made to begin with it, for the purpose of inferring
from it that idea of a necessary existence which it was in fact called in to complete. Thus arose that
unfortunate ontological argument, which neither satisfies the healthy common sense of humanity, nor
sustains the scientific examination of the philosopher.
The cosmological proof, which we are about to examine, retains the connection between absolute necessity
and the highest reality; but, instead of reasoning from this highest reality to a necessary existence, like the
preceding argument, it concludes from the given. unconditioned necessity of some being its unlimited reality.
The track it pursues, whether rational or sophistical, is at least natural, and not only goes far to persuade the
common understanding, but shows itself deserving of respect from the speculative intellect; while it contains,
at the same time, the outlines of all the arguments employed in natural theology arguments which always
have been, and still will be, in use and authority. These, however adorned, and hid under whatever
embellishments of rhetoric and sentiment, are at bottom identical with the arguments we are at present to
discuss. This proof, termed by Leibnitz the argumentum a contingentia mundi, I shall now lay before the
reader, and subject to a strict examination.
It is framed in the following manner: If something exists, an absolutely necessary being must likewise exist.
Now I, at least, exist. Consequently, there exists an absolutely necessary being. The minor contains an
experience, the major reasons from a general experience to the existence of a necessary being.* Thus this
argument really begins at experience, and is not completely a priori, or ontological. The object of all possible
experience being the world, it is called the cosmological proof. It contains no reference to any peculiar
property of sensuous objects, by which this world of sense might be distinguished from other possible
worlds; and in this respect it differs from the physicotheological proof, which is based upon the
consideration of the peculiar constitution of our sensuous world.
*This inference is too well known to require more detailed discussion. It is based upon the spurious
transcendental law of causality, that everything which is contingent has a cause, which, if itself contingent,
must also have a cause; and so on, till the series of subordinated causes must end with an absolutely
necessary cause, without which it would not possess completeness.
The proof proceeds thus: A necessary being can be determined only in one way, that is, it can be determined
by only one of all possible opposed predicates; consequently, it must be completely determined in and by its
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God. 200
Page No 205
conception. But there is only a single conception of a thing possible, which completely determines the thing a
priori: that is, the conception of the ens realissimum. It follows that the conception of the ens realissimum is
the only conception by and in which we can cogitate a necessary being. Consequently, a Supreme Being
necessarily exists.
In this cosmological argument are assembled so many sophistical propositions that speculative reason seems
to have exerted in it all her dialectical skill to produce a transcendental illusion of the most extreme character.
We shall postpone an investigation of this argument for the present, and confine ourselves to exposing the
stratagem by which it imposes upon us an old argument in a new dress, and appeals to the agreement of two
witnesses, the one with the credentials of pure reason, and the other with those of empiricism; while, in fact,
it is only the former who has changed his dress and voice, for the purpose of passing himself off for an
additional witness. That it may possess a secure foundation, it bases its conclusions upon experience, and
thus appears to be completely distinct from the ontological argument, which places its confidence entirely in
pure a priori conceptions. But this experience merely aids reason in making one step to the existence of a
necessary being. What the properties of this being are cannot be learned from experience; and therefore
reason abandons it altogether, and pursues its inquiries in the sphere of pure conception, for the purpose of
discovering what the properties of an absolutely necessary being ought to be, that is, what among all possible
things contain the conditions (requisita) of absolute necessity. Reason believes that it has discovered these
requisites in the conception of an ens realissimum and in it alone, and hence concludes: The ens
realissimum is an absolutely necessary being. But it is evident that reason has here presupposed that the
conception of an ens realissimum is perfectly adequate to the conception of a being of absolute necessity, that
is, that we may infer the existence of the latter from that of the former a proposition which formed the basis
of the ontological argument, and which is now employed in the support of the cosmological argument,
contrary to the wish and professions of its inventors. For the existence of an absolutely necessary being is
given in conceptions alone. But if I say: "The conception of the ens realissimum is a conception of this kind,
and in fact the only conception which is adequate to our idea of a necessary being," I am obliged to admit,
that the latter may be inferred from the former. Thus it is properly the ontological argument which figures in
the cosmological, and constitutes the whole strength of the latter; while the spurious basis of experience has
been of no further use than to conduct us to the conception of absolute necessity, being utterly insufficient to
demonstrate the presence of this attribute in any determinate existence or thing. For when we propose to
ourselves an aim of this character, we must abandon the sphere of experience, and rise to that of pure
conceptions, which we examine with the purpose of discovering whether any one contains the conditions of
the possibility of an absolutely necessary being. But if the possibility of such a being is thus demonstrated, its
existence is also proved; for we may then assert that, of all possible beings there is one which possesses the
attribute of necessity in other words, this being possesses an absolutely necessary existence.
All illusions in an argument are more easily detected when they are presented in the formal manner employed
by the schools, which we now proceed to do.
If the proposition: "Every absolutely necessary being is likewise an ens realissimum," is correct (and it is this
which constitutes the nervus probandi of the cosmological argument), it must, like all affirmative judgements,
be capable of conversion the conversio per accidens, at least. It follows, then, that some entia realissima are
absolutely necessary beings. But no ens realissimum is in any respect different from another, and what is
valid of some is valid of all. In this present case, therefore, I may employ simple conversion, and say: "Every
ens realissimum is a necessary being." But as this proposition is determined a priori by the conceptions
contained in it, the mere conception of an ens realissimum must possess the additional attribute of absolute
necessity. But this is exactly what was maintained in the ontological argument, and not recognized by the
cosmological, although it formed the real ground of its disguised and illusory reasoning.
Thus the second mode employed by speculative reason of demonstrating the existence of a Supreme Being, is
not only, like the first, illusory and inadequate, but possesses the additional blemish of an ignoratio elenchi
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God. 201
Page No 206
professing to conduct us by a new road to the desired goal, but bringing us back, after a short circuit, to the
old path which we had deserted at its call.
I mentioned above that this cosmological argument contains a perfect nest of dialectical assumptions, which
transcendental criticism does not find it difficult to expose and to dissipate. I shall merely enumerate these,
leaving it to the reader, who must by this time be well practised in such matters, to investigate the fallacies
residing therein.
The following fallacies, for example, are discoverable in this mode of proof: 1. The transcendental principle:
"Everything that is contingent must have a cause" a principle without significance, except in the sensuous
world. For the purely intellectual conception of the contingent cannot produce any synthetical proposition,
like that of causality, which is itself without significance or distinguishing characteristic except in the
phenomenal world. But in the present case it is employed to help us beyond the limits of its sphere. 2. "From
the impossibility of an infinite ascending series of causes in the world of sense a first cause is inferred"; a
conclusion which the principles of the employment of reason do not justify even in the sphere of experience,
and still less when an attempt is made to pass the limits of this sphere. 3. Reason allows itself to be satisfied
upon insufficient grounds, with regard to the completion of this series. It removes all conditions (without
which, however, no conception of Necessity can take place); and, as after this it is beyond our power to form
any other conceptions, it accepts this as a completion of the conception it wishes to form of the series. 4. The
logical possibility of a conception of the total of reality (the criterion of this possibility being the absence of
contradiction) is confound. ed with the transcendental, which requires a principle of the practicability of such
a synthesis a principle which again refers us to the world of experience. And so on.
The aim of the cosmological argument is to avoid the necessity of proving the existence of a necessary being
priori from mere conceptions a proof which must be ontological, and of which we feel ourselves quite
incapable. With this purpose, we reason from an actual existence an experience in general, to an absolutely
necessary condition of that existence. It is in this case unnecessary to demonstrate its possibility. For after
having proved that it exists, the question regarding its possibility is superfluous. Now, when we wish to
define more strictly the nature of this necessary being, we do not look out for some being the conception of
which would enable us to comprehend the necessity of its being for if we could do this, an empirical
presupposition would be unnecessary; no, we try to discover merely the negative condition (conditio sine qua
non), without which a being would not be absolutely necessary. Now this would be perfectly admissible in
every sort of reasoning, from a consequence to its principle; but in the present case it unfortunately happens
that the condition of absolute necessity can be discovered in but a single being, the conception of which must
consequently contain all that is requisite for demonstrating the presence of absolute necessity, and thus entitle
me to infer this absolute necessity a priori. That is, it must be possible to reason conversely, and say: The
thing, to which the conception of the highest reality belongs, is absolutely necessary. But if I cannot reason
thus and I cannot, unless I believe in the sufficiency of the ontological argument I find insurmountable
obstacles in my new path, and am really no farther than the point from which I set out. The conception of a
Supreme Being satisfies all questions a priori regarding the internal determinations of a thing, and is for this
reason an ideal without equal or parallel, the general conception of it indicating it as at the same time an ens
individuum among all possible things. But the conception does not satisfy the question regarding its
existence which was the purpose of all our inquiries; and, although the existence of a necessary being were
admitted, we should find it impossible to answer the question: What of all things in the world must be
regarded as such?
It is certainly allowable to admit the existence of an allsufficient being a cause of all possible effects for
the purpose of enabling reason to introduce unity into its mode and grounds of explanation with regard to
phenomena. But to assert that such a being necessarily exists, is no longer the modest enunciation of an
admissible hypothesis, but the boldest declaration of an apodeictic certainty; for the cognition of that which is
absolutely necessary must itself possess that character.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God. 202
Page No 207
The aim of the transcendental ideal formed by the mind is either to discover a conception which shall
harmonize with the idea of absolute necessity, or a conception which shall contain that idea. If the one is
possible, so is the other; for reason recognizes that alone as absolutely necessary which is necessary from its
conception. But both attempts are equally beyond our power we find it impossible to satisfy the
understanding upon this point, and as impossible to induce it to remain at rest in relation to this incapacity.
Unconditioned necessity, which, as the ultimate support and stay of all existing things, is an indispensable
requirement of the mind, is an abyss on the verge of which human reason trembles in dismay. Even the idea
of eternity, terrible and sublime as it is, as depicted by Haller, does not produce upon the mental vision such a
feeling of awe and terror; for, although it measures the duration of things, it does not support them. We
cannot bear, nor can we rid ourselves of the thought that a being, which we regard as the greatest of all
possible existences, should say to himself: I am from eternity to eternity; beside me there is nothing, except
that which exists by my will; whence then am I? Here all sinks away from under us; and the greatest, as the
smallest, perfection, hovers without stay or footing in presence of the speculative reason, which finds it as
easy to part with the one as with the other.
Many physical powers, which evidence their existence by their effects, are perfectly inscrutable in their
nature; they elude all our powers of observation. The transcendental object which forms the basis of
phenomena, and, in connection with it, the reason why our sensibility possesses this rather than that particular
kind of conditions, are and must ever remain hidden from our mental vision; the fact is there, the reason of
the fact we cannot see. But an ideal of pure reason cannot be termed mysterious or inscrutable, because the
only credential of its reality is the need of it felt by reason, for the purpose of giving completeness to the
world of synthetical unity. An ideal is not even given as a cogitable object, and therefore cannot be
inscrutable; on the contrary, it must, as a mere idea, be based on the constitution of reason itself, and on this
account must be capable of explanation and solution. For the very essence of reason consists in its ability to
give an account, of all our conceptions, opinions, and assertions upon objective, or, when they happen to be
illusory and fallacious, upon subjective grounds.
Detection and Explanation of the Dialectical Illusion in
all Transcendental Arguments for the Existence of a
Necessary Being.
Both of the above arguments are transcendental; in other words, they do not proceed upon empirical
principles. For, although the cosmological argument professed to lay a basis of experience for its edifice of
reasoning, it did not ground its procedure upon the peculiar constitution of experience, but upon pure
principles of reason in relation to an existence given by empirical consciousness; utterly abandoning its
guidance, however, for the purpose of supporting its assertions entirely upon pure conceptions. Now what is
the cause, in these transcendental arguments, of the dialectical, but natural, illusion, which connects the
conceptions of necessity and supreme reality, and hypostatizes that which cannot be anything but an idea?
What is the cause of this unavoidable step on the part of reason, of admitting that some one among all
existing things must be necessary, while it falls back from the assertion of the existence of such a being as
from an abyss? And how does reason proceed to explain this anomaly to itself, and from the wavering
condition of a timid and reluctant approbation always again withdrawn arrive at a calm and settled insight
into its cause?
It is something very remarkable that, on the supposition that something exists, I cannot avoid the inference
that something exists necessarily. Upon this perfectly natural but not on that account reliable inference
does the cosmological argument rest. But, let me form any conception whatever of a thing, I find that I cannot
cogitate the existence of the thing as absolutely necessary, and that nothing prevents me be the thing or
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God. 203
Page No 208
being what it may from cogitating its nonexistence. I may thus be obliged to admit that all existing things
have a necessary basis, while I cannot cogitate any single or individual thing as necessary. In other words, I
can never complete the regress through the conditions of existence, without admitting the existence of a
necessary being; but, on the other hand, I cannot make a commencement from this being.
If I must cogitate something as existing necessarily as the basis of existing things, and yet am not permitted to
cogitate any individual thing as in itself necessary, the inevitable inference is that necessity and contingency
are not properties of things themselves otherwise an internal contradiction would result; that consequently
neither of these principles are objective, but merely subjective principles of reason the one requiring us to
seek for a necessary ground for everything that exists, that is, to be satisfied with no other explanation than
that which is complete a priori, the other forbidding us ever to hope for the attainment of this completeness,
that is, to regard no member of the empirical world as unconditioned. In this mode of viewing them, both
principles, in their purely heuristic and regulative character, and as concerning merely the formal interest of
reason, are quite consistent with each other. The one says: "You must philosophize upon nature," as if there
existed a necessary primal basis of all existing things, solely for the purpose of introducing systematic unity
into your knowledge, by pursuing an idea of this character a foundation which is arbitrarily admitted to be
ultimate; while the other warns you to consider no individual determination, concerning the existence of
things, as such an ultimate foundation, that is, as absolutely necessary, but to keep the way always open for
further progress in the deduction, and to treat every determination as determined by some other. But if all that
we perceive must be regarded as conditionally necessary, it is impossible that anything which is empirically
given should be absolutely necessary.
It follows from this that you must accept the absolutely necessary as out of and beyond the world, inasmuch
as it is useful only as a principle of the highest possible unity in experience, and you cannot discover any such
necessary existence in the would, the second rule requiring you to regard all empirical causes of unity as
themselves deduced.
The philosophers of antiquity regarded all the forms of nature as contingent; while matter was considered by
them, in accordance with the judgement of the common reason of mankind, as primal and necessary. But if
they had regarded matter, not relatively as the substratum of phenomena, but absolutely and in itself as an
independent existence, this idea of absolute necessity would have immediately disappeared. For there is
nothing absolutely connecting reason with such an existence; on the contrary, it can annihilate it in thought,
always and without selfcontradiction. But in thought alone lay the idea of absolute necessity. A regulative
principle must, therefore, have been at the foundation of this opinion. In fact, extension and impenetrability
which together constitute our conception of matter form the supreme empirical principle of the unity of
phenomena, and this principle, in so far as it is empirically unconditioned, possesses the property of a
regulative principle. But, as every determination of matter which constitutes what is real in it and
consequently impenetrability is an effect, which must have a cause, and is for this reason always derived,
the notion of matter cannot harmonize with the idea of a necessary being, in its character of the principle of
all derived unity. For every one of its real properties, being derived, must be only conditionally necessary,
and can therefore be annihilated in thought; and thus the whole existence of matter can be so annihilated or
suppressed. If this were not the case, we should have found in the world of phenomena the highest ground or
condition of unity which is impossible, according to the second regulative principle. It follows that matter,
and, in general, all that forms part of the world of sense, cannot be a necessary primal being, nor even a
principle of empirical unity, but that this being or principle must have its place assigned without the world.
And, in this way, we can proceed in perfect confidence to deduce the phenomena of the world and their
existence from other phenomena, just as if there existed no necessary being; and we can at the same time,
strive without ceasing towards the attainment of completeness for our deduction, just as if such a being the
supreme condition of all existences were presupposed by the mind.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God. 204
Page No 209
These remarks will have made it evident to the reader that the ideal of the Supreme Being, far from being an
enouncement of the existence of a being in itself necessary, is nothing more than a regulative principle of
reason, requiring us to regard all connection existing between phenomena as if it had its origin from an
allsufficient necessary cause, and basing upon this the rule of a systematic and necessary unity in the
explanation of phenomena. We cannot, at the same time, avoid regarding, by a transcendental subreptio, this
formal principle as constitutive, and hypostatizing this unity. Precisely similar is the case with our notion of
space. Space is the primal condition of all forms, which are properly just so many different limitations of it;
and thus, although it is merely a principle of sensibility, we cannot help regarding it as an absolutely
necessary and selfsubsistent thing as an object given a priori in itself. In the same way, it is quite natural
that, as the systematic unity of nature cannot be established as a principle for the empirical employment of
reason, unless it is based upon the idea of an ens realissimum, as the supreme cause, we should regard this
idea as a real object, and this object, in its character of supreme condition, as absolutely necessary, and that in
this way a regulative should be transformed into a constitutive principle. This interchange becomes evident
when I regard this supreme being, which, relatively to the world, was absolutely (unconditionally) necessary,
as a thing per se. In this case, I find it impossible to represent this necessity in or by any conception, and it
exists merely in my own mind, as the formal condition of thought, but not as a material and hypostatic
condition of existence.
SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof.
If, then, neither a pure conception nor the general experience of an existing being can provide a sufficient
basis for the proof of the existence of the Deity, we can make the attempt by the only other mode that of
grounding our argument upon a determinate experience of the phenomena of the present world, their
constitution and disposition, and discover whether we can thus attain to a sound conviction of the existence of
a Supreme Being. This argument we shall term the physicotheological argument. If it is shown to be
insufficient, speculative reason cannot present us with any satisfactory proof of the existence of a being
corresponding to our transcendental idea.
It is evident from the remarks that have been made in the preceding sections, that an answer to this question
will be far from being difficult or unconvincing. For how can any experience be adequate with an idea? The
very essence of an idea consists in the fact that no experience can ever be discovered congruent or adequate
with it. The transcendental idea of a necessary and allsufficient being is so immeasurably great, so high
above all that is empirical, which is always conditioned, that we hope in vain to find materials in the sphere
of experience sufficiently ample for our conception, and in vain seek the unconditioned among things that are
conditioned, while examples, nay, even guidance is denied us by the laws of empirical synthesis.
If the Supreme Being forms a link in the chain of empirical conditions, it must be a member of the empirical
series, and, like the lower members which it precedes, have its origin in some higher member of the series. If,
on the other hand, we disengage it from the chain, and cogitate it as an intelligible being, apart from the series
of natural causes how shall reason bridge the abyss that separates the latter from the former? All laws
respecting the regress from effects to causes, all synthetical additions to our knowledge relate solely to
possible experience and the objects of the sensuous world, and, apart from them, are without significance.
The world around us opens before our view so magnificent a spectacle of order, variety, beauty, and
conformity to ends, that whether we pursue our observations into the infinity of space in the one direction, or
into its illimitable divisions in the other, whether we regard the world in its greatest or its least
manifestations even after we have attained to the highest summit of knowledge which our weak minds can
reach, we find that language in the presence of wonders so inconceivable has lost its force, and number its
power to reckon, nay, even thought fails to conceive adequately, and our conception of the whole dissolves
into an astonishment without power of expression all the more eloquent that it is dumb. Everywhere around
us we observe a chain of causes and effects, of means and ends, of death and birth; and, as nothing has
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof. 205
Page No 210
entered of itself into the condition in which we find it, we are constantly referred to some other thing, which
itself suggests the same inquiry regarding its cause, and thus the universe must sink into the abyss of
nothingness, unless we admit that, besides this infinite chain of contingencies, there exists something that is
primal and selfsubsistent something which, as the cause of this phenomenal world, secures its continuance
and preservation.
This highest cause what magnitude shall we attribute to it? Of the content of the world we are ignorant; still
less can we estimate its magnitude by comparison with the sphere of the possible. But this supreme cause
being a necessity of the human mind, what is there to prevent us from attributing to it such a degree of
perfection as to place it above the sphere of all that is possible? This we can easily do, although only by the
aid of the faint outline of an abstract conception, by representing this being to ourselves as containing in
itself, as an individual substance, all possible perfection a conception which satisfies that requirement of
reason which demands parsimony in principles, which is free from selfcontradiction, which even contributes
to the extension of the employment of reason in experience, by means of the guidance afforded by this idea to
order and system, and which in no respect conflicts with any law of experience.
This argument always deserves to be mentioned with respect. It is the oldest, the clearest, and that most in
conformity with the common reason of humanity. It animates the study of nature, as it itself derives its
existence and draws ever new strength from that source. It introduces aims and ends into a sphere in which
our observation could not of itself have discovered them, and extends our knowledge of nature, by directing
our attention to a unity, the principle of which lies beyond nature. This knowledge of nature again reacts upon
this idea its cause; and thus our belief in a divine author of the universe rises to the power of an irresistible
conviction.
For these reasons it would be utterly hopeless to attempt to rob this argument of the authority it has always
enjoyed. The mind, unceasingly elevated by these considerations, which, although empirical, are so
remarkably powerful, and continually adding to their force, will not suffer itself to be depressed by the doubts
suggested by subtle speculation; it tears itself out of this state of uncertainty, the moment it casts a look upon
the wondrous forms of nature and the majesty of the universe, and rises from height to height, from condition
to condition, till it has elevated itself to the supreme and unconditioned author of all.
But although we have nothing to object to the reasonableness and utility of this procedure, but have rather to
commend and encourage it, we cannot approve of the claims which this argument advances to demonstrative
certainty and to a reception upon its own merits, apart from favour or support by other arguments. Nor can it
injure the cause of morality to endeavour to lower the tone of the arrogant sophist, and to teach him that
modesty and moderation which are the properties of a belief that brings calm and content into the mind,
without prescribing to it an unworthy subjection. I maintain, then, that the physicotheological argument is
insufficient of itself to prove the existence of a Supreme Being, that it must entrust this to the ontological
argument to which it serves merely as an introduction, and that, consequently, this argument contains the
only possible ground of proof (possessed by speculative reason) for the existence of this being.
The chief momenta in the physicotheological argument are as follow: 1. We observe in the world manifest
signs of an arrangement full of purpose, executed with great wisdom, and argument in whole of a content
indescribably various, and of an extent without limits. 2. This arrangement of means and ends is entirely
foreign to the things existing in the world it belongs to them merely as a contingent attribute; in other words,
the nature of different things could not of itself, whatever means were employed, harmoniously tend towards
certain purposes, were they not chosen and directed for these purposes by a rational and disposing principle,
in accordance with certain fundamental ideas. 3. There exists, therefore, a sublime and wise cause (or
several), which is not merely a blind, allpowerful nature, producing the beings and events which fill the
world in unconscious fecundity, but a free and intelligent cause of the world. 4. The unity of this cause may
be inferred from the unity of the reciprocal relation existing between the parts of the world, as portions of an
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof. 206
Page No 211
artistic edifice an inference which all our observation favours, and all principles of analogy support.
In the above argument, it is inferred from the analogy of certain products of nature with those of human art,
when it compels Nature to bend herself to its purposes, as in the case of a house, a ship, or a watch, that the
same kind of causality namely, understanding and will resides in nature. It is also declared that the internal
possibility of this freelyacting nature (which is the source of all art, and perhaps also of human reason) is
derivable from another and superhuman art a conclusion which would perhaps be found incapable of
standing the test of subtle transcendental criticism. But to neither of these opinions shall we at present object.
We shall only remark that it must be confessed that, if we are to discuss the subject of cause at all, we cannot
proceed more securely than with the guidance of the analogy subsisting between nature and such products of
design these being the only products whose causes and modes of organization are completely known to us.
Reason would be unable to satisfy her own requirements, if she passed from a causality which she does
know, to obscure and indemonstrable principles of explanation which she does not know.
According to the physicotheological argument, the connection and harmony existing in the world evidence
the contingency of the form merely, but not of the matter, that is, of the substance of the world. To establish
the truth of the latter opinion, it would be necessary to prove that all things would be in themselves incapable
of this harmony and order, unless they were, even as regards their substance, the product of a supreme
wisdom. But this would require very different grounds of proof from those presented by the analogy with
human art. This proof can at most, therefore, demonstrate the existence of an architect of the world, whose
efforts are limited by the capabilities of the material with which he works, but not of a creator of the world, to
whom all things are subject. Thus this argument is utterly insufficient for the task before us a demonstration
of the existence of an allsufficient being. If we wish to prove the contingency of matter, we must have
recourse to a transcendental argument, which the physicotheological was constructed expressly to avoid.
We infer, from the order and design visible in the universe, as a disposition of a thoroughly contingent
character, the existence of a cause proportionate thereto. The conception of this cause must contain certain
determinate qualities, and it must therefore be regarded as the conception of a being which possesses all
power, wisdom, and so on, in one word, all perfection the conception, that is, of an allsufficient being. For
the predicates of very great, astonishing, or immeasurable power and excellence, give us no determinate
conception of the thing, nor do they inform us what the thing may be in itself. They merely indicate the
relation existing between the magnitude of the object and the observer, who compares it with himself and
with his own power of comprehension, and are mere expressions of praise and reverence, by which the object
is either magnified, or the observing subject depreciated in relation to the object. Where we have to do with
the magnitude (of the perfection) of a thing, we can discover no determinate conception, except that which
comprehends all possible perfection or completeness, and it is only the total (omnitudo) of reality which is
completely determined in and through its conception alone.
Now it cannot be expected that any one will be bold enough to declare that he has a perfect insight into the
relation which the magnitude of the world he contemplates bears (in its extent as well as in its content) to
omnipotence, into that of the order and design in the world to the highest wisdom, and that of the unity of the
world to the absolute unity of a Supreme Being. Physicotheology is therefore incapable of presenting a
determinate conception of a supreme cause of the world, and is therefore insufficient as a principle of
theology a theology which is itself to be the basis of religion.
The attainment of absolute totality is completely impossible on the path of empiricism. And yet this is the
path pursued in the physicotheological argument. What means shall we employ to bridge the abyss?
After elevating ourselves to admiration of the magnitude of the power, wisdom, and other attributes of the
author of the world, and finding we can advance no further, we leave the argument on empirical grounds, and
proceed to infer the contingency of the world from the order and conformity to aims that are observable in it.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a PhysicoTheological Proof. 207
Page No 212
From this contingency we infer, by the help of transcendental conceptions alone, the existence of something
absolutely necessary; and, still advancing, proceed from the conception of the absolute necessity of the first
cause to the completely determined or determining conception thereof the conception of an allembracing
reality. Thus the physicotheological, failing in its undertaking, recurs in its embarrassment to the
cosmological argument; and, as this is merely the ontological argument in disguise, it executes its design
solely by the aid of pure reason, although it at first professed to have no connection with this faculty and to
base its entire procedure upon experience alone.
The physicotheologians have therefore no reason to regard with such contempt the transcendental mode of
argument, and to look down upon it, with the conceit of clearsighted observers of nature, as the
braincobweb of obscure speculatists. For, if they reflect upon and examine their own arguments, they will
find that, after following for some time the path of nature and experience, and discovering themselves no
nearer their object, they suddenly leave this path and pass into the region of pure possibility, where they hope
to reach upon the wings of ideas what had eluded all their empirical investigations. Gaining, as they think, a
firm footing after this immense leap, they extend their determinate conception into the possession of which
they have come, they know not how over the whole sphere of creation, and explain their ideal, which is
entirely a product of pure reason, by illustrations drawn from experience though in a degree miserably
unworthy of the grandeur of the object, while they refuse to acknowledge that they have arrived at this
cognition or hypothesis by a very different road from that of experience.
Thus the physicotheological is based upon the cosmological, and this upon the ontological proof of the
existence of a Supreme Being; and as besides these three there is no other path open to speculative reason, the
ontological proof, on the ground of pure conceptions of reason, is the only possible one, if any proof of a
proposition so far transcending the empirical exercise of the understanding is possible at all.
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles
of Reason.
If by the term theology I understand the cognition of a primal being, that cognition is based either upon
reason alone (theologia rationalis) or upon revelation (theologia revelata). The former cogitates its object
either by means of pure transcendental conceptions, as an ens originarium, realissimum, ens entium, and is
termed transcendental theology; or, by means of a conception derived from the nature of our own mind, as a
supreme intelligence, and must then be entitled natural theology. The person who believes in a transcendental
theology alone, is termed a deist; he who acknowledges the possibility of a natural theology also, a theist.
The former admits that we can cognize by pure reason alone the existence of a Supreme Being, but at the
same time maintains that our conception of this being is purely transcendental, and that all we can say of it is
that it possesses all reality, without being able to define it more closely. The second asserts that reason is
capable of presenting us, from the analogy with nature, with a more definite conception of this being, and that
its operations, as the cause of all things, are the results of intelligence and free will. The former regards the
Supreme Being as the cause of the world whether by the necessity of his nature, or as a free agent, is left
undetermined; the latter considers this being as the author of the world.
Transcendental theology aims either at inferring the existence of a Supreme Being from a general experience,
without any closer reference to the world to which this experience belongs, and in this case it is called
cosmotheology; or it endeavours to cognize the existence of such a being, through mere conceptions, without
the aid of experience, and is then termed ontotheology.
Natural theology infers the attributes and the existence of an author of the world, from the constitution of, the
order and unity observable in, the world, in which two modes of causality must be admitted to exist those of
nature and freedom. Thus it rises from this world to a supreme intelligence, either as the principle of all
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 208
Page No 213
natural, or of all moral order and perfection. In the former case it is termed physicotheology, in the latter,
ethical or moraltheology.*
*Not theological ethics; for this science contains ethical laws, which presuppose the existence of a Supreme
Governor of the world; while moraltheology, on the contrary, is the expression of a conviction of the
existence of a Supreme Being, founded upon ethical laws.
As we are wont to understand by the term God not merely an eternal nature, the operations of which are
insensate and blind, but a Supreme Being, who is the free and intelligent author of all things, and as it is this
latter view alone that can be of interest to humanity, we might, in strict rigour, deny to the deist any belief in
God at all, and regard him merely as a maintainer of the existence of a primal being or thing the supreme
cause of all other things. But, as no one ought to be blamed, merely because he does not feel himself justified
in maintaining a certain opinion, as if he altogether denied its truth and asserted the opposite, it is more
correct as it is less harsh to say, the deist believes in a God, the theist in a living God (summa
intelligentia). We shall now proceed to investigate the sources of all these attempts of reason to establish the
existence of a Supreme Being.
It may be sufficient in this place to define theoretical knowledge or cognition as knowledge of that which is,
and practical knowledge as knowledge of that which ought to be. In this view, the theoretical employment of
reason is that by which I cognize a priori (as necessary) that something is, while the practical is that by which
I cognize a priori what ought to happen. Now, if it is an indubitably certain, though at the same time an
entirely conditioned truth, that something is, or ought to happen, either a certain determinate condition of this
truth is absolutely necessary, or such a condition may be arbitrarily presupposed. In the former case the
condition is postulated (per thesin), in the latter supposed (per hypothesin). There are certain practical laws
those of morality which are absolutely necessary. Now, if these laws necessarily presuppose the existence of
some being, as the condition of the possibility of their obligatory power, this being must be postulated,
because the conditioned, from which we reason to this determinate condition, is itself cognized a priori as
absolutely necessary. We shall at some future time show that the moral laws not merely presuppose the
existence of a Supreme Being, but also, as themselves absolutely necessary in a different relation, demand or
postulate it although only from a practical point of view. The discussion of this argument we postpone for
the present.
When the question relates merely to that which is, not to that which ought to be, the conditioned which is
presented in experience is always cogitated as contingent. For this reason its condition cannot be regarded as
absolutely necessary, but merely as relatively necessary, or rather as needful; the condition is in itself and a
priori a mere arbitrary presupposition in aid of the cognition, by reason, of the conditioned. If, then, we are to
possess a theoretical cognition of the absolute necessity of a thing, we cannot attain to this cognition
otherwise than a priori by means of conceptions; while it is impossible in this way to cognize the existence of
a cause which bears any relation to an existence given in experience.
Theoretical cognition is speculative when it relates to an object or certain conceptions of an object which is
not given and cannot be discovered by means of experience. It is opposed to the cognition of nature, which
concerns only those objects or predicates which can be presented in a possible experience.
