Title: The Graves of Academe
Subject:
Author: Richard Mitchell
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
The Graves of Academe
Richard Mitchell
Page No 2
Table of Contents
The Graves of Academe ......................................................................................................................................1
Richard Mitchell......................................................................................................................................1
Contents...............................................................................................................................................................2
Foreword .............................................................................................................................................................3
Propositions Three and Seven ...........................................................................................................................4
The End of the String......................................................................................................................................11
The Wundter of It All......................................................................................................................................20
The Seven Deadly Principles ...........................................................................................................................32
The Principles March On ................................................................................................................................41
The Pygmies' Revenge.....................................................................................................................................52
ProblemSolving in the Content Area...........................................................................................................65
Every Three Second .........................................................................................................................................80
Afterword: Plus Ça Change ............................................................................................................................91
The Graves of Academe
i
Page No 3
The Graves of Academe
Richard Mitchell
Foreword
Propositions Three and Seven
The End of the String
The Wundter of It All
The Seven Deadly Principles
The Principles March On
The Pygmies' Revenge
ProblemSolving in the Content Area
Every Three Second
Afterword: Plus Ça Change
It is ordained in the eternal constitution of things that men of intemperate minds cannot be
free; their passions forge their fetters.
Edmund Burke
Praised by critics across the nation, The Graves of Academe is Richard Mitchell's angry and brilliant tour
through America's bloated public school system whose mangled, selfserving language and policies
would make Orwell wince. Stamped with vintage Mitchell wit and laced with stinging examples from The
Underground Grammarian, The Graves of Academe pinpoints the historic sources of the mindboggling
``educationist'' bureaucracy and reveals why today's schools are riddled not only with illiterate students but
with illiterate teachers and administrators as well.
The Graves of Academe is a book of the highest importance...its slashing and irrefutable attack, not on
teachers, but on the educational establishment that trains them and which his trained us...Mr. Mitchell is
invaluable. Also he's enormously entertaining: Clifton Fadiman
``This is one of those books that seem to make such eminent common sense that you feel compelled to read
aloud selected passages to those within hearing regardless of whether they want to listen.'' Dallas Times
Herald
``...makes H.L. Mencken sound like a waffler.'' Time
``Mitchell is a brilliant stylist, a shrewd observer and a genuine wit.'' National Review
``...a delightfully satirical book on the malaise of the American educational system, `the professional
educator,' the people who, in the eyes of the authors Richard Mitchell, are responsible for the deplorable state
of American English...Amen and hallelujah, this is fine reading.'' Charleston Evening Post
``...this angry, witty, and very accurate assessment of the current educational scene should be required
reading for every parent who has or will have children in what Mitchell calls `The Great Dismal Swamp' of
public education.'' Fresno Bee
``Witty, literate, thoughtful and provocative...'' Atlantic City Sunday Press
The Graves of Academe 1
Page No 4
Contents
The Graves of Academe
Contents 2
Page No 5
Foreword
This book started out to be a large collection of pieces from The Underground Grammarian, a dissident if
tiny journal that has achieved notoriety if not fame, and to which I am a party. Such a collection was
proposed by a publisher (not, I am happy to say, my publisher) and recommended as a nottoodifficult task.
My own publisher, Little, Brown, although wise enough not to suggest such a venture, was nevertheless not
as prudent when it came to signing a contract.
I spent several months choosing, ordering, and contemplating selections from The Underground
Grammarian, intending to sort them by themes and stitch them together with running commentaries,
elaborations, and second thoughts. Even third thoughts. It turned out a stupid and pointless exercise. If there
is anyone who thinks that the world needs such a collection, let him make it.
What stopped me was this: As I went through scores of essays on the relation of language to the work of the
mind and critical commentaries on displays of ignorance and stupidity in the written work of academicians, I
could see that some were more important than others. They suggested a single theme. They were all more or
less about the same thing, that special and unmistakable kind of mendacious babble that characterizes
not politicians or businessmen, not Pentagon spokesmen or commercial hucksters, but, always and only,
those members of the academic community who are pleased to call themselves the ``professionals'' of
education. Those pieces, taken together, seemed to me at least a skimpy outline, or, better, scattered reference
points suggesting something much larger and more momentous than a mere collection of ponderous inanities.
It seemed to me that I could, from certain of those small articles, make out the murky form of the hidden
monster whose mere projections they were, breaking here and there the oily surface of some dark pool.
As a result, I abandoned the collection and undertook the task of describing, by extrapolation from one visible
protuberance to another, and with a little probing, the great invisible hulk of the beast, the brooding
monstrosity of American educationism, the immense, mindless brute that by now troubles the waters of all,
all that is done in our land in the supposed cause of ``education,'' since when, as you see, I can rarely bring
myself to write that word without quotation marks, or even fashion a sentence less than nine or ten lines long,
lest I inadvertently fail to suggest the creature's awesome dimensions and seemingly endless tentacular
complexities. I will try to do better. The somber subject requires clarity.
Thou canst not, however, draw out this Leviathan with an hook either. A complete, thoughtful history and
analysis of American educationism would require several fat volumes, and even the author's best friends
would not read it. It is, after all, a boring subject. I have done my best to make it interesting by dwelling on
its startling and horrifying attributes, which are, in any case, the most important indicators of its harmful
powers. It's not a pretty sight. I have been, too, as brief as possible. In consequence, there is probably no
understanding in this book of which it is not possible to say: ``Well, true, but there's more to it than that.''
Quite so. I hope that many will someday look for the ``more,'' but I will be content, for now, with the ``true.''
I have everywhere provided as true an understanding as I can discover, and I am persuaded that a
comprehensive and detailed historical analysis will, if it ever appears, show that my assessment of American
educationism is encyclopaedically incomplete but right anyway. The prodigious monster is down there, I
know, and even if its tentacles and appendages, its gross organs and protrusions, its subtle convolutions and
recesses, are invisible, I have still seen enough to know the nature of the beast.
Foreword 3
Page No 6
Propositions Three and Seven
In the country of the blind, the oneeyed man is, as we all know, king. And across the way, in the country of
the witless, the halfwit is king. And why not? It's only natural, and considering the circumstances, not really
a bad system. We do the best we can.
But it is a system with some unhappy consequences. The oneeyed man knows that he could never be king in
the land of the twoeyed, and the halfwit knows that he would be small potatoes indeed in a land where
most people had all or most of their wits about them. These rulers, therefore, will be inordinately selective
about their social programs, which will be designed not only to protect against the rise of the witful and the
sighted, but, just as important, to ensure a neverfailing supply of the witless and utterly blind. Even to the
halfwit and the oneeyed man, it is clear that other halfwits and oneeyed men are potential competitors
and supplanters, and they invert the ancient tale in which an anxious tyrant kept watch against a
onesandaled stranger by keeping watch against wanderers with both eyes and operating minds. Uneasy lies
the head.
Unfortunately, most people are born with two eyes and even the propensity to think. If nothing is done about
this, chaos, obviously, threatens the land. Even worse, unemployment threatens the oneeyed man and the
halfwit. However, since they do in fact rule, those potentates have not much to fear, for they can command
the construction and perpetuation of a statesupported and legally enforced system for the early detection and
obliteration of antisocial traits, and thus arrange that witfulness and 2020 vision will trouble the land as little
as possible. The system is called ``education.''
Such is our case. Nor should that surprise anyone. Like living creatures, institutions intend primarily to live
and do whatever else they do only to that end. Unlike some living creatures, however, who do in fact
occasionally decide that there is something even more to be prized than their own survival, institutions are
never capable of altruism, heroism, or even selfdenial. If you imagine that they are, if, for instance, you
fancy that the welfare system or the Federal Reserve exists and labors for ``the good of the people,'' then you
can be sure that the minions of the oneeyed man and the halfwit are pleased with you.
Furthermore, any institution that still stands must, by that very fact, be successful. When we say, as we seem
to more and more these days, that education in America is ``failing,'' it is because we don't understand the
institution. It is, in fact, succeeding enormously. It grows daily, hourly, in power and wealth, and that
precisely because of our accusations of failure. The more we complain against it, the more it can lay claim to
our power and wealth, in the name of curing those ills of which we complain. And, in our special case, in a
land ostensibly committed to individual freedom and rights, it can and does make the ultimate claim to be,
that is, the free, universal system of public education that alone can raise up to a free land citizens who will
understand and love and defend individual freedom and rights. Like any politician, the institution of
education claims direct descent in apostolic succession from the Founding Fathers.
Jefferson was in favor of education, indubitably, but he meant the condition, not the word. He held that there
was no expectation, ``in a state of civilization,'' that we could be both free and ignorant. The modifier is
important; it is to suggest that we might indeed be ``free'' and ignorant in savagery. Free at least from the
conventional and mutually admitted restraints to which civilized people bind themselves.
Using Jefferson's terms, we can derive exactly eight propositions to think about:
>
We can be ignorant and free in savagery.
>
Propositions Three and Seven 4
Page No 7
We can be ignorant and free in civilization.
>
We can be ignorant and unfree in civilization.
>
We can be ignorant and unfree in savagery.
>
We can be educated and free in savagery.
>
We can be educated and free in civilization.
>
We can be educated and unfree in civilization.
>
We can be educated and unfree in savagery.
Jefferson asserts that the second is impossible, thereby implying the possibility of the first and the sixth. The
fifth and the eighth seem unlikely, for if we are indeed educated it will be both a result of civilization and a
cause of civilization. The fourth is just a quibble, for the ``freedom'' at issue is not freedom from natural
exigencies, to which all are subject, but from the devised constraints possible only in a state of civilization.
The truth of the third and the seventh, unhappily, is recommended by knowledge and experience.
Omitting those propositions that seem impossible or meaningless, we are left with:
>
We can be ignorant and free in savagery.
>
We can be ignorant and unfree in civilization.
>
We can be educated and free in civilization.
>
We can be educated and unfree in civilization.
And, of those four, Propositions 1 and 6 are explicitly Jefferson's, while 3 and 7 are implicitly Jefferson's.
They describe conditions not only perfectly possible but perfectly real. Unfreedom, the forced submission to
constraints beyond those mutually admitted by knowing and willing members of a civilization, is not unheard
of. Indeed, it is, in greater or less degree, the current condition of all humanity.
Civilization is itself an institution and has, like all institutions, one paramount goal, its own perpetuation. It
was Jefferson's dream that that civilization could best perpetuate itself in which the citizens were ``educated,''
whatever he meant by that, and we do have some clue as to what he meant. He wrote of the ``informed
discretion'' of the people as the only acceptable depository of power in a republic. He knew very well that the
people might be neither informed nor discreet, that is, able to make fine distinctions, but held that the remedy
for that was not to be sought in depriving the people of their proper power but in better informing their
discretion.
And to what end were the people to exercise the power of their informed discretion? The answer, of course,
shouldn't be surprising, but, because we have been taught to confuse government and its institutions with
civilization in general, it often is. Jefferson saw the informed discretion of the people as one of those checks
and balances for which our constitutional democracy is justly famous, for it was only with such a power that
the people could defend themselves against government and its institutions. ``The functionaries of
every government,'' wrote Jefferson, although the italics are mine, ``have propensities to command at will the
liberty and property of their constituents.'' Jefferson knew isn't this the unique genius of American
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 5
Page No 8
constitutionalism? that government was a dangerous master and a treacherous servant and that the first
concern of free people was to keep their government on a leash, a pretty short one at that.
Consider again Propositions 3 and 7: 3. We can be ignorant and unfree in civilization, and 7. We can be
educated and unfree in civilization. Imagine that you are one of those functionaries of government in whom
there has grown, it seems inescapable, the propensity to command, in however oblique a fashion and for
whatever supposedly good purpose, the liberty and property of your constituents. Which would you prefer,
educated constituents or ignorant ones? Wait. Be sure to answer the question in Jefferson's terms. Which
would you rather face, even considering your own conviction that the cause in which you want to command
liberty and property is just citizens with or without the power of informed discretion? Citizens having that
power will require of you a laborious and detailed justification of your intentions and expectations and may,
even having that, adduce other information and exercise further discretion to the contrary of your
propensities. On the other hand, the illinformed and undiscriminating can easily be persuaded by the
recitation of popular slogans and the appeal to selfinterest, however spurious. It is only informed discretion
that can detect such maneuvers.
And that's how government works. There is nothing evil about it. It's perfectly natural. You and I would do it
the same way. In fact, the chances are good that we are doing things that way, since more and more of us are
in fact functionaries of government in one way or another and dependent for our daily bread on some share of
the property of our constituents, and sometimes (as in the public schools) upon the restriction of their liberty.
It was the genius of Jefferson to see that free people would rarely have to defend their freedom against
principalities and powers and satanic enemies of the good, but that they would have to defend it daily against
the perfectly natural and inevitable propensities of functionaries. Any fool, can see, eventually, the danger to
freedom in a selfconfessed military dictatorship, but it takes informed discretion to see the same danger in
bland bureaucracies made up entirely of decent people who are just doing their jobs. But Jefferson was
optimistic. As to the liberty and property of the people, he saw that ``there is no safe deposit for them but
with the people themselves; nor can they be safe with them without information.'' And he was convinced,
alas, that the people could easily come by that information: ``Where the press is free, and every man able to
read, all is secure.''
That sounds so simple. A free press, and universal literacy. We have those things, don't we? So all is secure,
no? No.
Just as we cannot assume that what we call ``education'' is the same as Jefferson's ``informed discretion,'' we
cannot assume that Jefferson meant what we mean by ``press'' and ``able to read.'' In our time, the press, in
spite of threats real or imagined, is in fact free. And, if we define ``literacy'' in a very special and limited way,
almost everyone is able to read, more or less. But when Jefferson looked at ``the press,'' what did he see? Or,
more to the point, what did he not see? He did not see monthly periodicals devoted entirely to such things as
hair care and motorcycling and the imagined intimate details of the lives of television stars and rock singers.
He did not see a sports page, a fashion page, a household hints column, or an astrological forecast. He did not
see a neverending succession of breathless articles on lowbudget decorating for the executive couple in the
big city, career enhancement through creative haberdashery, and the achievement of orgasm through
enlightened selfinterest. He did not see a nationwide portrayal of ``the important'' as composed primarily of
the doings and undoings of entertainers, athletes, politicians, and criminals.
He would not, I think, have been unduly dismayed by all that. Of course, he would have been dismayed, but
not unduly. Such things are implicit in the freedom of the press, and if enough people want them, they'll have
them. (Jefferson would surely have wondered why so many people wanted such things, but that's not to the
point just now.) Jefferson did, naturally, see ``the press'' giving news and information, but, more than that, he
also saw in it the very practice of informed discretion. In his time, after all, Common Sense and The
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 6
Page No 9
Federalist Papers were simply parts of ``the press.'' And ``every man able to read'' would have been, for
Jefferson, every man able to read, weigh, and consider things like Common Sense and The Federalist Papers.