The principle that everything which happens (the empirically contingent) must have a cause, is a principle of
the cognition of nature, but not of speculative cognition. For, if we change it into an abstract principle, and
deprive it of its reference to experience and the empirical, we shall find that it cannot with justice be regarded
any longer as a synthetical proposition, and that it is impossible to discover any mode of transition from that
which exists to something entirely different termed cause. Nay, more, the conception of a cause likewise
that of the contingent loses, in this speculative mode of employing it, all significance, for its objective
reality and meaning are comprehensible from experience alone.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 209
Page No 214
When from the existence of the universe and the things in it the existence of a cause of the universe is
inferred, reason is proceeding not in the natural, but in the speculative method. For the principle of the former
enounces, not that things themselves or substances, but only that which happens or their states as
empirically contingent, have a cause: the assertion that the existence of substance itself is contingent is not
justified by experience, it is the assertion of a reason employing its principles in a speculative manner. If,
again, I infer from the form of the universe, from the way in which all things are connected and act and react
upon each other, the existence of a cause entirely distinct from the universe this would again be a judgement
of purely speculative reason; because the object in this case the cause can never be an object of possible
experience. In both these cases the principle of causality, which is valid only in the field of experience
useless and even meaningless beyond this region, would be diverted from its proper destination.
Now I maintain that all attempts of reason to establish a theology by the aid of speculation alone are fruitless,
that the principles of reason as applied to nature do not conduct us to any theological truths, and,
consequently, that a rational theology can have no existence, unless it is founded upon the laws of morality.
For all synthetical principles of the understanding are valid only as immanent in experience; while the
cognition of a Supreme Being necessitates their being employed transcendentally, and of this the
understanding is quite incapable. If the empirical law of causality is to conduct us to a Supreme Being, this
being must belong to the chain of empirical objects in which case it would be, like all phenomena, itself
conditioned. If the possibility of passing the limits of experience be admitted, by means of the dynamical law
of the relation of an effect to its cause, what kind of conception shall we obtain by this procedure? Certainly
not the conception of a Supreme Being, because experience never presents us with the greatest of all possible
effects, and it is only an effect of this character that could witness to the existence of a corresponding cause.
If, for the purpose of fully satisfying the requirements of Reason, we recognize her right to assert the
existence of a perfect and absolutely necessary being, this can be admitted only from favour, and cannot be
regarded as the result or irresistible demonstration. The physicotheological proof may add weight to others
if other proofs there are by connecting speculation with experience; but in itself it rather prepares the mind
for theological cognition, and gives it a right and natural direction, than establishes a sure foundation for
theology.
It is now perfectly evident that transcendental questions admit only of transcendental answers those
presented a priori by pure conceptions without the least empirical admixture. But the question in the present
case is evidently synthetical it aims at the extension of our cognition beyond the bounds of experience it
requires an assurance respecting the existence of a being corresponding with the idea in our minds, to which
no experience can ever be adequate. Now it has been abundantly proved that all a priori synthetical cognition
is possible only as the expression of the formal conditions of a possible experience; and that the validity of all
principles depends upon their immanence in the field of experience, that is, their relation to objects of
empirical cognition or phenomena. Thus all transcendental procedure in reference to speculative theology is
without result.
If any one prefers doubting the conclusiveness of the proofs of our analytic to losing the persuasion of the
validity of these old and time honoured arguments, he at least cannot decline answering the question how he
can pass the limits of all possible experience by the help of mere ideas. If he talks of new arguments, or of
improvements upon old arguments, I request him to spare me. There is certainly no great choice in this sphere
of discussion, as all speculative arguments must at last look for support to the ontological, and I have,
therefore, very little to fear from the argumentative fecundity of the dogmatical defenders of a nonsensuous
reason. Without looking upon myself as a remarkably combative person, I shall not decline the challenge to
detect the fallacy and destroy the pretensions of every attempt of speculative theology. And yet the hope of
better fortune never deserts those who are accustomed to the dogmatical mode of procedure. I shall, therefore,
restrict myself to the simple and equitable demand that such reasoners will demonstrate, from the nature of
the human mind as well as from that of the other sources of knowledge, how we are to proceed to extend our
cognition completely a priori, and to carry it to that point where experience abandons us, and no means exist
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 210
Page No 215
of guaranteeing the objective reality of our conceptions. In whatever way the understanding may have
attained to a conception, the existence of the object of the conception cannot be discovered in it by analysis,
because the cognition of the existence of the object depends upon the object's being posited and given in itself
apart from the conception. But it is utterly impossible to go beyond our conception, without the aid of
experience which presents to the mind nothing but phenomena, or to attain by the help of mere conceptions
to a conviction of the existence of new kinds of objects or supernatural beings.
But although pure speculative reason is far from sufficient to demonstrate the existence of a Supreme Being,
it is of the highest utility in correcting our conception of this being on the supposition that we can attain to
the cognition of it by some other means in making it consistent with itself and with all other conceptions of
intelligible objects, clearing it from all that is incompatible with the conception of an ens summun, and
eliminating from it all limitations or admixtures of empirical elements.
Transcendental theology is still therefore, notwithstanding its objective insufficiency, of importance in a
negative respect; it is useful as a test of the procedure of reason when engaged with pure ideas, no other than
a transcendental standard being in this case admissible. For if, from a practical point of view, the hypothesis
of a Supreme and Allsufficient Being is to maintain its validity without opposition, it must be of the highest
importance to define this conception in a correct and rigorous manner as the transcendental conception of a
necessary being, to eliminate all phenomenal elements (anthropomorphism in its most extended
signification), and at the same time to overflow all contradictory assertions be they atheistic, deistic, or
anthropomorphic. This is of course very easy; as the same arguments which demonstrated the inability of
human reason to affirm the existence of a Supreme Being must be alike sufficient to prove the invalidity of its
denial. For it is impossible to gain from the pure speculation of reason demonstration that there exists no
Supreme Being, as the ground of all that exists, or that this being possesses none of those properties which
we regard as analogical with the dynamical qualities of a thinking being, or that, as the anthropomorphists
would have us believe, it is subject to all the limitations which sensibility imposes upon those intelligences
which exist in the world of experience.
A Supreme Being is, therefore, for the speculative reason, a mere ideal, though a faultless one a conception
which perfects and crowns the system of human cognition, but the objective reality of which can neither be
proved nor disproved by pure reason. If this defect is ever supplied by a moral theology, the problematic
transcendental theology which has preceded, will have been at least serviceable as demonstrating the mental
necessity existing for the conception, by the complete determination of it which it has furnished, and the
ceaseless testing of the conclusions of a reason often deceived by sense, and not always in harmony with its
own ideas. The attributes of necessity, infinitude, unity, existence apart from the world (and not as a world
soul), eternity (free from conditions of time), omnipresence (free from conditions of space), omnipotence,
and others, are pure transcendental predicates; and thus the accurate conception of a Supreme Being, which
every theology requires, is furnished by transcendental theology alone. APPENDIX
APPENDIX.
Of the Regulative Employment of the Ideas of
Pure Reason.
The result of all the dialectical attempts of pure reason not only confirms the truth of what we have already
proved in our Transcendental Analytic, namely, that all inferences which would lead us beyond the limits of
experience are fallacious and groundless, but it at the same time teaches us this important lesson, that human
reason has a natural inclination to overstep these limits, and that transcendental ideas are as much the natural
property of the reason as categories are of the understanding. There exists this difference, however, that while
the categories never mislead us, outward objects being always in perfect harmony therewith, ideas are the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 211
Page No 216
parents of irresistible illusions, the severest and most subtle criticism being required to save us from the
fallacies which they induce.
Whatever is grounded in the nature of our powers will be found to be in harmony with the final purpose and
proper employment of these powers, when once we have discovered their true direction and aim. We are
entitled to suppose, therefore, that there exists a mode of employing transcendental ideas which is proper and
immanent; although, when we mistake their meaning, and regard them as conceptions of actual things, their
mode of application is transcendent and delusive. For it is not the idea itself, but only the employment of the
idea in relation to possible experience, that is transcendent or immanent. An idea is employed transcendently,
when it is applied to an object falsely believed to be adequate with and to correspond to it; imminently, when
it is applied solely to the employment of the understanding in the sphere of experience. Thus all errors of
subreptio of misapplication, are to be ascribed to defects of judgement, and not to understanding or reason.
Reason never has an immediate relation to an object; it relates immediately to the understanding alone. It is
only through the understanding that it can be employed in the field of experience. It does not form
conceptions of objects, it merely arranges them and gives to them that unity which they are capable of
possessing when the sphere of their application has been extended as widely as possible. Reason avails itself
of the conception of the understanding for the sole purpose of producing totality in the different series. This
totality the understanding does not concern itself with; its only occupation is the connection of experiences,
by which series of conditions in accordance with conceptions are established. The object of reason is,
therefore, the understanding and its proper destination. As the latter brings unity into the diversity of objects
by means of its conceptions, so the former brings unity into the diversity of conceptions by means of ideas; as
it sets the final aim of a collective unity to the operations of the understanding, which without this occupies
itself with a distributive unity alone.
I accordingly maintain that transcendental ideas can never be employed as constitutive ideas, that they cannot
be conceptions of objects, and that, when thus considered, they assume a fallacious and dialectical character.
But, on the other hand, they are capable of an admirable and indispensably necessary application to objects
as regulative ideas, directing the understanding to a certain aim, the guiding lines towards which all its laws
follow, and in which they all meet in one point. This point though a mere idea (focus imaginarius), that is,
not a point from which the conceptions of the understanding do really proceed, for it lies beyond the sphere
of possible experience serves, notwithstanding, to give to these conceptions the greatest possible unity
combined with the greatest possible extension. Hence arises the natural illusion which induces us to believe
that these lines proceed from an object which lies out of the sphere of empirical cognition, just as objects
reflected in a mirror appear to be behind it. But this illusion which we may hinder from imposing upon us
is necessary and unavoidable, if we desire to see, not only those objects which lie before us, but those which
are at a great distance behind us; that is to say, when, in the present case, we direct the aims of the
understanding, beyond every given experience, towards an extension as great as can possibly be attained.
If we review our cognitions in their entire extent, we shall find that the peculiar business of reason is to
arrange them into a system, that is to say, to give them connection according to a principle. This unity
presupposes an idea the idea of the form of a whole (of cognition), preceding the determinate cognition of
the parts, and containing the conditions which determine a priori to every part its place and relation to the
other parts of the whole system. This idea, accordingly, demands complete unity in the cognition of the
understanding not the unity of a contingent aggregate, but that of a system connected according to necessary
laws. It cannot be affirmed with propriety that this idea is a conception of an object; it is merely a conception
of the complete unity of the conceptions of objects, in so far as this unity is available to the understanding as
a rule. Such conceptions of reason are not derived from nature; on the contrary, we employ them for the
interrogation and investigation of nature, and regard our cognition as defective so long as it is not adequate to
them. We admit that such a thing as pure earth, pure water, or pure air, is not to be discovered. And yet we
require these conceptions (which have their origin in the reason, so far as regards their absolute purity and
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 212
Page No 217
completeness) for the purpose of determining the share which each of these natural causes has in every
phenomenon. Thus the different kinds of matter are all ref erred to earths, as mere weight; to salts and
inflammable bodies, as pure force; and finally, to water and air, as the vehicula of the former, or the machines
employed by them in their operations for the purpose of explaining the chemical action and reaction of
bodies in accordance with the idea of a mechanism. For, although not actually so expressed, the influence of
such ideas of reason is very observable in the procedure of natural philosophers.
If reason is the faculty of deducing the particular from the general, and if the general be certain in se and
given, it is only necessary that the judgement should subsume the particular under the general, the particular
being thus necessarily determined. I shall term this the demonstrative or apodeictic employment of reason. If,
however, the general is admitted as problematical only, and is a mere idea, the particular case is certain, but
the universality of the rule which applies to this particular case remains a problem. Several particular cases,
the certainty of which is beyond doubt, are then taken and examined, for the purpose of discovering whether
the rule is applicable to them; and if it appears that all the particular cases which can be collected follow from
the rule, its universality is inferred, and at the same time, all the causes which have not, or cannot be
presented to our observation, are concluded to be of the same character with those which we have observed.
This I shall term the hypothetical employment of the reason.
The hypothetical exercise of reason by the aid of ideas employed as problematical conceptions is properly not
constitutive. That is to say, if we consider the subject strictly, the truth of the rule, which has been employed
as an hypothesis, does not follow from the use that is made of it by reason. For how can we know all the
possible cases that may arise? some of which may, however, prove exceptions to the universality of the rule.
This employment of reason is merely regulative, and its sole aim is the introduction of unity into the
aggregate of our particular cognitions, and thereby the approximating of the rule to universality.
The object of the hypothetical employment of reason is therefore the systematic unity of cognitions; and this
unity is the criterion of the truth of a rule. On the other hand, this systematic unity as a mere idea is in fact
merely a unity projected, not to be regarded as given, but only in the light of a problem a problem which
serves, however, as a principle for the various and particular exercise of the understanding in experience,
directs it with regard to those cases which are not presented to our observation, and introduces harmony and
consistency into all its operations.
All that we can be certain of from the above considerations is that this systematic unity is a logical principle,
whose aim is to assist the understanding, where it cannot of itself attain to rules, by means of ideas, to bring
all these various rules under one principle, and thus to ensure the most complete consistency and connection
that can be attained. But the assertion that objects and the understanding by which they are cognized are so
constituted as to be determined to systematic unity, that this may be postulated a priori, without any reference
to the interest of reason, and that we are justified in declaring all possible cognitions empirical and others
to possess systematic unity, and to be subject to general principles from which, notwithstanding their various
character, they are all derivable such an assertion can be founded only upon a transcendental principle of
reason, which would render this systematic unity not subjectively and logically in its character of a method,
but objectively necessary.
We shall illustrate this by an example. The conceptions of the understanding make us acquainted, among
many other kinds of unity, with that of the causality of a substance, which is termed power. The different
phenomenal manifestations of the same substance appear at first view to be so very dissimilar that we are
inclined to assume the existence of just as many different powers as there are different effects as, in the case
of the human mind, we have feeling, consciousness, imagination, memory, wit, analysis, pleasure, desire and
so on. Now we are required by a logical maxim to reduce these differences to as small a number as possible,
by comparing them and discovering the hidden identity which exists. We must inquire, for example, whether
or not imagination (connected with consciousness), memory, wit, and analysis are not merely different forms
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 213
Page No 218
of understanding and reason. The idea of a fundamental power, the existence of which no effort of logic can
assure us of, is the problem to be solved, for the systematic representation of the existing variety of powers.
The logical principle of reason requires us to produce as great a unity as is possible in the system of our
cognitions; and the more the phenomena of this and the other power are found to be identical, the more
probable does it become, that they are nothing but different manifestations of one and the same power, which
may be called, relatively speaking, a fundamental power. And so with other cases.
These relatively fundamental powers must again be compared with each other, to discover, if possible, the
one radical and absolutely fundamental power of which they are but the manifestations. But this unity is
purely hypothetical. It is not maintained, that this unity does really exist, but that we must, in the interest of
reason, that is, for the establishment of principles for the various rules presented by experience, try to
discover and introduce it, so far as is practicable, into the sphere of our cognitions.
But the transcendental employment of the understanding would lead us to believe that this idea of a
fundamental power is not problematical, but that it possesses objective reality, and thus the systematic unity
of the various powers or forces in a substance is demanded by the understanding and erected into an
apodeictic or necessary principle. For, without having attempted to discover the unity of the various powers
existing in nature, nay, even after all our attempts have failed, we notwithstanding presuppose that it does
exist, and may be, sooner or later, discovered. And this reason does, not only, as in the case above adduced,
with regard to the unity of substance, but where many substances, although all to a certain extent
homogeneous, are discoverable, as in the case of matter in general. Here also does reason presuppose the
existence of the systematic unity of various powers inasmuch as particular laws of nature are subordinate to
general laws; and parsimony in principles is not merely an economical principle of reason, but an essential
law of nature.
We cannot understand, in fact, how a logical principle of unity can of right exist, unless we presuppose a
transcendental principle, by which such a systematic unit as a property of objects themselves is regarded as
necessary a priori. For with what right can reason, in its logical exercise, require us to regard the variety of
forces which nature displays, as in effect a disguised unity, and to deduce them from one fundamental force
or power, when she is free to admit that it is just as possible that all forces should be different in kind, and
that a systematic unity is not conformable to the design of nature? In this view of the case, reason would be
proceeding in direct opposition to her own destination, by setting as an aim an idea which entirely conflicts
with the procedure and arrangement of nature. Neither can we assert that reason has previously inferred this
unity from the contingent nature of phenomena. For the law of reason which requires us to seek for this unity
is a necessary law, inasmuch as without it we should not possess a faculty of reason, nor without reason a
consistent and selfaccordant mode of employing the understanding, nor, in the absence of this, any proper
and sufficient criterion of empirical truth. In relation to this criterion, therefore, we must suppose the idea of
the systematic unity of nature to possess objective validity and necessity.
We find this transcendental presupposition lurking in different forms in the principles of philosophers,
although they have neither recognized it nor confessed to themselves its presence. That the diversities of
individual things do not exclude identity of species, that the various species must be considered as merely
different determinations of a few genera, and these again as divisions of still higher races, and so on that,
accordingly, a certain systematic unity of all possible empirical conceptions, in so far as they can be deduced
from higher and more general conceptions, must be sought for, is a scholastic maxim or logical principle,
without which reason could not be employed by us. For we can infer the particular from the general, only in
so far as general properties of things constitute the foundation upon which the particular rest.
That the same unity exists in nature is presupposed by philosophers in the wellknown scholastic maxim,
which forbids us unnecessarily to augment the number of entities or principles (entia praeter necessitatem non
esse multiplicanda). This maxim asserts that nature herself assists in the establishment of this unity of reason,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 214
Page No 219
and that the seemingly infinite diversity of phenomena should not deter us from the expectation of
discovering beneath this diversity a unity of fundamental properties, of which the aforesaid variety is but a
more or less determined form. This unity, although a mere idea, thinkers have found it necessary rather to
moderate the desire than to encourage it. It was considered a great step when chemists were able to reduce all
salts to two main genera acids and alkalis; and they regard this difference as itself a mere variety, or
different manifestation of one and the same fundamental material. The different kinds of earths (stones and
even metals) chemists have endeavoured to reduce to three, and afterwards to two; but still, not content with
this advance, they cannot but think that behind these diversities there lurks but one genus nay, that even
salts and earths have a common principle. It might be conjectured that this is merely an economical plan of
reason, for the purpose of sparing itself trouble, and an attempt of a purely hypothetical character, which,
when successful, gives an appearance of probability to the principle of explanation employed by the reason.
But a selfish purpose of this kind is easily to be distinguished from the idea, according to which every one
presupposes that this unity is in accordance with the laws of nature, and that reason does not in this case
request, but requires, although we are quite unable to determine the proper limits of this unity.
If the diversity existing in phenomena a diversity not of form (for in this they may be similar) but of
content were so great that the subtlest human reason could never by comparison discover in them the least
similarity (which is not impossible), in this case the logical law of genera would be without foundation, the
conception of a genus, nay, all general conceptions would be impossible, and the faculty of the
understanding, the exercise of which is restricted to the world of conceptions, could not exist. The logical
principle of genera, accordingly, if it is to be applied to nature (by which I mean objects presented to our
senses), presupposes a transcendental principle. In accordance with this principle, homogeneity is necessarily
presupposed in the variety of phenomena (although we are unable to determine a priori the degree of this
homogeneity), because without it no empirical conceptions, and consequently no experience, would be
possible.
The logical principle of genera, which demands identity in phenomena, is balanced by another principle that
of species, which requires variety and diversity in things, notwithstanding their accordance in the same genus,
and directs the understanding to attend to the one no less than to the other. This principle (of the faculty of
distinction) acts as a check upon the reason and reason exhibits in this respect a double and conflicting
interest on the one hand, the interest in the extent (the interest of generality) in relation to genera; on the
other, that of the content (the interest of individuality) in relation to the variety of species. In the former case,
the understanding cogitates more under its conceptions, in the latter it cogitates more in them. This distinction
manifests itself likewise in the habits of thought peculiar to natural philosophers, some of whom the
remarkably speculative heads may be said to be hostile to heterogeneity in phenomena, and have their eyes
always fixed on the unity of genera, while others with a strong empirical tendency aim unceasingly at the
analysis of phenomena, and almost destroy in us the hope of ever being able to estimate the character of these
according to general principles.
The latter mode of thought is evidently based upon a logical principle, the aim of which is the systematic
completeness of all cognitions. This principle authorizes me, beginning at the genus, to descend to the
various and diverse contained under it; and in this way extension, as in the former case unity, is assured to the
system. For if we merely examine the sphere of the conception which indicates a genus, we cannot discover
how far it is possible to proceed in the division of that sphere; just as it is impossible, from the consideration
of the space occupied by matter, to determine how far we can proceed in the division of it. Hence every genus
must contain different species, and these again different subspecies; and as each of the latter must itself
contain a sphere (must be of a certain extent, as a conceptus communis), reason demands that no species or
subspecies is to be considered as the lowest possible. For a species or subspecies, being always a
conception, which contains only what is common to a number of different things, does not completely
determine any individual thing, or relate immediately to it, and must consequently contain other conceptions,
that is, other subspecies under it. This law of specification may be thus expressed: entium varietates non
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 215
Page No 220
temere sunt minuendae.
But it is easy to see that this logical law would likewise be without sense or application, were it not based
upon a transcendental law of specification, which certainly does not require that the differences existing
phenomena should be infinite in number, for the logical principle, which merely maintains the
indeterminateness of the logical sphere of a conception, in relation to its possible division, does not authorize
this statement; while it does impose upon the understanding the duty of searching for subspecies to every
species, and minor differences in every difference. For, were there no lower conceptions, neither could there
be any higher. Now the understanding cognizes only by means of conceptions; consequently, how far soever
it may proceed in division, never by mere intuition, but always by lower and lower conceptions. The
cognition of phenomena in their complete determination (which is possible only by means of the
understanding) requires an unceasingly continued specification of conceptions, and a progression to ever
smaller differences, of which abstraction bad been made in the conception of the species, and still more in
that of the genus.
This law of specification cannot be deduced from experience; it can never present us with a principle of so
universal an application. Empirical specification very soon stops in its distinction of diversities, and requires
the guidance of the transcendental law, as a principle of the reason a law which imposes on us the necessity
of never ceasing in our search for differences, even although these may not present themselves to the senses.
That absorbent earths are of different kinds could only be discovered by obeying the anticipatory law of
reason, which imposes upon the understanding the task of discovering the differences existing between these
earths, and supposes that nature is richer in substances than our senses would indicate. The faculty of the
understanding belongs to us just as much under the presupposition of differences in the objects of nature, as
under the condition that these objects are homogeneous, because we could not possess conceptions, nor make
any use of our understanding, were not the phenomena included under these conceptions in some respects
dissimilar, as well as similar, in their character.
Reason thus prepares the sphere of the understanding for the operations of this faculty: 1. By the principle of
the homogeneity of the diverse in higher genera; 2. By the principle of the variety of the homogeneous in
lower species; and, to complete the systematic unity, it adds, 3. A law of the affinity of all conceptions which
prescribes a continuous transition from one species to every other by the gradual increase of diversity. We
may term these the principles of the homogeneity, the specification, and the continuity of forms. The latter
results from the union of the two former, inasmuch as we regard the systematic connection as complete in
thought, in the ascent to higher genera, as well as in the descent to lower species. For all diversities must be
related to each other, as they all spring from one highest genus, descending through the different gradations
of a more and more extended determination.
We may illustrate the systematic unity produced by the three logical principles in the following manner.
Every conception may be regarded as a point, which, as the standpoint of a spectator, has a certain horizon,
which may be said to enclose a number of things that may be viewed, so to speak, from that centre. Within
this horizon there must be an infinite number of other points, each of which has its own horizon, smaller and
more circumscribed; in other words, every species contains subspecies, according to the principle of
specification, and the logical horizon consists of smaller horizons (subspecies), but not of points
(individuals), which possess no extent. But different horizons or genera, which include under them so many
conceptions, may have one common horizon, from which, as from a midpoint, they may be surveyed; and
we may proceed thus, till we arrive at the highest genus, or universal and true horizon, which is determined
by the highest conception, and which contains under itself all differences and varieties, as genera, species,
and subspecies.
To this highest standpoint I am conducted by the law of homogeneity, as to all lower and more
variouslydetermined conceptions by the law of specification. Now as in this way there exists no void in the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 216
Page No 221
whole extent of all possible conceptions, and as out of the sphere of these the mind can discover nothing,
there arises from the presupposition of the universal horizon above mentioned, and its complete division, the
principle: Non datur vacuum formarum. This principle asserts that there are not different primitive and
highest genera, which stand isolated, so to speak, from each other, but all the various genera are mere
divisions and limitations of one highest and universal genus; and hence follows immediately the principle:
Datur continuum formarum. This principle indicates that all differences of species limit each other, and do
not admit of transition from one to another by a saltus, but only through smaller degrees of the difference
between the one species and the other. In one word, there are no species or subspecies which (in the view of
reason) are the nearest possible to each other; intermediate species or subspecies being always possible, the
difference of which from each of the former is always smaller than the difference existing between these.
The first law, therefore, directs us to avoid the notion that there exist different primal genera, and enounces
the fact of perfect homogeneity; the second imposes a check upon this tendency to unity and prescribes the
distinction of subspecies, before proceeding to apply our general conceptions to individuals. The third unites
both the former, by enouncing the fact of homogeneity as existing even in the most various diversity, by
means of the gradual transition from one species to another. Thus it indicates a relationship between the
different branches or species, in so far as they all spring from the same stem.
But this logical law of the continuum specierum (formarum logicarum) presupposes a transcendental
principle (lex continui in natura), without which the understanding might be led into error, by following the
guidance of the former, and thus perhaps pursuing a path contrary to that prescribed by nature. This law must,
consequently, be based upon pure transcendental, and not upon empirical, considerations. For, in the latter
case, it would come later than the system; whereas it is really itself the parent of all that is systematic in our
cognition of nature. These principles are not mere hypotheses employed for the purpose of experimenting
upon nature; although when any such connection is discovered, it forms a solid ground for regarding the
hypothetical unity as valid in the sphere of nature and thus they are in this respect not without their use. But
we go farther, and maintain that it is manifest that these principles of parsimony in fundamental causes,
variety in effects, and affinity in phenomena, are in accordance both with reason and nature, and that they are
not mere methods or plans devised for the purpose of assisting us in our observation of the external world.
But it is plain that this continuity of forms is a mere idea, to which no adequate object can be discovered in
experience. And this for two reasons. First, because the species in nature are really divided, and hence form
quanta discreta; and, if the gradual progression through their affinity were continuous, the intermediate
members lying between two given species must be infinite in number, which is impossible. Secondly,
because we cannot make any determinate empirical use of this law, inasmuch as it does not present us with
any criterion of affinity which could aid us in determining how far we ought to pursue the graduation of
differences: it merely contains a general indication that it is our duty to seek for and, if possible, to discover
them.
When we arrange these principles of systematic unity in the order conformable to their employment in
experience, they will stand thus: Variety, Affinity, Unity, each of them, as ideas, being taken in the highest
degree of their completeness. Reason presupposes the existence of cognitions of the understanding, which
have a direct relation to experience, and aims at the ideal unity of these cognitions a unity which far
transcends all experience or empirical notions. The affinity of the diverse, notwithstanding the differences
existing between its parts, has a relation to things, but a still closer one to the mere properties and powers of
things. For example, imperfect experience may represent the orbits of the planets as circular. But we discover
variations from this course, and we proceed to suppose that the planets revolve in a path which, if not a circle,
is of a character very similar to it. That is to say, the movements of those planets which do not form a circle
will approximate more or less to the properties of a circle, and probably form an ellipse. The paths of comets
exhibit still greater variations, for, so far as our observation extends, they do not return upon their own course
in a circle or ellipse. But we proceed to the conjecture that comets describe a parabola, a figure which is
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 217
Page No 222
closely allied to the ellipse. In fact, a parabola is merely an ellipse, with its longer axis produced to an
indefinite extent. Thus these principles conduct us to a unity in the genera of the forms of these orbits, and,
proceeding farther, to a unity as regards the cause of the motions of the heavenly bodies that is, gravitation.
But we go on extending our conquests over nature, and endeavour to explain all seeming deviations from
these rules, and even make additions to our system which no experience can ever substantiate for example,
the theory, in affinity with that of ellipses, of hyperbolic paths of comets, pursuing which, these bodies leave
our solar system and, passing from sun to sun, unite the most distant parts of the infinite universe, which is
held together by the same moving power.
The most remarkable circumstance connected with these principles is that they seem to be transcendental,
and, although only containing ideas for the guidance of the empirical exercise of reason, and although this
empirical employment stands to these ideas in an asymptotic relation alone (to use a mathematical term), that
is, continually approximate, without ever being able to attain to them, they possess, notwithstanding, as a
priori synthetical propositions, objective though undetermined validity, and are available as rules for possible
experience. In the elaboration of our experience, they may also be employed with great advantage, as
heuristic* principles. A transcendental deduction of them cannot be made; such a deduction being always
impossible in the case of ideas, as has been already shown.
*From the Greek, eurhioko.
We distinguished, in the Transcendental Analytic, the dynamical principles of the understanding, which are
regulative principles of intuition, from the mathematical, which are constitutive principles of intuition. These
dynamical laws are, however, constitutive in relation to experience, inasmuch as they render the conceptions
without which experience could not exist possible a priori. But the principles of pure reason cannot be
constitutive even in regard to empirical conceptions, because no sensuous schema corresponding to them can
be discovered, and they cannot therefore have an object in concreto. Now, if I grant that they cannot be
employed in the sphere of experience, as constitutive principles, how shall I secure for them employment and
objective validity as regulative principles, and in what way can they be so employed?
The understanding is the object of reason, as sensibility is the object of the understanding. The production of
systematic unity in all the empirical operations of the understanding is the proper occupation of reason; just
as it is the business of the understanding to connect the various content of phenomena by means of
conceptions, and subject them to empirical laws. But the operations of the understanding are, without the
schemata of sensibility, undetermined; and, in the same manner, the unity of reason is perfectly undetermined
as regards the conditions under which, and the extent to which, the understanding ought to carry the
systematic connection of its conceptions. But, although it is impossible to discover in intuition a schema for
the complete systematic unity of all the conceptions of the understanding, there must be some analogon of
this schema. This analogon is the idea of the maximum of the division and the connection of our cognition in
one principle. For we may have a determinate notion of a maximum and an absolutely perfect, all the
restrictive conditions which are connected with an indeterminate and various content having been abstracted.
Thus the idea of reason is analogous with a sensuous schema, with this difference, that the application of the
categories to the schema of reason does not present a cognition of any object (as is the case with the
application of the categories to sensuous schemata), but merely provides us with a rule or principle for the
systematic unity of the exercise of the understanding. Now, as every principle which imposes upon the
exercise of the understanding a priori compliance with the rule of systematic unity also relates, although only
in an indirect manner, to an object of experience, the principles of pure reason will also possess objective
reality and validity in relation to experience. But they will not aim at determining our knowledge in regard to
any empirical object; they will merely indicate the procedure, following which the empirical and determinate
exercise of the understanding may be in complete harmony and connection with itself a result which is
produced by its being brought into harmony with the principle of systematic unity, so far as that is possible,
and deduced from it.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 218
Page No 223
I term all subjective principles, which are not derived from observation of the constitution of an object, but
from the interest which Reason has in producing a certain completeness in her cognition of that object,
maxims of reason. Thus there are maxims of speculative reason, which are based solely upon its speculative
interest, although they appear to be objective principles.
When principles which are really regulative are regarded as constitutive, and employed as objective
principles, contradictions must arise; but if they are considered as mere maxims, there is no room for
contradictions of any kind, as they then merely indicate the different interests of reason, which occasion
differences in the mode of thought. In effect, Reason has only one single interest, and the seeming
contradiction existing between her maxims merely indicates a difference in, and a reciprocal limitation of, the
methods by which this interest is satisfied.
This reasoner has at heart the interest of diversity in accordance with the principle of specification; another,
the interest of unity in accordance with the principle of aggregation. Each believes that his judgement rests
upon a thorough insight into the subject he is examining, and yet it has been influenced solely by a greater or
less degree of adherence to some one of the two principles, neither of which are objective, but originate
solely from the interest of reason, and on this account to be termed maxims rather than principles. When I
observe intelligent men disputing about the distinctive characteristics of men, animals, or plants, and even of
minerals, those on the one side assuming the existence of certain national characteristics, certain
welldefined and hereditary distinctions of family, race, and so on, while the other side maintain that nature
has endowed all races of men with the same faculties and dispositions, and that all differences are but the
result of external and accidental circumstances I have only to consider for a moment the real nature of the
subject of discussion, to arrive at the conclusion that it is a subject far too deep for us to judge of, and that
there is little probability of either party being able to speak from a perfect insight into and understanding of
the nature of the subject itself. Both have, in reality, been struggling for the twofold interest of reason; the
one maintaining the one interest, the other the other. But this difference between the maxims of diversity and
unity may easily be reconciled and adjusted; although, so long as they are regarded as objective principles,
they must occasion not only contradictions and polemic, but place hinderances in the way of the advancement
of truth, until some means is discovered of reconciling these conflicting interests, and bringing reason into
union and harmony with itself.
The same is the case with the socalled law discovered by Leibnitz, and supported with remarkable ability by
Bonnet the law of the continuous gradation of created beings, which is nothing more than an inference from
the principle of affinity; for observation and study of the order of nature could never present it to the mind as
an objective truth. The steps of this ladder, as they appear in experience, are too far apart from each other,
and the socalled petty differences between different kinds of animals are in nature commonly so wide
separations that no confidence can be placed in such views (particularly when we reflect on the great variety
of things, and the ease with which we can discover resemblances), and no faith in the laws which are said to
express the aims and purposes of nature. On the other hand, the method of investigating the order of nature in
the light of this principle, and the maxim which requires us to regard this order it being still undetermined
how far it extends as really existing in nature, is beyond doubt a legitimate and excellent principle of
reason a principle which extends farther than any experience or observation of ours and which, without
giving us any positive knowledge of anything in the region of experience, guides us to the goal of systematic
unity.
Of the Ultimate End of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason.
The ideas of pure reason cannot be, of themselves and in their own nature, dialectical; it is from their
misemployment alone that fallacies and illusions arise. For they originate in the nature of reason itself, and it
is impossible that this supreme tribunal for all the rights and claims of speculation should be itself
undeserving of confidence and promotive of error. It is to be expected, therefore, that these ideas have a
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 219
Page No 224
genuine and legitimate aim. It is true, the mob of sophists raise against reason the cry of inconsistency and
contradiction, and affect to despise the government of that faculty, because they cannot understand its
constitution, while it is to its beneficial influences alone that they owe the position and the intelligence which
enable them to criticize and to blame its procedure.
We cannot employ an a priori conception with certainty, until we have made a transcendental deduction
therefore. The ideas of pure reason do not admit of the same kind of deduction as the categories. But if they
are to possess the least objective validity, and to represent anything but mere creations of thought (entia
rationis ratiocinantis), a deduction of them must be possible. This deduction will complete the critical task
imposed upon pure reason; and it is to this part Of our labours that we now proceed.
There is a great difference between a thing's being presented to the mind as an object in an absolute sense, or
merely as an ideal object. In the former case I employ my conceptions to determine the object; in the latter
case nothing is present to the mind but a mere schema, which does not relate directly to an object, not even in
a hypothetical sense, but which is useful only for the purpose of representing other objects to the mind, in a
mediate and indirect manner, by means of their relation to the idea in the intellect. Thus I say the conception
of a supreme intelligence is a mere idea; that is to say, its objective reality does not consist in the fact that it
has an immediate relation to an object (for in this sense we have no means of establishing its objective
validity), it is merely a schema constructed according to the necessary conditions of the unity of reason the
schema of a thing in general, which is useful towards the production of the highest degree of systematic unity
in the empirical exercise of reason, in which we deduce this or that object of experience from the imaginary
object of this idea, as the ground or cause of the said object of experience. In this way, the idea is properly a
heuristic, and not an ostensive, conception; it does not give us any information respecting the constitution of
an object, it merely indicates how, under the guidance of the idea, we ought to investigate the constitution and
the relations of objects in the world of experience. Now, if it can be shown that the three kinds of
transcendental ideas (psychological, cosmological, and theological), although not relating directly to any
object nor determining it, do nevertheless, on the supposition of the existence of an ideal object, produce
systematic unity in the laws of the empirical employment of the reason, and extend our empirical cognition,
without ever being inconsistent or in opposition with it it must be a necessary maxim of reason to regulate
its procedure according to these ideas. And this forms the transcendental deduction of all speculative ideas,
not as constitutive principles of the extension of our cognition beyond the limits of our experience, but as
regulative principles of the systematic unity of empirical cognition, which is by the aid of these ideas
arranged and emended within its own proper limits, to an extent unattainable by the operation of the
principles of the understanding alone.
I shall make this plainer. Guided by the principles involved in these ideas, we must, in the first place, so
connect all the phenomena, actions, and feelings of the mind, as if it were a simple substance, which,
endowed with personal identity, possesses a permanent existence (in this life at least), while its states, among
which those of the body are to be included as external conditions, are in continual change. Secondly, in
cosmology, we must investigate the conditions of all natural phenomena, internal as well as external, as if
they belonged to a chain infinite and without any prime or supreme member, while we do not, on this
account, deny the existence of intelligible grounds of these phenomena, although we never employ them to
explain phenomena, for the simple reason that they are not objects of our cognition. Thirdly, in the sphere of
theology, we must regard the whole system of possible experience as forming an absolute, but dependent and
sensuouslyconditioned unity, and at the same time as based upon a sole, supreme, and allsufficient ground
existing apart from the world itself a ground which is a selfsubsistent, primeval and creative reason, in
relation to which we so employ our reason in the field of experience, as if all objects drew their origin from
that archetype of all reason. In other words, we ought not to deduce the internal phenomena of the mind from
a simple thinking substance, but deduce them from each other under the guidance of the regulative idea of a
simple being; we ought not to deduce the phenomena, order, and unity of the universe from a supreme
intelligence, but merely draw from this idea of a supremely wise cause the rules which must guide reason in
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 220
Page No 225
its connection of causes and effects.
Now there is nothing to hinder us from admitting these ideas to possess an objective and hyperbolic
existence, except the cosmological ideas, which lead reason into an antinomy: the psychological and
theological ideas are not antinomial. They contain no contradiction; and how, then, can any one dispute their
objective reality, since he who denies it knows as little about their possibility as we who affirm? And yet,
when we wish to admit the existence of a thing, it is not sufficient to convince ourselves that there is no
positive obstacle in the way; for it cannot be allowable to regard mere creations of thought, which transcend,
though they do not contradict, all our conceptions, as real and determinate objects, solely upon the authority
of a speculative reason striving to compass its own aims. They cannot, therefore, be admitted to be real in
themselves; they can only possess a comparative reality that of a schema of the regulative principle of the
systematic unity of all cognition. They are to be regarded not as actual things, but as in some measure
analogous to them. We abstract from the object of the idea all the conditions which limit the exercise of our
understanding, but which, on the other hand, are the sole conditions of our possessing a determinate
conception of any given thing. And thus we cogitate a something, of the real nature of which we have not the
least conception, but which we represent to ourselves as standing in a relation to the whole system of
phenomena, analogous to that in which phenomena stand to each other.
By admitting these ideal beings, we do not really extend our cognitions beyond the objects of possible
experience; we extend merely the empirical unity of our experience, by the aid of systematic unity, the
schema of which is furnished by the idea, which is therefore valid not as a constitutive, but as a regulative
principle. For although we posit a thing corresponding to the idea a something, an actual existence we do
not on that account aim at the extension of our cognition by means of transcendent conceptions. This
existence is purely ideal, and not objective; it is the mere expression of the systematic unity which is to be the
guide of reason in the field of experience. There are no attempts made at deciding what the ground of this
unity may be, or what the real nature of this imaginary being.
Thus the transcendental and only determinate conception of God, which is presented to us by speculative
reason, is in the strictest sense deistic. In other words, reason does not assure us of the objective validity of
the conception; it merely gives us the idea of something, on which the supreme and necessary unity of all
experience is based. This something we cannot, following the analogy of a real substance, cogitate otherwise
than as the cause of all things operating in accordance with rational laws, if we regard it as an individual
object; although we should rest contented with the idea alone as a regulative principle of reason, and make no
attempt at completing the sum of the conditions imposed by thought. This attempt is, indeed, inconsistent
with the grand aim of complete systematic unity in the sphere of cognition a unity to which no bounds are
set by reason.
Hence it happens that, admitting a divine being, I can have no conception of the internal possibility of its
perfection, or of the necessity of its existence. The only advantage of this admission is that it enables me to
answer all other questions relating to the contingent, and to give reason the most complete satisfaction as
regards the unity which it aims at attaining in the world of experience. But I cannot satisfy reason with regard
to this hypothesis itself; and this proves that it is not its intelligence and insight into the subject, but its
speculative interest alone which induces it to proceed from a point lying far beyond the sphere of our
cognition, for the purpose of being able to consider all objects as parts of a systematic whole.
Here a distinction presents itself, in regard to the way in which we may cogitate a presupposition a
distinction which is somewhat subtle, but of great importance in transcendental philosophy. I may have
sufficient grounds to admit something, or the existence of something, in a relative point of view (suppositio
relativa), without being justified in admitting it in an absolute sense (suppositio absoluta). This distinction is
undoubtedly requisite, in the case of a regulative principle, the necessity of which we recognize, though we
are ignorant of the source and cause of that necessity, and which we assume to be based upon some ultimate
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 221
Page No 226
ground, for the purpose of being able to cogitate the universality of the principle in a more determinate way.
For example, I cogitate the existence of a being corresponding to a pure transcendental idea. But I cannot
admit that this being exists absolutely and in itself, because all of the conceptions by which I can cogitate an
object in a determinate manner fall short of assuring me of its existence; nay, the conditions of the objective
validity of my conceptions are excluded by the idea by the very fact of its being an idea. The conceptions of
reality, substance, causality, nay, even that of necessity in existence, have no significance out of the sphere of
empirical cognition, and cannot, beyond that sphere, determine any object. They may, accordingly, be
employed to explain the possibility of things in the world of sense, but they are utterly inadequate to explain
the possibility of the universe itself considered as a whole; because in this case the ground of explanation
must lie out of and beyond the world, and cannot, therefore, be an object of possible experience. Now, I may
admit the existence of an incomprehensible being of this nature the object of a mere idea, relatively to the
world of sense; although I have no ground to admit its existence absolutely and in itself. For if an idea (that of
a systematic and complete unity, of which I shall presently speak more particularly) lies at the foundation of
the most extended empirical employment of reason, and if this idea cannot be adequately represented in
concreto, although it is indispensably necessary for the approximation of empirical unity to the highest
possible degree I am not only authorized, but compelled, to realize this idea, that is, to posit a real object
corresponding thereto. But I cannot profess to know this object; it is to me merely a something, to which, as
the ground of systematic unity in cognition, I attribute such properties as are analogous to the conceptions
employed by the understanding in the sphere of experience. Following the analogy of the notions of reality,
substance, causality, and necessity, I cogitate a being, which possesses all these attributes in the highest
degree; and, as this idea is the offspring of my reason alone, I cogitate this being as selfsubsistent reason,
and as the cause of the universe operating by means of ideas of the greatest possible harmony and unity. Thus
I abstract all conditions that would limit my idea, solely for the purpose of rendering systematic unity
possible in the world of empirical diversity, and thus securing the widest possible extension for the exercise
of reason in that sphere. This I am enabled to do, by regarding all connections and relations in the world of
sense, as if they were the dispositions of a supreme reason, of which our reason is but a faint image. I then
proceed to cogitate this Supreme Being by conceptions which have, properly, no meaning or application,
except in the world of sense. But as I am authorized to employ the transcendental hypothesis of such a being
in a relative respect alone, that is, as the substratum of the greatest possible unity in experience I may
attribute to a being which I regard as distinct from the world, such properties as belong solely to the sphere of
sense and experience. For I do not desire, and am not justified in desiring, to cognize this object of my idea,
as it exists in itself; for I possess no conceptions sufficient for or task, those of reality, substance, causality,
nay, even that of necessity in existence, losing all significance, and becoming merely the signs of
conceptions, without content and without applicability, when I attempt to carry them beyond the limits of the
world of sense. I cogitate merely the relation of a perfectly unknown being to the greatest possible systematic
unity of experience, solely for the purpose of employing it as the schema of the regulative principle which
directs reason in its empirical exercise.
It is evident, at the first view, that we cannot presuppose the reality of this transcendental object, by means of
the conceptions of reality, substance, causality, and so on, because these conceptions cannot be applied to
anything that is distinct from the world of sense. Thus the supposition of a Supreme Being or cause is purely
relative; it is cogitated only in behalf of the systematic unity of experience; such a being is but a something,
of whose existence in itself we have not the least conception. Thus, too, it becomes sufficiently manifest why
we required the idea of a necessary being in relation to objects given by sense, although we can never have
the least conception of this being, or of its absolute necessity.
And now we can clearly perceive the result of our transcendental dialectic, and the proper aim of the ideas of
pure reason which become dialectical solely from misunderstanding and inconsiderateness. Pure reason is,
in fact, occupied with itself, and not with any object. Objects are not presented to it to be embraced in the
unity of an empirical conception; it is only the cognitions of the understanding that are presented to it, for the
purpose of receiving the unity of a rational conception, that is, of being connected according to a principle.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 222
Page No 227
The unity of reason is the unity of system; and this systematic unity is not an objective principle, extending
its dominion over objects, but a subjective maxim, extending its authority over the empirical cognition of
objects. The systematic connection which reason gives to the empirical employment of the understanding not
only advances the extension of that employment, but ensures its correctness, and thus the principle of a
systematic unity of this nature is also objective, although only in an indefinite respect (principium vagum). It
is not, however, a constitutive principle, determining an object to which it directly relates; it is merely a
regulative principle or maxim, advancing and strengthening the empirical exercise of reason, by the opening
up of new paths of which the understanding is ignorant, while it never conflicts with the laws of its exercise
in the sphere of experience.
But reason cannot cogitate this systematic unity, without at the same time cogitating an object of the idea an
object that cannot be presented in any experience, which contains no concrete example of a complete
systematic unity. This being (ens rationis ratiocinatae) is therefore a mere idea and is not assumed to be a
thing which is real absolutely and in itself. On the contrary, it forms merely the problematical foundation of
the connection which the mind introduces among the phenomena of the sensuous world. We look upon this
connection, in the light of the abovementioned idea, as if it drew its origin from the supposed being which
corresponds to the idea. And yet all we aim at is the possession of this idea as a secure foundation for the
systematic unity of experience a unity indispensable to reason, advantageous to the understanding, and
promotive of the interests of empirical cognition.
We mistake the true meaning of this idea when we regard it as an enouncement, or even as a hypothetical
declaration of the existence of a real thing, which we are to regard as the origin or ground of a systematic
constitution of the universe. On the contrary, it is left completely undetermined what the nature or properties
of this socalled ground may be. The idea is merely to be adopted as a point of view, from which this unity,
so essential to reason and so beneficial to the understanding, may be regarded as radiating. In one word, this
transcendental thing is merely the schema of a regulative principle, by means of which Reason, so far as in
her lies, extends the dominion of systematic unity over the whole sphere of experience.
The first object of an idea of this kind is the ego, considered merely as a thinking nature or soul. If I wish to
investigate the properties of a thinking being, I must interrogate experience. But I find that I can apply none
of the categories to this object, the schema of these categories, which is the condition of their application,
being given only in sensuous intuition. But I cannot thus attain to the cognition of a systematic unity of all the
phenomena of the internal sense. Instead, therefore, of an empirical conception of what the soul really is,
reason takes the conception of the empirical unity of all thought, and, by cogitating this unity as
unconditioned and primitive, constructs the rational conception or idea of a simple substance which is in
itself unchangeable, possessing personal identity, and in connection with other real things external to it; in
one word, it constructs the idea of a simple selfsubsistent intelligence. But the real aim of reason in this
procedure is the attainment of principles of systematic unity for the explanation of the phenomena of the soul.
That is, reason desires to be able to represent all the determinations of the internal sense as existing in one
subject, all powers as deduced from one fundamental power, all changes as mere varieties in the condition of
a being which is permanent and always the same, and all phenomena in space as entirely different in their
nature from the procedure of thought. Essential simplicity (with the other attributes predicated of the ego) is
regarded as the mere schema of this regulative principle; it is not assumed that it is the actual ground of the
properties of the soul. For these properties may rest upon quite different grounds, of which we are completely
ignorant; just as the above predicates could not give us any knowledge of the soul as it is in itself, even if we
regarded them as valid in respect of it, inasmuch as they constitute a mere idea, which cannot be represented
in concreto. Nothing but good can result from a psychological idea of this kind, if we only take proper care
not to consider it as more than an idea; that is, if we regard it as valid merely in relation to the employment of
reason, in the sphere of the phenomena of the soul. Under the guidance of this idea, or principle, no empirical
laws of corporeal phenomena are called in to explain that which is a phenomenon of the internal sense alone;
no windy hypotheses of the generation, annihilation, and palingenesis of souls are admitted. Thus the
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 223
Page No 228
consideration of this object of the internal sense is kept pure, and unmixed with heterogeneous elements;
while the investigation of reason aims at reducing all the grounds of explanation employed in this sphere of
knowledge to a single principle. All this is best effected, nay, cannot be effected otherwise than by means of
such a schema, which requires us to regard this ideal thing as an actual existence. The psychological idea is,
therefore, meaningless and inapplicable, except as the schema of a regulative conception. For, if I ask
whether the soul is not really of a spiritual nature it is a question which has no meaning. From such a
conception has been abstracted, not merely all corporeal nature, but all nature, that is, all the predicates of a
possible experience; and consequently, all the conditions which enable us to cogitate an object to this
conception have disappeared. But, if these conditions are absent, it is evident that the conception is
meaningless.
The second regulative idea of speculative reason is the conception of the universe. For nature is properly the
only object presented to us, in regard to which reason requires regulative principles. Nature is twofold
thinking and corporeal nature. To cogitate the latter in regard to its internal possibility, that is, to determine
the application of the categories to it, no idea is required no representation which transcends experience. In
this sphere, therefore, an idea is impossible, sensuous intuition being our only guide; while, in the sphere of
psychology, we require the fundamental idea (I), which contains a priori a certain form of thought namely,
the unity of the ego. Pure reason has, therefore, nothing left but nature in general, and the completeness of
conditions in nature in accordance with some principle. The absolute totality of the series of these conditions
is an idea, which can never be fully realized in the empirical exercise of reason, while it is serviceable as a
rule for the procedure of reason in relation to that totality. It requires us, in the explanation of given
phenomena (in the regress or ascent in the series), to proceed as if the series were infinite in itself, that is,
were prolonged in indefinitum,; while on the other hand, where reason is regarded as itself the determining
cause (in the region of freedom), we are required to proceed as if we had not before us an object of sense, but
of the pure understanding. In this latter case, the conditions do not exist in the series of phenomena, but may
be placed quite out of and beyond it, and the series of conditions may be regarded as if it had an absolute
beginning from an intelligible cause. All this proves that the cosmological ideas are nothing but regulative
principles, and not constitutive; and that their aim is not to realize an actual totality in such series. The full
discussion of this subject will be found in its proper place in the chapter on the antinomy of pure reason.
The third idea of pure reason, containing the hypothesis of a being which is valid merely as a relative
hypothesis, is that of the one and allsufficient cause of all cosmological series, in other words, the idea of
God. We have not the slightest ground absolutely to admit the existence of an object corresponding to this
idea; for what can empower or authorize us to affirm the existence of a being of the highest perfection a
being whose existence is absolutely necessary merely because we possess the conception of such a being?
The answer is: It is the existence of the world which renders this hypothesis necessary. But this answer makes
it perfectly evident that the idea of this being, like all other speculative ideas, is essentially nothing more than
a demand upon reason that it shall regulate the connection which it and its subordinate faculties introduce into
the phenomena of the world by principles of systematic unity and, consequently, that it shall regard all
phenomena as originating from one allembracing being, as the supreme and allsufficient cause. From this
it is plain that the only aim of reason in this procedure is the establishment of its own formal rule for the
extension of its dominion in the world of experience; that it does not aim at an extension of its cognition
beyond the limits of experience; and that, consequently, this idea does not contain any constitutive principle.
The highest formal unity, which is based upon ideas alone, is the unity of all things a unity in accordance
with an aim or purpose; and the speculative interest of reason renders it necessary to regard all order in the
world as if it originated from the intention and design of a supreme reason. This principle unfolds to the view
of reason in the sphere of experience new and enlarged prospects, and invites it to connect the phenomena of
the world according to teleological laws, and in this way to attain to the highest possible degree of systematic
unity. The hypothesis of a supreme intelligence, as the sole cause of the universe an intelligence which has
for us no more than an ideal existence is accordingly always of the greatest service to reason. Thus, if we
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 224
Page No 229
presuppose, in relation to the figure of the earth (which is round, but somewhat flattened at the poles),* or
that of mountains or seas, wise designs on the part of an author of the universe, we cannot fail to make, by the
light of this supposition, a great number of interesting discoveries. If we keep to this hypothesis, as a
principle which is purely regulative, even error cannot be very detrimental. For, in this case, error can have
no more serious consequences than that, where we expected to discover a teleological connection (nexus
finalis), only a mechanical or physical connection appears. In such a case, we merely fail to find the
additional form of unity we expected, but we do not lose the rational unity which the mind requires in its
procedure in experience. But even a miscarriage of this sort cannot affect the law in its general and
teleological relations. For although we may convict an anatomist of an error, when he connects the limb of
some animal with a certain purpose, it is quite impossible to prove in a single case that any arrangement of
nature, be it what it may, is entirely without aim or design. And thus medical physiology, by the aid of a
principle presented to it by pure reason, extends its very limited empirical knowledge of the purposes of the
different parts of an organized body so far that it may be asserted with the utmost confidence, and with the
approbation of all reflecting men, that every organ or bodily part of an animal has its use and answers a
certain design. Now, this is a supposition which, if regarded as of a constitutive character, goes much farther
than any experience or observation of ours can justify. Hence it is evident that it is nothing more than a
regulative principle of reason, which aims at the highest degree of systematic unity, by the aid of the idea of a
causality according to design in a supreme cause a cause which it regards as the highest intelligence.
*The advantages which a circular form, in the case of the earth, has over every other, are well known. But
few are aware that the slight flattening at the poles, which gives it the figure of a spheroid, is the only cause
which prevents the elevations of continents or even of mountains, perhaps thrown up by some internal
convulsion, from continually altering the position of the axis of the earth and that to some considerable
degree in a short time. The great protuberance of the earth under the Equator serves to overbalance the
impetus of all other masses of earth, and thus to preserve the axis of the earth, so far as we can observe, in its
present position. And yet this wise arrangement has been unthinkingly explained from the equilibrium of the
formerly fluid mass.
If, however, we neglect this restriction of the idea to a purely regulative influence, reason is betrayed into
numerous errors. For it has then left the ground of experience, in which alone are to be found the criteria of
truth, and has ventured into the region of the incomprehensible and unsearchable, on the heights of which it
loses its power and collectedness, because it has completely severed its connection with experience.
The first error which arises from our employing the idea of a Supreme Being as a constitutive (in repugnance
to the very nature of an idea), and not as a regulative principle, is the error of inactive reason (ignava ratio).*
We may so term every principle which requires us to regard our investigations of nature as absolutely
complete, and allows reason to cease its inquiries, as if it had fully executed its task. Thus the psychological
idea of the ego, when employed as a constitutive principle for the explanation of the phenomena of the soul,
and for the extension of our knowledge regarding this subject beyond the limits of experience even to the
condition of the soul after death is convenient enough for the purposes of pure reason, but detrimental and
even ruinous to its interests in the sphere of nature and experience. The dogmatizing spiritualist explains the
unchanging unity of our personality through all changes of condition from the unity of a thinking substance,
the interest which we take in things and events that can happen only after our death, from a consciousness of
the immaterial nature of our thinking subject, and so on. Thus he dispenses with all empirical investigations
into the cause of these internal phenomena, and with all possible explanations of them upon purely natural
grounds; while, at the dictation of a transcendent reason, he passes by the immanent sources of cognition in
experience, greatly to his own ease and convenience, but to the sacrifice of all, genuine insight and
intelligence. These prejudicial consequences become still more evident, in the case of the dogmatical
treatment of our idea of a Supreme Intelligence, and the theological system of nature (physicotheology)
which is falsely based upon it. For, in this case, the aims which we observe in nature, and often those which
we merely fancy to exist, make the investigation of causes a very easy task, by directing us to refer such and
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 225
Page No 230
such phenomena immediately to the unsearchable will and counsel of the Supreme Wisdom, while we ought
to investigate their causes in the general laws of the mechanism of matter. We are thus recommended to
consider the labour of reason as ended, when we have merely dispensed with its employment, which is
guided surely and safely only by the order of nature and the series of changes in the world which are
arranged according to immanent and general laws. This error may be avoided, if we do not merely consider
from the viewpoint of final aims certain parts of nature, such as the division and structure of a continent, the
constitution and direction of certain mountainchains, or even the organization existing in the vegetable and
animal kingdoms, but look upon this systematic unity of nature in a perfectly general way, in relation to the
idea of a Supreme Intelligence. If we pursue this advice, we lay as a foundation for all investigation the
conformity to aims of all phenomena of nature in accordance with universal laws, for which no particular
arrangement of nature is exempt, but only cognized by us with more or less difficulty; and we possess a
regulative principle of the systematic unity of a teleological connection, which we do not attempt to anticipate
or predetermine. All that we do, and ought to do, is to follow out the physicomechanical connection in
nature according to general laws, with the hope of discovering, sooner or later, the teleological connection
also. Thus, and thus only, can the principle of final unity aid in the extension of the employment of reason in
the sphere of experience, without being in any case detrimental to its interests.
*This was the term applied by the old dialecticians to a sophistical argument, which ran thus: If it is your fate
to die of this disease, you will die, whether you employ a physician or not. Cicero says that this mode of
reasoning has received this appellation, because, if followed, it puts an end to the employment of reason in
the affairs of life. For a similar reason, I have applied this designation to the sophistical argument of pure
reason.
The second error which arises from the misconception of the principle of systematic unity is that of perverted
reason (perversa ratio, usteron roteron rationis). The idea of systematic unity is available as a regulative
principle in the connection of phenomena according to general natural laws; and, how far soever we have to
travel upon the path of experience to discover some fact or event, this idea requires us to believe that we have
approached all the more nearly to the completion of its use in the sphere of nature, although that completion
can never be attained. But this error reverses the procedure of reason. We begin by hypostatizing the principle
of systematic unity, and by giving an anthropomorphic determination to the conception of a Supreme
Intelligence, and then proceed forcibly to impose aims upon nature. Thus not only does teleology, which
ought to aid in the completion of unity in accordance with general laws, operate to the destruction of its
influence, but it hinders reason from attaining its proper aim, that is, the proof, upon natural grounds, of the
existence of a supreme intelligent cause. For, if we cannot presuppose supreme finality in nature a priori, that
is, as essentially belonging to nature, how can we be directed to endeavour to discover this unity and, rising
gradually through its different degrees, to approach the supreme perfection of an author of all a perfection
which is absolutely necessary, and therefore cognizable a priori? The regulative principle directs us to
presuppose systematic unity absolutely and, consequently, as following from the essential nature of things
but only as a unity of nature, not merely cognized empirically, but presupposed a priori, although only in an
indeterminate manner. But if I insist on basing nature upon the foundation of a supreme ordaining Being, the
unity of nature is in effect lost. For, in this case, it is quite foreign and unessential to the nature of things, and
cannot be cognized from the general laws of nature. And thus arises a vicious circular argument, what ought
to have been proved having been presupposed.
To take the regulative principle of systematic unity in nature for a constitutive principle, and to hypostatize
and make a cause out of that which is properly the ideal ground of the consistent and harmonious exercise of
reason, involves reason in inextricable embarrassments. The investigation of nature pursues its own path
under the guidance of the chain of natural causes, in accordance with the general laws of nature, and ever
follows the light of the idea of an author of the universe not for the purpose of deducing the finality, which
it constantly pursues, from this Supreme Being, but to attain to the cognition of his existence from the finality
which it seeks in the existence of the phenomena of nature, and, if possible, in that of all things to cognize
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 226
Page No 231
this being, consequently, as absolutely necessary. Whether this latter purpose succeed or not, the idea is and
must always be a true one, and its employment, when merely regulative, must always be accompanied by
truthful and beneficial results.
Complete unity, in conformity with aims, constitutes absolute perfection. But if we do not find this unity in
the nature of the things which go to constitute the world of experience, that is, of objective cognition,
consequently in the universal and necessary laws of nature, how can we infer from this unity the idea of the
supreme and absolutely necessary perfection of a primal being, which is the origin of all causality? The
greatest systematic unity, and consequently teleological unity, constitutes the very foundation of the
possibility of the most extended employment of human reason. The idea of unity is therefore essentially and
indissolubly connected with the nature of our reason. This idea is a legislative one; and hence it is very
natural that we should assume the existence of a legislative reason corresponding to it, from which the
systematic unity of nature the object of the operations of reason must be derived.
In the course of our discussion of the antinomies, we stated that it is always possible to answer all the
questions which pure reason may raise; and that the plea of the limited nature of our cognition, which is
unavoidable and proper in many questions regarding natural phenomena, cannot in this case be admitted,
because the questions raised do not relate to the nature of things, but are necessarily originated by the nature
of reason itself, and relate to its own internal constitution. We can now establish this assertion, which at first
sight appeared so rash, in relation to the two questions in which reason takes the greatest interest, and thus
complete our discussion of the dialectic of pure reason.
If, then, the question is asked, in relation to transcendental theology,* first, whether there is anything distinct
from the world, which contains the ground of cosmical order and connection according to general laws? The
answer is: Certainly. For the world is a sum of phenomena; there must, therefore, be some transcendental
basis of these phenomena, that is, a basis cogitable by the pure understanding alone. If, secondly, the question
is asked whether this being is substance, whether it is of the greatest reality, whether it is necessary, and so
forth? I answer that this question is utterly without meaning. For all the categories which aid me in forming a
conception of an object cannot be employed except in the world of sense, and are without meaning when not
applied to objects of actual or possible experience. Out of this sphere, they are not properly conceptions, but
the mere marks or indices of conceptions, which we may admit, although they cannot, without the help of
experience, help us to understand any subject or thing. If, thirdly, the question is whether we may not cogitate
this being, which is distinct from the world, in analogy with the objects of experience? The answer is:
Undoubtedly, but only as an ideal, and not as a real object. That is, we must cogitate it only as an unknown
substratum of the systematic unity, order, and finality of the world a unity which reason must employ as the
regulative principle of its investigation of nature. Nay, more, we may admit into the idea certain
anthropomorphic elements, which are promotive of the interests of this regulative principle. For it is no more
than an idea, which does not relate directly to a being distinct from the world, but to the regulative principle
of the systematic unity of the world, by means, however, of a schema of this unity the schema of a Supreme
Intelligence, who is the wiselydesigning author of the universe. What this basis of cosmical unity may be in
itself, we know not we cannot discover from the idea; we merely know how we ought to employ the idea of
this unity, in relation to the systematic operation of reason in the sphere of experience.
*After what has been said of the psychological idea of the ego and its proper employment as a regulative
principle of the operations of reason, I need not enter into details regarding the transcendental illusion by
which the systematic unity of all the various phenomena of the internal sense is hypostatized. The procedure
is in this case very similar to that which has been discussed in our remarks on the theological ideal.
But, it will be asked again, can we on these grounds, admit the existence of a wise and omnipotent author of
the world? Without doubt; and not only so, but we must assume the existence of such a being. But do we thus
extend the limits of our knowledge beyond the field of possible experience? By no means. For we have
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 227
Page No 232
merely presupposed a something, of which we have no conception, which we do not know as it is in itself;
but, in relation to the systematic disposition of the universe, which we must presuppose in all our observation
of nature, we have cogitated this unknown being in analogy with an intelligent existence (an empirical
conception), that is to say, we have endowed it with those attributes, which, judging from the nature of our
own reason, may contain the ground of such a systematic unity. This idea is therefore valid only relatively to
the employment in experience of our reason. But if we attribute to it absolute and objective validity, we
overlook the fact that it is merely an ideal being that we cogitate; and, by setting out from a basis which is not
determinable by considerations drawn from experience, we place ourselves in a position which incapacitates
us from applying this principle to the empirical employment of reason.