He would have recognized at once our editorial pages and our journals of enquiry and opinion, but he would
have found it ominous that hardly anyone reads those things, and positively portentous that this omission
arises not so much from casual neglect as from a common and measurable inability to read such things with
either comprehension or pleasure.
Thus Jefferson is cheated. The press is free and almost everyone can make out many words, but all is not
secure. Wait. That's not quite clear. Some things are secure. The agencies and institutions of government are
secure. The functionaries whose propensity it is to command our liberty and property, they are secure. And,
as the oneeyed man is the more secure in proportion to the number of citizens he can blind, our
functionaries are the more secure in proportion to those of us who are strangers to the powers of informed
discretion. It is possible, of course, to keep educated people unfree in a state of civilization, but it's much
easier to keep ignorant people unfree in a state of civilization. And it is easiest of all if you can convince the
ignorant that they are educated, for you can thus make them collaborators in your disposition of their liberty
and property. That is the institutionally assigned task, for all that it may be invisible to those who perform it,
of American public education.
Public education does its work superbly, almost perfectly. It works in fairly strict accordance with its own
implicit theory of ``education,'' an elaborate ideology of which only some small details are generally known
to the public. This is hardly surprising, for the rare citizen who actually wants to know something about
educationistic theory, a dismal subject, finds that it is habitually expressed in tangled, ungrammatical jargon,
penetrable, when it is at all, only to one who has nothing better to do. I hope, little by little, to dissect and
elucidate that theory, for it is in fact even more frightening than it is dismal. For now, I can take only a first
but essential step and urge you to consider this principle: The clouded language of educational theory is an
evolved, protective adaptation that hinders thought and understanding. As such, it is no more the result of
conscious intention than the markings of a moth. But it works. Thus, those who give themselves to the
presumed study and the presumptuous promulgation of educational theory are usually both deceivers
and deceived. The murky language where their minds habitually dwell at once unminds them and gives them
the power to unmind others.
We will, with appropriate examples, explore the evolution of that strange trait, especially in that portion of
the educational establishment where it is most evident: that is, among the people to whom we have given the
training of teachers and the formulation of educational theory. In the cumbersome and complicated
contraption we call ``public education,'' the trainers of teachers have special powers and privileges. Although
in law they are governed by civilian boards and legislatures, they are in fact but little governed, for they have
convinced the boards and legislatures that only teachertrainers can judge the work of teachertrainers. That
wasn't hard to do, for boards and legislatures are made up largely of people who have, in their time, already
been blinded by the oneeyed man, having been given, as helpless children, what we call ``education'' rather
than practice in informed discretion. The very language in which the teachertrainers explain their labors will
quickly discourage close scrutiny in even a thoughtful board member, perhaps especially in a thoughtful
board member, who has after all, other and more important (he thinks) things to do.
It is not strictly true that the public schools are a statesupported monopoly. There are other schools. But the
teachertrainers are certainly a statesupported monopoly. There are no other teachertrainers than the ones
we have, and they are all in the business of teaching something they call ``education.'' No one knows exactly
what that is, and even among educationists there is some mild contention as to whether there actually exists
some body of knowledge that can be called ``education'' as separate from other knowable subjects. You may
want to make up your own mind as to that, for in later chapters you will see examples of what is actually
done by those who teach ``education.'' But for now we must consider the usually unnoticed effects of the
monopoly they enjoy.
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 7
Page No 10
The laws of supply and demand work in the academic world just as they do in the marketplace, which is to
say, of course, that what is natural and reasonable will not happen where government intervenes. Our schools
can be usefully likened to a nationalized industrial system in which the production of goods is directed not by
entrepreneurs looking to profit but by social planners intending to change the world. Thus it is the business of
the schools, and the special task of the educationists who produce teachers, to generate both supply
and demand, so that the nation will want exactly what it is they intend to provide.
Within the academic marketplace, there are many enterprises other than educationism, however. Historically,
they have not seen themselves in competition with one another, although I'm sure that the faculties of the
medieval universities were not reluctant to claim that their disciplines were more noble than the others.
Individual professors, of course, must indeed have competed for students, by whom they were paid, but the
students, many of whom were to become professors themselves, were free to devote themselves to whatever
discipline seemed good. But between one discipline and another there seems to have been, rather than
competition, sectarianism.
A similar sectarianism has been revivified by our current educational disorders. If you ask a professor of
geography why we seem to be turning into a nation of ignorant rabble, he will not be able to refrain from
pointing out that we don't teach geography anymore and that high school graduates aren't even sure of the
name of the next state, never mind the climatic characteristics of the Great Plains or the rivers that drain the
Ohio Valley. Professors of physics will allude to the alltooinevitable consequences of ignorance of the
laws of motion and thermodynamics. You can easily devise for yourself the comments of professors of
mathematics, languages, history, literature, and indeed of any who teach those things we think of as
traditional academic disciplines. Their views will be, of course, at least partly predictable expressions of
selfinterest; however, they will also be correct, and, if taken all together, will indeed tell us much about our
present troubles.
The academic world is like any other group of related enterprises in which everybody can provide something
but nobody can provide everything. For the building of houses, for instance, we need many different things,
and they are not easily interchangeable. When we need copper tubing, we need copper tubing, and we can't
make do with wallboard instead. If houses are built, therefore, many people making many different things
will be able to produce what is both useful and profitable. And, while the makers of copper tubing won't have
to worry about competition from the makers of wallboard, they will have to be mindful of other makers of
copper tubing and also of the makers of plastic tubing. That will be good for the whole enterprise.
Suppose, though, that the coppertubing people should, through quirk or cunning, secure for themselves
some special legal privilege. First they persuade the state, which already has the power to license the building
of houses, to prohibit the use of plastic tubing. That's good, but so long as the state is willing to go that far,
the coppertubing makers seek and achieve a regulation requiring some absolute minimum quantity of
copper tubing in every new house. Now you must suppose that the coppertubing lobby has grown so rich
and powerful that the law now requires that fifty percent of the mass of every new house must be made up of
copper tubing.
Houses could still be built. Walls, floors, and ceilings could be made of coils and bundles of copper tubing
smeared over with plaster or stucco. Copper tubing could be cleverly welded and twisted into everything
from doorknobs to windowsills and produced in large sizes for heating ducts and chimneys. The houses
would be dreadful, of course, and, should you ask why, you will discover that craftsmen in the building trades
are more direct and outspoken than college professors. They'll just tell you straight out that these are lousy
houses because of all that damn copper tubing. If the professor of mathematics were equally frank, he'd tell
you that our schools are full of supposed teachers of mathematics who have studied ``education'' when they
should have studied mathematics.
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 8
Page No 11
This is, I admit, not an exact analogy. The manufacture of copper tubing actually does have some relationship
to the building of houses, while the study of ``education'' has no relationship at all to the making of educated
people. The analogy would perhaps have been better had I chosen, instead of the manufacturers of copper
tubing, the manufacturers of gelatin desserts. To grasp the true nature of the place of educationism in the
academic world, you have to imagine that houses are to be made mostly of JellO each flavor equally
represented and that the builders must eat a bowl an hour.
(Well, that analogy fails, too. JellO is at least a colorful and entertaining treat with no known harmful side
effects. The same cannot be said of the study of ``education.'')
Our public system of education, from Head Start to the graduate schools of the state universities, might also
be called a government system. Those who teach in its primary and secondary schools are required by law to
serve time, often as much as one half of their undergraduate program, in the classes of the teachertrainers.
Should they seek graduate degrees, which will bring them automatic raises, they will still have to spend about
one half their time taking yet again courses devoted to things like interpersonal relations and the appreciation
of alternative remediation enhancements. The educationistic monopoly is strong enough that in at least one
state (there are probably others, but I'm afraid to find out), a high school mathematics teacher who is arrogant
enough to take a master's degree in mathematics will discover that he is no longer certified to teach that
subject. If he wants to keep his job, he must take a degree in ``mathematics education,'' which will, of course,
permit him to spend some of his time studying his subject. Even where there is no such visibly monopolistic
requirement, the laws and regulations of the public schools, which have been devised by educationists in the
teachers' colleges, provide an effective equivalent.
The intellectual climate of the public schools, which must inevitably become the intellectual climate of the
nation, does not seem to be conducive to the spread of what Jefferson called informed discretion. The
intellectual climate of the nation today came from the public schools, where almost every one of us was
schooled in the work of the mind. We are a people who imagine that we are weighing important issues when
we exchange generalizations and wellknown opinions. We decide how to vote or what to buy according to
whim or fancied selfinterest, either of which is easily engendered in us by the manipulation of language,
which we have neither the will nor the ability to analyze. We believe that we can reach conclusions without
having the faintest idea of the difference between inferences and statements of fact, often without any
suspicions that there are such things and that they are different. We are easily persuaded and repersuaded by
what seems authoritative, without any notion of those attributes and abilities that characterize authority. We
do not notice elementary fallacies in logic; it doesn't even occur to us to look for them; few of us are even
aware that such things exist. We make no regular distinctions between those kinds of things that can be
known and objectively verified and those that can only be believed or not. Nor are we likely to examine,
when we believe or not, the induced predispositions that may make us do the one or the other. We are easy
prey.
That these seem to be the traits of the human condition always and everywhere is not to the point. They just
won't do for a free society. Jefferson and his friends made a revolution against ignorance and unreason, which
would preclude freedom in any form of government whatsoever. If we cannot make ourselves a
knowledgeable and thoughtful people those are the requisites of informed discretion then we cannot be
free. But our revolutionists did at least provide us with that form of government which, unlike others, does
grant the possibility of freedom, provided, of course, the public has the habit of informed discretion. That
possibility is all we have just now.
Proposition 3 is in effect. We are largely a nation of illinformed and casually thoughtless captives. Even
when we are wellinformed and thoughtful, however, we cannot be free where the character of the nation and
its institutions must reflect the ignorance and unreason of the popular will. But if we are wellinformed and
thoughtful, we can take comfort in the fact that our form of government is carefully designed to preclude that
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 9
Page No 12
condition described in Proposition 7. As long as we remain a constitutional republic, we cannot ever be both
educated and unfree. It just won't work, and that may be the single greatest insight of the makers of our
revolution.
Therefore, whatever it is they do in the teachers' colleges of America has had and will always have
tremendous consequences. By comparison with the attitudes and intellectual habits and ideological
predispositions inculcated in American teachers, the acts of Congress are trivial. Indeed, the latter proceed
from the former. If, as a result of the labors of our educationists, we were obviously clearsighted and
thoughtful and thus able to enjoy the freedom promised in our constitutional system, then we would know
something about those educationists. If, on the other hand, we are blind and witless, then we would know if
there are any of us who can know something else about them. To know anything at all about those
educationists, however, we must look at what they do, at what they say they do, and even at how they say
what they do.
The Graves of Academe
Propositions Three and Seven 10
Page No 13
The End of the String
As a schoolboy, I always presumed that my teachers were experts in the subjects that they taught. My physics
teacher must, of course, be a physicist, and my history teacher a historian. I knew that my music teacher was
a musician, for I had actually heard him play, and, during a dismal year in military school, I could see with
my own eyes that the Professor of Military Science and Tactics was a bird colonel.
Even when I became a schoolteacher myself, quite by accident, I imagined that I had been chosen for the
work because of my knowledge of the subject I was to teach. It turned out not to be exactly so, for I was soon
asked to teach something else, of which my knowledge was scanty. No matter, I was told. I could bone up
over the summer. Eventually, I was asked to teach something about which I knew nothing, nothing at all. Still
no matter. I seemed to be a fairly effective teacher and at least smart enough to stay a lesson or two ahead of
the students. That's just what I did. No one saw anything wrong with that, and the students never caught me.
It was nevertheless depressing, for it led me to suspect that my physics teacher perhaps hadn't been a
physicist after all.
What then, exactly, was he? What was it that made a teacher a teacher, if it wasn't, as it obviously wasn't, an
expert knowledge of some subject matter? How could it be that I was able to teach, to the complete
satisfaction of my colleagues and supervisors, and with no visible detriment to my students, a subject of
which I knew practically nothing at first, and of which, after a year of teaching it, I knew just about what
anyone could know of it after one year of study? Was there something wrong with that? Was there something
wrong with me that I suspected that there was something wrong with that?
It took me many years to find answers to those questions, and, when I did, it wasn't because I was looking for
them. It was because I finally settled in what was called a State Teachers College. (Like Pikes Peak, it had no
apostrophe.) As it happens, it is no longer a State Teachers College. The legislature later enacted a long and
complicated law which had, as far as I can tell, the sole effect of removing from that title the word
``Teachers.'' The college has not changed much, except that where it was once unashamedly a teachers'
college, it is now ashamedly a teachers' college. There I was, and I couldn't help looking around.
At the end of my first semester, I walked into a classroom where I was to give a final examination. (We don't
do much of that anymore, since it may just be a violation of someone's rights.) On the blackboard was the
final examination that had just been given to some other class. Very neatly written it was, too. The last
question I'll never forget it was worth fiftytwo percent of the grade: ``Draw all the letters of the alphabet,
both upper and lower case.'' Draw.
There is some truth in the ``ivory tower'' notion of academic life. I had spent my whole life in one school or
another, and I was, of course, faintly aware that I was only faintly aware of what was going on out in the
world. When I looked at that blackboard and imagined all those students dutifully ``drawing'' the alphabet in
their bluebooks, I realized that I didn't even know what was going on down at the other end of the hall.
Nevertheless, it still didn't occur to me that this astonishing examination had something to do with those
questions that I had long since stopped asking myself.
It turned out, of course, that what I had seen was a final examination in one of those ``education'' courses,
about which, at that time, I knew nothing. Well, that's not quite true: I did know one thing, because earlier
that semester I had looked into a classroom where something amazing was happening. There, in front of the
class, stood an unusually attractive young lady, a student, tricked out in a fetching bunny outfit not the kind
you're probably imagining, just a pair of paper ears pinned into her hair and a stunning puff of absorbent
cotton somehow or other tacked on behind and clothes, too, of course, but I can't recall any details. She was
reading aloud, with expression, and even with an occasional hop, from a large book spread out flat at about
The End of the String 11
Page No 14
hip level, glancing down at it remarkably infrequently. Large type. She was doing a practice lesson. I
awarded her instantly an A plus.
So I knew two things about the making of a teacher. Both seemed engaging rather than repellent. After all,
who can be against legible writing on the blackboard? To be sure, I myself wouldn't have assigned it a value
of more than half the grade on a final examination; perhaps, had it been in my charge to foster, I would
simply have required it as a tool of the trade without bestowing upon it any special credit at all. And it did
occur to me that what the students drew in their examination books might not be an accurate measure of their
skill in drawing the same things on a blackboard, an unusually intractable medium, but the motive seemed
good. And as for pretty girls in cunning outfits, what could be more cheering? It seemed to me that those
teachertrainers must be amiable and playful folk with welldeveloped aesthetic sensibilities and a penchant
for drama, in bold contrast to the rest of us who taught what you call ``subjects,'' dour and narrow people
reciting lectures and devising ``thought'' questions. And who knows? Could it be that I would now actually
remember the political consequences of Henry's sad pilgrimage to Canossa if only my history professor had
put on sackcloth and lectured on his knees?