But, it will be asked further, can I make any use of this conception and hypothesis in my investigations into
the world and nature? Yes, for this very purpose was the idea established by reason as a fundamental basis.
But may I regard certain arrangements, which seemed to have been made in conformity with some fixed aim,
as the arrangements of design, and look upon them as proceeding from the divine will, with the intervention,
however, of certain other particular arrangements disposed to that end? Yes, you may do so; but at the same
time you must regard it as indifferent, whether it is asserted that divine wisdom has disposed all things in
conformity with his highest aims, or that the idea of supreme wisdom is a regulative principle in the
investigation of nature, and at the same time a principle of the systematic unity of nature according to general
laws, even in those cases where we are unable to discover that unity. In other words, it must be perfectly
indifferent to you whether you say, when you have discovered this unity: God has wisely willed it so; or:
Nature has wisely arranged this. For it was nothing but the systematic unity, which reason requires as a basis
for the investigation of nature, that justified you in accepting the idea of a supreme intelligence as a schema
for a regulative principle; and, the farther you advance in the discovery of design and finality, the more
certain the validity of your idea. But, as the whole aim of this regulative principle was the discovery of a
necessary and systematic unity in nature, we have, in so far as we attain this, to attribute our success to the
idea of a Supreme Being; while, at the same time, we cannot, without involving ourselves in contradictions,
overlook the general laws of nature, as it was in reference to them alone that this idea was employed. We
cannot, I say, overlook the general laws of nature, and regard this conformity to aims observable in nature as
contingent or hyperphysical in its origin; inasmuch as there is no ground which can justify us in the
admission of a being with such properties distinct from and above nature. All that we are authorized to assert
is that this idea may be employed as a principle, and that the properties of the being which is assumed to
correspond to it may be regarded as systematically connected in analogy with the causal determination of
phenomena.
For the same reasons we are justified in introducing into the idea of the supreme cause other anthropomorphic
elements (for without these we could not predicate anything of it); we may regard it as allowable to cogitate
this cause as a being with understanding, the feelings of pleasure and displeasure, and faculties of desire and
will corresponding to these. At the same time, we may attribute to this being infinite perfection a perfection
which necessarily transcends that which our knowledge of the order and design in the world authorize us to
predicate of it. For the regulative law of systematic unity requires us to study nature on the supposition that
systematic and final unity in infinitum is everywhere discoverable, even in the highest diversity. For,
although we may discover little of this cosmical perfection, it belongs to the legislative prerogative of reason
to require us always to seek for and to expect it; while it must always be beneficial to institute all inquiries
into nature in accordance with this principle. But it is evident that, by this idea of a supreme author of all,
which I place as the foundation of all inquiries into nature, I do not mean to assert the existence of such a
being, or that I have any knowledge of its existence; and, consequently, I do not really deduce anything from
the existence of this being, but merely from its idea, that is to say, from the nature of things in this world, in
accordance with this idea. A certain dim consciousness of the true use of this idea seems to have dictated to
the philosophers of all times the moderate language used by them regarding the cause of the world. We find
them employing the expressions wisdom and care of nature, and divine wisdom, as synonymous nay, in
purely speculative discussions, preferring the former, because it does not carry the appearance of greater
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 228
Page No 233
pretensions than such as we are entitled to make, and at the same time directs reason to its proper field of
action nature and her phenomena.
Thus, pure reason, which at first seemed to promise us nothing less than the extension of our cognition
beyond the limits of experience, is found, when thoroughly examined, to contain nothing but regulative
principles, the virtue and function of which is to introduce into our cognition a higher degree of unity than the
understanding could of itself. These principles, by placing the goal of all our struggles at so great a distance,
realize for us the most thorough connection between the different parts of our cognition, and the highest
degree of systematic unity. But, on the other hand, if misunderstood and employed as constitutive principles
of transcendent cognition, they become the parents of illusions and contradictions, while pretending to
introduce us to new regions of knowledge.
Thus all human cognition begins with intuitions, proceeds from thence to conceptions, and ends with ideas.
Although it possesses, in relation to all three elements, a priori sources of cognition, which seemed to
transcend the limits of all experience, a thoroughgoing criticism demonstrates that speculative reason can
never, by the aid of these elements, pass the bounds of possible experience, and that the proper destination of
this highest faculty of cognition is to employ all methods, and all the principles of these methods, for the
purpose of penetrating into the innermost secrets of nature, by the aid of the principles of unity (among all
kinds of which teleological unity is the highest), while it ought not to attempt to soar above the sphere of
experience, beyond which there lies nought for us but the void inane. The critical examination, in our
Transcendental Analytic, of all the propositions which professed to extend cognition beyond the sphere of
experience, completely demonstrated that they can only conduct us to a possible experience. If we were not
distrustful even of the clearest abstract theorems, if we were not allured by specious and inviting prospects to
escape from the constraining power of their evidence, we might spare ourselves the laborious examination of
all the dialectical arguments which a transcendent reason adduces in support of its pretensions; for we should
know with the most complete certainty that, however honest such professions might be, they are null and
valueless, because they relate to a kind of knowledge to which no man can by any possibility attain. But, as
there is no end to discussion, if we cannot discover the true cause of the illusions by which even the wisest
are deceived, and as the analysis of all our transcendent cognition into its elements is of itself of no slight
value as a psychological study, while it is a duty incumbent on every philosopher it was found necessary to
investigate the dialectical procedure of reason in its primary sources. And as the inferences of which this
dialectic is the parent are not only deceitful, but naturally possess a profound interest for humanity, it was
advisable at the same time, to give a full account of the momenta of this dialectical procedure, and to deposit
it in the archives of human reason, as a warning to all future metaphysicians to avoid these causes of
speculative error. METHOD
II.
TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD.
If we regard the sum of the cognition of pure speculative reason as an edifice, the idea of which, at least,
exists in the human mind, it may be said that we have in the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements examined
the materials and determined to what edifice these belong, and what its height and stability. We have found,
indeed, that, although we had purposed to build for ourselves a tower which should reach to Heaven, the
supply of materials sufficed merely for a habitation, which was spacious enough for all terrestrial purposes,
and high enough to enable us to survey the level plain of experience, but that the bold undertaking designed
necessarily failed for want of materials not to mention the confusion of tongues, which gave rise to endless
disputes among the labourers on the plan of the edifice, and at last scattered them over all the world, each to
erect a separate building for himself, according to his own plans and his own inclinations. Our present task
relates not to the materials, but to the plan of an edifice; and, as we have had sufficient warning not to venture
blindly upon a design which may be found to transcend our natural powers, while, at the same time, we
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason. 229
Page No 234
cannot give up the intention of erecting a secure abode for the mind, we must proportion our design to the
material which is presented to us, and which is, at the same time, sufficient for all our wants.
I understand, then, by the transcendental doctrine of method, the determination of the formal conditions of a
complete system of pure reason. We shall accordingly have to treat of the discipline, the canon, the
architectonic, and, finally, the history of pure reason. This part of our Critique will accomplish, from the
transcendental point of view, what has been usually attempted, but miserably executed, under the name of
practical logic. It has been badly executed, I say, because general logic, not being limited to any particular
kind of cognition (not even to the pure cognition of the understanding) nor to any particular objects, it cannot,
without borrowing from other sciences, do more than present merely the titles or signs of possible methods
and the technical expressions, which are employed in the systematic parts of all sciences; and thus the pupil is
made acquainted with names, the meaning and application of which he is to learn only at some future time.
CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason.
Negative judgements those which are so not merely as regards their logical form, but in respect of their
content are not commonly held in especial respect. They are, on the contrary, regarded as jealous enemies of
our insatiable desire for knowledge; and it almost requires an apology to induce us to tolerate, much less to
prize and to respect them.
All propositions, indeed, may be logically expressed in a negative form; but, in relation to the content of our
cognition, the peculiar province of negative judgements is solely to prevent error. For this reason, too,
negative propositions, which are framed for the purpose of correcting false cognitions where error is
absolutely impossible, are undoubtedly true, but inane and senseless; that is, they are in reality purposeless
and, for this reason, often very ridiculous. Such is the proposition of the schoolman that Alexander could not
have subdued any countries without an army.
But where the limits of our possible cognition are very much contracted, the attraction to new fields of
knowledge great, the illusions to which the mind is subject of the most deceptive character, and the evil
consequences of error of no inconsiderable magnitude the negative element in knowledge, which is useful
only to guard us against error, is of far more importance than much of that positive instruction which makes
additions to the sum of our knowledge. The restraint which is employed to repress, and finally to extirpate the
constant inclination to depart from certain rules, is termed discipline. It is distinguished from culture, which
aims at the formation of a certain degree of skill, without attempting to repress or to destroy any other mental
power, already existing. In the cultivation of a talent, which has given evidence of an impulse towards
selfdevelopment, discipline takes a negative,* culture and doctrine a positive, part.
*I am well aware that, in the language of the schools, the term discipline is usually employed as synonymous
with instruction. But there are so many cases in which it is necessary to distinguish the notion of the former,
as a course of corrective training, from that of the latter, as the communication of knowledge, and the nature
of things itself demands the appropriation of the most suitable expressions for this distinction, that it is my
desire that the former terms should never be employed in any other than a negative signification.
That natural dispositions and talents (such as imagination and with, which ask a free and unlimited
development, require in many respects the corrective influence of discipline, every one will readily grant. But
it may well appear strange that reason, whose proper duty it is to prescribe rules of discipline to all the other
powers of the mind, should itself require this corrective. It has, in fact, hitherto escaped this humiliation, only
because, in presence of its magnificent pretensions and high position, no one could readily suspect it to be
capable of substituting fancies for conceptions, and words for things.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason. 230
Page No 235
Reason, when employed in the field of experience, does not stand in need of criticism, because its principles
are subjected to the continual test of empirical observations. Nor is criticism requisite in the sphere of
mathematics, where the conceptions of reason must always be presented in concreto in pure intuition, and
baseless or arbitrary assertions are discovered without difficulty. But where reason is not held in a plain track
by the influence of empirical or of pure intuition, that is, when it is employed in the transcendental sphere of
pure conceptions, it stands in great need of discipline, to restrain its propensity to overstep the limits of
possible experience and to keep it from wandering into error. In fact, the utility of the philosophy of pure
reason is entirely of this negative character. Particular errors may be corrected by particular animadversions,
and the causes of these errors may be eradicated by criticism. But where we find, as in the case of pure
reason, a complete system of illusions and fallacies, closely connected with each other and depending upon
grand general principles, there seems to be required a peculiar and negative code of mental legislation, which,
under the denomination of a discipline, and founded upon the nature of reason and the objects of its exercise,
shall constitute a system of thorough examination and testing, which no fallacy will be able to withstand or
escape from, under whatever disguise or concealment it may lurk.
But the reader must remark that, in this the second division of our transcendental Critique the discipline of
pure reason is not directed to the content, but to the method of the cognition of pure reason. The former task
has been completed in the doctrine of elements. But there is so much similarity in the mode of employing the
faculty of reason, whatever be the object to which it is applied, while, at the same time, its employment in the
transcendental sphere is so essentially different in kind from every other, that, without the warning negative
influence of a discipline specially directed to that end, the errors are unavoidable which spring from the
unskillful employment of the methods which are originated by reason but which are out of place in this
sphere.
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism.
The science of mathematics presents the most brilliant example of the extension of the sphere of pure reason
without the aid of experience. Examples are always contagious; and they exert an especial influence on the
same faculty, which naturally flatters itself that it will have the same good fortune in other case as fell to its
lot in one fortunate instance. Hence pure reason hopes to be able to extend its empire in the transcendental
sphere with equal success and security, especially when it applies the same method which was attended with
such brilliant results in the science of mathematics. It is, therefore, of the highest importance for us to know
whether the method of arriving at demonstrative certainty, which is termed mathematical, be identical with
that by which we endeavour to attain the same degree of certainty in philosophy, and which is termed in that
science dogmatical.
Philosophical cognition is the cognition of reason by means of conceptions; mathematical cognition is
cognition by means of the construction of conceptions. The construction of a conception is the presentation a
priori of the intuition which corresponds to the conception. For this purpose a nonempirical intuition is
requisite, which, as an intuition, is an individual object; while, as the construction of a conception (a general
representation), it must be seen to be universally valid for all the possible intuitions which rank under that
conception. Thus I construct a triangle, by the presentation of the object which corresponds to this
conception, either by mere imagination, in pure intuition, or upon paper, in empirical intuition, in both cases
completely a priori, without borrowing the type of that figure from any experience. The individual figure
drawn upon paper is empirical; but it serves, notwithstanding, to indicate the conception, even in its
universality, because in this empirical intuition we keep our eye merely on the act of the construction of the
conception, and pay no attention to the various modes of determining it, for example, its size, the length of its
sides, the size of its angles, these not in the least affecting the essential character of the conception.
Philosophical cognition, accordingly, regards the particular only in the general; mathematical the general in
the particular, nay, in the individual. This is done, however, entirely a priori and by means of pure reason, so
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 231
Page No 236
that, as this individual figure is determined under certain universal conditions of construction, the object of
the conception, to which this individual figure corresponds as its schema, must be cogitated as universally
determined.
The essential difference of these two modes of cognition consists, therefore, in this formal quality; it does not
regard the difference of the matter or objects of both. Those thinkers who aim at distinguishing philosophy
from mathematics by asserting that the former has to do with quality merely, and the latter with quantity,
have mistaken the effect for the cause. The reason why mathematical cognition can relate only to quantity is
to be found in its form alone. For it is the conception of quantities only that is capable of being constructed,
that is, presented a priori in intuition; while qualities cannot be given in any other than an empirical intuition.
Hence the cognition of qualities by reason is possible only through conceptions. No one can find an intuition
which shall correspond to the conception of reality, except in experience; it cannot be presented to the mind a
priori and antecedently to the empirical consciousness of a reality. We can form an intuition, by means of the
mere conception of it, of a cone, without the aid of experience; but the colour of the cone we cannot know
except from experience. I cannot present an intuition of a cause, except in an example which experience
offers to me. Besides, philosophy, as well as mathematics, treats of quantities; as, for example, of totality,
infinity, and so on. Mathematics, too, treats of the difference of lines and surfaces as spaces of different
quality, of the continuity of extension as a quality thereof. But, although in such cases they have a common
object, the mode in which reason considers that object is very different in philosophy from what it is in
mathematics. The former confines itself to the general conceptions; the latter can do nothing with a mere
conception, it hastens to intuition. In this intuition it regards the conception in concreto, not empirically, but
in an a priori intuition, which it has constructed; and in which, all the results which follow from the general
conditions of the construction of the conception are in all cases valid for the object of the constructed
conception.
Suppose that the conception of a triangle is given to a philosopher and that he is required to discover, by the
philosophical method, what relation the sum of its angles bears to a right angle. He has nothing before him
but the conception of a figure enclosed within three right lines, and, consequently, with the same number of
angles. He may analyse the conception of a right line, of an angle, or of the number three as long as he
pleases, but he will not discover any properties not contained in these conceptions. But, if this question is
proposed to a geometrician, he at once begins by constructing a triangle. He knows that two right angles are
equal to the sum of all the contiguous angles which proceed from one point in a straight line; and he goes on
to produce one side of his triangle, thus forming two adjacent angles which are together equal to two right
angles. He then divides the exterior of these angles, by drawing a line parallel with the opposite side of the
triangle, and immediately perceives that be has thus got an exterior adjacent angle which is equal to the
interior. Proceeding in this way, through a chain of inferences, and always on the ground of intuition, he
arrives at a clear and universally valid solution of the question.
But mathematics does not confine itself to the construction of quantities (quanta), as in the case of geometry;
it occupies itself with pure quantity also (quantitas), as in the case of algebra, where complete abstraction is
made of the properties of the object indicated by the conception of quantity. In algebra, a certain method of
notation by signs is adopted, and these indicate the different possible constructions of quantities, the
extraction of roots, and so on. After having thus denoted the general conception of quantities, according to
their different relations, the different operations by which quantity or number is increased or diminished are
presented in intuition in accordance with general rules. Thus, when one quantity is to be divided by another,
the signs which denote both are placed in the form peculiar to the operation of division; and thus algebra, by
means of a symbolical construction of quantity, just as geometry, with its ostensive or geometrical
construction (a construction of the objects themselves), arrives at results which discursive cognition cannot
hope to reach by the aid of mere conceptions.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 232
Page No 237
Now, what is the cause of this difference in the fortune of the philosopher and the mathematician, the former
of whom follows the path of conceptions, while the latter pursues that of intuitions, which he represents, a
priori, in correspondence with his conceptions? The cause is evident from what has been already
demonstrated in the introduction to this Critique. We do not, in the present case, want to discover analytical
propositions, which may be produced merely by analysing our conceptions for in this the philosopher would
have the advantage over his rival; we aim at the discovery of synthetical propositions such synthetical
propositions, moreover, as can be cognized a priori. I must not confine myself to that which I actually
cogitate in my conception of a triangle, for this is nothing more than the mere definition; I must try to go
beyond that, and to arrive at properties which are not contained in, although they belong to, the conception.
Now, this is impossible, unless I determine the object present to my mind according to the conditions, either
of empirical, or of pure, intuition. In the former case, I should have an empirical proposition (arrived at by
actual measurement of the angles of the triangle), which would possess neither universality nor necessity; but
that would be of no value. In the latter, I proceed by geometrical construction, by means of which I collect, in
a pure intuition, just as I would in an empirical intuition, all the various properties which belong to the
schema of a triangle in general, and consequently to its conception, and thus construct synthetical
propositions which possess the attribute of universality.
It would be vain to philosophize upon the triangle, that is, to reflect on it discursively; I should get no further
than the definition with which I had been obliged to set out. There are certainly transcendental synthetical
propositions which are framed by means of pure conceptions, and which form the peculiar distinction of
philosophy; but these do not relate to any particular thing, but to a thing in general, and enounce the
conditions under which the perception of it may become a part of possible experience. But the science of
mathematics has nothing to do with such questions, nor with the question of existence in any fashion; it is
concerned merely with the properties of objects in themselves, only in so far as these are connected with the
conception of the objects.
In the above example, we merely attempted to show the great difference which exists between the discursive
employment of reason in the sphere of conceptions, and its intuitive exercise by means of the construction of
conceptions. The question naturally arises: What is the cause which necessitates this twofold exercise of
reason, and how are we to discover whether it is the philosophical or the mathematical method which reason
is pursuing in an argument?
All our knowledge relates, finally, to possible intuitions, for it is these alone that present objects to the mind.
An a priori or nonempirical conception contains either a pure intuition and in this case it can be
constructed; or it contains nothing but the synthesis of possible intuitions, which are not given a priori. In this
latter case, it may help us to form synthetical a priori judgements, but only in the discursive method, by
conceptions, not in the intuitive, by means of the construction of conceptions.
The only a priori intuition is that of the pure form of phenomena space and time. A conception of space and
time as quanta may be presented a priori in intuition, that is, constructed, either alone with their quality
(figure), or as pure quantity (the mere synthesis of the homogeneous), by means of number. But the matter of
phenomena, by which things are given in space and time, can be presented only in perception, a posteriori.
The only conception which represents a priori this empirical content of phenomena is the conception of a
thing in general; and the a priori synthetical cognition of this conception can give us nothing more than the
rule for the synthesis of that which may be contained in the corresponding a posteriori perception; it is utterly
inadequate to present an a priori intuition of the real object, which must necessarily be empirical.
Synthetical propositions, which relate to things in general, an a priori intuition of which is impossible, are
transcendental. For this reason transcendental propositions cannot be framed by means of the construction of
conceptions; they are a priori, and based entirely on conceptions themselves. They contain merely the rule, by
which we are to seek in the world of perception or experience the synthetical unity of that which cannot be
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 233
Page No 238
intuited a priori. But they are incompetent to present any of the conceptions which appear in them in an a
priori intuition; these can be given only a posteriori, in experience, which, however, is itself possible only
through these synthetical principles.
If we are to form a synthetical judgement regarding a conception, we must go beyond it, to the intuition in
which it is given. If we keep to what is contained in the conception, the judgement is merely analytical it is
merely an explanation of what we have cogitated in the conception. But I can pass from the conception to the
pure or empirical intuition which corresponds to it. I can proceed to examine my conception in concreto, and
to cognize, either a priori or a posterio, what I find in the object of the conception. The former a priori
cognition is rationalmathematical cognition by means of the construction of the conception; the latter a
posteriori cognition is purely empirical cognition, which does not possess the attributes of necessity and
universality. Thus I may analyse the conception I have of gold; but I gain no new information from this
analysis, I merely enumerate the different properties which I had connected with the notion indicated by the
word. My knowledge has gained in logical clearness and arrangement, but no addition has been made to it.
But if I take the matter which is indicated by this name, and submit it to the examination of my senses, I am
enabled to form several synthetical although still empirical propositions. The mathematical conception of a
triangle I should construct, that is, present a priori in intuition, and in this way attain to rationalsynthetical
cognition. But when the transcendental conception of reality, or substance, or power is presented to my mind,
I find that it does not relate to or indicate either an empirical or pure intuition, but that it indicates merely the
synthesis of empirical intuitions, which cannot of course be given a priori. The synthesis in such a conception
cannot proceed a priori without the aid of experience to the intuition which corresponds to the conception;
and, for this reason, none of these conceptions can produce a determinative synthetical proposition, they can
never present more than a principle of the synthesis* of possible empirical intuitions. A transcendental
proposition is, therefore, a synthetical cognition of reason by means of pure conceptions and the discursive
method, and it renders possible all synthetical unity in empirical cognition, though it cannot present us with
any intuition a priori.
*In the case of the conception of cause, I do really go beyond the empirical conception of an event but not
to the intuition which presents this conception in concreto, but only to the timeconditions, which may be
found in experience to correspond to the conception. My procedure is, therefore, strictly according to
conceptions; I cannot in a case of this kind employ the construction of conceptions, because the conception is
merely a rule for the synthesis of perceptions, which are not pure intuitions, and which, therefore, cannot be
given a priori.
There is thus a twofold exercise of reason. Both modes have the properties of universality and an a priori
origin in common, but are, in their procedure, of widely different character. The reason of this is that in the
world of phenomena, in which alone objects are presented to our minds, there are two main elements the
form of intuition (space and time), which can be cognized and determined completely a priori, and the matter
or content that which is presented in space and time, and which, consequently, contains a something an
existence corresponding to our powers of sensation. As regards the latter, which can never be given in a
determinate mode except by experience, there are no a priori notions which relate to it, except the
undetermined conceptions of the synthesis of possible sensations, in so far as these belong (in a possible
experience) to the unity of consciousness. As regards the former, we can determine our conceptions a priori
in intuition, inasmuch as we are ourselves the creators of the objects of the conceptions in space and time
these objects being regarded simply as quanta. In the one case, reason proceeds according to conceptions and
can do nothing more than subject phenomena to these which can only be determined empirically, that is, a
posteriori in conformity, however, with those conceptions as the rules of all empirical synthesis. In the other
case, reason proceeds by the construction of conceptions; and, as these conceptions relate to an a priori
intuition, they may be given and determined in pure intuition a priori, and without the aid of empirical data.
The examination and consideration of everything that exists in space or time whether it is a quantum or not,
in how far the particular something (which fills space or time) is a primary substratum, or a mere
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 234
Page No 239
determination of some other existence, whether it relates to anything else either as cause or effect, whether
its existence is isolated or in reciprocal connection with and dependence upon others, the possibility of this
existence, its reality and necessity or opposites all these form part of the cognition of reason on the ground
of conceptions, and this cognition is termed philosophical. But to determine a priori an intuition in space (its
figure), to divide time into periods, or merely to cognize the quantity of an intuition in space and time, and to
determine it by number all this is an operation of reason by means of the construction of conceptions, and is
called mathematical.
The success which attends the efforts of reason in the sphere of mathematics naturally fosters the expectation
that the same good fortune will be its lot, if it applies the mathematical method in other regions of mental
endeavour besides that of quantities. Its success is thus great, because it can support all its conceptions by a
priori intuitions and, in this way, make itself a master, as it were, over nature; while pure philosophy, with its
a priori discursive conceptions, bungles about in the world of nature, and cannot accredit or show any a priori
evidence of the reality of these conceptions. Masters in the science of mathematics are confident of the
success of this method; indeed, it is a common persuasion that it is capable of being applied to any subject of
human thought. They have hardly ever reflected or philosophized on their favourite science a task of great
difficulty; and the specific difference between the two modes of employing the faculty of reason has never
entered their thoughts. Rules current in the field of common experience, and which common sense stamps
everywhere with its approval, are regarded by them as axiomatic. From what source the conceptions of space
and time, with which (as the only primitive quanta) they have to deal, enter their minds, is a question which
they do not trouble themselves to answer; and they think it just as unnecessary to examine into the origin of
the pure conceptions of the understanding and the extent of their validity. All they have to do with them is to
employ them. In all this they are perfectly right, if they do not overstep the limits of the sphere of nature. But
they pass, unconsciously, from the world of sense to the insecure ground of pure transcendental conceptions
(instabilis tellus, innabilis unda), where they can neither stand nor swim, and where the tracks of their
footsteps are obliterated by time; while the march of mathematics is pursued on a broad and magnificent
highway, which the latest posterity shall frequent without fear of danger or impediment.
As we have taken upon us the task of determining, clearly and certainly, the limits of pure reason in the
sphere of transcendentalism, and as the efforts of reason in this direction are persisted in, even after the
plainest and most expressive warnings, hope still beckoning us past the limits of experience into the
splendours of the intellectual world it becomes necessary to cut away the last anchor of this fallacious and
fantastic hope. We shall, accordingly, show that the mathematical method is unattended in the sphere of
philosophy by the least advantage except, perhaps, that it more plainly exhibits its own inadequacy that
geometry and philosophy are two quite different things, although they go band in hand in hand in the field of
natural science, and, consequently, that the procedure of the one can never be imitated by the other.
The evidence of mathematics rests upon definitions, axioms, and demonstrations. I shall be satisfied with
showing that none of these forms can be employed or imitated in philosophy in the sense in which they are
understood by mathematicians; and that the geometrician, if he employs his method in philosophy, will
succeed only in building cardcastles, while the employment of the philosophical method in mathematics can
result in nothing but mere verbiage. The essential business of philosophy, indeed, is to mark out the limits of
the science; and even the mathematician, unless his talent is naturally circumscribed and limited to this
particular department of knowledge, cannot turn a deaf ear to the warnings of philosophy, or set himself
above its direction.
I. Of Definitions. A definition is, as the term itself indicates, the representation, upon primary grounds, of the
complete conception of a thing within its own limits.* Accordingly, an empirical conception cannot be
defined, it can only be explained. For, as there are in such a conception only a certain number of marks or
signs, which denote a certain class of sensuous objects, we can never be sure that we do not cogitate under
the word which indicates the same object, at one time a greater, at another a smaller number of signs. Thus,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 235
Page No 240
one person may cogitate in his conception of gold, in addition to its properties of weight, colour, malleability,
that of resisting rust, while another person may be ignorant of this quality. We employ certain signs only so
long as we require them for the sake of distinction; new observations abstract some and add new ones, so that
an empirical conception never remains within permanent limits. It is, in fact, useless to define a conception of
this kind. If, for example, we are speaking of water and its properties, we do not stop at what we actually
think by the word water, but proceed to observation and experiment; and the word, with the few signs
attached to it, is more properly a designation than a conception of the thing. A definition in this case would
evidently be nothing more than a determination of the word. In the second place, no a priori conception, such
as those of substance, cause, right, fitness, and so on, can be defined. For I can never be sure, that the clear
representation of a given conception (which is given in a confused state) has been fully developed, until I
know that the representation is adequate with its object. But, inasmuch as the conception, as it is presented to
the mind, may contain a number of obscure representations, which we do not observe in our analysis,
although we employ them in our application of the conception, I can never be sure that my analysis is
complete, while examples may make this probable, although they can never demonstrate the fact. instead of
the word definition, I should rather employ the term exposition a more modest expression, which the critic
may accept without surrendering his doubts as to the completeness of the analysis of any such conception.
As, therefore, neither empirical nor a priori conceptions are capable of definition, we have to see whether the
only other kind of conceptions arbitrary conceptions can be subjected to this mental operation. Such a
conception can always be defined; for I must know thoroughly what I wished to cogitate in it, as it was I who
created it, and it was not given to my mind either by the nature of my understanding or by experience. At the
same time, I cannot say that, by such a definition, I have defined a real object. If the conception is based upon
empirical conditions, if, for example, I have a conception of a clock for a ship, this arbitrary conception does
not assure me of the existence or even of the possibility of the object. My definition of such a conception
would with more propriety be termed a declaration of a project than a definition of an object. There are no
other conceptions which can bear definition, except those which contain an arbitrary synthesis, which can be
constructed a priori. Consequently, the science of mathematics alone possesses definitions. For the object
here thought is presented a priori in intuition; and thus it can never contain more or less than the conception,
because the conception of the object has been given by the definition and primarily, that is, without deriving
the definition from any other source. Philosophical definitions are, therefore, merely expositions of given
conceptions, while mathematical definitions are constructions of conceptions originally formed by the mind
itself; the former are produced by analysis, the completeness of which is never demonstratively certain, the
latter by a synthesis. In a mathematical definition the conception is formed, in a philosophical definition it is
only explained. From this it follows:
*The definition must describe the conception completely that is, omit none of the marks or signs of which it
composed; within its own limits, that is, it must be precise, and enumerate no more signs than belong to the
conception; and on primary grounds, that is to say, the limitations of the bounds of the conception must not
be deduced from other conceptions, as in this case a proof would be necessary, and the socalled definition
would be incapable of taking its place at the bead of all the judgements we have to form regarding an object.
(a) That we must not imitate, in philosophy, the mathematical usage of commencing with definitions except
by way of hypothesis or experiment. For, as all socalled philosophical definitions are merely analyses of
given conceptions, these conceptions, although only in a confused form, must precede the analysis; and the
incomplete exposition must precede the complete, so that we may be able to draw certain inferences from the
characteristics which an incomplete analysis has enabled us to discover, before we attain to the complete
exposition or definition of the conception. In one word, a full and clear definition ought, in philosophy, rather
to form the conclusion than the commencement of our labours.* In mathematics, on the contrary, we cannot
have a conception prior to the definition; it is the definition which gives us the conception, and it must for
this reason form the commencement of every chain of mathematical reasoning.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 236
Page No 241
*Philosophy abounds in faulty definitions, especially such as contain some of the elements requisite to form a
complete definition. If a conception could not be employed in reasoning before it had been defined, it would
fare ill with all philosophical thought. But, as incompletely defined conceptions may always be employed
without detriment to truth, so far as our analysis of the elements contained in them proceeds, imperfect
definitions, that is, propositions which are properly not definitions, but merely approximations thereto, may
be used with great advantage. In mathematics, definition belongs ad esse, in philosophy ad melius esse. It is a
difficult task to construct a proper definition. Jurists are still without a complete definition of the idea of right.
(b) Mathematical definitions cannot be erroneous. For the conception is given only in and through the
definition, and thus it contains only what has been cogitated in the definition. But although a definition
cannot be incorrect, as regards its content, an error may sometimes, although seldom, creep into the form.
This error consists in a want of precision. Thus the common definition of a circle that it is a curved line,
every point in which is equally distant from another point called the centre is faulty, from the fact that the
determination indicated by the word curved is superfluous. For there ought to be a particular theorem, which
may be easily proved from the definition, to the effect that every line, which has all its points at equal
distances from another point, must be a curved line that is, that not even the smallest part of it can be
straight. Analytical definitions, on the other hand, may be erroneous in many respects, either by the
introduction of signs which do not actually exist in the conception, or by wanting in that completeness which
forms the essential of a definition. In the latter case, the definition is necessarily defective, because we can
never be fully certain of the completeness of our analysis. For these reasons, the method of definition
employed in mathematics cannot be imitated in philosophy.