And I began to watch the teachertrainers in idle moments, in my idle moments, that is, not theirs. They were
rarely idle. They were busy rumbling down the hall pushing metal carts laden with projectors and
loudspeakers, which they actually knew how to hook up and operate. I could hear them in the next classroom
shoving the desks into sociable circles so that, as in King Arthur's court, no one would be disadvantaged by
having to sit below the salt, or breaking up into small groups, so that understanding could be reached by
democratic consensus rather than imposed by authority. Sometimes whole classes could be heard singing a
delightful change of atmosphere in precincts otherwise darkened by realism and naturalism and the
intellectual despair of eminent Victorians.
All in all, I thought the teachertrainers harmless and childlike, optimistic and ingenuous. I knew, to be sure,
that many of them held what they called doctorates in things like comparative storage systems for badminton
supplies and for cafeteria management, but so what? They weren't pretending to teach anything that called for
traditional training in scholarship, were they? Doctorates in education, I remembered from my days in
graduate school, are much easier to get than any other kind, but what did that matter? A doctorate, after all
was just a union card, a ticket of admission to a remarkably good life, and why shouldn't those decent and
wellmeaning people have doctorates just like everybody else? As to whether what they did had any value in
the training of teachers, I just didn't know. I wasn't curious enough to pay thoughtful attention, and they didn't
seem to be hurting anyone. Live and let live.
So I did. Once the novelty of their techniques wore off, and long before it dawned on me that those
techniques were better called ``antics,'' I just stopped thinking about them. The teachertrainers were not in
my mind at all when I started to publish The Underground Grammarian in 1976. The Bicentennial Year was
in my mind, and Tom Paine and even William Lloyd Garrison, and, most of all, the ghastly, fractured,
ignorant English that is routinely written and spread around by college administrators, the people charged
with the making and executing of policy in the cause of higher education in America. I presumed that those
administrators would be the natural prey of a journal devoted to the display of ignorance in unlikely places. It
never even struck me then that most administrators were once the teachertrainers who were not in my mind.
And I will beg your indulgence, reader, in suggesting that when you look at the world and wonder what's
going on, the teachertrainers are not in your mind. Nuclear weapons and taxes are in your mind, along with
politicians and other criminals. Pollution and racial discord are in your mind. Prices double and pleasures
dwindle, violence and ignorance multiply and expectations diminish, and all the season's new television
shows are aimed at demented children, and master sergeants have to puzzle out in comicbook style manuals
how to pull the triggers on their Titan missiles, and sometimes, in a moment of pure panic, you wonder
whether you shouldn't have voted for Goldwater after all. And when you wave a finger this way and that,
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 12
Page No 15
trying to point it at someone, anyone, the teachertrainers are not in your mind.
Sometimes, to be sure, you do suspect and even indict ``the schools.'' Ah, if only ``the schools'' would do this
or that. But what? Everybody has a formula, sort of. Money, obviously, isn't the answer. They have money
beyond counting. Less money can hardly be the answer just ask the National Education Association. So
what are we to do? Public schools? Private schools? Vouchers? Integration? Remediation? Consolidation?
Back to basics? Forward to relevancy in bold innovative thrusts?
Then again, you may not even ask these questions, for to do so is to see a connection that not many
Americans have thought to make. Millions of us have nothing at all to do with the schools. We have no
children in the schools, and we don't know what they're doing, and we don't much care, except about the
taxes we pay to support the enterprise. We can easily think of many things that must be far more important
than education, a notably dreary topic in any case. Surely politics is more important than education. So is
economics. Technology. National defense. Even art! And the six o'clock news in any city in the land makes it
perfectly clear that the most important things that happened in your part of the world today were murders,
rapes, and a fire of unknown origin in an abandoned warehouse. And as for the schools, most of us just hope
that they'll teach the children to read and write and cipher someday soon and just not bother us. We have all
those important things to worry about and we really can't be bothered with wondering about whether the
schools should experiment with a groundbreaking return to the selfcontained classroom.
In fact, the destiny of this land, of any land, is exactly and inevitably determined by the nature and abilities of
the children now in school. The future simply has no other resources. And, an even more dismaying fact,
because it tells of us, not them, this land as it is today is the exact and inevitable result of the nature and
abilities of the schoolchildren that we were. And the things that you think important, everything from the
politics to the rapes and murders and fires, are what they are and have for us the meanings that they have
precisely because of what we were.
Public education, because it is so nearly universal and because, notwithstanding minor variations, it is a
monolithic and selfsustaining institution, has more power to create our national character than anything else
in America. While it does not bring us oil shortages or volcanic eruptions, it does determine what we will
think and do about such things. It determines what we will feel and how we will do the work of the mind.
This should not be surprising. You, and you alone, could do as much if you could somehow manage to
influence almost every American child day after day for about twelve years, although, as an individual
controlling consciousness, you would probably do a better job in many respects. There is, of course, no
individual controlling consciousness in the institution of education no villain need be but the institution,
like any institution, has a kind of mind and will of its own. It changes, if at all, only very slowly, and, since
you don't find it as important as politics or fire, it changes only at the will of those relatively few people who
actually do find it important, because they live by it. Nor is it their will and why should it be ? to make
any change that is not in their selfinterest. ``They,'' of course are a loosely confederated host of
administrators, bureaucrats, consultants, professors, researchers, and Heaven only knows how many other
titled functionaries. They are a very diverse group, but they have, with astonishingly rare exceptions, one
thing in common. They have all been through the process that we call teachertraining, and most of them
have done some of that themselves. They are the people who are not in your mind when you wonder what the
hell is happening to us.
And they would never have gotten back into my mind had I not undertaken, for what I now think frivolous
reasons, what turned out to be a serious and infuriating study of the use of language, a study that had to lead
to a consideration of the meaning of the use of language. That study is, of course, the business of The
Underground Grammarian, which has been accurately enough described as a journal of radical, academic
terrorism. It is radical because it seeks in language the root of the thoughtlessness that more and more seems
to characterize our culture. It is academic both because the tenor of the study to which it subjects the work of
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 13
Page No 16
its victims is scholastic and because it finds the most egregious examples of mindless and mendacious babble
neither in the corporation nor in the Congress but in the schools. It is terrorist because it exploits the fear that
many academics feel when they know that their words might appear in print before the eyes of the public,
mere civilians who are not members of the education club.
Here is the brief statement of editorial policies that appeared in the first issue of The Underground
Grammarian:
Editorial Policies
The Underground Grammarian is an unauthorized journal devoted to the protection of the
Mother Tongue at Glassboro State College. Our language can be written and even spoken
correctly, even beautifully. We do not demand beauty, but bad English cannot be excused or
tolerated in a college. The Underground Grammarian will expose and ridicule examples of
jargon, faulty syntax, redundancy, needless neologism, and any other kind of outrage against
English.
Clear language engenders clear thought, and clear thought is the most important benefit of
education. We are neither peddlers nor politicians that we should prosper by that use of
language which carries the least meaning. We cannot honorably accept the wages,
confidence, or licensure of the citizens who employ us as we darken counsel by words
without understanding.
My first motives were just about what you would expect from an English teacher: a supposed reverence for
that ``Mother Tongue,'' the noble and ancient language of Shakespeare and Milton and all the others; the
notion that the judicious choice of a semicolon was a nice display of what Veblen called ``the instinct of
workmanship,'' a good thing; and especially that sense of smug satisfaction that comes from knowing exactly
why to use the word ``nice'' when making a nice display. There was also the natural, and perfectly justifiable,
contempt that any frontline teacher feels for administrators. So many of them seem to be born
aluminumsiding salesmen who took a wrong turn somewhere along the line. Nor is that contempt mitigated
by the fact that many of them (but by no means all) were once frontline teachers themselves. On the
contrary, that reveals what they really think of teaching: a humble and tedious calling useful only as a
necessary step to a better life and better pay. There is furthermore, in almost every teacher, a small, dark
current of fascism, and the work of administration not only permits but actually encourages it.
I did say, to be sure, that ``clear language engenders clear thought, and clear thought is the most important
benefit of education,'' but that was little more than a recitation. That's what we're expected to say in this
business, and we keep saying it and nodding, saying it and nodding. And, like most of the things that people
are expected to say, it's true in a way, and false in a way, and not well thought out. There is an important
principle to be drawn here: Many of our supposed ``ideas'' are in fact recitations, recitations not of what we
think or understand but of what we simply believe that we believe. Thinking is done in language, and
understanding, a result of thinking, is expressed in language, but, when we simply adopt and recite what has
been expressed, we have committed neither thinking nor understanding. When the first issue of The
Underground Grammarian appeared, I had neither thought about nor understood that lofty proposition about
clear language and. clear thought. But the words were there on the page, and they demanded attention.
All that talk about the ability to write letters of application for jobs is bunk; here is the real value of teaching
everybody, everybody, to write clear, coherent, and more or less conventional prose: The words we write
demand far more attention than those we speak. The habit of writing exposes us to that demand, and skill in
writing makes us able to pay logical and thoughtful attention. Having done that, we can come to understand
what before we could only recite. We may find it bunk or wisdom, but, while we had better reject the bunk,
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 14
Page No 17
we can accept the wisdom as truly our own rather than some random suggestion of popular belief. If we have
neither the habit nor the skill of writing, however, we have to guess which is the bunk and which the wisdom,
and we will almost invariably guess according to something we feel, not according to something to which we
have given thoughtful attention.
I had not, in fact, given thoughtful attention to ``clear thought'' and ``clear language'' and the ways in which
they might relate to each other, but I had at least taken hold of one end of what turned out to be a long and
tangled string. An examination, if only of comma faults and dangling participles, had begun. Examination has
a life of its own. You simply cannot think about commas and the place of modifiers without finding that you
are thinking about thinking. It is impossible to examine language at any level without examining the work of
a mind. I knew that Wittgenstein had said that all philosophy was the examination of language, but I
assumed, because I wasn't paying thoughtful attention, that he was referring to the obvious fact that
philosophy was about ideas, and that ideas could be read only in language. I don't think that anymore. I'm
convinced that he was talking about language as language, with its commas and modifiers, and especially
about writing, a special case of language, permanently accessible.
Consider, for example, the following sentence, which was quoted without comment in a much later issue:
Teratology
During the 198081 school year, the project will provide teachers and administrators with
education and support designed to optimize the behaviors and conditions in the school which
support student learning to the extent that at least two thirds of the teachers receiving training
and support in Expectations will report, on a specifically designed survey, changes in at least
two school related operational characteristics that have been identified as critical elements of
the network of expectations that support learning.
What we learn from studying that sentence has very little to do with the digest of rules in the back of the
composition handbook. It has to do with the nature of a mind and the way it does its work. That is revealing
enough, but it's only the beginning. The mind we see at work in that sentence is not the mind of an isolated
eccentric. That writer is a member, and probably in all too good standing, of a community of minds and the
inheritor of a massive tradition. It represents what is obviously acceptable to a society of likeminded peers
and superiors and subordinates. It speaks, one might say, for the mind of a vast bureaucracy, and,
furthermore, since no mind works that way naturally, it must have learned that trick.
When we study that sentence, therefore, we study the intellectual climate of the society in which such work
of the mind is not only acceptable but desirable, and we study the traditions and practices that must have
formed both the society and the individual mind. That example is in no way extraordinary or even unusual; it
is, in fact, typical. (You will know that, of course, if you have any acquaintance with the business of the
schools, and, if you haven't, you'll soon see for yourself.) So we can ask: What is the intellectual climate of
that society? What traditions and practices have formed that climate? Having answers to those questions, we
can ask: Why is a society so endowed and so constituted given the task of teaching minds to work well, and
how likely is it to succeed in that work?
In speaking of that ``society'' in such general terms, I have to advise civilians that I do not mean ``the
teachers,'' or at least not simply the teachers. Most people think that teachers are the agents of public
education and that all those guidance counselors and curriculum facilitators and others are merely support
services. This is not so. Of all the agents of our system of public education, the teachers are by far the least
influential, and what they actually accomplish or don't accomplish in their classrooms has very little to do
with the worth of ``education'' in the large sense. This is not to say that teachers are uninfluenced by the
intellectual climate of the system as a whole, far from it, but only that they are the lowliest footsloggers in a
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 15
Page No 18
vast army. Some of them will rise from the ranks and will be no longer teachers. They will become the people
whose minds work like the mind of that writer just cited. Indeed, if their minds work that way, they are all the
more likely to rise. But as long as they remain teachers they are, and they're so treated as, mere employees,
who may or may not be seeking admittance to the seats of power.
Incipient schoolteachers I have known hundreds of them are generally decent young people of average
intelligence. Some are stupid, of course, and some rarer few are brilliant. Almost all of them seem a bit more
than ordinarily ethical, and I can't believe that any one of them ever decided to be a teacher for the sake of
doing harm. Furthermore, the task of teaching a mind to work well is not a particularly difficult one. Teachers
do not have to be brilliant, although they probably shouldn't be stupid. In short, almost all of those who seek
to be teachers are quite capable of being good teachers, but something happens to them on the way to the
classroom. They fall into bad company. Here is an example of what they must face:
Pontiffs and Peasants
Unlike socialism, the realm of educationism was never meant to be a classless society. Just
now it's an emasculated feudalism whose few surviving pugnantes have decided to settle
down with the unholy but happy Saracens, leaving the miserable laborantes to fend for
themselves under the silly governance of the puffedup orantes. The gogetter,
selfpromoting grantgrabbers have all wangled themselves cushy consultancies and juicy
jobs in government. The wretched tillers of the soil are hoeing hard rows in the public
schools and risking life and limb in the cause of minimum competence. The jargonbesotted
clergy are bestowing upon each other rich benefices of experiential continua and peddling
cheap remediational indulgences, fighting to keep their teachertraining academies growing
in an age of closing schools and dwindling faith in bold innovative thrusts in noncognitive
curriculum design facilitation. Fat flocks, fat shepherds. Things do look bad, but let us not
despair. The Black Death has been reported in Arizona, and it may yet spread.
It's not always easy to tell the pontiffs from the peasants. The sumptuary laws no longer apply. In the time of
lovebeads, both classes wear lovebeads; in the time of Levi's, Levi's. Our best clue always the best clue
when we want to assess the work of the mind is the language used by each class, Lumpensprache by the
peasants and Pfaffesprache, a classier lingo indeed, by the pontiffs.
Here's a typical passage of the latter as it appeared, unfortunately without attribution, in an otherwise splendid
column by Howard Hurwitz, a syndicated writer on education:
``These instructional approaches are perhaps best conceived on a systems model, where
instructional variables (input factors) are mediated by factors of students' existing cognitive
structure (organizational properties of the learner's immediately relevant concepts in the
particular subject field); and by personal predispositions and tolerance toward the
requirements of inference, abstraction, and impulse control, all prerequisite to achievement in
the discovery or the hypothetical learning mode.''
So. It may mean that what a student learns depends on what he already knows and on whether or not he gives
a damn. For a pontiff of educationism, that's already a novel and arresting idea, but if he said it in plain
English he wouldn't be allowed to teach any courses in it. Indeed, if he could say it in plain English he would
probably have enough sense not to say it, thus disclosing to the world that years of study have brought him at
last to a firm grasp on the obvious.
Even when intoning the obvious, however, a pontiff keeps his head down. Did you notice that ``perhaps''? He
doesn't actually commit himself to the proposition that approaches are best conceived as a model where
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 16
Page No 19
variables are mediated by factors; he is willing only to opine that approaches are ``perhaps'' best conceived as
a model where variables are mediated by factors. If that were humility rather than selfdefense, it would suit
him well, for he seems to think that ``conceived'' means ``understood'' and that ``mediated'' means
``mitigated'' and that ``factors'' and ``variables'' can mean anything at all. He's not so good with semicolons
either.
That point is important. Although inflated with fake erudition, Pfaffesprache always reveals, inadvertently,
its roots in the vulgar, but usually honest, Lumpensprache. Thus we find in that passage the defensive errors
of the ignorant, who always use too many modifiers and achieve thereby either redundancy or incoherence.
There is no need to specify that a student's ``disposition'' is ``personal'' or to elaborate ``subject'' into ``the
particular subject field.'' We are not enlightened by hearing that a property is organizational or that the
relevant is immediately relevant. ``The hypothetical learning mode'' tells us only that this pontiff is hazy
about the meanings of ``mode'' and ``hypothetical'' and short on ``learning.''
The pontiff, of course, preaches what he practices in some teachertraining academy. Nevertheless, in spite
of his baleful influence, many of his students do not adopt his ignorant babble. They cling faithfully to their
own ignorant babble.
They become schoolteachers and compose ``thought'' questions for study guides: ``What did the sculpture
told the archologists?'' They admonish parents: ``Scott is dropping in his studies he acts as if don't care. Scott
want pass in his assignment it all, he had a poem to learn and he fell to do it.'' When asked to demonstrate
their own literacy, they go out on strike, demanding on the placards ``quality educacion'' and ``descent
wages.''
Maybe you can't fool all of the people all of the time, but the pontiffs can fool all of the peasants forever.
That accounts for the fact that the society of educationism is made up of two apparently dissimilar classes.
Deep down where it really counts, they're equally less than minimally competent.
We can understand why the educationists defend so truculently that bizarre article of their faith which
pronounces superior intelligence and academic accomplishment traits not suitable to schoolteachers. Well,
they may have a good point there. There's more than enough violence in the schools already. If we were to
send a bunch of bright and able students to study with the hypothetical learning mode pontiff, they'd ride him
out of town on a rail and hurry back to burn down the whole damn teachertraining academy.
It seems, at first, a puzzling fact that those who have spent as much as one half of their time in college
studying under professors who fancy that they conceive their instructional approaches on systems models
mediated by factors can then go out into the world unable to compose complete sentences or even to spell
``education.'' However, not until quite recently, and then only in response to external demands, have the
teachertrainers thought it their responsibility to see to it that newly graduated teachers could in fact write
complete sentences and spell correctly. (We will see later some entertaining examples of what they do in
response to those demands.) Those things were the business of the English department people, and if they
failed to teach them, well, too bad, the fledgling teachers would just have to do without them.
Furthermore, the students in teachertraining academies are not in fact expected to adopt or even to examine
the language of that ``mediated by factors'' passage. That is the language of the education textbooks, not the
language of the classroom, although in education courses whole classes are not infrequently devoted to the
reading of some text, as mealtime in monasteries is devoted to Scripture. Should a student ask, for instance,
the meaning of the passage cited, he would probably be told something very much like the suggested
translation. Should he ask, however, why such an obvious generalization had to be couched in such strange
language, I don't know what answer he would get, but I would bet that he will soon want to reconsider his
choice of a calling. Should he take the last step and ask why anyone would think such a banal truism worthy
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 17
Page No 20
of serious study, then he probably won't have to reconsider his choice of a calling. His adviser will do that for
him.
The passage is only a ritual recitation which is not supposed to be subjected to thoughtful scrutiny. It is a
formulized pastiche of acceptable jargon terms and stock phrases. While it has, for the inattentive, a
formidable sound, it is the kind of writing that is surprisingly easy to compose for anyone who is familiar
with all of its traditional devices. (The craft of making such prose, strangely enough, is similar to what we
can find to this day in the extemporaneous epic recitations of mendicant storytellers in the marketplaces of
the Near East. They remember and stitch together thousands of recurring epithets, stock descriptions of the
hero, his horse, his armor, standardized metaphors and narrative devices. Educationistic prose, however, is
usually less stirring than the recitations of clever beggars.) And who, in any case, would want to scrutinize
such a passage? Who? A more than ordinarily inquisitive (and perhaps skeptical) student, that's who. One
who might indeed be able to compose a complete sentence and even spell ``education.''
Even in teachertraining academics, there are such students. They usually learn to keep their mouths shut, but
those who don't can be a nuisance. They are not only disconcerting in class, but they are likely to give the
place a bad name by complaining in public that their education courses seem silly. (Most schoolteachers go
and ask some will shrug off their education courses as a kind of necessary evil, a ``waste of time.'' Those
courses, however, are a ``waste of time'' only for the students enrolled in them; for the institution of
teachertraining they are immensely profitable.) That is why the pontiffs feel most comfortable when they
can in fact preach to peasants, which is one of the reasons (there are others) for that ``bizarre article of faith.''
The ordinary civilian, who may very well remember with awe the apparent erudition of some teacher or
other, is not generally aware of this strange doctrine, but there is little enthusiasm in the teachertraining
business for outstanding intellectual accomplishment in wouldbe teachers. One claimed theory is that since
a teacher must be able to ``relate'' to the students before any learning can happen, the teacher ought to be as
much like the student as possible, very unlikely in the case of an especially intellectual teacher. The
democratizing leaven of ignorance, therefore, may be in fact desirable in a teacher. It is also a supposition of
educationistic folklore that intellectuals are likely to be more interested in the subjects they teach than in their
students, which will make them cold and distant, perhaps even authoritarian. The latter, at least, is hard to
quarrel with, for the pronouncements of one who can in fact speak with authority on some subject are by
definition ``authoritarian.'' They are also, however, exactly the pronouncements any thoughtful person would
want to hear if he sought knowledge. This doctrine would seem to suggest that if you feel the need of a diet it
would be better to consult with a hairdresser than with a physician, for the hairdresser is much easier to relate
to than the frosty physician, whose advice, furthermore, would surely be authoritarian.
The tangled evolution of this strange tenet, which is not at all the same as the contention that it doesn't require
more than ordinary intelligence to teach children the work of the mind, will be considered in later chapters.
For now, though, we have to consider the problem that it causes for those who hold it. One part of that
problem is invisible to the believers: How can we at once denigrate the authoritarianism of the intellectual
while adopting in our own pronouncements the tone, if not the substance, of authoritative intellectualism?
While that question does not trouble the teachertrainers, who are simply unmindful of it, it must bother us,
eventually. That part of the problem visible to them, probably because it is a matter of clear selfinterest, is
this: If intellectualism is undesirable, its opposite must be desirable; but the opposite of intellectualism, by
whatever name, is hard to champion in a supposedly academic context. It would take a bold professor indeed
to come out in favor of ignorance and stupidity and offer in their favor arguments based on knowledge and
reason, arguments of the sort that are still expected in some of our colleges and universities. It requires only a
presumptuous professor to plump for ignorance and stupidity on other grounds, and this is not unheard of,
especially in enthusiasts of drugs and pop pseudoreligions. For the institution of teachertraining as a
whole, however, something more publicly defensible is needed, and, since the defense can afford neither
kookiness nor the appeal to knowledge and reason, it must rest upon what is likely to prove emotionally
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 18
Page No 21
acceptable to the largest possible audience.
And there is such a defense. Over and against the overweening demands of scholarly intellectualism, the
teachertrainers have set the presumably unquestionable virtues of what they call ``humanism.'' They use this
term in so many different contexts and to characterize so many different kinds of acts and ideologies that I
will not attempt to discuss it fully here. It will just have to grow on you. It does not, as you might think,
denote as usual a particular school of thought or slant of philosophical or religious speculation connected
especially but not exclusively with the Renaissance, although many who use the term have heard of the
Renaissance. This is something closer to ``humaneness,'' as that word is used by what used to be called the
``Humane Society,'' an organization that publicly deplored the cruel treatment of horses. One of the aims of
``humanistic'' educationism is to deplore the cruel treatment of children subjected to the overbearing demands
of knowledge, scholarship, and logic by the traditional powers of authoritarian intellectualism.
We will return to that strange ``humanism,'' for it is one of the two fundamental principles that can be said to
make up the underlying theory of education in America. The other is what might be called the iron law of
behavior modification. Like Free Will and The Omniscience of God, educationistic humanism and behavior
modification are ultimately irreconcilable, and their collisions are at the heart of our educational disorders.
The theologians, at least, are not unaware of their stubborn little problem, but the educationists seem
oblivious to the contradictions inherent in their two favorite principles. Nor could they abandon either, for in
their ``humanism'' they can pose as philosophers and priests, and as modifiers of behavior they can claim to
be scientists and healers. We can consider their claims by looking first at the roots of the presumed science of
educationism.
The Graves of Academe
The End of the String 19
Page No 22
The Wundter of It All
The true grandfather of modern educationism is neither Horace Mann, who has a bit more to answer for than
we usually imagine, nor John Dewey, who in fact has less to answer for than you would conclude from the
deeds of people who haven't read him. Mann had very good intentions, and if he was unable to predict the
future of state supported education in an age of ballooning statism, he was hardly alone. Dewey's thought was
so complicated and diverse, and often so muddily expressed, that it is not (much) to his discredit that facile
faddists have seized slogans from his books and elaborated them into strange pedagogical practices.
The illuminating spirit, or evil genius, of modern educationism was Wilhelm Max Wundt, a Hegelian
psychologist who established the world's first laboratory for psychological experimentation at the University
of Leipzig, where he worked and taught from 1875 to 1920. He dreamed of transforming psychology, a
notably ``soft'' science dealing in vague generalizations and abstract pronouncements, into a ``hard'' science,
like physics. About human behavior, he hoped to make exact and publicly verifiable statements of empirical
fact, from which he could go on to do what scientists must do, formulate hypotheses and make predictions
subject to the test of observation and experiment.
Those are hardly evil designs, and they are, of course, as Hegel might have warned Wundt had he had the
chance, clearly an expression of the Zeitgeist of the late nineteenth century. They are not evil any more than
science itself is evil, but their ``scientific'' intentions take on a strange flavor when we consider that
Zeitgeist. That was the age in which Zola embarked on a mighty series of novels, an enterprise that he fancied
a genuinely scientific experiment. That's the point of his nowforgotten book on the novel as a kind of
science, Le Roman Experimental: True, we cannot raise whole generations in miniature worlds in the
laboratory and chart their deeds and destinies, but we can, if we are sufficiently knowledgeable and
disciplined, do pretty much the same thing in a book. Zola, thus, was never without his notebook, in which he
jotted, probably to the consternation of all who knew him, his ``observations'' of (presumably) unguarded
human behavior.
That was also the age of Marx and Freud, and the growing suspicion, the worm that late Victorian
intellectuals were bound and determined to eat even if it didn't kill them, that Darwin had shown us only one
of the mighty determinisms that governed human behavior and destiny. Who can blame Wundt, therefore, if
he imagined that one who knew enough could measure, predict, and even elicit all those things that we call
feelings, sentiments, emotions, attitudes, and ideas, to say nothing of mere deeds. But while we are
considerately not blaming him, let us call on his own ``science'' in a rough and ready way, without precise
measurements, alas, and be a little suspicious of his motives.
People who make their livings in ``soft'' sciences and the arts are not entirely at ease in the company of
chemists and physicists and other ``hard'' scientists. In such company, the psychologists and sociologists and
the professors of English feel like touchfootball enthusiasts who have wandered by mistake into the locker
room of the Pittsburgh Steelers. Only true philosophers, not professors of philosophy, are entirely immune to
that nasty suspicion that rises in the heart of the ``humanist'' when he hears about recombinant DNA or
quarks. (Well, that's not quite true. The untempered clod is also immune, a fact whose importance will appear
later.) This is a modern condition, and quite unlike that of older times, in which the fledgling ``hard''
scientists were held in contempt by those who did their work entirely in the mind without the help of
apparatus, proper only to artisans. It seems only fair; it's the alchemist's revenge.
Wundt, with his laboratory and machines, was certainly trying to better himself and win for his discipline a
new kind of legitimacy. It was just for that reason that he attracted so many students, many of them
Americans who came home to found schools of educational psychology and psychological testing and to
impress upon our whole system of schooling the indelible mark of clinical practice. One of them was a
The Wundter of It All 20
Page No 23
certain James Cattell, who, while playing with some of Wundt's apparatus, made a remarkable and portentous
discovery. Here, in brief, is the story, as told by Lance J. Klass in The Leipzig Connection (The Delphian
Press, 1978), a useful little book on the influence of Wundt in the history of American educationism:
One series of experiments Cattell performed while at Leipzig examined the manner in which
a person sees the words he is reading. By testing adults who knew how to read, Cattell
``discovered'' that individuals can recognize words without having to sound out the letters.
From this, he reasoned that words are not read by compounding the letters, but are perceived
as ``total word pictures.'' He determined that little is gained by teaching the child his sounds
and letters as the first step to being able to read. Since individuals could recognize words
very rapidly, the way to teach children how to read was to show them words, and tell them
what the words were. The result was the dropping of the phonic or alphabetic method of
teaching reading, and its replacement by the sightreading method in use throughout
America.
The consequences of Cattell's ``discovery'' have surely been enormous, for they include not only the
stupefaction of almost the whole of American culture but even the birth and colossal growth of a lucrative
industry devoted first to assuring that children won't be able to read and then to selling an endless succession
of ``remedies'' for that inability; but Wundt in fact brought us much worse. He brought us the very
atmosphere in which such silliness can thrive. Out of the internal exigencies of his ``science,'' he was led to
consider ``education'' a human phenomenon similar to other human psychic conditions, a conditioned
response to stimuli. ``Teaching'' had to be seen as the application of stimuli that will elicit whatever response
we choose to call ``learning.'' Contrariwise, anyone who has learned something, to read or cipher, for
instance, must obviously have done so as a result of being exposed not simply to the substance of his
learning, the reading or ciphering, but to some stimulus that probably, but by no means certainly, was visited
upon him somewhere in the vicinity of reading and ciphering.