2. Of Axioms. These, in so far as they are immediately certain, are a priori synthetical principles. Now, one
conception cannot be connected synthetically and yet immediately with another; because, if we wish to
proceed out of and beyond a conception, a third mediating cognition is necessary. And, as philosophy is a
cognition of reason by the aid of conceptions alone, there is to be found in it no principle which deserves to
be called an axiom. Mathematics, on the other hand, may possess axioms, because it can always connect the
predicates of an object a priori, and without any mediating term, by means of the construction of conceptions
in intuition. Such is the case with the proposition: Three points can always lie in a plane. On the other hand,
no synthetical principle which is based upon conceptions, can ever be immediately certain (for example, the
proposition: Everything that happens has a cause), because I require a mediating term to connect the two
conceptions of event and cause namely, the condition of timedetermination in an experience, and I cannot
cognize any such principle immediately and from conceptions alone. Discursive principles are, accordingly,
very different from intuitive principles or axioms. The former always require deduction, which in the case of
the latter may be altogether dispensed with. Axioms are, for this reason, always selfevident, while
philosophical principles, whatever may be the degree of certainty they possess, cannot lay any claim to such a
distinction. No synthetical proposition of pure transcendental reason can be so evident, as is often rashly
enough declared, as the statement, twice two are four. It is true that in the Analytic I introduced into the list of
principles of the pure understanding, certain axioms of intuition; but the principle there discussed was not
itself an axiom, but served merely to present the principle of the possibility of axioms in general, while it was
really nothing more than a principle based upon conceptions. For it is one part of the duty of transcendental
philosophy to establish the possibility of mathematics itself. Philosophy possesses, then, no axioms, and has
no right to impose its a priori principles upon thought, until it has established their authority and validity by a
thoroughgoing deduction.
3. Of Demonstrations. Only an apodeictic proof, based upon intuition, can be termed a demonstration.
Experience teaches us what is, but it cannot convince us that it might not have been otherwise. Hence a proof
upon empirical grounds cannot be apodeictic. A priori conceptions, in discursive cognition, can never
produce intuitive certainty or evidence, however certain the judgement they present may be. Mathematics
alone, therefore, contains demonstrations, because it does not deduce its cognition from conceptions, but
from the construction of conceptions, that is, from intuition, which can be given a priori in accordance with
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 237
Page No 242
conceptions. The method of algebra, in equations, from which the correct answer is deduced by reduction, is
a kind of construction not geometrical, but by symbols in which all conceptions, especially those of the
relations of quantities, are represented in intuition by signs; and thus the conclusions in that science are
secured from errors by the fact that every proof is submitted to ocular evidence. Philosophical cognition does
not possess this advantage, it being required to consider the general always in abstracto (by means of
conceptions), while mathematics can always consider it in concreto (in an individual intuition), and at the
same time by means of a priori representation, whereby all errors are rendered manifest to the senses. The
former discursive proofs ought to be termed acroamatic proofs, rather than demonstrations, as only words
are employed in them, while demonstrations proper, as the term itself indicates, always require a reference to
the intuition of the object.
It follows from all these considerations that it is not consonant with the nature of philosophy, especially in the
sphere of pure reason, to employ the dogmatical method, and to adorn itself with the titles and insignia of
mathematical science. It does not belong to that order, and can only hope for a fraternal union with that
science. Its attempts at mathematical evidence are vain pretensions, which can only keep it back from its true
aim, which is to detect the illusory procedure of reason when transgressing its proper limits, and by fully
explaining and analysing our conceptions, to conduct us from the dim regions of speculation to the clear
region of modest selfknowledge. Reason must not, therefore, in its transcendental endeavours, look forward
with such confidence, as if the path it is pursuing led straight to its aim, nor reckon with such security upon
its premisses, as to consider it unnecessary to take a step back, or to keep a strict watch for errors, which,
overlooked in the principles, may be detected in the arguments themselves in which case it may be requisite
either to determine these principles with greater strictness, or to change them entirely.
I divide all apodeictic propositions, whether demonstrable or immediately certain, into dogmata and
mathemata. A direct synthetical proposition, based on conceptions, is a dogma; a proposition of the same
kind, based on the construction of conceptions, is a mathema. Analytical judgements do not teach us any
more about an object than what was contained in the conception we had of it; because they do not extend our
cognition beyond our conception of an object, they merely elucidate the conception. They cannot therefore be
with propriety termed dogmas. Of the two kinds of a priori synthetical propositions above mentioned, only
those which are employed in philosophy can, according to the general mode of speech, bear this name; those
of arithmetic or geometry would not be rightly so denominated. Thus the customary mode of speaking
confirms the explanation given above, and the conclusion arrived at, that only those judgements which are
based upon conceptions, not on the construction of conceptions, can be termed dogmatical.
Thus, pure reason, in the sphere of speculation, does not contain a single direct synthetical judgement based
upon conceptions. By means of ideas, it is, as we have shown, incapable of producing synthetical judgements,
which are objectively valid; by means of the conceptions of the understanding, it establishes certain
indubitable principles, not, however, directly on the basis of conceptions, but only indirectly by means of the
relation of these conceptions to something of a purely contingent nature, namely, possible experience. When
experience is presupposed, these principles are apodeictically certain, but in themselves, and directly, they
cannot even be cognized a priori. Thus the given conceptions of cause and event will not be sufficient for the
demonstration of the proposition: Every event has a cause. For this reason, it is not a dogma; although from
another point of view, that of experience, it is capable of being proved to demonstration. The proper term for
such a proposition is principle, and not theorem (although it does require to be proved), because it possesses
the remarkable peculiarity of being the condition of the possibility of its own ground of proof, that is,
experience, and of forming a necessary presupposition in all empirical observation.
If then, in the speculative sphere of pure reason, no dogmata are to be found; all dogmatical methods, whether
borrowed from mathematics, or invented by philosophical thinkers, are alike inappropriate and inefficient.
They only serve to conceal errors and fallacies, and to deceive philosophy, whose duty it is to see that reason
pursues a safe and straight path. A philosophical method may, however, be systematical. For our reason is,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism. 238
Page No 243
subjectively considered, itself a system, and, in the sphere of mere conceptions, a system of investigation
according to principles of unity, the material being supplied by experience alone. But this is not the proper
place for discussing the peculiar method of transcendental philosophy, as our present task is simply to
examine whether our faculties are capable of erecting an edifice on the basis of pure reason, and how far they
may proceed with the materials at their command.
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics.
Reason must be subject, in all its operations, to criticism, which must always be permitted to exercise its
functions without restraint; otherwise its interests are imperilled and its influence obnoxious to suspicion.
There is nothing, however useful, however sacred it may be, that can claim exemption from the searching
examination of this supreme tribunal, which has no respect of persons. The very existence of reason depends
upon this freedom; for the voice of reason is not that of a dictatorial and despotic power, it is rather like the
vote of the citizens of a free state, every member of which must have the privilege of giving free expression
to his doubts, and possess even the right of veto.
But while reason can never decline to submit itself to the tribunal of criticism, it has not always cause to
dread the judgement of this court. Pure reason, however, when engaged in the sphere of dogmatism, is not so
thoroughly conscious of a strict observance of its highest laws, as to appear before a higher judicial reason
with perfect confidence. On the contrary, it must renounce its magnificent dogmatical pretensions in
philosophy.
Very different is the case when it has to defend itself, not before a judge, but against an equal. If dogmatical
assertions are advanced on the negative side, in opposition to those made by reason on the positive side, its
justification kat authrhopon is complete, although the proof of its propositions is kat aletheian unsatisfactory.
By the polemic of pure reason I mean the defence of its propositions made by reason, in opposition to the
dogmatical counterpropositions advanced by other parties. The question here is not whether its own
statements may not also be false; it merely regards the fact that reason proves that the opposite cannot be
established with demonstrative certainty, nor even asserted with a higher degree of probability. Reason does
not hold her possessions upon sufferance; for, although she cannot show a perfectly satisfactory title to them,
no one can prove that she is not the rightful possessor.
It is a melancholy reflection that reason, in its highest exercise, falls into an antithetic; and that the supreme
tribunal for the settlement of differences should not be at union with itself. It is true that we had to discuss the
question of an apparent antithetic, but we found that it was based upon a misconception. In conformity with
the common prejudice, phenomena were regarded as things in themselves, and thus an absolute completeness
in their synthesis was required in the one mode or in the other (it was shown to be impossible in both); a
demand entirely out of place in regard to phenomena. There was, then, no real selfcontradiction of reason in
the propositions: The series of phenomena given in themselves has an absolutely first beginning; and: This
series is absolutely and in itself without beginning. The two propositions are perfectly consistent with each
other, because phenomena as phenomena are in themselves nothing, and consequently the hypothesis that
they are things in themselves must lead to selfcontradictory inferences.
But there are cases in which a similar misunderstanding cannot be provided against, and the dispute must
remain unsettled. Take, for example, the theistic proposition: There is a Supreme Being; and on the other
hand, the atheistic counterstatement: There exists no Supreme Being; or, in psychology: Everything that
thinks possesses the attribute of absolute and permanent unity, which is utterly different from the transitory
unity of material phenomena; and the counterproposition: The soul is not an immaterial unity, and its nature
is transitory, like that of phenomena. The objects of these questions contain no heterogeneous or
contradictory elements, for they relate to things in themselves, and not to phenomena. There would arise,
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 239
Page No 244
indeed, a real contradiction, if reason came forward with a statement on the negative side of these questions
alone. As regards the criticism to which the grounds of proof on the affirmative side must be subjected, it
may be freely admitted, without necessitating the surrender of the affirmative propositions, which have, at
least, the interest of reason in their favour an advantage which the opposite party cannot lay claim to.
I cannot agree with the opinion of several admirable thinkers Sulzer among the rest that, in spite of the
weakness of the arguments hitherto in use, we may hope, one day, to see sufficient demonstrations of the two
cardinal propositions of pure reason the existence of a Supreme Being, and the immortality of the soul. I am
certain, on the contrary, that this will never be the case. For on what ground can reason base such synthetical
propositions, which do not relate to the objects of experience and their internal possibility? But it is also
demonstratively certain that no one will ever be able to maintain the contrary with the least show of
probability. For, as he can attempt such a proof solely upon the basis of pure reason, he is bound to prove that
a Supreme Being, and a thinking subject in the character of a pure intelligence, are impossible. But where
will he find the knowledge which can enable him to enounce synthetical judgements in regard to things which
transcend the region of experience? We may, therefore, rest assured that the opposite never will be
demonstrated. We need not, then, have recourse to scholastic arguments; we may always admit the truth of
those propositions which are consistent with the speculative interests of reason in the sphere of experience,
and form, moreover, the only means of uniting the speculative with the practical interest. Our opponent, who
must not be considered here as a critic solely, we can be ready to meet with a non liquet which cannot fail to
disconcert him; while we cannot deny his right to a similar retort, as we have on our side the advantage of the
support of the subjective maxim of reason, and can therefore look upon all his sophistical arguments with
calm indifference.
From this point of view, there is properly no antithetic of pure reason. For the only arena for such a struggle
would be upon the field of pure theology and psychology; but on this ground there can appear no combatant
whom we need to fear. Ridicule and boasting can be his only weapons; and these may be laughed at, as mere
child's play. This consideration restores to Reason her courage; for what source of confidence could be found,
if she, whose vocation it is to destroy error, were at variance with herself and without any reasonable hope of
ever reaching a state of permanent repose?
Everything in nature is good for some purpose. Even poisons are serviceable; they destroy the evil effects of
other poisons generated in our system, and must always find a place in every complete pharmacopoeia. The
objections raised against the fallacies and sophistries of speculative reason, are objections given by the nature
of this reason itself, and must therefore have a destination and purpose which can only be for the good of
humanity. For what purpose has Providence raised many objects, in which we have the deepest interest, so far
above us, that we vainly try to cognize them with certainty, and our powers of mental vision are rather
excited than satisfied by the glimpses we may chance to seize? It is very doubtful whether it is for our benefit
to advance bold affirmations regarding subjects involved in such obscurity; perhaps it would even be
detrimental to our best interests. But it is undoubtedly always beneficial to leave the investigating, as well as
the critical reason, in perfect freedom, and permit it to take charge of its own interests, which are advanced as
much by its limitation, as by its extension of its views, and which always suffer by the interference of foreign
powers forcing it, against its natural tendencies, to bend to certain preconceived designs.
Allow your opponent to say what he thinks reasonable, and combat him only with the weapons of reason.
Have no anxiety for the practical interests of humanity these are never imperilled in a purely speculative
dispute. Such a dispute serves merely to disclose the antinomy of reason, which, as it has its source in the
nature of reason, ought to be thoroughly investigated. Reason is benefited by the examination of a subject on
both sides, and its judgements are corrected by being limited. It is not the matter that may give occasion to
dispute, but the manner. For it is perfectly permissible to employ, in the presence of reason, the language of a
firmly rooted faith, even after we have been obliged to renounce all pretensions to knowledge.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 240
Page No 245
If we were to ask the dispassionate David Hume a philosopher endowed, in a degree that few are, with a
wellbalanced judgement: What motive induced you to spend so much labour and thought in undermining
the consoling and beneficial persuasion that reason is capable of assuring us of the existence, and presenting
us with a determinate conception of a Supreme Being? his answer would be: Nothing but the desire of
teaching reason to know its own powers better, and, at the same time, a dislike of the procedure by which that
faculty was compelled to support foregone conclusions, and prevented from confessing the internal
weaknesses which it cannot but feel when it enters upon a rigid selfexamination. If, on the other hand, we
were to ask Priestley a philosopher who had no taste for transcendental speculation, but was entirely
devoted to the principles of empiricism what his motives were for overturning those two main pillars of
religion the doctrines of the freedom of the will and the immortality of the soul (in his view the hope of a
future life is but the expectation of the miracle of resurrection) this philosopher, himself a zealous and pious
teacher of religion, could give no other answer than this: I acted in the interest of reason, which always
suffers, when certain objects are explained and judged by a reference to other supposed laws than those of
material nature the only laws which we know in a determinate manner. It would be unfair to decry the latter
philosopher, who endeavoured to harmonize his paradoxical opinions with the interests of religion, and to
undervalue an honest and reflecting man, because he finds himself at a loss the moment he has left the field
of natural science. The same grace must be accorded to Hume, a man not less welldisposed, and quite as
blameless in his moral character, and who pushed his abstract speculations to an extreme length, because, as
he rightly believed, the object of them lies entirely beyond the bounds of natural science, and within the
sphere of pure ideas.
What is to be done to provide against the danger which seems in the present case to menace the best interests
of humanity? The course to be pursued in reference to this subject is a perfectly plain and natural one. Let
each thinker pursue his own path; if he shows talent, if be gives evidence of profound thought, in one word, if
he shows that he possesses the power of reasoning reason is always the gainer. If you have recourse to other
means, if you attempt to coerce reason, if you raise the cry of treason to humanity, if you excite the feelings
of the crowd, which can neither understand nor sympathize with such subtle speculations you will only
make yourselves ridiculous. For the question does not concern the advantage or disadvantage which we are
expected to reap from such inquiries; the question is merely how far reason can advance in the field of
speculation, apart from all kinds of interest, and whether we may depend upon the exertions of speculative
reason, or must renounce all reliance on it. Instead of joining the combatants, it is your part to be a tranquil
spectator of the struggle a laborious struggle for the parties engaged, but attended, in its progress as well as
in its result, with the most advantageous consequences for the interests of thought and knowledge. It is absurd
to expect to be enlightened by Reason, and at the same time to prescribe to her what side of the question she
must adopt. Moreover, reason is sufficiently held in check by its own power, the limits imposed on it by its
own nature are sufficient; it is unnecessary for you to place over it additional guards, as if its power were
dangerous to the constitution of the intellectual state. In the dialectic of reason there is no victory gained
which need in the least disturb your tranquility.
The strife of dialectic is a necessity of reason, and we cannot but wish that it had been conducted long ere this
with that perfect freedom which ought to be its essential condition. In this case, we should have had at an
earlier period a matured and profound criticism, which must have put an end to all dialectical disputes, by
exposing the illusions and prejudices in which they originated.
There is in human nature an unworthy propensity a propensity which, like everything that springs from
nature, must in its final purpose be conducive to the good of humanity to conceal our real sentiments, and to
give expression only to certain received opinions, which are regarded as at once safe and promotive of the
common good. It is true, this tendency, not only to conceal our real sentiments, but to profess those which
may gain us favour in the eyes of society, has not only civilized, but, in a certain measure, moralized us; as no
one can break through the outward covering of respectability, honour, and morality, and thus the
seeminglygood examples which we which we see around us form an excellent school for moral
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 241
Page No 246
improvement, so long as our belief in their genuineness remains unshaken. But this disposition to represent
ourselves as better than we are, and to utter opinions which are not our own, can be nothing more than a kind
of provisionary arrangement of nature to lead us from the rudeness of an uncivilized state, and to teach us
how to assume at least the appearance and manner of the good we see. But when true principles have been
developed, and have obtained a sure foundation in our habit of thought, this conventionalism must be
attacked with earnest vigour, otherwise it corrupts the heart, and checks the growth of good dispositions with
the mischievous weed of air appearances.
I am sorry to remark the same tendency to misrepresentation and hypocrisy in the sphere of speculative
discussion, where there is less temptation to restrain the free expression of thought. For what can be more
prejudicial to the interests of intelligence than to falsify our real sentiments, to conceal the doubts which we
feel in regard to our statements, or to maintain the validity of grounds of proof which we well know to be
insufficient? So long as mere personal vanity is the source of these unworthy artifices and this is generally
the case in speculative discussions, which are mostly destitute of practical interest, and are incapable of
complete demonstration the vanity of the opposite party exaggerates as much on the other side; and thus the
result is the same, although it is not brought about so soon as if the dispute had been conducted in a sincere
and upright spirit. But where the mass entertains the notion that the aim of certain subtle speculators is
nothing less than to shake the very foundations of public welfare and morality it seems not only prudent, but
even praise worthy, to maintain the good cause by illusory arguments, rather than to give to our supposed
opponents the advantage of lowering our declarations to the moderate tone of a merely practical conviction,
and of compelling us to confess our inability to attain to apodeictic certainty in speculative subjects. But we
ought to reflect that there is nothing, in the world more fatal to the maintenance of a good cause than deceit,
misrepresentation, and falsehood. That the strictest laws of honesty should be observed in the discussion of a
purely speculative subject is the least requirement that can be made. If we could reckon with security even
upon so little, the conflict of speculative reason regarding the important questions of God, immortality, and
freedom, would have been either decided long ago, or would very soon be brought to a conclusion. But, in
general, the uprightness of the defence stands in an inverse ratio to the goodness of the cause; and perhaps
more honesty and fairness are shown by those who deny than by those who uphold these doctrines.
I shall persuade myself, then, that I have readers who do not wish to see a righteous cause defended by unfair
arguments. Such will now recognize the fact that, according to the principles of this Critique, if we consider
not what is, but what ought to be the case, there can be really no polemic of pure reason. For how can two
persons dispute about a thing, the reality of which neither can present in actual or even in possible
experience? Each adopts the plan of meditating on his idea for the purpose of drawing from the idea, if he
can, what is more than the idea, that is, the reality of the object which it indicates. How shall they settle the
dispute, since neither is able to make his assertions directly comprehensible and certain, but must restrict
himself to attacking and confuting those of his opponent? All statements enounced by pure reason transcend
the conditions of possible experience, beyond the sphere of which we can discover no criterion of truth, while
they are at the same time framed in accordance with the laws of the understanding, which are applicable only
to experience; and thus it is the fate of all such speculative discussions that while the one party attacks the
weaker side of his opponent, he infallibly lays open his own weaknesses.
The critique of pure reason may be regarded as the highest tribunal for all speculative disputes; for it is not
involved in these disputes, which have an immediate relation to certain objects and not to the laws of the
mind, but is instituted for the purpose of determining the rights and limits of reason.
Without the control of criticism, reason is, as it were, in a state of nature, and can only establish its claims and
assertions by war. Criticism, on the contrary, deciding all questions according to the fundamental laws of its
own institution, secures to us the peace of law and order, and enables us to discuss all differences in the more
tranquil manner of a legal process. In the former case, disputes are ended by victory, which both sides may
claim and which is followed by a hollow armistice; in the latter, by a sentence, which, as it strikes at the root
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 242
Page No 247
of all speculative differences, ensures to all concerned a lasting peace. The endless disputes of a dogmatizing
reason compel us to look for some mode of arriving at a settled decision by a critical investigation of reason
itself; just as Hobbes maintains that the state of nature is a state of injustice and violence, and that we must
leave it and submit ourselves to the constraint of law, which indeed limits individual freedom, but only that it
may consist with the freedom of others and with the common good of all.
This freedom will, among other things, permit of our openly stating the difficulties and doubts which we are
ourselves unable to solve, without being decried on that account as turbulent and dangerous citizens. This
privilege forms part of the native rights of human reason, which recognizes no other judge than the universal
reason of humanity; and as this reason is the source of all progress and improvement, such a privilege is to be
held sacred and inviolable. It is unwise, moreover, to denounce as dangerous any bold assertions against, or
rash attacks upon, an opinion which is held by the largest and most moral class of the community; for that
would be giving them an importance which they do not deserve. When I hear that the freedom of the will, the
hope of a future life, and the existence of God have been overthrown by the arguments of some able writer, I
feel a strong desire to read his book; for I expect that he will add to my knowledge and impart greater
clearness and distinctness to my views by the argumentative power shown in his writings. But I am perfectly
certain, even before I have opened the book, that he has not succeeded in a single point, not because I believe
I am in possession of irrefutable demonstrations of these important propositions, but because this
transcendental critique, which has disclosed to me the power and the limits of pure reason, has fully
convinced me that, as it is insufficient to establish the affirmative, it is as powerless, and even more so, to
assure us of the truth of the negative answer to these questions. From what source does this freethinker
derive his knowledge that there is, for example, no Supreme Being? This proposition lies out of the field of
possible experience, and, therefore, beyond the limits of human cognition. But I would not read at, all the
answer which the dogmatical maintainer of the good cause makes to his opponent, because I know well
beforehand, that he will merely attack the fallacious grounds of his adversary, without being able to establish
his own assertions. Besides, a new illusory argument, in the construction of which talent and acuteness are
shown, is suggestive of new ideas and new trains of reasoning, and in this respect the old and everyday
sophistries are quite useless. Again, the dogmatical opponent of religion gives employment to criticism, and
enables us to test and correct its principles, while there is no occasion for anxiety in regard to the influence
and results of his reasoning.
But, it will be said, must we not warn the youth entrusted to academical care against such writings, must we
not preserve them from the knowledge of these dangerous assertions, until their judgement is ripened, or
rather until the doctrines which we wish to inculcate are so firmly rooted in their minds as to withstand all
attempts at instilling the contrary dogmas, from whatever quarter they may come?
If we are to confine ourselves to the dogmatical procedure in the sphere of pure reason, and find ourselves
unable to settle such disputes otherwise than by becoming a party in them, and setting counterassertions
against the statements advanced by our opponents, there is certainly no plan more advisable for the moment,
but, at the same time, none more absurd and inefficient for the future, than this retaining of the youthful mind
under guardianship for a time, and thus preserving it for so long at least from seduction into error. But
when, at a later period, either curiosity, or the prevalent fashion of thought places such writings in their
hands, will the socalled convictions of their youth stand firm? The young thinker, who has in his armoury
none but dogmatical weapons with which to resist the attacks of his opponent, and who cannot detect the
latent dialectic which lies in his own opinions as well as in those of the opposite party, sees the advance of
illusory arguments and grounds of proof which have the advantage of novelty, against as illusory grounds of
proof destitute of this advantage, and which, perhaps, excite the suspicion that the natural credulity of his
youth has been abused by his instructors. He thinks he can find no better means of showing that he has out
grown the discipline of his minority than by despising those wellmeant warnings, and, knowing no system
of thought but that of dogmatism, he drinks deep draughts of the poison that is to sap the principles in which
his early years were trained.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 243
Page No 248
Exactly the opposite of the system here recommended ought to be pursued in academical instruction. This can
only be effected, however, by a thorough training in the critical investigation of pure reason. For, in order to
bring the principles of this critique into exercise as soon as possible, and to demonstrate their perfect even in
the presence of the highest degree of dialectical illusion, the student ought to examine the assertions made on
both sides of speculative questions step by step, and to test them by these principles. It cannot be a difficult
task for him to show the fallacies inherent in these propositions, and thus he begins early to feel his own
power of securing himself against the influence of such sophistical arguments, which must finally lose, for
him, all their illusory power. And, although the same blows which overturn the edifice of his opponent are as
fatal to his own speculative structures, if such he has wished to rear; he need not feel any sorrow in regard to
this seeming misfortune, as he has now before him a fair prospect into the practical region in which he may
reasonably hope to find a more secure foundation for a rational system.
There is, accordingly, no proper polemic in the sphere of pure reason. Both parties beat the air and fight with
their own shadows, as they pass beyond the limits of nature, and can find no tangible point of attack no firm
footing for their dogmatical conflict. Fight as vigorously as they may, the shadows which they hew down,
immediately start up again, like the heroes in Walhalla, and renew the bloodless and unceasing contest.
But neither can we admit that there is any proper sceptical employment of pure reason, such as might be
based upon the principle of neutrality in all speculative disputes. To excite reason against itself, to place
weapons in the hands of the party on the one side as well as in those of the other, and to remain an
undisturbed and sarcastic spectator of the fierce struggle that ensues, seems, from the dogmatical point of
view, to be a part fitting only a malevolent disposition. But, when the sophist evidences an invincible
obstinacy and blindness, and a pride which no criticism can moderate, there is no other practicable course
than to oppose to this pride and obstinacy similar feelings and pretensions on the other side, equally well or
ill founded, so that reason, staggered by the reflections thus forced upon it, finds it necessary to moderate its
confidence in such pretensions and to listen to the advice of criticism. But we cannot stop at these doubts,
much less regard the conviction of our ignorance, not only as a cure for the conceit natural to dogmatism, but
as the settlement of the disputes in which reason is involved with itself. On the contrary, scepticism is merely
a means of awakening reason from its dogmatic dreams and exciting it to a more careful investigation into its
own powers and pretensions. But, as scepticism appears to be the shortest road to a permanent peace in the
domain of philosophy, and as it is the track pursued by the many who aim at giving a philosophical colouring
to their contemptuous dislike of all inquiries of this kind, I think it necessary to present to my readers this
mode of thought in its true light.
Scepticism not a Permanent State for Human Reason.
The consciousness of ignorance unless this ignorance is recognized to be absolutely necessary ought,
instead of forming the conclusion of my inquiries, to be the strongest motive to the pursuit of them. All
ignorance is either ignorance of things or of the limits of knowledge. If my ignorance is accidental and not
necessary, it must incite me, in the first case, to a dogmatical inquiry regarding the objects of which I am
ignorant; in the second, to a critical investigation into the bounds of all possible knowledge. But that my
ignorance is absolutely necessary and unavoidable, and that it consequently absolves from the duty of all
further investigation, is a fact which cannot be made out upon empirical grounds from observation but
upon critical grounds alone, that is, by a thoroughgoing investigation into the primary sources of cognition. It
follows that the determination of the bounds of reason can be made only on a priori grounds; while the
empirical limitation of reason, which is merely an indeterminate cognition of an ignorance that can never be
completely removed, can take place only a posteriori. In other words, our empirical knowledge is limited by
that which yet remains for us to know. The former cognition of our ignorance, which is possible only on a
rational basis, is a science; the latter is merely a perception, and we cannot say how far the inferences drawn
from it may extend. If I regard the earth, as it really appears to my senses, as a flat surface, I am ignorant how
far this surface extends. But experience teaches me that, how far soever I go, I always see before me a space
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 244
Page No 249
in which I can proceed farther; and thus I know the limits merely visual of my actual knowledge of the
earth, although I am ignorant of the limits of the earth itself. But if I have got so far as to know that the earth
is a sphere, and that its surface is spherical, I can cognize a priori and determine upon principles, from my
knowledge of a small part of this surface say to the extent of a degree the diameter and circumference of
the earth; and although I am ignorant of the objects which this surface contains, I have a perfect knowledge of
its limits and extent.
The sum of all the possible objects of our cognition seems to us to be a level surface, with an apparent
horizon that which forms the limit of its extent, and which has been termed by us the idea of unconditioned
totality. To reach this limit by empirical means is impossible, and all attempts to determine it a priori
according to a principle, are alike in vain. But all the questions raised by pure reason relate to that which lies
beyond this horizon, or, at least, in its boundary line.
The celebrated David Hume was one of those geographers of human reason who believe that they have given
a sufficient answer to all such questions by declaring them to lie beyond the horizon of our knowledge a
horizon which, however, Hume was unable to determine. His attention especially was directed to the
principle of causality; and he remarked with perfect justice that the truth of this principle, and even the
objective validity of the conception of a cause, was not commonly based upon clear insight, that is, upon a
priori cognition. Hence he concluded that this law does not derive its authority from its universality and
necessity, but merely from its general applicability in the course of experience, and a kind of subjective
necessity thence arising, which he termed habit. From the inability of reason to establish this principle as a
necessary law for the acquisition of all experience, he inferred the nullity of all the attempts of reason to pass
the region of the empirical.
This procedure of subjecting the facta of reason to examination, and, if necessary, to disapproval, may be
termed the censura of reason. This censura must inevitably lead us to doubts regarding all transcendent
employment of principles. But this is only the second step in our inquiry. The first step in regard to the
subjects of pure reason, and which marks the infancy of that faculty, is that of dogmatism. The second, which
we have just mentioned, is that of scepticism, and it gives evidence that our judgement has been improved by
experience. But a third step is necessary indicative of the maturity and manhood of the judgement, which
now lays a firm foundation upon universal and necessary principles. This is the period of criticism, in which
we do not examine the facta of reason, but reason itself, in the whole extent of its powers, and in regard to its
capability of a priori cognition; and thus we determine not merely the empirical and evershifting bounds of
our knowledge, but its necessary and eternal limits. We demonstrate from indubitable principles, not merely
our ignorance in respect to this or that subject, but in regard to all possible questions of a certain class. Thus
scepticism is a resting place for reason, in which it may reflect on its dogmatical wanderings and gain some
knowledge of the region in which it happens to be, that it may pursue its way with greater certainty; but it
cannot be its permanent dwellingplace. It must take up its abode only in the region of complete certitude,
whether this relates to the cognition of objects themselves, or to the limits which bound all our cognition.
Reason is not to be considered as an indefinitely extended plane, of the bounds of which we have only a
general knowledge; it ought rather to be compared to a sphere, the radius of which may be found from the
curvature of its surface that is, the nature of a priori synthetical propositions and, consequently, its
circumference and extent. Beyond the sphere of experience there are no objects which it can cognize; nay,
even questions regarding such supposititious objects relate only to the subjective principles of a complete
determination of the relations which exist between the understandingconceptions which lie within this
sphere.
We are actually in possession of a priori synthetical cognitions, as is proved by the existence of the principles
of the understanding, which anticipate experience. If any one cannot comprehend the possibility of these
principles, he may have some reason to doubt whether they are really a priori; but he cannot on this account
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 245
Page No 250
declare them to be impossible, and affirm the nullity of the steps which reason may have taken under their
guidance. He can only say: If we perceived their origin and their authenticity, we should be able to determine
the extent and limits of reason; but, till we can do this, all propositions regarding the latter are mere random
assertions. In this view, the doubt respecting all dogmatical philosophy, which proceeds without the guidance
of criticism, is well grounded; but we cannot therefore deny to reason the ability to construct a sound
philosophy, when the way has been prepared by a thorough critical investigation. All the conceptions
produced, and all the questions raised, by pure reason, do not lie in the sphere of experience, but in that of
reason itself, and hence they must be solved, and shown to be either valid or inadmissible, by that faculty. We
have no right to decline the solution of such problems, on the ground that the solution can be discovered only
from the nature of things, and under pretence of the limitation of human faculties, for reason is the sole
creator of all these ideas, and is therefore bound either to establish their validity or to expose their illusory
nature.
The polemic of scepticism is properly directed against the dogmatist, who erects a system of philosophy
without having examined the fundamental objective principles on which it is based, for the purpose of
evidencing the futility of his designs, and thus bringing him to a knowledge of his own powers. But, in itself,
scepticism does not give us any certain information in regard to the bounds of our knowledge. All
unsuccessful dogmatical attempts of reason are facia, which it is always useful to submit to the censure of the
sceptic. But this cannot help us to any decision regarding the expectations which reason cherishes of better
success in future endeavours; the investigations of scepticism cannot, therefore, settle the dispute regarding
the rights and powers of human reason.
Hume is perhaps the ablest and most ingenious of all sceptical philosophers, and his writings have,
undoubtedly, exerted the most powerful influence in awakening reason to a thorough investigation into its
own powers. It will, therefore, well repay our labours to consider for a little the course of reasoning which he
followed and the errors into which he strayed, although setting out on the path of truth and certitude.