The widespread acceptance of the teaching of reading as inspired by Cattell was possible only where there
was already a predisposition to concentrate not on the substance of what can be learned but on some attribute
that can be detected in the supposed learner. Exactly that predisposition was provided by Wundt's view of
teaching and learning as psychological stimuli and responses, an arrangement presumed to have its own
validity without reference to what was taught and learned. This view was gladly received in the United
States, where, as we will see, a growing educationistic establishment made up mostly of people with little or
no academic expertise was looking for attractive alternatives to the constricting demands of ``subjects.''
Thus it is that our educationists prefer not to treat the multiplication table as something that just has to be
learned. They rather think of multiplying as a desirable ``student outcome,'' a ``behavioral modification'' of
one who does not know how to multiply. This would be only a harmless playing with words if it weren't for
the fact that not all students learn to multiply with equal ease. If we simply think of the multiplication table as
a set of numbers that must be learned by brute force, we can demand more force of those who fail to learn. If
we think of the ability to multiply as a ``behavioral objective,'' an appropriate response to stimuli, then the
student who doesn't learn to multiply must drive us to seek other stimuli and perhaps, in stubborn cases, to
decide that learning the multiplication table has only limited value for the student outcome of multiplication.
From such a view, other follies may flow.
The folly at hand, the wordrecognition teaching of reading, is the result of just such tormented thinking. It
is perfectly true that people who can read do not stop to sound out letters. That, therefore, is an attribute of
readers. So, to the mortally wundted, the path to reading requires the not sounding out of letters as a student
outcome, and student behavior must be modified accordingly. Thus, the rare and pesky student who has
learned the sounds of some letters must be discouraged, which stimulus will elicit a response characteristic of
those who do in fact know how to read. Simple, no?
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 21
Page No 24
Leaving aside the incidental, if momentous, destruction of a whole nation's ability to read, we have still two
far more important and ominous legacies from Wundt. We can afford to leave the reading problem aside
because it is only a practice, a practice that can change, and, in fact, does show signs of changing. But the
major principles that generated and maintained that practice show no signs of changing, and those principles
generate and maintain numerous other unnatural practices and will yet bring us more. They can be put thus:
1. Mental and emotional conditions and events are natural phenomena subject to natural law
and fully subsumable in a rigidly scientific system.
2. Teaching and learning are mental and emotional conditions and events.
In another context, of course, there would be no need to make of the second a ``principle'' equal in weight to
the first, but here it seems useful. These principles are ominous legacies not because they are false. For all I
know, and for all anyone knows, they may be true. But that wouldn't make them ominous either, although it
certainly would lead me to drop this project, and all others, here and now. What makes them ominous is that
they are utterly, for humanity in its present state at least, beyond our powers to test. They require what we
seem unable to achieve, the total understanding of human beings by human beings. We lack that. And, for all
the promises of our Freuds, Marxes, and Wundts, we seem no closer to it then ever before. We may assume
what suits us, of course, about the nature of humanity, and when we act on our assumptions, consequences
will flow accordingly. American educationists have assumed the truth of Wundt's principles, in spite of the
fact that few of them have ever heard of Wundt, and the consequences are what we see.
It is possible to imagine in fact, you don't have to imagine, for Marx makes a good example some
meticulously logical and disciplined thinker who, having made assumptions something like Wundt's, could
derive from them an iron system, complete and internally consistent. Such might have been the nature of
American education today had Wundtian psychology been adopted by expert and learned thinkers. But it was
in fact adopted by the educationists, who already saw themselves as the appointed democratic supplanters of
learned and expert thinkers, remnants of an elitist authoritarianism. When the principles of Wundt are taken
up by people actually hostile to academic learning and traditional intellectualism, strange consequences will
flow. Thus it is that educationistic thought and language have a disconcerting hermaphroditic quality, for the
educationist is committed on the one hand to the proposition that human qualities are quantifiable and
predictable (through the work of the intellect, presumably, for how else can we quantify and predict?), and on
the other hand to the proposition that the practice of the intellect is of less significance and ``value'' than the
possession of certain human qualities.
Here is an excerpt from The Underground Grammarian that shows how the automatic if unknowing
adherence to Wundt's principles, in combination with the disorder of the intellect enforced by
antiintellectualism, causes things to happen in the schools and teacher academies:
The Most Unkindest Cutting Edge of All
In March of 1979, we printed some gabble by a thenunidentified doctoral candidate at New Mexico State
University in Las Cruces. It was about ``a short extrapolation to the prediction of transpersonal innovations
from selfactualization traits.'' Ten months later, the writer was identified as Robert D. Waterman. The man
who fingered him was a colleague, James Dyke, who wanted not the handsome reward we had offered, but
rather to rebuke us for our treatment of Waterman.
Having pointed out, as though it made a difference, that Waterman's degree was not in guidance but in
Educational Management/Development, Dyke said further:
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 22
Page No 25
I hold little faith in your critical abilities with respect to Bob Waterman until such time that
you can demonstrate that you can handle the cutting edge of the exploration of ideas without
bleeding.
And he even sent along an actual piece of the cutting edge, Waterman's complete abstract and a thin slice
from Chapter II of the dissertation, ``Value and Philosophical Characteristics of Transpersonal Teachers.''
We admit that we have no ``critical abilities with respect to Bob Waterman,'' but Dyke may have meant
something other than what he wrote. The critical abilities that we do seek are those that enable us to write
exactly what we mean. They would also find ``until such time that'' a silly inflation of ``until,'' and an
example of the thoughtlessness so common in freshman compositions.
Well, no matter. Dyke doesn't claim to be the cutting edge. So let's take up his challenge and try to handle the
edge itself. We'll start with the very edge of the edge, Waterman's first paragraph. Mind your fingers:
Though an increasing interest on the part of the educational community is being shown in
transpersonal teaching, the literature reflects a lack of empirically based studies concerning
the teacher characteristics associated with its adoption. The purpose of this study, therefore,
was to attempt to identify characteristics (values, attitudes, and teaching philosophy)
pertinent to transpersonally oriented nonpublic school teachers and to compare and contrast
those characteristics to those of public school oriented teachers.
We expected some incisiveness out there on the cutting edge, but the first paragraph is clouded by uncertainty
and imprecision:
Like other educationists, Waterman evades clear declarations and active verbs, as though he were
afraid to take any chances even on a bland generalization like the assertion that somebody is showing
interest in something. He retreats into an awkward and periphrastic jumble, saying that increasing
interest ``on the part'' of somebody is ``being'' shown in transpersonal teaching. (Let's get to
that later.)
The timidity of educationistic prose is not simply a stylistic twitch. It expresses an uncertain mind
and the fear of challenge. That ``literature'' named by Waterman either lacks something or it doesn't,
but he will say only that it ``reflects'' a lack. Likewise, he assigns himself not exactly the task of
``identifying'' but only of ``attempting'' to identify something or other just in case.
In what way, we wonder, is a characteristic ``pertinent to'' some teachers different from a
characteristic ``of'' some teachers? What can we suppose about the mind that prefers the former to the
latter?
Are those ``public school oriented teachers'' actually teachers in public schools, or could they be
teachers anywhere who just happen to be obsessed with thinking about the public schools? Could
they even be teachers who face in the direction of public schools?
Enough. The cutting edge in New Mexico is indeed blunted and ragged, and probably septic as well, and it
was thoughtful of Dyke to warn us of the horrible wound it might inflict. Let's get out the long tongs.
Educationists feel secure, or as secure as they can feel, when they can prattle about the unmeasurable. If you
natter about attitudes and values, no one can prove you a fool by pointing to some facts. However, while the
retreat from the measurable provides comfort for the educationist, it makes it hard for him to claim, as he
would so dearly love to, that ``education'' actually is a body of knowledge and that his Faculty Club card
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 23
Page No 26
should not be stamped: ``Valid only when accompanied by an adult.'' What a dilemma.
Many doctoral candidates in education just head for the nearest exit. They bestow upon us ``conclusive
findings'' as to the efficacy of yellow traffic lines on the cafeteria floor and the number of junior high school
girls in the suburbs of Duluth who elected badminton rather than archery.
For those who want to do serious research way out there on the cutting edge, however, a trickier dodge is
needed, and the education academy is quick to supply it. Most D.Ed. programs require of their candidates no
competence in foreign languages, which makes them attractive and accessible to those whose verbal abilities
are meager. It assures that those abilities will remain meager, too, lest the teacher academies hatch out some
thankless bird capable of seeing, and telling the world, that the teachertraining professors just can't make
sense. The teachertrainers, therefore, make virtue of necessity by claiming that an educationistic scholar
doesn't need verbal skill anyway, but a onesemester course in statistics instead. And that's why their
``research'' bristles with commensurate model analyses and stepwise regression strategies.
Now we can look at Waterman's ``transpersonal teaching.'' In the pages that we have, there is no definition,
but we know that
the personal characteristics related to transpersonal teaching are: (1) a view of man as
essentially and inherently good at his core, (2) that the locus of power and authority in one's
life is within the individual, and (3) that when dealing with life situations it is most effective
to apply one's values to a solution with flexibility, and free of preconceptions or prejudice.
We already know how Waterman writes, so we're not surprised by redundancy or jargon, or even that
disconcerting violation of parallelism. What does surprise us is that the work of the mind way out there on the
cutting edge of the exploration of ideas sounds so much like a mimeographed prospectus for a
nondenominational Sundayschool class to be taught by some amiable but slightly addled addict of popular
selfhelp paperbacks and magazine articles about the cutting edge of the exploration of ideas in Marin
County.
Waterman's values, quasitheological and pseudophilosophical, can become objects of ``research'' only to
educationists. First they circulate questionnaires, either homemade or, as in Waterman's case, prefabricated
by other educationists. Then they tabulate the ``answers,'' which are usually spaces filled in or numbers
checked by captives eager to finish a stupid questionnaire. The answers reveal, of course, only what the
answerers have chosen to say, which may or may not reveal what they feel or believe. In fact, it probably
does not, especially in this ``research.'' Even non transpersonal teachers know enough not to give straight
answers to prying busybodies.
Most of us can see a difference between a study of angels and a study of testimony about angels. Waterman
sees that the R2 of SelfRegard is .0123, and, of InnerDirected, a hefty .4544. Existentiality's R2 is a
modest .0460. Yeah. And next year he's going to whip off Weltschmerz and Ennui, and we'll know
exactly how we feel about the cutting edge of the exploration of ideas in New Mexico.
In the meantime, though, we are going to cook up a little ``empirically based study'' of our own. We're just
dying to find out some nifty data about the R2 of Hubris.
It would surely be an injustice to Wundt, who was meticulously intelligent, by all accounts, to think that
he would be a party to the granting of a doctorate, even in Educational Management/Development, for such
cloudy work. Nevertheless, he asked for it. The presumed method of Waterman's ``empirically based study''
promises to quantify mental and emotional conditions and events in publicly verifiable measurements. Those
strange numbers, left unexplained in the original article, are typical of the measurements. They are
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 24
Page No 27
determined statistically by counting up and manipulating the answers to the questionnaires. Such is the
educationist's equivalent of the scientific method, and even Wundt would reject it.
There is no counting the doctorates in education that have been awarded to those who have done nothing
more than tabulate the answers to questionnaires. That such degrees are so common, however, is not only
because the work is easy, bad enough, but also because the supposed objects of study often cannot be known
directly. When they can, in fact, they are obviously trivial. When all the badminton and archery coaches have
sent in their completed questionnaires, then you know something about the junior high school girls in the
suburbs of Duluth. Or, to be more exact, you know what the badminton and archery coaches say about those
girls. Nevertheless, the nature of the knowledge is such that it is publicly verifiable through direct
observation. But it is of very limited use and will not bring great renown to its discoverer.
On the other hand, the nature of knowledge about the ``values, attitudes, and teaching philosophy'' of
``transpersonal teachers'' does not recommend such knowledge as verifiable through observation. We do not
``see'' such things; we can only make inferences about them. We do not even know what ``transpersonal''
might mean, for its form, analogous to ``transcontinental,'' suggests nothing rational. Nor can we figure it out
by imagining its antonym, i.e., what would we mean if we said that some teacher was ``nontranspersonal.''
When we are told the ``personal characteristics related to transpersonal teaching,'' we learn only that teachers
who seem to have these certain beliefs rather than others are being called ``transpersonal,'' but the term
distinguishes them only from the nontranspersonal teachers, who, presumably, do not have those beliefs. And
a surly pack of misanthropes and defeatists they must be.
Never mind. Educationists love to sound technical, and they have a penchant for giving importantsounding
names to things that need no names at all. In that fashion, for instance, they do not call a very small class a
very small class or helping one student helping one student. They decide that such things are properly named
``microteaching.'' It may seem to you that it doesn't make any difference, but it turns out to make a big
difference indeed. You cannot write dissertations and articles, you cannot teach courses in teacher academies,
you cannot get grants of public money, you cannot hire out as a consultant, you cannot set up a project and
assemble a staff, if all you're going to do is talk about very small classes and the fact that a teacher will often
help one student. You can do all of those things, and more, if you are an expert in microteaching. Thus
Waterman, by giving a classy name to people who would otherwise be nothing more than reasonably kind,
confident, and resourceful teachers, provides himself with a topic worthy of serious study.
Well, nice people are nice, no doubt. But how do we know that, and how can we decide which are the
nicer nice people and by precisely how much they are nicer? This is the kind of concern that modern
educationism has inherited from Wundt's by now muchdebased principles. And answers are sought not by
recourse to evidence but by the gathering of testimony, testimony invariably and inevitably tainted by
subjectivity. It would be bad enough that such methods nullify the value of educationistic ``research.'' What is
far worse is that such research becomes the pattern for the study of ``education'' generally. Students of
teachertraining are continuously exposed to such presumed methods of inquiry. Since they spend so much
of their time in education courses, they can have little training in rigidly scientific disciplines, even if they
intend to teach them, and they are easily bamboozled into thinking that this kind of exercise is science. Their
bewilderment has to be compounded by the fact that this putative science is about things which, for other
purposes than dissertations, educationists will claim as human ``values'' to be inculcated as separate from
``mere'' intellectual attainments. Those are things like Waterman's SelfRegard, Existentiality, and
InnerDirected (which desperately needs a substantive).
The educationistic mind is deeply divided against itself. It wants to follow Wundt and believe that teaching
and learning are objectively measurable phenomena and that those who study teaching and learning are
therefore scientists and worthy of chairs in colleges and universities. At the same time it wants to contend that
the profoundly important results of an education, especially the education of a teacher, are attitudes, values,
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 25
Page No 28
and ``philosophies'' that transcend cognition. Waterman, an educationist, asks this kind of question: How do
public and private school teachers compare with each other in their Existentiality? He who asks after the
degree of your Existentiality may just as well ask for a numerical value for your hunger, and will, in either
case, simply have to accept what you tell him. Such ``research'' wouldn't even make an interesting parlor
game.
But what else can Waterman, or any orthodox educationist, do? He is not likely to ask, for instance: How do
public and private school teachers of mathematics compare with each other in their knowledge of
mathematics? That question could be answered in publicly verifiable measurements. But it is not an answer
that a prudent educationist would want, and it would probably not win you a doctorate in any graduate school
of education in America. Your committee will throw you out for several reasons: Since the teaching of
anything is the design and application of appropriate stimuli, the teacher's knowledge of mathematics,
although there ought to be some, is not what makes him a teacher. We do not teach mathematics just so that
students can do mathematics, but for a higher purpose, for the inculcation, perhaps, of an appreciation of
Logic and Rationality; so you would be better to seek findings about Logic/Rationality Appreciation, which
is exactly as easy to measure as Existentiality. Your research is, in any case, likely to give a false impression,
since many private school teachers, to the detriment of their professionalism, are not legitimately certified
and have probably taken more courses in mathematics than in education, which makes their possibly superior
knowledge of mathematics a matter of no consequence.
In other words: Measurable things are not important; unmeasurable things are paramount. Let us therefore
measure only the unmeasurable. Of course, Wundt never dreamed of measuring the unmeasurable. He
claimed rather that the psychological conditions and events of humanity were not unmeasurable at all, and
that the task of psychological science was to discover how to measure them. He did not suggest that we go
around asking people how they felt, however, for reasons that are perfectly obvious to anyone with any
rudimentary understanding of science. But he did hold, for equally obvious reasons, that the study of human
psychology required the direct observation of human beings. That tenet of Wundtianism, hardly startling, has
been happily accepted by educationists, for if there is one thing they have always at hand it is a large
collection of captive human beings.
You have surely heard of ``childcentered'' education, that process that will educate the ``whole child.'' It
sounds so decent. What could be better than centering on the child, the whole child, no less? But what,
exactly, do halfbaked neoWundtians mean when they speak of ``childcentered'' education? Here is an
article that provides some evidence toward an answer to that question:
The Nonredundant Interactive Relationship of Perceived Teacher Directiveness and Student
Personological Variables to Grades and Satisfaction
Recent research has shown that a number of student variables authoritarianism, dogmatism, intelligence,
conceptual level, convergentdivergent ability, locus of control, anxiety, compulsivity, need for achievement,
achievement orientation, independencedependence, and extraversionintroversion may moderate the
relationship between teacher directiveness and grades and satisfaction. There is a fair degree of moderate
intercorrelation among these student variables and such intercorrelation suggests that some of the found
interactive relationships may be overlapping or redundant. The purpose of the present research is to develop
multivariate mathematical models of the interactive relationships using stepwise regression strategies. Such
models should facilitate a more parsimonious interpretation of the interactive relationships which are...
We were going to show you all of that mess and even give you the name and address of the chappie who
made it, but we can't. Before our typesetter was able to finish, a member of our staff borrowed the original
(and only) copy and took it to Texas. There, while fumbling for his entry permit at the Immigration Control
Office, he lost the evidence. Maybe it's just as well. There's no telling what those Rangers might have done
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 26
Page No 29
had they caught him with a smoking dissertation abstract. They don't cotton much to that kind of stuff down
there.
We can tell you, at least, that the original came from Calgary, Alberta, and we have to hope, if justice is ever
to be done, that the Mounties don't want any of this stuff in their country either. They shouldn't have much
trouble getting their man and his sidekick in this case. The author and his dissertation adviser were so
proud of themselves that they had their photographs printed right on the page with the evidence. Perfectly
decent and respectable young fellows they seemed, too. Who would have thought it?
Since personology must be too subtle a science for the likes of us, we cannot explain how ``personological''
variables might be different from differences in persons. We would guess, though, that ``student'' variables
are young variables studying to become teacher variables. And we're a little disappointed by that list of
student variables, a measly twelve items. In the better teacher academies, you'd never get a doctorate for such
a skimpy, or ``parsimonious,'' elaboration of the obvious commingled with the incomprehensible.
The most instructive thing about the passage is that its pretentiousness is eloquently, although inadvertently,
undone by its timidity. Notice that all those nifty variables may ``moderate the relationship.'' Educationists
won't take chances, even on the obvious and simple. After all, how can we be sure, without multivariate
mathematical models of the interactive relationships, that different people feel different about different
things?
Of course, should this research achieve its goal, we might have to change our opinions. A ``parsimonious
interpretation'' of a ``fair'' degree of ``moderate'' intercorrelation is not to be sneezed at. Before such an
awesome discovery, we'd just have to back off, treading cautiously in our best stepwise regression strategies.
Let's try to imagine some possible facts and events that might incite such an undertaking, that is, the
development of multivariate mathematical models of interactive relationships. First, be careful to remember
something that might easily blow away in the storm of jargon all of this has something to do with children
in school. So we can imagine: There are some children in school. They are, in some ways, different from each
other, that is, they have (could that be the right word?) different student variables. They get grades in school,
probably some good, some bad, some indifferent. They are, or are not, as the case may be, ``satisfied,'' either
by school, or by their grades, or by both, in various degrees. They ``perceive,'' or not, maybe, something
called ``teacherdirectiveness.'' How can these things be seen as functions of one another?
Before we can begin this research, we have to be clear about some things that might confuse mere laymen.
Notice first that whether a teacher actually is ``directive'' or not is not at issue; all that matters is whether a
student ``perceives'' a teacher as ``directive.'' This is childcentered research. Although grades do go into the
hopper, it's not because we are interested in what a student has learned or how that can be measured, but
because we want to know about the student's ``satisfaction,'' which depends only in part on his grade, which
must be factored in with his own perception of directiveness and his own student variables. This is still
childcentered research.
Bearing in mind those warnings, we can now proceed with our research. If we are successful, we can expect
to be able to answer questions like this:
Who will be more satisfied with a B plus, a moderately intelligent student with better than
average convergentdivergent ability but little if any locus of control, or a very bright,
dogmatic student who shows normal achievement orientation but no compulsivity to speak of
and does not, unlike the first student, perceive the teacher as directive ?
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 27
Page No 30
You can devise other such examples for yourself. The possibilities are probably infinite. None of them,
however, will have any objective meaning, which would require a precise numerical evaluation of hosts of
human traits, beliefs, attitudes, prejudices, and emotions. In fact, that kind of study must end exactly where it
begins, in a vague generalization. You and I, if asked and forced to answer, could also have said that there
may be a fair degree of moderate intercorrelation between a person's characteristic traits and the way he
feels about things. This is the kind of revelation that educationistic research provides.
It does that useless work, obviously more for profit than for fun, since it is impossible that even the dullest
educationist can find the ecstasy of discovery in such an enterprise, precisely because it is childcentered.
Here in the shadow of Wundt, education and the presumable content of an education are not the objects of the
educationist's concern. It is the children, the students, who are to be studied, for the education is something
that is being done to them with certain modifications in mind. While the originally intended modification
may be nothing more than changing children who can't add into children who can, the process of
modification itself is obviously more likely to produce a ``scholarship'' of the kind just cited than a mere
counting of those who can add and those who can't. That scholarship, you surely noticed, is not about what
children may have learned and how, but about how they feel; and it isn't even about how they feel about what
they may have learned, but about how they feel about their grades and their teacher. If we could hope to
learn anything from such research, it would be not about education but about children. But, following Wundt,
that is exactly what we need to know, for ``education'' is the psychologically appropriate manipulation of
learners. If that is so, the more we know about the manipulee the better.
That view of ``education'' is not entirely without merit. Some things can be taught to some people just that
way, although the system works far more dependably with horses and dogs. But human beings are immensely
different from one another even while they are very much alike, and even the most avidly childcentered
educationists have not yet suggested an educational system in which every child, after a stupefying battery of
psychological tests, is assigned a perfectly matched teacher, who has also had all those tests. Therefore, the
teaching of anything has to be a compromise, a generalized set of stimuli aimed at producing the desired
responses in most of the children. In some cases, therefore, it is bound to fail.
Several things can happen when education fails, none of them good. No. I will be more precise. None of them
can be good as long as we think of education as the design of appropriate stimuli to produce certain behavior
in an individual human being. If we do think that, then there are three things we can think of doing when
some students fail to learn, since there are three factors in our equation the stimulus, the student, the
response.
We can change the stimulus. This is a big job, for it requires changing an already institutionalized
compromise designed to elicit the right response from as many children as possible, a massive system.
Nevertheless, it has been done. Every simplified revision of some already simplified text is just such a
change, and so is the widespread use of films and even television programs in place of books. When such a
change is made, of course, it is made in the supposed interests of those who have failed to respond
appropriately. That accounts for the fact that methods of instruction are designed to accommodate not the
most ordinary children, but those who learn most slowly.
We can also change the expected response. If some children do not seem to learn history, we can decide to
teach them civic pride and responsibility instead. This is especially attractive if we have already decided that
civic pride and responsibility might well be the proper student outcomes of the study of history anyway. This
is a common device, of which I will have more to say in the next chapter.
We can even try to change the student. This is hardest of all, but educationists never give up. On this matter,
too, there is much to say later, but for now we must look at what happens in the Wundtian system before or
unless such a change can be made. What follows, along with some notably ghastly language, is a display of
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 28
Page No 31
one of the educationist's most cherished devices, the psychological manipulator's last resort:
Nobody Here But Us Professionals
The works of Weischadle, associate professor of education at Montclair State College in New Jersey, can be
studied at length in the New Jersey section of The New York Times for July 16, 1978. His piece is called,
naturally, ``Educating the Parents.''
Mass illiteracy he easily dismisses as a matter of ``problem youngsters,'' but those uppity parents who are
beginning to complain about illiteracy they need to be taught a lesson. They can vote! If we don't
straighten those malcontents out right away, they might end up listening to demagogues and voting against
some of our favorite monies. Worse yet, and it's with this fear that Weischadle begins his fingerwagging,
some of them might win those malpractice suits that they're discussing with their lawyers.
Weischadle protests that even if illiteracy were the fault of the schools, that wouldn't mean that the schools
were to blame. Here's the delicate way he puts it:
Have the critics been fair to the schools? To the extent that schools are responsible for a
youngster's educational growth, the critics have dealt with the right party. However, it does
not necessarily mean that professionals in the schools are inept. It does mean that educational
leadership has failed to articulate the problem effectively and carry out the necessary
programs.
It's hard to know exactly what Weischadle means by that ``articulate.'' First we thought that the
``professionals'' had been unable to utter intelligible sounds, for that reading does reflect experience.
However, in this kind of writing, no ``professional'' would ever waste a nifty word like ``articulate'' on such a
simple thought. Next we guessed that the man might be saying that the ``professionals'' had been unable to
define the problem thoroughly and accurately. That, too, we had to reject. Such inability would be
remarkably similar to ineptitude in ``professionals,'' surely, but Weischadle says they're not inept. Only one
possibility remains: ``To articulate the problem effectively'' must mean to find some description that will
keep irate parents from thinking that the ``professionals'' are inept. Of course! That's just what Weischadle's is
up to in this piece educating the parents.
He does some pretty fancy articulating as well. Where do they learn that language? In the ordinary graduate
school, candidates are expected to be competent in a couple of foreign languages, but in those education
places they know that skill in language will cripple the budding ``professional'' by enabling him to say things
plainly. You get no monies that way. Straight talk would mean the end of effective articulation as we know it.
Here are some examples of bent talk from Weischadle's little piece. He won't say that people are talking
about something; he says that ``much recent discussion has focused on'' it. He can't say, ``Hurry''; he says that
``delay should not be allowed to take place.'' He can't say that people should use wisely what they have; he
says that ``an enlightened utilization...must be present.'' He can't say that the people who deal out discipline
should be consistent; he says that ``the haphazard application of disciplinary action...must be eliminated.'' He
can't say, ``Don't worry.'' He says that ``uneasiness should be settled.''
Still, we worry. For one thing, there is no clear meaning in the settling of uneasiness. In fact, it sounds
ominous. If the settling of uneasiness has the same effect as the settling of terms or plans, we don't want any
part of it. For another, how can we take any comfort from a teacher of teachers who condescends, in broken
English, to explain why we should have ``complete confidence'' in him and other ``professionals,'' so that
they may get on, unhampered by our illinformed and amateurish complaints, with the ``acquisition...of
monies to enact better programs'' that will, this time around, solve the illiteracy problem ?
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 29
Page No 32
In these examples of Weischadle's tortured English, the grammatical subjects are things, not persons, and
abstract things at that. All things that must be done by people, but we see no people. This language suggests a
world where responsible agents, the doers of deeds, have been magically occulted by the deeds themselves. A
weird structure of that sort, ``utilization must be present,'' for example, has the merit (?) of excusing
somebody from an obligation to use something. If things go wrong, therefore, it's not any person's fault; it's
just that utilization wasn't present.
Such structures, furthermore, often generate certain morally flavored auxiliary verbs: ``delay should not''
``application must,'' etc. This is another grammatically symbolized copout which implies that moral
obligation falls upon deeds rather than doers. It is up to those negligent deeds to get themselves done. This is
convenient for those ``professionals'' who won't be able to do them.
Normal English, in its typical structure, a simple sentence in the active voice, implies a world where agents
perform acts. There are times when we would wish it otherwise, and in our minds we can devise subterfuges
that will make it seem otherwise. We do the business of the mind in language, and we make our subterfuges
of the same stuff. Weischadle, in his grammatical gyrations, is not just writing bad English; he is positing a
certain kind of world. In that world, one can parler sans parler like Castorp and reject in advance all
responsibility for what one says. Here's how Weischadle does it indeed, how almost anyone of those
``professionals'' would do it: ``The preschool years have been recognized as being important formulative
years.''
He probably means ``formative,'' although he may be thinking that the preschool years are the years spent
sucking a formula from bottles but no matter. The important thing is the grotesque contortion by which he
escapes having to say that the preschool years are formative, or, if you like, formulative. It matters not at all
to the ``professional'' that what he has to say is obvious and banal and widely enough known that it needs no
saying; he still finds a way to evade responsibility for having said it. In this timid language of misdirection
and abdication, no one would dare stand forth and proclaim that a turkey is a turkey. He might mutter,
tentatively, that a turkey has been recognized as being a turkey although not necessarily by him.
Into such prose, human beings vanish. No wonder we couldn't discover Weischadle's salary. He has
withdrawn into the precincts of the passive voice. He has given over all doing of deeds and drawn up about
him the mists of circumlocution. Far from our ken, he has sojourned in the land of the selfeliminating
application and followed the spoor of the placetaking delay. He is, by now, by gloomy night and
periphrastics compassed round. He is, in short, or sort of short, no longer recognized as being Weischadle.
Now we see the truth. There is no Weischadle.
What could be more obvious? When the object of a psychological manipulation fails to respond in the usual
way, there must be something wrong with him. This conclusion is the same as the neurologist's, for whom the
failure of a knee to jerk has one ominous significance. In Wundt's psychology, the mind itself is held to be,
must be if the system is to be concretely scientific, a neurological phenomenon, and a predisposition against
arithmetic must be a psychoneurological aberration. Thus we must conclude, when children fail to respond
appropriately to tested stimuli, that they have learning problems. That being so, it becomes the aim of
educational research to find out all about learning problems and to discover, naturally, that the schools are
full of ``problem youngsters'' harboring hosts of hitherto unsuspected ``learning disabilities.'' From this
preoccupation with pathology, the teachertraining profession takes many benefits.