Hume was probably aware, although he never clearly developed the notion, that we proceed in judgements of
a certain class beyond our conception if the object. I have termed this kind of judgement synthetical. As
regard the manner in which I pass beyond my conception by the aid of experience, no doubts can be
entertained. Experience is itself a synthesis of perceptions; and it employs perceptions to increment the
conception, which I obtain by means of another perception. But we feel persuaded that we are able to proceed
beyond a conception, and to extend our cognition a priori. We attempt this in two ways either, through the
pure understanding, in relation to that which may become an object of experience, or, through pure reason, in
relation to such properties of things, or of the existence of things, as can never be presented in any
experience. This sceptical philosopher did not distinguish these two kinds of judgements, as he ought to have
done, but regarded this augmentation of conceptions, and, if we may so express ourselves, the spontaneous
generation of understanding and reason, independently of the impregnation of experience, as altogether
impossible. The socalled a priori principles of these faculties he consequently held to be invalid and
imaginary, and regarded them as nothing but subjective habits of thought originating in experience, and
therefore purely empirical and contingent rules, to which we attribute a spurious necessity and universality. In
support of this strange assertion, he referred us to the generally acknowledged principle of the relation
between cause and effect. No faculty of the mind can conduct us from the conception of a thing to the
existence of something else; and hence he believed he could infer that, without experience, we possess no
source from which we can augment a conception, and no ground sufficient to justify us in framing a
judgement that is to extend our cognition a priori. That the light of the sun, which shines upon a piece of wax,
at the same time melts it, while it hardens clay, no power of the understanding could infer from the
conceptions which we previously possessed of these substances; much less is there any a priori law that could
conduct us to such a conclusion, which experience alone can certify. On the other hand, we have seen in our
discussion of transcendental logic, that, although we can never proceed immediately beyond the content of
the conception which is given us, we can always cognize completely a priori in relation, however, to a third
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 246
Page No 251
term, namely, possible experience the law of its connection with other things. For example, if I observe that
a piece of wax melts, I can cognize a priori that there must have been something (the sun's heat) preceding,
which this law; although, without the aid of experience, I could not cognize a priori and in a determinate
manner either the cause from the effect, or the effect from the cause. Hume was, therefore, wrong in
inferring, from the contingency of the determination according to law, the contingency of the law itself; and
the passing beyond the conception of a thing to possible experience (which is an a priori proceeding,
constituting the objective reality of the conception), he confounded with our synthesis of objects in actual
experience, which is always, of course, empirical. Thus, too, he regarded the principle of affinity, which has
its seat in the understanding and indicates a necessary connection, as a mere rule of association, lying in the
imitative faculty of imagination, which can present only contingent, and not objective connections.
The sceptical errors of this remarkably acute thinker arose principally from a defect, which was common to
him with the dogmatists, namely, that he had never made a systematic review of all the different kinds of a
priori synthesis performed by the understanding. Had he done so, he would have found, to take one example
among many, that the principle of permanence was of this character, and that it, as well as the principle of
causality, anticipates experience. In this way he might have been able to describe the determinate limits of the
a priori operations of understanding and reason. But he merely declared the understanding to be limited,
instead of showing what its limits were; he created a general mistrust in the power of our faculties, without
giving us any determinate knowledge of the bounds of our necessary and unavoidable ignorance; he
examined and condemned some of the principles of the understanding, without investigating all its powers
with the completeness necessary to criticism. He denies, with truth, certain powers to the understanding, but
he goes further, and declares it to be utterly inadequate to the a priori extension of knowledge, although he
has not fully examined all the powers which reside in the faculty; and thus the fate which always overtakes
scepticism meets him too. That is to say, his own declarations are doubted, for his objections were based
upon facta, which are contingent, and not upon principles, which can alone demonstrate the necessary
invalidity of all dogmatical assertions.
As Hume makes no distinction between the wellgrounded claims of the understanding and the dialectical
pretensions of reason, against which, however, his attacks are mainly directed, reason does not feel itself shut
out from all attempts at the extension of a priori cognition, and hence it refuses, in spite of a few checks in
this or that quarter, to relinquish such efforts. For one naturally arms oneself to resist an attack, and becomes
more obstinate in the resolve to establish the claims he has advanced. But a complete review of the powers of
reason, and the conviction thence arising that we are in possession of a limited field of action, while we must
admit the vanity of higher claims, puts an end to all doubt and dispute, and induces reason to rest satisfied
with the undisturbed possession of its limited domain.
To the uncritical dogmatist, who has not surveyed the sphere of his understanding, nor determined, in
accordance with principles, the limits of possible cognition, who, consequently, is ignorant of his own
powers, and believes he will discover them by the attempts he makes in the field of cognition, these attacks of
scepticism are not only dangerous, but destructive. For if there is one proposition in his chain of reasoning
which be he cannot prove, or the fallacy in which be cannot evolve in accordance with a principle, suspicion
falls on all his statements, however plausible they may appear.
And thus scepticism, the bane of dogmatical philosophy, conducts us to a sound investigation into the
understanding and the reason. When we are thus far advanced, we need fear no further attacks; for the limits
of our domain are clearly marked out, and we can make no claims nor become involved in any disputes
regarding the region that lies beyond these limits. Thus the sceptical procedure in philosophy does not present
any solution of the problems of reason, but it forms an excellent exercise for its powers, awakening its
circumspection, and indicating the means whereby it may most fully establish its claims to its legitimate
possessions.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics. 247
Page No 252
SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis.
This critique of reason has now taught us that all its efforts to extend the bounds of knowledge, by means of
pure speculation, are utterly fruitless. So much the wider field, it may appear, lies open to hypothesis; as,
where we cannot know with certainty, we are at liberty to make guesses and to form suppositions.
Imagination may be allowed, under the strict surveillance of reason, to invent suppositions; but, these must be
based on something that is perfectly certain and that is the possibility of the object. If we are well assured
upon this point, it is allowable to have recourse to supposition in regard to the reality of the object; but this
supposition must, unless it is utterly groundless, be connected, as its ground of explanation, with that which is
really given and absolutely certain. Such a supposition is termed a hypothesis.
It is beyond our power to form the least conception a priori of the possibility of dynamical connection in
phenomena; and the category of the pure understanding will not enable us to ex. cogitate any such
connection, but merely helps us to understand it, when we meet with it in experience. For this reason we
cannot, in accordance with the categories, imagine or invent any object or any property of an object not
given, or that may not be given in experience, and employ it in a hypothesis; otherwise, we should be basing
our chain of reasoning upon mere chimerical fancies, and not upon conceptions of things. Thus, we have no
right to assume the existence of new powers, not existing in nature for example, an understanding with a
nonsensuous intuition, a force of attraction without contact, or some new kind of substances occupying
space, and yet without the property of impenetrability and, consequently, we cannot assume that there is any
other kind of community among substances than that observable in experience, any kind of presence than that
in space, or any kind of duration than that in time. In one word, the conditions of possible experience are for
reason the only conditions of the possibility of things; reason cannot venture to form, independently of these
conditions, any conceptions of things, because such conceptions, although not selfcontradictory, are without
object and without application.
The conceptions of reason are, as we have already shown, mere ideas, and do not relate to any object in any
kind of experience. At the same time, they do not indicate imaginary or possible objects. They are purely
problematical in their nature and, as aids to the heuristic exercise of the faculties, form the basis of the
regulative principles for the systematic employment of the understanding in the field of experience. If we
leave this ground of experience, they become mere fictions of thought, the possibility of which is quite
indemonstrable; and they cannot, consequently, be employed as hypotheses in the explanation of real
phenomena. It is quite admissible to cogitate the soul as simple, for the purpose of enabling ourselves to
employ the idea of a perfect and necessary unity of all the faculties of the mind as the principle of all our
inquiries into its internal phenomena, although we cannot cognize this unity in concreto. But to assume that
the soul is a simple substance (a transcendental conception) would be enouncing a proposition which is not
only indemonstrable as many physical hypotheses are but a proposition which is purely arbitrary, and in
the highest degree rash. The simple is never presented in experience; and, if by substance is here meant the
permanent object of sensuous intuition, the possibility of a simple phenomenon is perfectly inconceivable.
Reason affords no good grounds for admitting the existence of intelligible beings, or of intelligible properties
of sensuous things, although as we have no conception either of their possibility or of their impossibility it
will always be out of our power to affirm dogmatically that they do not exist. In the explanation of given
phenomena, no other things and no other grounds of explanation can be employed than those which stand in
connection with the given phenomena according to the known laws of experience. A transcendental
hypothesis, in which a mere idea of reason is employed to explain the phenomena of nature, would not give
us any better insight into a phenomenon, as we should be trying to explain what we do not sufficiently
understand from known empirical principles, by what we do not understand at all. The principles of such a
hypothesis might conduce to the satisfaction of reason, but it would not assist the understanding in its
application to objects. Order and conformity to aims in the sphere of nature must be themselves explained
upon natural grounds and according to natural laws; and the wildest hypotheses, if they are only physical, are
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis. 248
Page No 253
here more admissible than a hyperphysical hypothesis, such as that of a divine author. For such a hypothesis
would introduce the principle of ignava ratio, which requires us to give up the search for causes that might be
discovered in the course of experience and to rest satisfied with a mere idea. As regards the absolute totality
of the grounds of explanation in the series of these causes, this can be no hindrance to the understanding in
the case of phenomena; because, as they are to us nothing more than phenomena, we have no right to look for
anything like completeness in the synthesis of the series of their conditions.
Transcendental hypotheses are therefore inadmissible; and we cannot use the liberty of employing, in the
absence of physical, hyperphysical grounds of explanation. And this for two reasons; first, because such
hypothesis do not advance reason, but rather stop it in its progress; secondly, because this licence would
render fruitless all its exertions in its own proper sphere, which is that of experience. For, when the
explanation of natural phenomena happens to be difficult, we have constantly at hand a transcendental ground
of explanation, which lifts us above the necessity of investigating nature; and our inquiries are brought to a
close, not because we have obtained all the requisite knowledge, but because we abut upon a principle which
is incomprehensible and which, indeed, is so far back in the track of thought as to contain the conception of
the absolutely primal being.
The next requisite for the admissibility of a hypothesis is its sufficiency. That is, it must determine a priori
the consequences which are given in experience and which are supposed to follow from the hypothesis itself.
If we require to employ auxiliary hypotheses, the suspicion naturally arises that they are mere fictions;
because the necessity for each of them requires the same justification as in the case of the original hypothesis,
and thus their testimony is invalid. If we suppose the existence of an infinitely perfect cause, we possess
sufficient grounds for the explanation of the conformity to aims, the order and the greatness which we
observe in the universe; but we find ourselves obliged, when we observe the evil in the world and the
exceptions to these laws, to employ new hypothesis in support of the original one. We employ the idea of the
simple nature of the human soul as the foundation of all the theories we may form of its phenomena; but
when we meet with difficulties in our way, when we observe in the soul phenomena similar to the changes
which take place in matter, we require to call in new auxiliary hypotheses. These may, indeed, not be false,
but we do not know them to be true, because the only witness to their certitude is the hypothesis which they
themselves have been called in to explain.
We are not discussing the abovementioned assertions regarding the immaterial unity of the soul and the
existence of a Supreme Being as dogmata, which certain philosophers profess to demonstrate a priori, but
purely as hypotheses. In the former case, the dogmatist must take care that his arguments possess the
apodeictic certainty of a demonstration. For the assertion that the reality of such ideas is probable is as absurd
as a proof of the probability of a proposition in geometry. Pure abstract reason, apart from all experience, can
either cognize nothing at all; and hence the judgements it enounces are never mere opinions, they are either
apodeictic certainties, or declarations that nothing can be known on the subject. Opinions and probable
judgements on the nature of things can only be employed to explain given phenomena, or they may relate to
the effect, in accordance with empirical laws, of an actually existing cause. In other words, we must restrict
the sphere of opinion to the world of experience and nature. Beyond this region opinion is mere invention;
unless we are groping about for the truth on a path not yet fully known, and have some hopes of stumbling
upon it by chance.
But, although hypotheses are inadmissible in answers to the questions of pure speculative reason, they may
be employed in the defence of these answers. That is to say, hypotheses are admissible in polemic, but not in
the sphere of dogmatism. By the defence of statements of this character, I do not mean an attempt at
discovering new grounds for their support, but merely the refutation of the arguments of opponents. All a
priori synthetical propositions possess the peculiarity that, although the philosopher who maintains the reality
of the ideas contained in the proposition is not in possession of sufficient knowledge to establish the certainty
of his statements, his opponent is as little able to prove the truth of the opposite. This equality of fortune does
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis. 249
Page No 254
not allow the one party to be superior to the other in the sphere of speculative cognition; and it is this sphere,
accordingly, that is the proper arena of these endless speculative conflicts. But we shall afterwards show that,
in relation to its practical exercise, Reason has the right of admitting what, in the field of pure speculation,
she would not be justified in supposing, except upon perfectly sufficient grounds; because all such
suppositions destroy the necessary completeness of speculation a condition which the practical reason,
however, does not consider to be requisite. In this sphere, therefore, Reason is mistress of a possession, her
title to which she does not require to prove which, in fact, she could not do. The burden of proof
accordingly rests upon the opponent. But as he has just as little knowledge regarding the subject discussed,
and is as little able to prove the nonexistence of the object of an idea, as the philosopher on the other side is
to demonstrate its reality, it is evident that there is an advantage on the side of the philosopher who maintains
his proposition as a practically necessary supposition (melior est conditio possidentis). For he is at liberty to
employ, in selfdefence, the same weapons as his opponent makes use of in attacking him; that is, he has a
right to use hypotheses not for the purpose of supporting the arguments in favour of his own propositions, but
to show that his opponent knows no more than himself regarding the subject under 'discussion and cannot
boast of any speculative advantage.
Hypotheses are, therefore, admissible in the sphere of pure reason only as weapons for selfdefence, and not
as supports to dogmatical assertions. But the opposing party we must always seek for in ourselves. For
speculative reason is, in the sphere of transcendentalism, dialectical in its own nature. The difficulties and
objections we have to fear lie in ourselves. They are like old but never superannuated claims; and we must
seek them out, and settle them once and for ever, if we are to expect a permanent peace. External tranquility
is hollow and unreal. The root of these contradictions, which lies in the nature of human reason, must be
destroyed; and this can only be done by giving it, in the first instance, freedom to grow, nay, by nourishing it,
that it may send out shoots, and thus betray its own existence. It is our duty, therefore, to try to discover new
objections, to put weapons in the bands of our opponent, and to grant him the most favourable position in the
arena that he can wish. We have nothing to fear from these concessions; on the contrary, we may rather hope
that we shall thus make ourselves master of a possession which no one will ever venture to dispute.
The thinker requires, to be fully equipped, the hypotheses of pure reason, which, although but leaden
weapons (for they have not been steeled in the armoury of experience), are as useful as any that can be
employed by his opponents. If, accordingly, we have assumed, from a nonspeculative point of view, the
immaterial nature of the soul, and are met by the objection that experience seems to prove that the growth and
decay of our mental faculties are mere modifications of the sensuous organism we can weaken the force of
this objection by the assumption that the body is nothing but the fundamental phenomenon, to which, as a
necessary condition, all sensibility, and consequently all thought, relates in the present state of our existence;
and that the separation of soul and body forms the conclusion of the sensuous exercise of our power of
cognition and the beginning of the intellectual. The body would, in this view of the question, be regarded, not
as the cause of thought, but merely as its restrictive condition, as promotive of the sensuous and animal, but
as a hindrance to the pure and spiritual life; and the dependence of the animal life on the constitution of the
body, would not prove that the whole life of man was also dependent on the state of the organism. We might
go still farther, and discover new objections, or carry out to their extreme consequences those which have
already been adduced.
Generation, in the human race as well as among the irrational animals, depends on so many accidents of
occasion, of proper sustenance, of the laws enacted by the government of a country of vice even, that it is
difficult to believe in the eternal existence of a being whose life has begun under circumstances so mean and
trivial, and so entirely dependent upon our own control. As regards the continuance of the existence of the
whole race, we need have no difficulties, for accident in single cases is subject to general laws; but, in the
case of each individual, it would seem as if we could hardly expect so wonderful an effect from causes so
insignificant. But, in answer to these objections, we may adduce the transcendental hypothesis that all life is
properly intelligible, and not subject to changes of time, and that it neither began in birth, nor will end in
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis. 250
Page No 255
death. We may assume that this life is nothing more than a sensuous representation of pure spiritual life; that
the whole world of sense is but an image, hovering before the faculty of cognition which we exercise in this
sphere, and with no more objective reality than a dream; and that if we could intuite ourselves and other
things as they really are, we should see ourselves in a world of spiritual natures, our connection with which
did not begin at our birth and will not cease with the destruction of the body. And so on.
We cannot be said to know what has been above asserted, nor do we seriously maintain the truth of these
assertions; and the notions therein indicated are not even ideas of reason, they are purely fictitious
conceptions. But this hypothetical procedure is in perfect conformity with the laws of reason. Our opponent
mistakes the absence of empirical conditions for a proof of the complete impossibility of all that we have
asserted; and we have to show him that be has not exhausted the whole sphere of possibility and that he can
as little compass that sphere by the laws of experience and nature, as we can lay a secure foundation for the
operations of reason beyond the region of experience. Such hypothetical defences against the pretensions of
an opponent must not be regarded as declarations of opinion. The philosopher abandons them, so soon as the
opposite party renounces its dogmatical conceit. To maintain a simply negative position in relation to
propositions which rest on an insecure foundation, well befits the moderation of a true philosopher; but to
uphold the objections urged against an opponent as proofs of the opposite statement is a proceeding just as
unwarrantable and arrogant as it is to attack the position of a philosopher who advances affirmative
propositions regarding such a subject.
It is evident, therefore, that hypotheses, in the speculative sphere, are valid, not as independent propositions,
but only relatively to opposite transcendent assumptions. For, to make the principles of possible experience
conditions of the possibility of things in general is just as transcendent a procedure as to maintain the
objective reality of ideas which can be applied to no objects except such as lie without the limits of possible
experience. The judgements enounced by pure reason must be necessary, or they must not be enounced at all.
Reason cannot trouble herself with opinions. But the hypotheses we have been discussing are merely
problematical judgements, which can neither be confuted nor proved; while, therefore, they are not personal
opinions, they are indispensable as answers to objections which are liable to be raised. But we must take care
to confine them to this function, and guard against any assumption on their part of absolute validity, a
proceeding which would involve reason in inextricable difficulties and contradictions.
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs.
It is a peculiarity, which distinguishes the proofs of transcendental synthetical propositions from those of all
other a priori synthetical cognitions, that reason, in the case of the former, does not apply its conceptions
directly to an object, but is first obliged to prove, a priori, the objective validity of these conceptions and the
possibility of their syntheses. This is not merely a prudential rule, it is essential to the very possibility of the
proof of a transcendental proposition. If I am required to pass, a priori, beyond the conception of an object, I
find that it is utterly impossible without the guidance of something which is not contained in the conception.
In mathematics, it is a priori intuition that guides my synthesis; and, in this case, all our conclusions may be
drawn immediately from pure intuition. In transcendental cognition, so long as we are dealing only with
conceptions of the understanding, we are guided by possible experience. That is to say, a proof in the sphere
of transcendental cognition does not show that the given conception (that of an event, for example) leads
directly to another conception (that of a cause) for this would be a saltus which nothing can justify; but it
shows that experience itself, and consequently the object of experience, is impossible without the connection
indicated by these conceptions. It follows that such a proof must demonstrate the possibility of arriving,
synthetically and a priori, at a certain knowledge of things, which was not contained in our conceptions of
these things. Unless we pay particular attention to this requirement, our proofs, instead of pursuing the
straight path indicated by reason, follow the tortuous road of mere subjective association. The illusory
conviction, which rests upon subjective causes of association, and which is considered as resulting from the
perception of a real and objective natural affinity, is always open to doubt and suspicion. For this reason, all
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs. 251
Page No 256
the attempts which have been made to prove the principle of sufficient reason, have, according to the
universal admission of philosophers, been quite unsuccessful; and, before the appearance of transcendental
criticism, it was considered better, as this principle could not be abandoned, to appeal boldly to the common
sense of mankind (a proceeding which always proves that the problem, which reason ought to solve, is one in
which philosophers find great difficulties), rather than attempt to discover new dogmatical proofs.
But, if the proposition to be proved is a proposition of pure reason, and if I aim at passing beyond my
empirical conceptions by the aid of mere ideas, it is necessary that the proof should first show that such a step
in synthesis is possible (which it is not), before it proceeds to prove the truth of the proposition itself. The
socalled proof of the simple nature of the soul from the unity of apperception, is a very plausible one. But it
contains no answer to the objection, that, as the notion of absolute simplicity is not a conception which is
directly applicable to a perception, but is an idea which must be inferred if at all from observation, it is by
no means evident how the mere fact of consciousness, which is contained in all thought, although in so far a
simple representation, can conduct me to the consciousness and cognition of a thing which is purely a
thinking substance. When I represent to my mind the power of my body as in motion, my body in this
thought is so far absolute unity, and my representation of it is a simple one; and hence I can indicate this
representation by the motion of a point, because I have made abstraction of the size or volume of the body.
But I cannot hence infer that, given merely the moving power of a body, the body may be cogitated as simple
substance, merely because the representation in my mind takes no account of its content in space, and is
consequently simple. The simple, in abstraction, is very different from the objectively simple; and hence the
Ego, which is simple in the first sense, may, in the second sense, as indicating the soul itself, be a very
complex conception, with a very various content. Thus it is evident that in all such arguments there lurks a
paralogism. We guess (for without some such surmise our suspicion would not be excited in reference to a
proof of this character) at the presence of the paralogism, by keeping ever before us a criterion of the
possibility of those synthetical propositions which aim at proving more than experience can teach us. This
criterion is obtained from the observation that such proofs do not lead us directly from the subject of the
proposition to be proved to the required predicate, but find it necessary to presuppose the possibility of
extending our cognition a priori by means of ideas. We must, accordingly, always use the greatest caution;
we require, before attempting any proof, to consider how it is possible to extend the sphere of cognition by
the operations of pure reason, and from what source we are to derive knowledge, which is not obtained from
the analysis of conceptions, nor relates, by anticipation, to possible experience. We shall thus spare ourselves
much severe and fruitless labour, by not expecting from reason what is beyond its power, or rather by
subjecting it to discipline, and teaching it to moderate its vehement desires for the extension of the sphere of
cognition.
The first rule for our guidance is, therefore, not to attempt a transcendental proof, before we have considered
from what source we are to derive the principles upon which the proof is to be based, and what right we have
to expect that our conclusions from these principles will be veracious. If they are principles of the
understanding, it is vain to expect that we should attain by their means to ideas of pure reason; for these
principles are valid only in regard to objects of possible experience. If they are principles of pure reason, our
labour is alike in vain. For the principles of reason, if employed as objective, are without exception dialectical
and possess no validity or truth, except as regulative principles of the systematic employment of reason in
experience. But when such delusive proof are presented to us, it is our duty to meet them with the non liquet
of a matured judgement; and, although we are unable to expose the particular sophism upon which the proof
is based, we have a right to demand a deduction of the principles employed in it; and, if these principles have
their origin in pure reason alone, such a deduction is absolutely impossible. And thus it is unnecessary that
we should trouble ourselves with the exposure and confutation of every sophistical illusion; we may, at once,
bring all dialectic, which is inexhaustible in the production of fallacies, before the bar of critical reason,
which tests the principles upon which all dialectical procedure is based. The second peculiarity of
transcendental proof is that a transcendental proposition cannot rest upon more than a single proof. If I am
drawing conclusions, not from conceptions, but from intuition corresponding to a conception, be it pure
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs. 252
Page No 257
intuition, as in mathematics, or empirical, as in natural science, the intuition which forms the basis of my
inferences presents me with materials for many synthetical propositions, which I can connect in various
modes, while, as it is allowable to proceed from different points in the intention, I can arrive by different
paths at the same proposition.
But every transcendental proposition sets out from a conception, and posits the synthetical condition of the
possibility of an object according to this conception. There must, therefore, be but one ground of proof,
because it is the conception alone which determines the object; and thus the proof cannot contain anything
more than the determination of the object according to the conception. In our Transcendental Analytic, for
example, we inferred the principle: Every event has a cause, from the only condition of the objective
possibility of our conception of an event. This is that an event cannot be determined in time, and
consequently cannot form a part of experience, unless it stands under this dynamical law. This is the only
possible ground of proof; for our conception of an event possesses objective validity, that is, is a true
conception, only because the law of causality determines an object to which it can refer. Other arguments in
support of this principle have been attempted such as that from the contingent nature of a phenomenon; but
when this argument is considered, we can discover no criterion of contingency, except the fact of an event
of something happening, that is to say, the existence which is preceded by the nonexistence of an object,
and thus we fall back on the very thing to be proved. If the proposition: "Every thinking being is simple," is
to be proved, we keep to the conception of the ego, which is simple, and to which all thought has a relation.
The same is the case with the transcendental proof of the existence of a Deity, which is based solely upon the
harmony and reciprocal fitness of the conceptions of an ens realissimum and a necessary being, and cannot be
attempted in any other manner.
This caution serves to simplify very much the criticism of all propositions of reason. When reason employs
conceptions alone, only one proof of its thesis is possible, if any. When, therefore, the dogmatist advances
with ten arguments in favour of a proposition, we may be sure that not one of them is conclusive. For if he
possessed one which proved the proposition he brings forward to demonstration as must always be the case
with the propositions of pure reason what need is there for any more? His intention can only be similar to
that of the advocate who had different arguments for different judges; this availing himself of the weakness of
those who examine his arguments, who, without going into any profound investigation, adopt the view of the
case which seems most probable at first sight and decide according to it.
The third rule for the guidance of pure reason in the conduct of a proof is that all transcendental proofs must
never be apagogic or indirect, but always ostensive or direct. The direct or ostensive proof not only
establishes the truth of the proposition to be proved, but exposes the grounds of its truth; the apagogic, on the
other hand, may assure us of the truth of the proposition, but it cannot enable us to comprehend the grounds
of its possibility. The latter is, accordingly, rather an auxiliary to an argument, than a strictly philosophical
and rational mode of procedure. In one respect, however, they have an advantage over direct proofs, from the
fact that the mode of arguing by contradiction, which they employ, renders our understanding of the question
more clear, and approximates the proof to the certainty of an intuitional demonstration.
The true reason why indirect proofs are employed in different sciences is this. When the grounds upon which
we seek to base a cognition are too various or too profound, we try whether or not we may not discover the
truth of our cognition from its consequences. The modus ponens of reasoning from the truth of its inferences
to the truth of a proposition would be admissible if all the inferences that can be drawn from it are known to
be true; for in this case there can be only one possible ground for these inferences, and that is the true one.
But this is a quite impracticable procedure, as it surpasses all our powers to discover all the possible
inferences that can be drawn from a proposition. But this mode of reasoning is employed, under favour, when
we wish to prove the truth of an hypothesis; in which case we admit the truth of the conclusion which is
supported by analogy that, if all the inferences we have drawn and examined agree with the proposition
assumed, all other possible inferences will also agree with it. But, in this way, an hypothesis can never be
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs. 253
Page No 258
established as a demonstrated truth. The modus tollens of reasoning from known inferences to the unknown
proposition, is not only a rigorous, but a very easy mode of proof. For, if it can be shown that but one
inference from a proposition is false, then the proposition must itself be false. Instead, then, of examining, in
an ostensive argument, the whole series of the grounds on which the truth of a proposition rests, we need only
take the opposite of this proposition, and if one inference from it be false, then must the opposite be itself
false; and, consequently, the proposition which we wished to prove must be true.
The apagogic method of proof is admissible only in those sciences where it is impossible to mistake a
subjective representation for an objective cognition. Where this is possible, it is plain that the opposite of a
given proposition may contradict merely the subjective conditions of thought, and not the objective
cognition; or it may happen that both propositions contradict each other only under a subjective condition,
which is incorrectly considered to be objective, and, as the condition is itself false, both propositions may be
false, and it will, consequently, be impossible to conclude the truth of the one from the falseness of the other.
In mathematics such subreptions are impossible; and it is in this science, accordingly, that the indirect mode
of proof has its true place. In the science of nature, where all assertion is based upon empirical intuition, such
subreptions may be guarded against by the repeated comparison of observations; but this mode of proof is of
little value in this sphere of knowledge. But the transcendental efforts of pure reason are all made in the
sphere of the subjective, which is the real medium of all dialectical illusion; and thus reason endeavours, in
its premisses, to impose upon us subjective representations for objective cognitions. In the transcendental
sphere of pure reason, then, and in the case of synthetical propositions, it is inadmissible to support a
statement by disproving the counterstatement. For only two cases are possible; either, the counterstatement
is nothing but the enouncement of the inconsistency of the opposite opinion with the subjective conditions of
reason, which does not affect the real case (for example, we cannot comprehend the unconditioned necessity
of the existence of a being, and hence every speculative proof of the existence of such a being must be
opposed on subjective grounds, while the possibility of this being in itself cannot with justice be denied); or,
both propositions, being dialectical in their nature, are based upon an impossible conception. In this latter
case the rule applies: non entis nulla sunt predicata; that is to say, what we affirm and what we deny,
respecting such an object, are equally untrue, and the apagogic mode of arriving at the truth is in this case
impossible. If, for example, we presuppose that the world of sense is given in itself in its totality, it is false,
either that it is infinite, or that it is finite and limited in space. Both are false, because the hypothesis is false.
For the notion of phenomena (as mere representations) which are given in themselves (as objects) is
selfcontradictory; and the infinitude of this imaginary whole would, indeed, be unconditioned, but would be
inconsistent (as everything in the phenomenal world is conditioned) with the unconditioned determination
and finitude of quantities which is presupposed in our conception.
The apagogic mode of proof is the true source of those illusions which have always had so strong an
attraction for the admirers of dogmatical philosophy. It may be compared to a champion who maintains the
honour and claims of the party he has adopted by offering battle to all who doubt the validity of these claims
and the purity of that honour; while nothing can be proved in this way, except the respective strength of the
combatants, and the advantage, in this respect, is always on the side of the attacking party. Spectators,
observing that each party is alternately conqueror and conquered, are led to regard the subject of dispute as
beyond the power of man to decide upon. But such an opinion cannot be justified; and it is sufficient to apply
to these reasoners the remark:
Non defensoribus istis
Tempus eget.
Each must try to establish his assertions by a transcendental deduction of the grounds of proof employed in
his argument, and thus enable us to see in what way the claims of reason may be supported. If an opponent
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs. 254
Page No 259
bases his assertions upon subjective grounds, he may be refuted with ease; not, however to the advantage of
the dogmatist, who likewise depends upon subjective sources of cognition and is in like manner driven into a
corner by his opponent. But, if parties employ the direct method of procedure, they will soon discover the
difficulty, nay, the impossibility of proving their assertions, and will be forced to appeal to prescription and
precedence; or they will, by the help of criticism, discover with ease the dogmatical illusions by which they
had been mocked, and compel reason to renounce its exaggerated pretensions to speculative insight and to
confine itself within the limits of its proper sphere that of practical principles.
CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason.
It is a humiliating consideration for human reason that it is incompetent to discover truth by means of pure
speculation, but, on the contrary, stands in need of discipline to check its deviations from the straight path
and to expose the illusions which it originates. But, on the other hand, this consideration ought to elevate and
to give it confidence, for this discipline is exercised by itself alone, and it is subject to the censure of no other
power. The bounds, moreover, which it is forced to set to its speculative exercise, form likewise a check upon
the fallacious pretensions of opponents; and thus what remains of its possessions, after these exaggerated
claims have been disallowed, is secure from attack or usurpation. The greatest, and perhaps the only, use of
all philosophy of pure reason is, accordingly, of a purely negative character. It is not an organon for the
extension, but a discipline for the determination, of the limits of its exercise; and without laying claim to the
discovery of new truth, it has the modest merit of guarding against error.
At the same time, there must be some source of positive cognitions which belong to the domain of pure
reason and which become the causes of error only from our mistaking their true character, while they form
the goal towards which reason continually strives. How else can we account for the inextinguishable desire in
the human mind to find a firm footing in some region beyond the limits of the world of experience? It hopes
to attain to the possession of a knowledge in which it has the deepest interest. It enters upon the path of pure
speculation; but in vain. We have some reason, however, to expect that, in the only other way that lies open
to it the path of practical reason it may meet with better success.