One of them, of course, is simply the opportunity to do what can pass for scholarship or research, which leads
to promotion and pay and to government grants. There would be little hope of such things in a simpler calling
like plumbing. Plumbers install plumbing, and, when something goes wrong with the plumbing, they fix it.
They don't care how the pipes feel about it. Teaching reading and arithmetic is much more like plumbing than
you probably think. If you know how to read and cipher, you can, if you want to, teach those skills to almost
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 30
Page No 33
any child in America. The chances are, too, that you will do a better job of it, and in a shorter time, than the
schools. If you know a lot about mathematics and have paid thoughtful attention to language, you can do a
much better job, and better by far, probably, than anything you can manage with your plumbing. But if the
teaching of children were handled that way, simply by people who knew the skills and knowledge they were
teaching, and who wanted simply to teach them, then a vast and comfortable empire would fall.
That empire is not, however, the empire of the schools. It is the empire of the teachertraining establishment.
Most of what is taught and studied in the teacher academy has nothing to do with the subject matter that the
teachertrainees will someday teach. Teachertraining is itself ``childcentered,'' and the teachertrainees are
themselves among the children. That's why so many education courses are devoted either to ``enhanced
selfawareness'' or to a clinical scrutiny of children as psychological entities. The training of teachers is thus
a miniature lampoon of the training of the psychoanalyst, who must first be analyzed so that he may do unto
others as has been done unto him. The incipient teachers are to be, in fact, therapists, keen to discover, if
unable to treat, vast arrays of ``learning disabilities'' and ``problem youngsters.'' Teachertraining, therefore,
is a colossal and terribly serious enterprise. It calls for more and more courses and workshops and
``handson'' laboratory ``experiences'' and in and preservice training, all of which require larger and larger
faculties and counselors and facilitators and support services and more and more money. Without Wundt,
none of this would be possible, and the teaching of children would be degraded into nothing more than an
honest, honorable, skilled trade.
Wundt may have been wrong, but he was honest. He just wanted to know what he thought could be known.
His bequest to us, marvelously transformed, is essentially a metaphor, an ideal paradigm of the process of
education. We seem to imagine that there is something ``wrong'' with children, and that we must fix it. But by
that ``wrongness'' we don't mean something simple to fix, like the perfectly normal ignorance of arithmetic in
one who has not been taught arithmetic. We mean something more like a perverse bias against arithmetic, an
innate predisposition whose remedy lies in some ``treatment'' or other. We can see that the treatment,
therefore, must take priority, for the arithmetic depends on the treatment, the modification of behavior. Thus
we will first make the student whole, through devising and applying appropriate stimuli, so that he can, if it
still seems desirable, learn his arithmetic. This paradigm does not include the proposition, certainly
questionable but just as certainly intriguing, that we can make the student whole by teaching the arithmetic.
The Graves of Academe
The Wundter of It All 31
Page No 34
The Seven Deadly Principles
After sober and judicious consideration, and weighing one thing against another in the interests of reasonable
compromise, H. L. Mencken concluded that a startling and dramatic improvement in American education
required only that we hang all the professors and burn down the schools. His uncharacteristically moderate
proposal was not adopted. Those who actually knew more about education than Mencken did could see that
his plan was nothing more than cosmetic and would in fact provide only an outward appearance of
improvement. Those who knew less, on the other hand, had somewhat more elaborate plans of their own, and
they just happened to be in charge of the schools.
Those who knew less, to be specific, were the members of the National Education Association's Commission
on the Reorganization of Secondary Education, a.k.a. The Gang of Twentyseven, now long forgotten but
certainly not gone. They builded better than they knew, and their souls go marching on in every school in
America today. The Commission was established in 1913, the year that also brought us the income tax. Many
of its members were functionaries of school bureaucracies, from the United States Commissioner of
Education himself down through supervisors and associate superintendents and principals and even a high
school inspector, whatever that was, to no less a personage than a senior educational secretary of the YMCA.
Professors and assistant professors of education represented the higher learning. One of them was chairman
of the committee on mathematics, naturally, while the committees on lesser disciplines, notably classical and
modern languages, were directed by high school teachers. The stern sciences were served by a professor of
education, while the smiling sciences like social studies and the other household arts were overseen by
federal bureaucrats. In the whole motley crew there were no scientists, no mathematicians, no historians, no
traditional scholars of any sort.
That was surely no accident, for it seems to have been an article of the Commission's unspoken agenda to
overturn the work of an earlier NEA task force that had been made up largely of scholars, the Committee of
Ten, called together in 1892 and chaired by Charles W. Eliot, then president of Harvard University. That
committee had come out in favor of traditional academic study in the public schools, which they fancied
should be devoted to the pursuit of knowledge and the training of the intellect. But what can you expect from
a bunch of intellectuals? The Eliot Report of 1893 was given to things like this:
As studies in language and in the natural sciences are best adapted to cultivate the habits of
observation; as mathematics are the traditional training of the reasoning faculties; so history
and its allied branches are better adapted than any other studies to promote the invaluable
mental power which we call judgment.
Obviously, the Eliot committee did its work in the lost, dark days before the world of education had
discovered the power of the bold innovative thrust. All they asked of the high schools was the pursuit of
knowledge and the exercise of the mind in the cause of judgment.
The Gang of Twentyseven, unhampered by intellectual predispositions, found that proposal an elitist's
dream. They concluded, in other words, that precious few schoolchildren were capable of the pursuit of
knowledge and the exercise of the mind in the cause of judgment. That, of course, turned out to be the most
momentous selffulfilling prophecy of our century. It is also a splendid example of the muddled thought out
of which established educational practice derives its theories. The proposals of the Eliot report are deemed
elitist because they presume that most schoolchildren are generally capable of the mastery of subject matter
and intellectual skill; the proposals of the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education, on the
other hand, are ``democratic'' in presuming that most schoolchildren are not capable of such things and
should stick to homemaking and the manual arts.
The Seven Deadly Principles 32
Page No 35
This bizarre principle is still very much with us as a generator of educationistic theory and practice. It shows,
among other things, the immense power of words, especially nasty ones like ``elitism,'' notably abhorrent to
our egalitarian society. It is certainly true (and puzzling as well, since the men who made us this egalitarian
society were indubitable intellectuals) that we distrust intellectuals. They do seem to be an elite, although,
thank goodness, a powerless elite. They butter little bread. Nevertheless, when we ask those intellectuals what
we should do in the schools, they tell us to do everything we can to bring forth swarms of other intellectuals,
which must lead us to conclude that the intellectual elitists can't be too smart. What kind of an elitist can it be
who wants to generate his own competitors, and lots of them at that? But the champions of a ``democratic''
public education, righteous enemies of elitism, rejoice in the profitable belief that hardly any of the children
in their charge can expect to rise to the level of curriculum facilitator, to say nothing of superintendent of
schools.
In the cause of ``democratic'' public education, the Gang of Twentyseven compounded illogic with
ignorance by deciding that the education proposed by the Eliot committee was primarily meant as
``preparation for the college or university.'' True, relatively few high school graduates of 1913 went on to
college; but even fewer had done so in 1893. Indeed, it was just because so few would go on to more
education that the Eliot committee wanted so many to have so much in high school. But the Gang of
Twentyseven decided that since very few students would go on to the mastery of a discipline and the
rigorous training of the mind in college, which colleges were still fancied to provide in those days, there was
little need to fuss about such things in high school. They had far more interesting things to fuss about in any
case, their kinds of things. They enshrined them all, where they abide as holy relics of the cult of
educationism to this day, in their final report, issued in 1918 (and printed at government expense, like all the
outpourings of educationism ever since) as Cardinal Principles of Secondary Education.
Cardinal Principles was a small pamphlet, not much larger than The Communist Manifesto or a man's hand.
It rejected the elitist and undemocratic education of the dark past and provided in its place ``preparation for
effective living.'' It made us the effective livers we are today, and it sends forth every year from our public
schools and colleges all those effective livers who will make the future of the nation.
The seven cardinal principles were put forth as the paths to the seven ``main objectives of education,'' which
had finally been discovered once and for all after twentyfive hundred years of intellectual floundering. The
first of those main objectives was Health. Health. Its primacy is justified by that firm grasp on the obvious
that was to become the very foundation stone of educational theorizing: ``Health needs cannot be neglected
during the period of secondary education without serious danger to the individual and the race.'' How true.
You can't make effective livers out of dead children. And think of the race! Suppose they all die! How then
will we get the taxpayers ``to secure teachers competent to ascertain and meet the needs of individual pupils
and able to inculcate in the entire student body a love for clean sport?''
(It is interesting to notice that, like this one, all of the proposals in Cardinal Principles will call for vastly
increased faculties and administrative bureaucracies both in the high schools and in the teachers' colleges.
This has since become the Eighth Cardinal Principle, which you can see doing its work in your local school
system whenever any remedy to any problem or shortcoming is proposed: Whatever we do will require more
money, more teachers, more administrators, and more mandated courses in education.)
Cardinal Principles even proposed that there be in each school a kind of health officer, whose job would
range from looking around for insanitary conditions in the building to inquiring into the social lives of the
students, who might well be risking their health in the streets and in icecream parlors. It was in the cause of
health, I believe, that my own firstgrade teacher used to hold fingernail inspection every morning and cry
out now and then to some slouching young reprobate: ``Posture!'' It was in this cause, too, that what was
called ``physical education'' became the oppressive monster that it is today and, by the very power of its
name, compounded beyond remedy the educationistic delusion that ``education'' and ``training'' are the same
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 33
Page No 36
thing. It is not a coincidence, nor is it without large consequences, that so many of America's high school
principals were once phys. ed. teachers.
The second ``main objective'' is, at first, slightly surprising: Command of Fundamental Processes. In 1918
that meant just about what Basic Minimum Competence means today. Although it certainly did not mean
anything more than Basic Minimum Competence either, it did at least mean a higher minimum. Nowadays
we count ourselves lucky if the students can read and write at the ninthgrade level, whatever that means this
year. Cardinal Principles says that such a level of competence, even in 1918, ``is not sufficient for the needs
of modern life.'' (I must say, too, that Cardinal Principles, although stilted and dull, is not written in the
selfserving, mindless jargon of today's educationists. This credit, however, must be balanced against a large
debit. It was in the ensuing scramble of silly, pseudoscholarship required for the justification of the cardinal
principles that our educationists discovered the power of mendacious gobbledegook and adopted it as their
native tongue.)
Furthermore, it is clear that, while the drafters of Cardinal Principles do put Command of Fundamental
Processes second only to Health, they do so apparently as an involuntary bend of the knee to that discredited
old elitism. About the other ``main objectives'' they have a lot to say, and many suggestions as to how
curriculum might be manipulated in their accommodation and many new people hired in their cause. When
they have called for Command of Fundamental Processes, that's it. They proceed at once to Worthy
Homemembership, a main objective much more to their liking.
Cardinal Principles admits, affirms, in fact, that ``In the education of every highschool girl, the household
arts should have a prominent place because of their importance to the girl herself and to others whose welfare
will be directly in her keeping.'' It presumes, too, that even girls who do idle away a few more years in
college or in ``occupations not related to the household arts'' will someday have to face their ``actual needs
and future responsibilities'' and ``understand the essentials of food values, of sanitation, and of household
budgets.''
Although Worthy Homemembership obviously has a lot to do with cooking and sewing, it also provides for
the dilution of whatever may persist of the old elitist curriculum:
The social studies should deal with the home as a fundamental social institution and clarify
its relation to the wider interests outside. [That will disqualify history, a discipline notably
unconcerned with ``the home,'' as a worthy study.] Literature should interpret and idealize
the human elements that go to make the home. [That knocks out the study of literature, which
is remarkably unlikely to do what some educationists decree that it ``should'' do.] Music and
art should result in more beautiful homes and greater joy therein. [They really had to stretch
for that one, but it will call to order pretentious art and music teachers who peddle their
subjects as intrinsically worthwhile, and it will even justify the inclusion of interior
decorating in the high school curriculum.]
It is exactly that, the dilution of ordinary academic study, that makes this kind of ``education'' so pernicious.
Obviously no one can object to housekeeping skills or to beautiful homes and joy therein. But beauty and joy,
and even housekeeping skills, are either diminished or destroyed by ignorance and stupidity, which are likely
to flourish in a place where history is subordinated to a ``social study'' of the home as an institution and where
literature is chosen for study if it does what it ``should'' do.
Those funny ``educations'' are all the more powerful and longlived because they are designed to grow fat
and sassy through eating the bodies of their victims. When we embark on an ambitious program of Worthy
Homemembership Education, we justify ourselves by naming some indubitable benefits we intend to
bestow: an understanding of ``the essentials of food values, of sanitation, and of household budgets,'' for
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 34
Page No 37
instance. Those benefits, of course, can be had, along with a great deal more, by those who study and learn
such things as biology, chemistry, and mathematics, but those stern old disciplines offer little scope for the
bold, innovative thrust and the increased budget. So we pretend, or some of us may actually believe, that
home budgeting, which is a skill all these girls need, can be learned in the absence of mathematics, which is
an elitist skill useful only for a few.
And sure enough little by little the study and practice of such subjects as science and mathematics decline,
and fewer and fewer students take such courses. We have helped this decline by providing easy and
``democratic'' options for those who seem to have a little trouble with the demanding elitism of traditional
academic study. Now the day has come when very few high school girls can do any arithmetic at all. Now is
our triumph. We can redignify Worthy Homemembership Education with a trendy new name, Consumer
Education, and teach nutrition and wary shopping to girls who are innocent of science and unable to figure
out the price of an ounce of macaroni. Those deficits, which flow from our very existence, we can now put
forth as arguments for our continued existence. This pattern, of course, can describe the growth and triumph
of any of those ``educations.''
Another such education was the fourth main objective in Cardinal Principles: Vocation. The Commission's
proposals for a vocational education program that would take up ``much of the pupil's time'' derive from its
own cardinal principles: that few students can do academic work and would best spend their time in learning
homemaking skills and trades, and that the larger purpose of public education was to bring about a certain
social order. They urge vocational education not only to ``equip the individual to secure a livelihood for
himself and those dependent on him,'' but also so that he may ``maintain the right relationships toward his
fellow workers and society.'' The Commission does not, of course, explain what ``right relationships'' might
be, perhaps presuming that all the other educationists who read their report would surely favor right
relationships over wrong relationships without giving the matter any thought. As usual.