I understand by a canon a list of the a priori principles of the proper employment of certain faculties of
cognition. Thus general logic, in its analytical department, is a formal canon for the faculties of understanding
and reason. In the same way, Transcendental Analytic was seen to be a canon of the pure understanding; for it
alone is competent to enounce true a priori synthetical cognitions. But, when no proper employment of a
faculty of cognition is possible, no canon can exist. But the synthetical cognition of pure speculative reason
is, as has been shown, completely impossible. There cannot, therefore, exist any canon for the speculative
exercise of this faculty for its speculative exercise is entirely dialectical; and, consequently, transcendental
logic, in this respect, is merely a discipline, and not a canon. If, then, there is any proper mode of employing
the faculty of pure reason in which case there must be a canon for this faculty this canon will relate, not to
the speculative, but to the practical use of reason. This canon we now proceed to investigate.
SECTION I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason.
There exists in the faculty of reason a natural desire to venture beyond the field of experience, to attempt to
reach the utmost bounds of all cognition by the help of ideas alone, and not to rest satisfied until it has
fulfilled its course and raised the sum of its cognitions into a selfsubsistent systematic whole. Is the motive
for this endeavour to be found in its speculative, or in its practical interests alone?
Setting aside, at present, the results of the labours of pure reason in its speculative exercise, I shall merely
inquire regarding the problems the solution of which forms its ultimate aim, whether reached or not, and in
relation to which all other aims are but partial and intermediate. These highest aims must, from the nature of
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason. 255
Page No 260
reason, possess complete unity; otherwise the highest interest of humanity could not be successfully
promoted.
The transcendental speculation of reason relates to three things: the freedom of the will, the immortality of
the soul, and the existence of God. The speculative interest which reason has in those questions is very small;
and, for its sake alone, we should not undertake the labour of transcendental investigation a labour full of
toil and ceaseless struggle. We should be loth to undertake this labour, because the discoveries we might
make would not be of the smallest use in the sphere of concrete or physical investigation. We may find out
that the will is free, but this knowledge only relates to the intelligible cause of our volition. As regards the
phenomena or expressions of this will, that is, our actions, we are bound, in obedience to an inviolable
maxim, without which reason cannot be employed in the sphere of experience, to explain these in the same
way as we explain all the other phenomena of nature, that is to say, according to its unchangeable laws. We
may have discovered the spirituality and immortality of the soul, but we cannot employ this knowledge to
explain the phenomena of this life, nor the peculiar nature of the future, because our conception of an
incorporeal nature is purely negative and does not add anything to our knowledge, and the only inferences to
be drawn from it are purely fictitious. If, again, we prove the existence of a supreme intelligence, we should
be able from it to make the conformity to aims existing in the arrangement of the world comprehensible; but
we should not be justified in deducing from it any particular arrangement or disposition, or inferring any
where it is not perceived. For it is a necessary rule of the speculative use of reason that we must not overlook
natural causes, or refuse to listen to the teaching of experience, for the sake of deducing what we know and
perceive from something that transcends all our knowledge. In one word, these three propositions are, for the
speculative reason, always transcendent, and cannot be employed as immanent principles in relation to the
objects of experience; they are, consequently, of no use to us in this sphere, being but the valueless results of
the severe but unprofitable efforts of reason.
If, then, the actual cognition of these three cardinal propositions is perfectly useless, while Reason uses her
utmost endeavours to induce us to admit them, it is plain that their real value and importance relate to our
practical, and not to our speculative interest.
I term all that is possible through free will, practical. But if the conditions of the exercise of free volition are
empirical, reason can have only a regulative, and not a constitutive, influence upon it, and is serviceable
merely for the introduction of unity into its empirical laws. In the moral philosophy of prudence, for example,
the sole business of reason is to bring about a union of all the ends, which are aimed at by our inclinations,
into one ultimate end that of happiness and to show the agreement which should exist among the means of
attaining that end. In this sphere, accordingly, reason cannot present to us any other than pragmatical laws of
free action, for our guidance towards the aims set up by the senses, and is incompetent to give us laws which
are pure and determined completely a priori. On the other hand, pure practical laws, the ends of which have
been given by reason entirely a priori, and which are not empirically conditioned, but are, on the contrary,
absolutely imperative in their nature, would be products of pure reason. Such are the moral laws; and these
alone belong to the sphere of the practical exercise of reason, and admit of a canon.
All the powers of reason, in the sphere of what may be termed pure philosophy, are, in fact, directed to the
three abovementioned problems alone. These again have a still higher end the answer to the question, what
we ought to do, if the will is free, if there is a God and a future world. Now, as this problem relates to our in
reference to the highest aim of humanity, it is evident that the ultimate intention of nature, in the constitution
of our reason, has been directed to the moral alone.
We must take care, however, in turning our attention to an object which is foreign* to the sphere of
transcendental philosophy, not to injure the unity of our system by digressions, nor, on the other hand, to fail
in clearness, by saying too little on the new subject of discussion. I hope to avoid both extremes, by keeping
as close as possible to the transcendental, and excluding all psychological, that is, empirical, elements.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason. 256
Page No 261
*All practical conceptions relate to objects of pleasure and pain, and consequently in an indirect manner, at
least to objects of feeling. But as feeling is not a faculty of representation, but lies out of the sphere of our
powers of cognition, the elements of our judgements, in so far as they relate to pleasure or pain, that is, the
elements of our practical judgements, do not belong to transcendental philosophy, which has to do with pure
a priori cognitions alone.
I have to remark, in the first place, that at present I treat of the conception of freedom in the practical sense
only, and set aside the corresponding transcendental conception, which cannot be employed as a ground of
explanation in the phenomenal world, but is itself a problem for pure reason. A will is purely animal
(arbitrium brutum) when it is determined by sensuous impulses or instincts only, that is, when it is
determined in a pathological manner. A will, which can be determined independently of sensuous impulses,
consequently by motives presented by reason alone, is called a free will (arbitrium liberum); and everything
which is connected with this free will, either as principle or consequence, is termed practical. The existence
of practical freedom can be proved from experience alone. For the human will is not determined by that alone
which immediately affects the senses; on the contrary, we have the power, by calling up the notion of what is
useful or hurtful in a more distant relation, of overcoming the immediate impressions on our sensuous faculty
of desire. But these considerations of what is desirable in relation to our whole state, that is, is in the end
good and useful, are based entirely upon reason. This faculty, accordingly, enounces laws, which are
imperative or objective laws of freedom and which tell us what ought to take place, thus distinguishing
themselves from the laws of nature, which relate to that which does take place. The laws of freedom or of
free will are hence termed practical laws.
Whether reason is not itself, in the actual delivery of these laws, determined in its turn by other influences,
and whether the action which, in relation to sensuous impulses, we call free, may not, in relation to higher
and more remote operative causes, really form a part of nature these are questions which do not here
concern us. They are purely speculative questions; and all we have to do, in the practical sphere, is to inquire
into the rule of conduct which reason has to present. Experience demonstrates to us the existence of practical
freedom as one of the causes which exist in nature, that is, it shows the causal power of reason in the
determination of the will. The idea of transcendental freedom, on the contrary, requires that reason in
relation to its causal power of commencing a series of phenomena should be independent of all sensuous
determining causes; and thus it seems to be in opposition to the law of nature and to all possible experience.
It therefore remains a problem for the human mind. But this problem does not concern reason in its practical
use; and we have, therefore, in a canon of pure reason, to do with only two questions, which relate to the
practical interest of pure reason: Is there a God? and, Is there a future life? The question of transcendental
freedom is purely speculative, and we may therefore set it entirely aside when we come to treat of practical
reason. Besides, we have already discussed this subject in the antinomy of pure reason.
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining
Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason.
Reason conducted us, in its speculative use, through the field of experience and, as it can never find complete
satisfaction in that sphere, from thence to speculative ideas which, however, in the end brought us back
again to experience, and thus fulfilled the purpose of reason, in a manner which, though useful, was not at all
in accordance with our expectations. It now remains for us to consider whether pure reason can be employed
in a practical sphere, and whether it will here conduct us to those ideas which attain the highest ends of pure
reason, as we have just stated them. We shall thus ascertain whether, from the point of view of its practical
interest, reason may not be able to supply us with that which, on the speculative side, it wholly denies us.
The whole interest of reason, speculative as well as practical, is centred in the three following questions:
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason. 257
Page No 262
1. WHAT CAN I KNOW?
2. WHAT OUGHT I TO DO?
3. WHAT MAY I HOPE?
The first question is purely speculative. We have, as I flatter myself, exhausted all the replies of which it is
susceptible, and have at last found the reply with which reason must content itself, and with which it ought to
be content, so long as it pays no regard to the practical. But from the two great ends to the attainment of
which all these efforts of pure reason were in fact directed, we remain just as far removed as if we had
consulted our ease and declined the task at the outset. So far, then, as knowledge is concerned, thus much, at
least, is established, that, in regard to those two problems, it lies beyond our reach.
The second question is purely practical. As such it may indeed fall within the province of pure reason, but
still it is not transcendental, but moral, and consequently cannot in itself form the subject of our criticism.
The third question: If I act as I ought to do, what may I then hope? is at once practical and theoretical. The
practical forms a clue to the answer of the theoretical, and in its highest form speculative question. For all
hoping has happiness for its object and stands in precisely the same relation to the practical and the law of
morality as knowing to the theoretical cognition of things and the law of nature. The former arrives finally at
the conclusion that something is (which determines the ultimate end), because something ought to take place;
the latter, that something is (which operates as the highest cause), because something does take place.
Happiness is the satisfaction of all our desires; extensive, in regard to their multiplicity; intensive, in regard to
their degree; and protensive, in regard to their duration. The practical law based on the motive of happiness I
term a pragmatical law (or prudential rule); but that law, assuming such to exist, which has no other motive
than the worthiness of being happy, I term a moral or ethical law. The first tells us what we have to do, if we
wish to become possessed of happiness; the second dictates how we ought to act, in order to deserve
happiness. The first is based upon empirical principles; for it is only by experience that I can learn either what
inclinations exist which desire satisfaction, or what are the natural means of satisfying them. The second
takes no account of our desires or the means of satisfying them, and regards only the freedom of a rational
being, and the necessary conditions under which alone this freedom can harmonize with the distribution of
happiness according to principles. This second law may therefore rest upon mere ideas of pure reason, and
may be cognized a priori.
I assume that there are pure moral laws which determine, entirely a priori (without regard to empirical
motives, that is, to happiness), the conduct of a rational being, or in other words, to use which it makes of its
freedom, and that these laws are absolutely imperative (not merely hypothetically, on the supposition of other
empirical ends), and therefore in all respects necessary. I am warranted in assuming this, not only by the
arguments of the most enlightened moralists, but by the moral judgement of every man who will make the
attempt to form a distinct conception of such a law.
Pure reason, then, contains, not indeed in its speculative, but in its practical, or, more strictly, its moral use,
principles of the possibility of experience, of such actions, namely, as, in accordance with ethical precepts,
might be met with in the history of man. For since reason commands that such actions should take place, it
must be possible for them to take place; and hence a particular kind of systematic unity the moral must be
possible. We have found, it is true, that the systematic unity of nature could not be established according to
speculative principles of reason, because, while reason possesses a causal power in relation to freedom, it has
none in relation to the whole sphere of nature; and, while moral principles of reason can produce free actions,
they cannot produce natural laws. It is, then, in its practical, but especially in its moral use, that the principles
of pure reason possess objective reality.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason. 258
Page No 263
I call the world a moral world, in so far as it may be in accordance with all the ethical laws which, by virtue
of the freedom of reasonable beings, it can be, and according to the necessary laws of morality it ought to be.
But this world must be conceived only as an intelligible world, inasmuch as abstraction is therein made of all
conditions (ends), and even of all impediments to morality (the weakness or pravity of human nature). So far,
then, it is a mere idea though still a practical idea which may have, and ought to have, an influence on the
world of sense, so as to bring it as far as possible into conformity with itself. The idea of a moral world has,
therefore, objective reality, not as referring to an object of intelligible intuition for of such an object we can
form no conception whatever but to the world of sense conceived, however, as an object of pure reason in
its practical use and to a corpus mysticum of rational beings in it, in so far as the liberum arbitrium of the
individual is placed, under and by virtue of moral laws, in complete systematic unity both with itself and with
the freedom of all others.
That is the answer to the first of the two questions of pure reason which relate to its practical interest: Do that
which will render thee worthy of happiness. The second question is this: If I conduct myself so as not to be
unworthy of happiness, may I hope thereby to obtain happiness? In order to arrive at the solution of this
question, we must inquire whether the principles of pure reason, which prescribe a priori the law, necessarily
also connect this hope with it.
I say, then, that just as the moral principles are necessary according to reason in its practical use, so it is
equally necessary according to reason in its theoretical use to assume that every one has ground to hope for
happiness in the measure in which he has made himself worthy of it in his conduct, and that therefore the
system of morality is inseparably (though only in the idea of pure reason) connected with that of happiness.
Now in an intelligible, that is, in the moral world, in the conception of which we make abstraction of all the
impediments to morality (sensuous desires), such a system of happiness, connected with and proportioned to
morality, may be conceived as necessary, because freedom of volition partly incited, and partly restrained
by moral laws would be itself the cause of general happiness; and thus rational beings, under the guidance
of such principles, would be themselves the authors both of their own enduring welfare and that of others.
But such a system of selfrewarding morality is only an idea, the carrying out of which depends upon the
condition that every one acts as he ought; in other words, that all actions of reasonable beings be such as they
would be if they sprung from a Supreme Will, comprehending in, or under, itself all particular wills. But
since the moral law is binding on each individual in the use of his freedom of volition, even if others should
not act in conformity with this law, neither the nature of things, nor the causality of actions and their relation
to morality, determine how the consequences of these actions will be related to happiness; and the necessary
connection of the hope of happiness with the unceasing endeavour to become worthy of happiness, cannot be
cognized by reason, if we take nature alone for our guide. This connection can be hoped for only on the
assumption that the cause of nature is a supreme reason, which governs according to moral laws.
I term the idea of an intelligence in which the morally most perfect will, united with supreme blessedness, is
the cause of all happiness in the world, so far as happiness stands in strict } relation to morality (as the
worthiness of being happy), the ideal of the supreme Good. supreme original good, that pure reason can find
the ground of the practically necessary connection of both elements of the highest derivative good, and
accordingly of an intelligible, that is, moral world. Now since we are necessitated by reason to conceive
ourselves as belonging to such a world, while the senses present to us nothing but a world of phenomena, we
must assume the former as a consequence of our conduct in the world of sense (since the world of sense gives
us no hint of it), and therefore as future in relation to us. Thus God and a future life are two hypotheses
which, according to the principles of pure reason, are inseparable from the obligation which this reason
imposes upon us.
Morality per se constitutes a system. But we can form no system of happiness, except in so far as it is
dispensed in strict proportion to morality. But this is only possible in the intelligible world, under a wise
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason. 259
Page No 264
author and ruler. Such a ruler, together with life in such a world, which we must look upon as future, reason
finds itself compelled to assume; or it must regard the moral laws as idle dreams, since the necessary
consequence which this same reason connects with them must, without this hypothesis, fall to the ground.
Hence also the moral laws are universally regarded as commands, which they could not be did they not
connect a priori adequate consequences with their dictates, and thus carry with them promises and threats.
But this, again, they could not do, did they not reside in a necessary being, as the Supreme Good, which alone
can render such a teleological unity possible.
Leibnitz termed the world, when viewed in relation to the rational beings which it contains, and the moral
relations in which they stand to each other, under the government of the Supreme Good, the kingdom of
Grace, and distinguished it from the kingdom of Nature, in which these rational beings live, under moral
laws, indeed, but expect no other consequences from their actions than such as follow according to the course
of nature in the world of sense. To view ourselves, therefore, as in the kingdom of grace, in which all
happiness awaits us, except in so far as we ourselves limit our participation in it by actions which render us
unworthy of happiness, is a practically necessary idea of reason.
Practical laws, in so far as they are subjective grounds of actions, that is, subjective principles, are termed
maxims. The judgements of moral according to in its purity and ultimate results are framed according ideas;
the observance of its laws, according to according to maxims.
The whole course of our life must be subject to moral maxims; but this is impossible, unless with the moral
law, which is a mere idea, reason connects an efficient cause which ordains to all conduct which is in
conformity with the moral law an issue either in this or in another life, which is in exact conformity with our
highest aims. Thus, without a God and without a world, invisible to us now, but hoped for, the glorious ideas
of morality are, indeed, objects of approbation and of admiration, but cannot be the springs of purpose and
action. For they do not satisfy all the aims which are natural to every rational being, and which are
determined a priori by pure reason itself, and necessary.
Happiness alone is, in the view of reason, far from being the complete good. Reason does not approve of it
(however much inclination may desire it), except as united with desert. On the other hand, morality alone,
and with it, mere desert, is likewise far from being the complete good. To make it complete, he who conducts
himself in a manner not unworthy of happiness, must be able to hope for the possession of happiness. Even
reason, unbiased by private ends, or interested considerations, cannot judge otherwise, if it puts itself in the
place of a being whose business it is to dispense all happiness to others. For in the practical idea both points
are essentially combined, though in such a way that participation in happiness is rendered possible by the
moral disposition, as its condition, and not conversely, the moral disposition by the prospect of happiness.
For a disposition which should require the prospect of happiness as its necessary condition would not be
moral, and hence also would not be worthy of complete happiness a happiness which, in the view of reason,
recognizes no limitation but such as arises from our own immoral conduct.
Happiness, therefore, in exact proportion with the morality of rational beings (whereby they are made worthy
of happiness), constitutes alone the supreme good of a world into which we absolutely must transport
ourselves according to the commands of pure but practical reason. This world is, it is true, only an intelligible
world; for of such a systematic unity of ends as it requires, the world of sense gives us no hint. Its reality can
be based on nothing else but the hypothesis of a supreme original good. In it independent reason, equipped
with all the sufficiency of a supreme cause, founds, maintains, and fulfils the universal order of things, with
the most perfect teleological harmony, however much this order may be hidden from us in the world of sense.
This moral theology has the peculiar advantage, in contrast with speculative theology, of leading inevitably to
the conception of a sole, perfect, and rational First Cause, whereof speculative theology does not give us any
indication on objective grounds, far less any convincing evidence. For we find neither in transcendental nor
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason. 260
Page No 265
in natural theology, however far reason may lead us in these, any ground to warrant us in assuming the
existence of one only Being, which stands at the head of all natural causes, and on which these are entirely
dependent. On the other band, if we take our stand on moral unity as a necessary law of the universe, and
from this point of view consider what is necessary to give this law adequate efficiency and, for us, obligatory
force, we must come to the conclusion that there is one only supreme will, which comprehends all these laws
in itself. For how, under different wills, should we find complete unity of ends? This will must be
omnipotent, that all nature and its relation to morality in the world may be subject to it; omniscient, that it
may have knowledge of the most secret feelings and their moral worth; omnipresent, that it may be at hand to
supply every necessity to which the highest weal of the world may give rise; eternal, that this harmony of
nature and liberty may never fail; and so on.
But this systematic unity of ends in this world of intelligences which, as mere nature, is only a world of
sense, but, as a system of freedom of volition, may be termed an intelligible, that is, moral world (regnum
gratiae) leads inevitably also to the teleological unity of all things which constitute this great whole,
according to universal natural laws just as the unity of the former is according to universal and necessary
moral laws and unites the practical with the speculative reason. The world must be represented as having
originated from an idea, if it is to harmonize with that use of reason without which we cannot even consider
ourselves as worthy of reason namely, the moral use, which rests entirely on the idea of the supreme good.
Hence the investigation of nature receives a teleological direction, and becomes, in its widest extension,
physicotheology. But this, taking its rise in moral order as a unity founded on the essence of freedom, and
not accidentally instituted by external commands, establishes the teleological view of nature on grounds
which must be inseparably connected with the internal possibility of things. This gives rise to a
transcendental theology, which takes the ideal of the highest ontological perfection as a principle of
systematic unity; and this principle connects all things according to universal and necessary natural laws,
because all things have their origin in the absolute necessity of the one only Primal Being.
What use can we make of our understanding, even in respect of experience, if we do not propose ends to
ourselves? But the highest ends are those of morality, and it is only pure reason that can give us the
knowledge of these. Though supplied with these, and putting ourselves under their guidance, we can make no
teleological use of the knowledge of nature, as regards cognition, unless nature itself has established
teleological unity. For without this unity we should not even possess reason, because we should have no
school for reason, and no cultivation through objects which afford the materials for its conceptions. But
teleological unity is a necessary unity, and founded on the essence of the individual will itself. Hence this
will, which is the condition of the application of this unity in concreto, must be so likewise. In this way the
transcendental enlargement of our rational cognition would be, not the cause, but merely the effect of the
practical teleology which pure reason imposes upon us.
Hence, also, we find in the history of human reason that, before the moral conceptions were sufficiently
purified and determined, and before men had attained to a perception of the systematic unity of ends
according to these conceptions and from necessary principles, the knowledge of nature, and even a
considerable amount of intellectual culture in many other sciences, could produce only rude and vague
conceptions of the Deity, sometimes even admitting of an astonishing indifference with regard to this
question altogether. But the more enlarged treatment of moral ideas, which was rendered necessary by the
extreme pure moral law of our religion, awakened the interest, and thereby quickened the perceptions of
reason in relation to this object. In this way, and without the help either of an extended acquaintance with
nature, or of a reliable transcendental insight (for these have been wanting in all ages), a conception of the
Divine Being was arrived at, which we now bold to be the correct one, not because speculative reason
convinces us of its correctness, but because it accords with the moral principles of reason. Thus it is to pure
reason, but only in its practical use, that we must ascribe the merit of having connected with our highest
interest a cognition, of which mere speculation was able only to form a conjecture, but the validity of which it
was unable to establish and of having thereby rendered it, not indeed a demonstrated dogma, but a
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason. 261
Page No 266
hypothesis absolutely necessary to the essential ends of reason.
But if practical reason has reached this elevation, and has attained to the conception of a sole Primal Being as
the supreme good, it must not, therefore, imagine that it has transcended the empirical conditions of its
application, and risen to the immediate cognition of new objects; it must not presume to start from the
conception which it has gained, and to deduce from it the moral laws themselves. For it was these very laws,
the internal practical necessity of which led us to the hypothesis of an independent cause, or of a wise ruler of
the universe, who should give them effect. Hence we are not entitled to regard them as accidental and derived
from the mere will of the ruler, especially as we have no conception of such a will, except as formed in
accordance with these laws. So far, then, as practical reason has the right to conduct us, we shall not look
upon actions as binding on us, because they are the commands of God, but we shall regard them as divine
commands, because we are internally bound by them. We shall study freedom under the teleological unity
which accords with principles of reason; we shall look upon ourselves as acting in conformity with the divine
will only in so far as we hold sacred the moral law which reason teaches us from the nature of actions
themselves, and we shall believe that we can obey that will only by promoting the weal of the universe in
ourselves and in others. Moral theology is, therefore, only of immanent use. It teaches us to fulfil our destiny
here in the world, by placing ourselves in harmony with the general system of ends, and warns us against the
fanaticism, nay, the crime of depriving reason of its legislative authority in the moral conduct of life, for the
purpose of directly connecting this authority with the idea of the Supreme Being. For this would be, not an
immanent, but a transcendent use of moral theology, and, like the transcendent use of mere speculation,
would inevitably pervert and frustrate the ultimate ends of reason.
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief.
The holding of a thing to be true is a phenomenon in our understanding which may rest on objective grounds,
but requires, also, subjective causes in the mind of the person judging. If a judgement is valid for every
rational being, then its ground is objectively sufficient, and it is termed a conviction. If, on the other hand, it
has its ground in the particular character of the subject, it is termed a persuasion.
Persuasion is a mere illusion, the ground of the judgement, which lies solely in the subject, being regarded as
objective. Hence a judgement of this kind has only private validity is only valid for the individual who
judges, and the holding of a thing to be true in this way cannot be communicated. But truth depends upon
agreement with the object, and consequently the judgements of all understandings, if true, must be in
agreement with each other (consentientia uni tertio consentiunt inter se). Conviction may, therefore, be
distinguished, from an external point of view, from persuasion, by the possibility of communicating it and by
showing its validity for the reason of every man; for in this case the presumption, at least, arises that the
agreement of all judgements with each other, in spite of the different characters of individuals, rests upon the
common ground of the agreement of each with the object, and thus the correctness of the judgement is
established.
Persuasion, accordingly, cannot be subjectively distinguished from conviction, that is, so long as the subject
views its judgement simply as a phenomenon of its own mind. But if we inquire whether the grounds of our
judgement, which are valid for us, produce the same effect on the reason of others as on our own, we have
then the means, though only subjective means, not, indeed, of producing conviction, but of detecting the
merely private validity of the judgement; in other words, of discovering that there is in it the element of mere
persuasion.
If we can, in addition to this, develop the subjective causes of the judgement, which we have taken for its
objective grounds, and thus explain the deceptive judgement as a phenomenon in our mind, apart altogether
from the objective character of the object, we can then expose the illusion and need be no longer deceived by
it, although, if its subjective cause lies in our nature, we cannot hope altogether to escape its influence.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief. 262
Page No 267
I can only maintain, that is, affirm as necessarily valid for every one, that which produces conviction.
Persuasion I may keep for myself, if it is agreeable to me; but I cannot, and ought not, to attempt to impose it
as binding upon others.
Holding for true, or the subjective validity of a judgement in relation to conviction (which is, at the same
time, objectively valid), has the three following degrees: opinion, belief, and knowledge. Opinion is a
consciously insufficient judgement, subjectively as well as objectively. Belief is subjectively sufficient, but is
recognized as being objectively insufficient. Knowledge is both subjectively and objectively sufficient.
Subjective sufficiency is termed conviction (for myself); objective sufficiency is termed certainty (for all). I
need not dwell longer on the explanation of such simple conceptions.
I must never venture to be of opinion, without knowing something, at least, by which my judgement, in itself
merely problematical, is brought into connection with the truth which connection, although not perfect, is
still something more than an arbitrary fiction. Moreover, the law of such a connection must be certain. For if,
in relation to this law, I have nothing more than opinion, my judgement is but a play of the imagination,
without the least relation to truth. In the judgements of pure reason, opinion has no place. For, as they do not
rest on empirical grounds and as the sphere of pure reason is that of necessary truth and a priori cognition, the
principle of connection in it requires universality and necessity, and consequently perfect certainty
otherwise we should have no guide to the truth at all. Hence it is absurd to have an opinion in pure
mathematics; we must know, or abstain from forming a judgement altogether. The case is the same with the
maxims of morality. For we must not hazard an action on the mere opinion that it is allowed, but we must
know it to be so.
In the transcendental sphere of reason, on the other hand, the term opinion is too weak, while the word
knowledge is too strong. From the merely speculative point of view, therefore, we cannot form a judgement
at all. For the subjective grounds of a judgement, such as produce belief, cannot be admitted in speculative
inquiries, inasmuch as they cannot stand without empirical support and are incapable of being communicated
to others in equal measure.
But it is only from the practical point of view that a theoretically insufficient judgement can be termed belief.
Now the practical reference is either to skill or to morality; to the former, when the end proposed is arbitrary
and accidental, to the latter, when it is absolutely necessary.
If we propose to ourselves any end whatever, the conditions of its attainment are hypothetically necessary.
The necessity is subjectively, but still only comparatively, sufficient, if I am acquainted with no other
conditions under which the end can be attained. On the other hand, it is sufficient, absolutely and for every
one, if I know for certain that no one can be acquainted with any other conditions under which the attainment
of the proposed end would be possible. In the former case my supposition my judgement with regard to
certain conditions is a merely accidental belief; in the latter it is a necessary belief. The physician must
pursue some course in the case of a patient who is in danger, but is ignorant of the nature of the disease. He
observes the symptoms, and concludes, according to the best of his judgement, that it is a case of phthisis.
His belief is, even in his own judgement, only contingent: another man might, perhaps come nearer the truth.
Such a belief, contingent indeed, but still forming the ground of the actual use of means for the attainment of
certain ends, I term Pragmatical belief.
The usual test, whether that which any one maintains is merely his persuasion, or his subjective conviction at
least, that is, his firm belief, is a bet. It frequently happens that a man delivers his opinions with so much
boldness and assurance, that he appears to be under no apprehension as to the possibility of his being in error.
The offer of a bet startles him, and makes him pause. Sometimes it turns out that his persuasion may be
valued at a ducat, but not at ten. For he does not hesitate, perhaps, to venture a ducat, but if it is proposed to
stake ten, he immediately becomes aware of the possibility of his being mistaken a possibility which has
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief. 263
Page No 268
hitherto escaped his observation. If we imagine to ourselves that we have to stake the happiness of our whole
life on the truth of any proposition, our judgement drops its air of triumph, we take the alarm, and discover
the actual strength of our belief. Thus pragmatical belief has degrees, varying in proportion to the interests at
stake.
Now, in cases where we cannot enter upon any course of action in reference to some object, and where,
accordingly, our judgement is purely theoretical, we can still represent to ourselves, in thought, the possibility
of a course of action, for which we suppose that we have sufficient grounds, if any means existed of
ascertaining the truth of the matter. Thus we find in purely theoretical judgements an analogon of practical
judgements, to which the word belief may properly be applied, and which we may term doctrinal belief. I
should not hesitate to stake my all on the truth of the proposition if there were any possibility of bringing it
to the test of experience that, at least, some one of the planets, which we see, is inhabited. Hence I say that I
have not merely the opinion, but the strong belief, on the correctness of which I would stake even many of
the advantages of life, that there are inhabitants in other worlds.
Now we must admit that the doctrine of the existence of God belongs to doctrinal belief. For, although in
respect to the theoretical cognition of the universe I do not require to form any theory which necessarily
involves this idea, as the condition of my explanation of the phenomena which the universe presents, but, on
the contrary, am rather bound so to use my reason as if everything were mere nature, still teleological unity is
so important a condition of the application of my reason to nature, that it is impossible for me to ignore it
especially since, in addition to these considerations, abundant examples of it are supplied by experience. But
the sole condition, so far as my knowledge extends, under which this unity can be my guide in the
investigation of nature, is the assumption that a supreme intelligence has ordered all things according to the
wisest ends. Consequently, the hypothesis of a wise author of the universe is necessary for my guidance in
the investigation of nature is the condition under which alone I can fulfil an end which is contingent indeed,
but by no means unimportant. Moreover, since the result of my attempts so frequently confirms the utility of
this assumption, and since nothing decisive can be adduced against it, it follows that it would be saying far
too little to term my judgement, in this case, a mere opinion, and that, even in this theoretical connection, I
may assert that I firmly believe in God. Still, if we use words strictly, this must not be called a practical, but a
doctrinal belief, which the theology of nature (physicotheology) must also produce in my mind. In the
wisdom of a Supreme Being, and in the shortness of life, so inadequate to the development of the glorious
powers of human nature, we may find equally sufficient grounds for a doctrinal belief in the future life of the
human soul.
The expression of belief is, in such cases, an expression of modesty from the objective point of view, but, at
the same time, of firm confidence, from the subjective. If I should venture to term this merely theoretical
judgement even so much as a hypothesis which I am entitled to assume; a more complete conception, with
regard to another world and to the cause of the world, might then be justly required of me than I am, in
reality, able to give. For, if I assume anything, even as a mere hypothesis, I must, at least, know so much of
the properties of such a being as will enable me, not to form the conception, but to imagine the existence of it.
But the word belief refers only to the guidance which an idea gives me, and to its subjective influence on the
conduct of my reason, which forces me to hold it fast, though I may not be in a position to give a speculative
account of it.
But mere doctrinal belief is, to some extent, wanting in stability. We often quit our hold of it, in consequence
of the difficulties which occur in speculation, though in the end we inevitably return to it again.
It is quite otherwise with moral belief. For in this sphere action is absolutely necessary, that is, I must act in
obedience to the moral law in all points. The end is here incontrovertibly established, and there is only one
condition possible, according to the best of my perception, under which this end can harmonize with all other
ends, and so have practical validity namely, the existence of a God and of a future world. I know also, to a
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief. 264
Page No 269
certainty, that no one can be acquainted with any other conditions which conduct to the same unity of ends
under the moral law. But since the moral precept is, at the same time, my maxim (as reason requires that it
should be), I am irresistibly constrained to believe in the existence of God and in a future life; and I am sure
that nothing can make me waver in this belief, since I should thereby overthrow my moral maxims, the
renunciation of which would render me hateful in my own eyes.
Thus, while all the ambitious attempts of reason to penetrate beyond the limits of experience end in
disappointment, there is still enough left to satisfy us in a practical point of view. No one, it is true, will be
able to boast that he knows that there is a God and a future life; for, if he knows this, be is just the man whom
I have long wished to find. All knowledge, regarding an object of mere reason, can be communicated; and I
should thus be enabled to hope that my own knowledge would receive this wonderful extension, through the
instrumentality of his instruction. No, my conviction is not logical, but moral certainty; and since it rests on
subjective grounds (of the moral sentiment), I must not even say: It is morally certain that there is a God, etc.,
but: I am morally certain, that is, my belief in God and in another world is so interwoven with my moral
nature that I am under as little apprehension of having the former torn from me as of losing the latter.
The only point in this argument that may appear open to suspicion is that this rational belief presupposes the
existence of moral sentiments. If we give up this assumption, and take a man who is entirely indifferent with
regard to moral laws, the question which reason proposes, becomes then merely a problem for speculation
and may, indeed, be supported by strong grounds from analogy, but not by such as will compel the most
obstinate scepticism to give way.* But in these questions no man is free from all interest. For though the want
of good sentiments may place him beyond the influence of moral interests, still even in this case enough may
be left to make him fear the existence of God and a future life. For he cannot pretend to any certainty of the
nonexistence of God and of a future life, unless since it could only be proved by mere reason, and
therefore apodeictically he is prepared to establish the impossibility of both, which certainly no reasonable
man would undertake to do. This would be a negative belief, which could not, indeed, produce morality and
good sentiments, but still could produce an analogon of these, by operating as a powerful restraint on the
outbreak of evil dispositions.
*The human mind (as, I believe, every rational being must of necessity do) takes a natural interest in
morality, although this interest is not undivided, and may not be practically in preponderance. If you
strengthen and increase it, you will find the reason become docile, more enlightened, and more capable of
uniting the speculative interest with the practical. But if you do not take care at the outset, or at least midway,
to make men good, you will never force them into an honest belief.
But, it will be said, is this all that pure reason can effect, in opening up prospects beyond the limits of
experience? Nothing more than two articles of belief? Common sense could have done as much as this,
without taking the philosophers to counsel in the matter!
I shall not here eulogize philosophy for the benefits which the laborious efforts of its criticism have conferred
on human reason even granting that its merit should turn out in the end to be only negative for on this
point something more will be said in the next section. But, I ask, do you require that that knowledge which
concerns all men, should transcend the common understanding, and should only be revealed to you by
philosophers? The very circumstance which has called forth your censure, is the best confirmation of the
correctness of our previous assertions, since it discloses, what could not have been foreseen, that Nature is
not chargeable with any partial distribution of her gifts in those matters which concern all men without
distinction and that, in respect to the essential ends of human nature, we cannot advance further with the help
of the highest philosophy, than under the guidance which nature has vouchsafed to the meanest
understanding.
The Critique of Pure Reason
SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief. 265
Page No 270
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason.
By the term architectonic I mean the art of constructing a system. Without systematic unity, our knowledge
cannot become science; it will be an aggregate, and not a system. Thus architectonic is the doctrine of the
scientific in cognition, and therefore necessarily forms part of our methodology.
Reason cannot permit our knowledge to remain in an unconnected and rhapsodistic state, but requires that the
sum of our cognitions should constitute a system. It is thus alone that they can advance the ends of reason. By
a system I mean the unity of various cognitions under one idea. This idea is the conception given by reason
of the form of a whole, in so far as the conception determines a priori not only the limits of its content, but
the place which each of its parts is to occupy. The scientific idea contains, therefore, the end and the form of
the whole which is in accordance with that end. The unity of the end, to which all the parts of the system
relate, and through which all have a relation to each other, communicates unity to the whole system, so that
the absence of any part can be immediately detected from our knowledge of the rest; and it determines a
priori the limits of the system, thus excluding all contingent or arbitrary additions. The whole is thus an
organism (articulatio), and not an aggregate (coacervatio); it may grow from within (per intussusceptionem),
but it cannot increase by external additions (per appositionem). It is, thus, like an animal body, the growth of
which does not add any limb, but, without changing their proportions, makes each in its sphere stronger and
more active.
We require, for the execution of the idea of a system, a schema, that is, a content and an arrangement of parts
determined a priori by the principle which the aim of the system prescribes. A schema which is not projected
in accordance with an idea, that is, from the standpoint of the highest aim of reason, but merely empirically,
in accordance with accidental aims and purposes (the number of which cannot be predetermined), can give us
nothing more than technical unity. But the schema which is originated from an idea (in which case reason
presents us with aims a priori, and does not look for them to experience), forms the basis of architectonical
unity. A science, in the proper acceptation of that term. cannot be formed technically, that is, from
observation of the similarity existing between different objects, and the purely contingent use we make of our
knowledge in concreto with reference to all kinds of arbitrary external aims; its constitution must be framed
on architectonical principles, that is, its parts must be shown to possess an essential affinity, and be capable of
being deduced from one supreme and internal aim or end, which forms the condition of the possibility of the
scientific whole. The schema of a science must give a priori the plan of it (monogramma), and the division of
the whole into parts, in conformity with the idea of the science; and it must also distinguish this whole from
all others, according to certain understood principles.
No one will attempt to construct a science, unless he have some idea to rest on as a proper basis. But, in the
elaboration of the science, he finds that the schema, nay, even the definition which he at first gave of the
science, rarely corresponds with his idea; for this idea lies, like a germ, in our reason, its parts undeveloped
and hid even from microscopical observation. For this reason, we ought to explain and define sciences, not
according to the description which the originator gives of them, but according to the idea which we find
based in reason itself, and which is suggested by the natural unity of the parts of the science already
accumulated. For it will of ten be found that the originator of a science and even his latest successors remain
attached to an erroneous idea, which they cannot render clear to themselves, and that they thus fail in
determining the true content, the articulation or systematic unity, and the limits of their science.
It is unfortunate that, only after having occupied ourselves for a long time in the collection of materials, under
the guidance of an idea which lies undeveloped in the mind, but not according to any definite plan of
arrangement nay, only after we have spent much time and labour in the technical disposition of our
materials, does it become possible to view the idea of a science in a clear light, and to project, according to
architectonical principles, a plan of the whole, in accordance with the aims of reason. Systems seem, like
certain worms, to be formed by a kind of generatio aequivoca by the mere confluence of conceptions, and to
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. 266
Page No 271
gain completeness only with the progress of time. But the schema or germ of all lies in reason; and thus is not
only every system organized according to its own idea, but all are united into one grand system of human
knowledge, of which they form members. For this reason, it is possible to frame an architectonic of all human
cognition, the formation of which, at the present time, considering the immense materials collected or to be
found in the ruins of old systems, would not indeed be very difficult. Our purpose at present is merely to
sketch the plan of the architectonic of all cognition given by pure reason; and we begin from the point where
the main root of human knowledge divides into two, one of which is reason. By reason I understand here the
whole higher faculty of cognition, the rational being placed in contradistinction to the empirical.
If I make complete abstraction of the content of cognition, objectively considered, all cognition is, from a
subjective point of view, either historical or rational. Historical cognition is cognitio ex datis, rational,
cognitio ex principiis. Whatever may be the original source of a cognition, it is, in relation to the person who
possesses it, merely historical, if he knows only what has been given him from another quarter, whether that
knowledge was communicated by direct experience or by instruction. Thus the Person who has learned a
system of philosophy say the Wolfian although he has a perfect knowledge of all the principles,
definitions, and arguments in that philosophy, as well as of the divisions that have been made of the system,
possesses really no more than an historical knowledge of the Wolfian system; he knows only what has been
told him, his judgements are only those which he has received from his teachers. Dispute the validity of a
definition, and he is completely at a loss to find another. He has formed his mind on another's; but the
imitative faculty is not the productive. His knowledge has not been drawn from reason; and although,
objectively considered, it is rational knowledge, subjectively, it is merely historical. He has learned this or
that philosophy and is merely a plaster cast of a living man. Rational cognitions which are objective, that is,
which have their source in reason, can be so termed from a subjective point of view, only when they have
been drawn by the individual himself from the sources of reason, that is, from principles; and it is in this way
alone that criticism, or even the rejection of what has been already learned, can spring up in the mind.
All rational cognition is, again, based either on conceptions, or on the construction of conceptions. The
former is termed philosophical, the latter mathematical. I have already shown the essential difference of these
two methods of cognition in the first chapter. A cognition may be objectively philosophical and subjectively
historical as is the case with the majority of scholars and those who cannot look beyond the limits of their
system, and who remain in a state of pupilage all their lives. But it is remarkable that mathematical
knowledge, when committed to memory, is valid, from the subjective point of view, as rational knowledge
also, and that the same distinction cannot be drawn here as in the case of philosophical cognition. The reason
is that the only way of arriving at this knowledge is through the essential principles of reason, and thus it is
always certain and indisputable; because reason is employed in concreto but at the same time a priori that
is, in pure and, therefore, infallible intuition; and thus all causes of illusion and error are excluded. Of all the
a priori sciences of reason, therefore, mathematics alone can be learned. Philosophy unless it be in an
historical manner cannot be learned; we can at most learn to philosophize.
Philosophy is the system of all philosophical cognition. We must use this term in an objective sense, if we
understand by it the archetype of all attempts at philosophizing, and the standard by which all subjective
philosophies are to be judged. In this sense, philosophy is merely the idea of a possible science, which does
not exist in concreto, but to which we endeavour in various ways to approximate, until we have discovered
the right path to pursue a path overgrown by the errors and illusions of sense and the image we have
hitherto tried in vain to shape has become a perfect copy of the great prototype. Until that time, we cannot
learn philosophy it does not exist; if it does, where is it, who possesses it, and how shall we know it? We
can only learn to philosophize; in other words, we can only exercise our powers of reasoning in accordance
with general principles, retaining at the same time, the right of investigating the sources of these principles, of
testing, and even of rejecting them.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. 267
Page No 272
Until then, our conception of philosophy is only a scholastic conception a conception, that is, of a system of
cognition which we are trying to elaborate into a science; all that we at present know being the systematic
unity of this cognition, and consequently the logical completeness of the cognition for the desired end. But
there is also a cosmical conception (conceptus cosmicus) of philosophy, which has always formed the true
basis of this term, especially when philosophy was personified and presented to us in the ideal of a
philosopher. In this view philosophy is the science of the relation of all cognition to the ultimate and essential
aims of human reason (teleologia rationis humanae), and the philosopher is not merely an artist who
occupies himself with conceptions but a lawgiver, legislating for human reason. In this sense of the word, it
would be in the highest degree arrogant to assume the title of philosopher, and to pretend that we had reached
the perfection of the prototype which lies in the idea alone.
The mathematician, the natural philosopher, and the logician how far soever the first may have advanced in
rational, and the two latter in philosophical knowledge are merely artists, engaged in the arrangement and
formation of conceptions; they cannot be termed philosophers. Above them all, there is the ideal teacher, who
employs them as instruments for the advancement of the essential aims of human reason. Him alone can we
call philosopher; but he nowhere exists. But the idea of his legislative power resides in the mind of every
man, and it alone teaches us what kind of systematic unity philosophy demands in view of the ultimate aims
of reason. This idea is, therefore, a cosmical conception.*
*By a cosmical conception, I mean one in which all men necessarily take an interest; the aim of a science
must accordingly be determined according to scholastic conceptions, if it is regarded merely as a means to
certain arbitrarily proposed ends.
In view of the complete systematic unity of reason, there can only be one ultimate end of all the operations of
the mind. To this all other aims are subordinate, and nothing more than means for its attainment. This
ultimate end is the destination of man, and the philosophy which relates to it is termed moral philosophy. The
superior position occupied by moral philosophy, above all other spheres for the operations of reason,
sufficiently indicates the reason why the ancients always included the idea and in an especial manner of
moralist in that of philosopher. Even at the present day, we call a man who appears to have the power of
selfgovernment, even although his knowledge may be very limited, by the name of philosopher.
The legislation of human reason, or philosophy, has two objects nature and freedom and thus contains not
only the laws of nature, but also those of ethics, at first in two separate systems, which, finally, merge into
one grand philosophical system of cognition. The philosophy of nature relates to that which is, that of ethics
to that which ought to be.
But all philosophy is either cognition on the basis of pure reason, or the cognition of reason on the basis of
empirical principles. The former is termed pure, the latter empirical philosophy.
The philosophy of pure reason is either propaedeutic, that is, an inquiry into the powers of reason in regard to
pure a priori cognition, and is termed critical philosophy; or it is, secondly, the system of pure reason a
science containing the systematic presentation of the whole body of philosophical knowledge, true as well as
illusory, given by pure reason and is called metaphysic. This name may, however, be also given to the
whole system of pure philosophy, critical philosophy included, and may designate the investigation into the
sources or possibility of a priori cognition, as well as the presentation of the a priori cognitions which form a
system of pure philosophy excluding, at the same time, all empirical and mathematical elements.
Metaphysic is divided into that of the speculative and that of the practical use of pure reason, and is,
accordingly, either the metaphysic of nature, or the metaphysic of ethics. The former contains all the pure
rational principles based upon conceptions alone (and thus excluding mathematics) of all theoretical
cognition; the latter, the principles which determine and necessitate a priori all action. Now moral philosophy
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. 268
Page No 273
alone contains a code of laws for the regulation of our actions which are deduced from principles entirely a
priori. Hence the metaphysic of ethics is the only pure moral philosophy, as it is not based upon
anthropological or other empirical considerations. The metaphysic of speculative reason is what is commonly
called metaphysic in the more limited sense. But as pure moral philosophy properly forms a part of this
system of cognition, we must allow it to retain the name of metaphysic, although it is not requisite that we
should insist on so terming it in our present discussion.
It is of the highest importance to separate those cognitions which differ from others both in kind and in
origin, and to take great care that they are not confounded with those with which they are generally found
connected. What the chemist does in the analysis of substances, what the mathematician in pure mathematics,
is, in a still higher degree, the duty of the philosopher, that the value of each different kind of cognition, and
the part it takes in the operations of the mind, may be clearly defined. Human reason has never wanted a
metaphysic of some kind, since it attained the power of thought, or rather of reflection; but it has never been
able to keep this sphere of thought and cognition pure from all admixture of foreign elements. The idea of a
science of this kind is as old as speculation itself; and what mind does not speculate either in the scholastic
or in the popular fashion? At the same time, it must be admitted that even thinkers by profession have been
unable clearly to explain the distinction between the two elements of our cognition the one completely a
priori, the other a posteriori; and hence the proper definition of a peculiar kind of cognition, and with it the
just idea of a science which has so long and so deeply engaged the attention of the human mind, has never
been established. When it was said: "Metaphysic is the science of the first principles of human cognition,"
this definition did not signalize a peculiarity in kind, but only a difference in degree; these first principles
were thus declared to be more general than others, but no criterion of distinction from empirical principles
was given. Of these some are more general, and therefore higher, than others; and as we cannot distinguish
what is completely a priori from that which is known to be a posteriori where shall we draw the line which
is to separate the higher and socalled first principles, from the lower and subordinate principles of
cognition? What would be said if we were asked to be satisfied with a division of the epochs of the world into
the earlier centuries and those following them? "Does the fifth, or the tenth century belong to the earlier
centuries?" it would be asked. In the same way I ask: Does the conception of extension belong to
metaphysics? You answer, "Yes." Well, that of body too? "Yes." And that of a fluid body? You stop, you are
unprepared to admit this; for if you do, everything will belong to metaphysics. From this it is evident that the
mere degree of subordination of the particular to the general cannot determine the limits of a science; and
that, in the present case, we must expect to find a difference in the conceptions of metaphysics both in kind
and in origin. The fundamental idea of metaphysics was obscured on another side by the fact that this kind of
a priori cognition showed a certain similarity in character with the science of mathematics. Both have the
property in common of possessing an a priori origin; but, in the one, our knowledge is based upon
conceptions, in the other, on the construction of conceptions. Thus a decided dissimilarity between
philosophical and mathematical cognition comes out a dissimilarity which was always felt, but which could
not be made distinct for want of an insight into the criteria of the difference. And thus it happened that, as
philosophers themselves failed in the proper development of the idea of their science, the elaboration of the
science could not proceed with a definite aim, or under trustworthy guidance. Thus, too, philosophers,
ignorant of the path they ought to pursue and always disputing with each other regarding the discoveries
which each asserted he had made, brought their science into disrepute with the rest of the world, and finally,
even among themselves.
All pure a priori cognition forms, therefore, in view of the peculiar faculty which originates it, a peculiar and
distinct unity; and metaphysic is the term applied to the philosophy which attempts to represent that cognition
in this systematic unity. The speculative part of metaphysic, which has especially appropriated this
appellation that which we have called the metaphysic of nature and which considers everything, as it is
(not as it ought to be), by means of a priori conceptions, is divided in the following manner.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. 269
Page No 274
Metaphysic, in the more limited acceptation of the term, consists of two parts transcendental philosophy and
the physiology of pure reason. The former presents the system of all the conceptions and principles belonging
to the understanding and the reason, and which relate to objects in general, but not to any particular given
objects (Ontologia); the latter has nature for its subjectmatter, that is, the sum of given objects whether
given to the senses, or, if we will, to some other kind of intuition and is accordingly physiology, although
only rationalis. But the use of the faculty of reason in this rational mode of regarding nature is either physical
or hyperphysical, or, more properly speaking, immanent or transcendent. The former relates to nature, in so
far as our knowledge regarding it may be applied in experience (in concreto); the latter to that connection of
the objects of experience, which transcends all experience. Transcendent physiology has, again, an internal
and an external connection with its object, both, however, transcending possible experience; the former is the
physiology of nature as a whole, or transcendental cognition of the world, the latter of the connection of the
whole of nature with a being above nature, or transcendental cognition of God.
Immanent physiology, on the contrary, considers nature as the sum of all sensuous objects, consequently, as it
is presented to us but still according to a priori conditions, for it is under these alone that nature can be
presented to our minds at all. The objects of immanent physiology are of two kinds: 1. Those of the external
senses, or corporeal nature; 2. The object of the internal sense, the soul, or, in accordance with our
fundamental conceptions of it, thinking nature. The metaphysics of corporeal nature is called physics; but, as
it must contain only the principles of an a priori cognition of nature, we must term it rational physics. The
metaphysics of thinking nature is called psychology, and for the same reason is to be regarded as merely the
rational cognition of the soul.
Thus the whole system of metaphysics consists of four principal parts: 1. Ontology; 2. Rational Physiology;
3. Rational cosmology; and 4. Rational theology. The second part that of the rational doctrine of nature
may be subdivided into two, physica rationalis* and psychologia rationalis.
*It must not be supposed that I mean by this appellation what is generally called physica general is, and
which is rather mathematics than a philosophy of nature. For the metaphysic of nature is completely different
from mathematics, nor is it so rich in results, although it is of great importance as a critical test of the
application of pure understandingcognition to nature. For want of its guidance, even mathematicians,
adopting certain common notions which are, in fact, metaphysical have unconsciously crowded their
theories of nature with hypotheses, the fallacy of which becomes evident upon the application of the
principles of this metaphysic, without detriment, however, to the employment of mathematics in this sphere
of cognition.
The fundamental idea of a philosophy of pure reason of necessity dictates this division; it is, therefore,
architectonical in accordance with the highest aims of reason, and not merely technical, or according to
certain accidentallyobserved similarities existing between the different parts of the whole science. For this
reason, also, is the division immutable and of legislative authority. But the reader may observe in it a few
points to which he ought to demur, and which may weaken his conviction of its truth and legitimacy.
In the first place, how can I desire an a priori cognition or metaphysic of objects, in so far as they are given a
posteriori? and how is it possible to cognize the nature of things according to a priori principles, and to attain
to a rational physiology? The answer is this. We take from experience nothing more than is requisite to
present us with an object (in general) of the external or of the internal sense; in the former case, by the mere
conception of matter (impenetrable and inanimate extension), in the latter, by the conception of a thinking
being given in the internal empirical representation, I think. As to the rest, we must not employ in our
metaphysic of these objects any empirical principles (which add to the content of our conceptions by means
of experience), for the purpose of forming by their help any judgements respecting these objects.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason. 270
Page No 275
Secondly, what place shall we assign to empirical psychology, which has always been considered a part of
metaphysics, and from which in our time such important philosophical results have been expected, after the
hope of constructing an a priori system of knowledge had been abandoned? I answer: It must be placed by the
side of empirical physics or physics proper; that is, must be regarded as forming a part of applied philosophy,
the a priori principles of which are contained in pure philosophy, which is therefore connected, although it
must not be confounded, with psychology. Empirical psychology must therefore be banished from the sphere
of metaphysics, and is indeed excluded by the very idea of that science. In conformity, however, with
scholastic usage, we must permit it to occupy a place in metaphysics but only as an appendix to it. We adopt
this course from motives of economy; as psychology is not as yet full enough to occupy our attention as an
independent study, while it is, at the same time, of too great importance to be entirely excluded or placed
where it has still less affinity than it has with the subject of metaphysics. It is a stranger who has been long a
guest; and we make it welcome to stay, until it can take up a more suitable abode in a complete system of
anthropology the pendant to empirical physics.
The above is the general idea of metaphysics, which, as more was expected from it than could be looked for
with justice, and as these pleasant expectations were unfortunately never realized, fell into general disrepute.
Our Critique must have fully convinced the reader that, although metaphysics cannot form the foundation of
religion, it must always be one of its most important bulwarks, and that human reason, which naturally
pursues a dialectical course, cannot do without this science, which checks its tendencies towards dialectic
and, by elevating reason to a scientific and clear selfknowledge, prevents the ravages which a lawless
speculative reason would infallibly commit in the sphere of morals as well as in that of religion. We may be
sure, therefore, whatever contempt may be thrown upon metaphysics by those who judge a science not by its
own nature, but according to the accidental effects it may have produced, that it can never be completely
abandoned, that we must always return to it as to a beloved one who has been for a time estranged, because
the questions with which it is engaged relate to the highest aims of humanity, and reason must always labour
either to attain to settled views in regard to these, or to destroy those which others have already established.
Metaphysic, therefore that of nature, as well as that of ethics, but in an especial manner the criticism which
forms the propaedeutic to all the operations of reason forms properly that department of knowledge which
may be termed, in the truest sense of the word, philosophy. The path which it pursues is that of science,
which, when it has once been discovered, is never lost, and never misleads. Mathematics, natural science, the
common experience of men, have a high value as means, for the most part, to accidental ends but at last
also, to those which are necessary and essential to the existence of humanity. But to guide them to this high
goal, they require the aid of rational cognition on the basis of pure conceptions, which, be it termed as it may,
is properly nothing but metaphysics.
For the same reason, metaphysics forms likewise the completion of the culture of human reason. In this
respect, it is indispensable, setting aside altogether the influence which it exerts as a science. For its
subjectmatter is the elements and highest maxims of reason, which form the basis of the possibility of some
sciences and of the use of all. That, as a purely speculative science, it is more useful in preventing error than
in the extension of knowledge, does not detract from its value; on the contrary, the supreme office of censor
which it occupies assures to it the highest authority and importance. This office it administers for the purpose
of securing order, harmony, and wellbeing to science, and of directing its noble and fruitful labours to the
highest possible aim the happiness of all mankind.
CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason.
This title is placed here merely for the purpose of designating a division of the system of pure reason of
which I do not intend to treat at present. I shall content myself with casting a cursory glance, from a purely
transcendental point of view that of the nature of pure reason on the labours of philosophers up to the
present time. They have aimed at erecting an edifice of philosophy; but to my eye this edifice appears to be in
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason. 271
Page No 276
a very ruinous condition.
It is very remarkable, although naturally it could not have been otherwise, that, in the infancy of philosophy,
the study of the nature of God and the constitution of a future world formed the commencement, rather than
the conclusion, as we should have it, of the speculative efforts of the human mind. However rude the
religious conceptions generated by the remains of the old manners and customs of a less cultivated time, the
intelligent classes were not thereby prevented from devoting themselves to free inquiry into the existence and
nature of God; and they easily saw that there could be no surer way of pleasing the invisible ruler of the
world, and of attaining to happiness in another world at least, than a good and honest course of life in this.
Thus theology and morals formed the two chief motives, or rather the points of attraction in all abstract
inquiries. But it was the former that especially occupied the attention of speculative reason, and which
afterwards became so celebrated under the name of metaphysics.
I shall not at present indicate the periods of time at which the greatest changes in metaphysics took place, but
shall merely give a hasty sketch of the different ideas which occasioned the most important revolutions in this
sphere of thought. There are three different ends in relation to which these revolutions have taken place.
1. In relation to the object of the cognition of reason, philosophers may be divided into sensualists and
intellectualists. Epicurus may be regarded as the head of the former, Plato of the latter. The distinction here
signalized, subtle as it is, dates from the earliest times, and was long maintained. The former asserted that
reality resides in sensuous objects alone, and that everything else is merely imaginary; the latter, that the
senses are the parents of illusion and that truth is to be found in the understanding alone. The former did not
deny to the conceptions of the understanding a certain kind of reality; but with them it was merely logical,
with the others it was mystical. The former admitted intellectual conceptions, but declared that sensuous
objects alone possessed real existence. The latter maintained that all real objects were intelligible, and
believed that the pure understanding possessed a faculty of intuition apart from sense, which, in their opinion,
served only to confuse the ideas of the understanding.
2. In relation to the origin of the pure cognitions of reason, we find one school maintaining that they are
derived entirely from experience, and another that they have their origin in reason alone. Aristotle may be
regarded as the bead of the empiricists, and Plato of the noologists. Locke, the follower of Aristotle in
modern times, and Leibnitz of Plato (although he cannot be said to have imitated him in his mysticism), have
not been able to bring this question to a settled conclusion. The procedure of Epicurus in his sensual system,
in which he always restricted his conclusions to the sphere of experience, was much more consequent than
that of Aristotle and Locke. The latter especially, after having derived all the conceptions and principles of
the mind from experience, goes so far, in the employment of these conceptions and principles, as to maintain
that we can prove the existence of God and the existence of God and the immortality of them objects lying
beyond the soul both of them of possible experience with the same force of demonstration as any
mathematical proposition.
3. In relation to method. Method is procedure according to principles. We may divide the methods at present
employed in the field of inquiry into the naturalistic and the scientific. The naturalist of pure reason lays it
down as his principle that common reason, without the aid of science which he calls sound reason, or
common sense can give a more satisfactory answer to the most important questions of metaphysics than
speculation is able to do. He must maintain, therefore, that we can determine the content and circumference
of the moon more certainly by the naked eye, than by the aid of mathematical reasoning. But this system is
mere misology reduced to principles; and, what is the most absurd thing in this doctrine, the neglect of all
scientific means is paraded as a peculiar method of extending our cognition. As regards those who are
naturalists because they know no better, they are certainly not to be blamed. They follow common sense,
without parading their ignorance as a method which is to teach us the wonderful secret, how we are to find
the truth which lies at the bottom of the well of Democritus.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason. 272
Page No 277
Quod sapio satis est mihi, non ego curo Esse quod
Arcesilas aerumnosique Solones. PERSIUS* is their motto, under which they may lead a pleasant and praise
worthy life, without troubling themselves with science or troubling science with them.
*[Satirae, iii. 7879. "What I know is enough for I don't care to be what Arcesilas was, and the wretched
Solons."]
As regards those who wish to pursue a scientific method, they have now the choice of following either the
dogmatical or the sceptical, while they are bound never to desert the systematic mode of procedure. When I
mention, in relation to the former, the celebrated Wolf, and as regards the latter, David Hume, I may leave, in
accordance with my present intention, all others unnamed. The critical path alone is still open. If my reader
has been kind and patient enough to accompany me on this hitherto untravelled route, he can now judge
whether, if he and others will contribute their exertions towards making this narrow footpath a high road of
thought, that which many centuries have failed to accomplish may not be executed before the close of the
present namely, to bring Reason to perfect contentment in regard to that which has always, but without
permanent results, occupied her powers and engaged her ardent desire for knowledge.
The Critique of Pure Reason
CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason. 273
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. The Critique of Pure Reason, page = 6
3. Immanuel Kant, page = 6
4. PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781, page = 7
5. PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787, page = 11
6. INTRODUCTION., page = 20
7. I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge, page = 20
8. II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State, is in Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori"., page = 21
9. III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall Determine the Possibility, Principles, and Extent of Human Knowledge "a priori", page = 22
10. IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements., page = 23
11. V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements "a priori" are contained as Principles., page = 24
12. VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason., page = 26
13. VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the Name of a Critique of Pure Reason., page = 28
14. SS I. Introductory., page = 29
15. SECTION I. Of Space., page = 30
16. SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception., page = 30
17. SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space., page = 31
18. SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions., page = 32
19. SECTION II. Of Time., page = 33
20. SS 5 Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception., page = 33
21. SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time., page = 34
22. SS 7 Conclusions from the above Conceptions., page = 34
23. SS 8 Elucidation., page = 35
24. SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic., page = 37
25. SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic., page = 41
26. Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC. SS I., page = 45
27. BOOK I., page = 46
28. SS 2 Analytic of Conceptions. , page = 46
29. CHAPTER I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure Conceptions of the Understanding., page = 46
30. SS 3. Introductory. , page = 46
31. SECTION I. Of defined above Use of understanding in General. , page = 46
32. SS 4, page = 46
33. SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgements. , page = 47
34. SS 5. , page = 47
35. SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or Categories., page = 49
36. SS 6, page = 49
37. SS 7, page = 52
38. SS 8, page = 53
39. CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding., page = 54
40. SECTION I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in general. , page = 54
41. SS 9, page = 54
42. Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. SS 10, page = 56
43. SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of the Understanding. , page = 58
44. SS 11 Of the Possibility of a Conjunction of the manifold representations given by Sense., page = 58
45. Of the Originally Synthetical Unity of Apperception. SS 12, page = 58
46. The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception is the highest Principle of all exercise of the Understanding. SS 13, page = 60
47. What Objective Unity of Self-consciousness is. SS 14, page = 61
48. The Logical Form of all Judgements consists in the Objective Unity of Apperception of the Conceptions contained therein. SS 15, page = 61
49. All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as Conditions under which alone the manifold Content of them can be united in one Consciousness. SS 16, page = 62
50. Observation. SS 17, page = 62
51. In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is the only legitimate use of the Category. SS 18, page = 63
52. SS 19, page = 63
53. Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the Senses in general. SS 20, page = 64
54. SS 21, page = 66
55. Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the Understanding. SS 23, page = 68
56. BOOK II. Analytic of Principles., page = 70
57. CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding., page = 71
58. CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding., page = 75
59. SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements., page = 76
60. SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements., page = 77
61. SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical Principles of the Pure Understanding., page = 78
62. CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects into Phenomena and Noumena., page = 108
63. I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance., page = 123
64. BOOK I. OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON., page = 128
65. SECTION I - Of Ideas in General., page = 129
66. SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas., page = 131
67. SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas., page = 135
68. BOOK II. OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON., page = 137
69. CHAPTER I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason., page = 137
70. CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason., page = 147
71. SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas., page = 148
72. SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason., page = 152
73. SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these Self-contradictions., page = 164
74. SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental Problems., page = 168
75. SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems presented in the four Transcendental Ideas., page = 171
76. SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Pure Cosmological Dialectic., page = 173
77. SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem., page = 174
78. SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation to the Cosmological Ideas., page = 177
79. SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas., page = 179
80. CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason., page = 194
81. SECTION I. Of the Ideal in General., page = 194
82. SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon Trancendentale)., page = 195
83. SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being., page = 199
84. SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God., page = 201
85. SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God., page = 205
86. SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a Physico-Theological Proof., page = 210
87. SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative Principles of Reason., page = 213
88. CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason., page = 235
89. SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere of Dogmatism., page = 236
90. SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics., page = 244
91. SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis., page = 253
92. SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation to Proofs., page = 256
93. CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason., page = 260
94. SECTION I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason., page = 260
95. SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason., page = 262
96. SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief., page = 267
97. CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason., page = 271
98. CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason., page = 276