But vocational education, as imagined in Cardinal Principles, was not to be a separate program within the
schools; it was intended that even those students who did not spend ``much of their time'' in the wood shop
would nevertheless ``develop an appreciation of the significance'' of vocations ``and a clear conception of
right relations [there they are again] between the members of the chosen vocation, between different
vocational groups, between employer and employee, and between producer and consumer.'' All such things
can be studied, of course, in the context of several wellknown disciplines, but study can provide only
knowledge. Cardinal Principles does not call for knowledge of these matters, however, but for
``appreciation'' and a ``clear conception of right relations.''
It is a thematic illusion of our educational enterprise that understanding can be had without knowledge, that
the discretion can be informed without information, that judgment need not wait on evidence. Before we can
ask what are the right relations between producer and consumer, for instance, we must know what are all the
possible relations between producer and consumer. We must know antecedents and consequences; we must
know functions and contexts. We must, in fact, know more than we can hope to know, which is why
thoughtful people only reluctantly and armed with as much knowledge as possible leap from knowing into
judging and decide to ``hold'' some truths selfevident.
On the other hand, Cardinal Principles, in speaking of its fifth main objective, Civics Education, leaps
blithely into: ``Too frequently, however, does mere information, conventional in value and remote in its
bearing, make up the content of the social studies.'' Mere information. What the Commission might mean by
``conventional in value'' I just don't know, but I do know, along with all who have ever studied, that only a
fool is willing to take the risk that this or that bit of mere information is ``remote in its bearing.'' Facts seem
unrelated only to those who know few facts.
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 35
Page No 38
As you might expect, Civics Education what a noble cause! is given enormous power to alter and
dilute the content of traditional academic subjects:
History should so treat the growth of institutions that their present value may be appreciated.
Geography should show the interdependence of men while it shows their common
dependence on nature. Civics should concern itself less with constitutional questions and
remote governmental functions, and should direct attention to social agencies close at hand
and to the informal activities of daily life that regard and seek the common good. Such
agencies as childwelfare organizations and consumers' leagues afford specific opportunities
for the expression of civic qualities by the older pupils.
The work in English should kindle social ideals and give insight into social conditions and
into personal character as related to these conditions. Hence the emphasis by the committee
on English on the importance of a knowledge of social activities, social movements, and
social needs on the part of the teacher of English.
And, not content with prescribing an ``appreciation'' of institutions that would satisfy Lenin, ignorance of the
constitution in the name of responsible citizenship, and literature as an instigator of social compliance, the
Commission decides also that `` all subjects should contribute to good citizenship.'' (My italics.) While they
would probably not suggest, in that cause, that the binomial theorem be put to a vote in class, their
descendants and adherents will, in fact, suggest that mathematics, obviously ``remote in its bearing'' on good
citizenship, is not really at the heart of the educational enterprise.
While its concrete proposals for Civics Education are very much like its proposals for all the other
educations, Cardinal Principles, in the name of ``attitudes and habits important in a democracy,'' goes an
extra step and prescribes what should actually happen in the classroom. It urges ``the assignment of projects
and problems to groups of pupils for cooperative solution and the socialized recitation whereby the class as a
whole develops a sense of collective responsibility. Both of these devices give training in collective
thinking.'' Here we can see the theoretical foundations of the rap session, the encounter group, the values
clarification module, and the typical course in education, but also something far worse.
For thousands of years, many decent, knowing, and thoughtful people have hated and feared democracy, and
with good reasons. We don't think of it that way any longer, probably because we have all been to schools
devoted to the cardinal principles, but the framers of our society took great pains to guard us against the
obvious (to them) dangers inherent in majority rule. It was precisely to commend and elucidate the
constitution's ability to protect the few from the ignorance or selfinterest of the many that Madison wrote
the tenth Federalist Paper; which is, of course, not included in the Civics Education curriculum. The children
who are to generate ``cooperative solutions'' and ``socialized recitations'' are to do so without concern for, or
even any knowledge of, ``constitutional questions and remote governmental functions'' like checks and
balances. They will do their ``collective thinking'' unencumbered by ``mere information.''
It is another of the educationists' selfserving delusions that if enough of the ignorant pool their resources,
knowledge will appear, and that a parliament of fools can deliberate its way to wisdom. This delusion is not
entirely groundless. It is grounded in another delusion, the one that flows from a halfbaked adaptation of the
work of Wundt.
You will recall Cattell's curious conclusion that learning the sounds of letters was not useful in learning to
read because those who could read did not sound out the letters. Recall also that Wundt saw learning (he did
not say ``education'') as a conditioned response to stimuli. For American educationists, such ``facts'' were
absorbed into a generalized notion that might be put something like this: We notice that educated people,
whatever that might mean, have certain attributes and that they do things in certain ways, or, since we are
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 36
Page No 39
educationists, that they ``exhibit certain behaviors.'' So, if our students come to have those attributes and
exhibit those behaviors, they will be educated, and we will be educators.
Educated and thoughtful people have indeed often met and deliberated together and solved problems and
found wisdom. Just look at the Constitutional Convention, for example, or, if you're a little short on mere
information, consider the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education. Therefore, if we
assign projects and problems to groups of students we will instill in them the same ``sense of collective
responsibility'' that we see so often among the educated and thoughtful. In that fashion, furthermore, we will
engender in them an appropriate appreciation of ``the ideals of American democracy and loyalty to them,'' as
Cardinal Principles recommends.
An analogous line of reasoning would begin with the observation that musicians have been known to play
``Lady of Spain'' and end with the determination to train seals to play ``Lady of Spain'' on bicycle horns and
turn them into musicians.
And there is another ominous and farreaching implication in the Commission's assignment of projects and
problems hidden, not very deeply, in ``collective thinking.'' This phrase reveals an appalling ignorance and
thoughtlessness out of which terrifying educationistic malfeasances have been growing for decades.
Schooling is done in public places, but the roots of an education can grow only in the hidden ground of the
mind. Lessons are taught in social institutions, but they can be learned only by private people. The acts that
are at once the means and the ends of education, knowing, thinking, understanding, judging, are all
committed in solitude. It is only in a mind that the work of the mind can be done. There is no such thing as
``collective thinking.'' Our schools can be an instrument for socialization or an incentive to thoughtfulness,
but they cannot be both.
Thus it is, for instance, that such elementary skills as reading and writing, public analogues of private
thinking, are so ill taught in the schools. It is not sufficient explanation of this failure to point out that the
educationists who design the schools are themselves notoriously poor readers and writers, although they are.
That leads us only to ask in turn why that should be so. At the root of our widespread and institutionalized
illiteracy is a fevered commitment to socialization and an equally unhealthy hostility to the solitary, and thus
probably antisocial, work of the mind. In school, the inane and uninformed regurgitations of the ninthgrade
rap session on solar energy as a viable alternative to nuclear power are positive, creative,
selfesteemenhancing student behavioral outcomes; the child who sits alone at the turning of the staircase,
reading, is a weirdo. The students did not bring that ``appreciation'' to school; they learned it there.
Somewhat later in their history, the educationists will justify and formalize their hostility to the intellect, with
which they never did feel comfortable, by inventing the ``affective domain'' of feelings and attitudes and
appreciations and setting its gracious virtues over against the tedious and unimaginative ``rote'' learning of
the merely ``cognitive domain.'' But they will only raise walls where the Gang of Twentyseven has dug the
foundation. We can see the marks of their shovels in all those appreciations and attitudes and values and
``worthy'' attributes of this and that. And when they come to their sixth main objective of secondary
education, Worthy Use of Leisure, they outdo their successors in a sublime presumptuousness possible only
to the happily and profoundly ignorant.
As to the Worthy Use of Leisure, they counsel thus:
Heretofore the high school has given little conscious attention to this objective. It has so
exclusively sought intellectual discipline that it has seldom treated literature, art, and music
so as to evoke right emotional response and produce positive enjoyment. Its presentations of
science should aim, in part, to arouse a genuine appreciation of nature.
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 37
Page No 40
So. Intellectual discipline is not compatible with ``right emotional response'' and ``positive enjoyment.'' And
a pack of manual arts teachers, educationists, and bureaucrats can tell us what a right emotional response
would be, presumably. They can clarify for us, without any tedious attention to inorganic chemistry or the
laws of motion, not only an appreciation of nature but a genuine appreciation of nature. They are bestowers
of blessings on the benighted. Their discoveries, however, would probably come as a sad surprise to
Jefferson, who, in spite of his command of intellectual disciplines, labored all his life under the delusion that
he did take ``positive enjoyment'' from literature, art, and especially from music.
One of the characteristics of the mind of educationism, just as much now as in the days of Cardinal
Principles, is an apparent inability to follow paths of thought far enough to discover contradictions in logic. If
scientific research, or technological craftsmanship, for that matter, were as little given to selfexamination as
educationistic theory, we would have practically nothing that worked. The notion that intellectual discipline
is somehow an impediment to ``right response,'' a notion that we find not only in the context of the arts but
everywhere in Cardinal Principles and in subsequent educationistic theorizing, must eventually lead us to the
conclusion that those who hold it cannot be believed. It is, after all, by virtue of some fancied ``intellectual
discipline'' in themselves that educationistic theorists claim to prescribe the ``right'' responses, attitudes, and
appreciations that are precluded by intellectual discipline.
This is not only illogical but even antisocial, which is another disabling contradiction in a theory proposing
schooling as a means of socialization. They say, in effect, that students who are needlessly led into
intellectual discipline will not achieve right emotional response, but that educationists are not thus
handicapped. It is a strange sort of teacher who says in his heart that his students need never know what he
knows. That goes far beyond elitism; it is cultism. If a teacher is dedicated to knowledge and thought, he
works in the hope that his students, some of them, one of them, will come to know and think more than he
does, for only thus can knowledge and thought be served. To treat his students, or some of them, or even one
of them, as though they could never know and think what he knows and thinks, suggests a dedication to
something else. Perhaps to his job. Perhaps he fears to raise up what such a teacher would surely think of as
competition. While an individual teacher, of course, need have no realistic fears that some student will
supplant him, the same is not true of the ideologues who claim to define the whole system of teaching and
learning. How convenient it is, we notice, for the future welfare of the commissioners that they are immune
to the nasty side effects of intellectual discipline from which they will magnanimously shelter the children.
I must note, at this point, that the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education was assembled
by the National Education Association, a widely misunderstood outfit. The ordinary citizen reads its
pronouncements in the newspapers from time to time and notices that it gives its seal of approval to treacly
television shows and elementary dramatizations of popular ``classics.'' He has the impression that the NEA is
something ``official.'' But it is, of course, as it was in 1918 and long before, a trade union. That it should be
called on to set national policy in the public schools is like putting the teamsters' union in charge of traffic
laws and the licensing of drivers, but even more so. We have accepted the determinations of a teachers' union
as to how America should be educated only because the job of designing an educational system is so
hideously boring that only those whose selfinterest is clearly at stake will undertake it. Our corporate
selfinterest, to be sure, is also very much at stake, but not clearly , at least not clearly enough for the
ordinary citizen, who cannot see beyond the fact that all questions of education and schooling are hideously
boring.
The selfinterest of a massive educationists' trade union is evident on every page of Cardinal
Principles. Whether that selfinterest influences the document in partnership with shabby habits of thought,
or whether those habits are themselves the consequences of the selfinterest, who can say? But the result is
the same. In every ``main objective'' we can find generous provision for the employment of growing hosts of
duespaying members of the NEA. It is also assured that much room will be made in the academic world for
a new class, the arrivistes of educationism, the guidance counselors and curriculum facilitators, the physical
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 38
Page No 41
education and typing teachers, the appreciation experts and the right emotional response imparters, the
fingernail inspectors, and the right relationships inducers, who can launch themselves easily into secure and
respectable careers without worrying about the burdensome demands of mere information and intellectual
discipline.
In the world projected in Cardinal Principles, there is no place for scholars or scholarship. The whole, vast
enterprise of training the minds that will shape the thought and knowledge of the future is dealt with in
exactly one sentence: ``Provisions should be made also for those having distinctly academic interests and
needs.'' Exactly what provisions the Gang of Twentyseven might have had in mind, we'll never know,
although their provisions for the supervision of habits of hygiene and social events are detailed at length. We
have to wonder, too, how such provisions could be made at all, given that ``Each subject now taught in high
school is in need of extensive reorganization in order that it may contribute more effectively to the objectives
outlined herein, and the place of that subject in secondary education should depend on the value of such
contribution.'' By that principle, any course of study that might attract those wretched misfits with academic
interests, an intellectual discipline clogged with mere information, would have to be either diluted into the
pursuit of appreciation or simply eliminated. That, of course, has happened.
(All is not lost, however. In any school there are a few teachers who didn't know what they were getting into
when they went to the teachers' college and have stoutly and usually silently retained their devotion to
intellectual discipline and even improved their stores of mere information in spite of having to give most of
their time to education courses. They are the unintended ``provision...for those having distinctly academic
interests and needs.'' That's why every educated person you know will give special credit to this or that
certain teacher. Such teachers, however, are seldom popular with their colleagues, and never with the
administrators, so they often have to work underground. No matter. Those weird students will find those
weird teachers and will learn from them, in any subject at all, something of the work of the mind.)
In fact, the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education was simply not interested in students
with ``distinctly academic needs and interests.'' It began by assuming that there were few of those in any case,
and ended by projecting an ``education'' that would make them even fewer. In the Commission's plan there
was as little concern for academic talent as there was space on the page for naming the provisions, for the
commissioners were, deep down where it really counted, not teachers at all but Sundayschool supervisors
manqués, officious and illinformed laymen busily hastening to good makeworks and armed with the
serene selfconfidence that only ignorance can provide. They wanted to be not teachers but preachers, and
prophets too, charging themselves with the cure of the soul of democracy and the raising up in the faith of
true believers. They made concrete and formal the antiintellectual dogmatism that characterizes our schools
today.
The seventh and last of the Commission's main objectives of secondary education was nothing less than
Ethical Character, which they pronounced ``paramount'' in a democratic society, as if Plato, Epictetus, Saint
Augustine, Voltaire, Kant, Spinoza, and so on, for countless thinkers who lived under all sorts of
governments, had somehow missed the point now perfectly clear to certain manual arts teachers and associate
superintendents. They were as smugly confident of their ability to engender Ethical Character through ``the
wise selection of content and methods of instruction in all subjects of study'' as they were of their ability to
tell right emotional response from wrong. All it takes, after all, is what they are certain they have: wisdom.
I have more to say later on the vexatious question of the role of public education, all too accurately described
in Cardinal Principles as ``the one agency that may be controlled definitely and consciously,'' in the
supposed formation of Ethical Character. For now, it is useful to point to the obvious fact that you will have a
hard time finding a citizen who is opposed to the formation of ethical character. Or to worthy use of leisure
time. Or to health, or any of the ``main objectives'' of secondary education as discovered in Cardinal
Principles. Those objectives can be seen to constitute what is essentially a political platform eminently
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 39
Page No 42
acceptable to all those who are in favor of good and against evil. Public acceptance of that platform was all
the more certain because there was, after all, no opposing party.
And how could there be? In this case, opposition could hardly be the simple recommendation of contrary
``main objectives.'' No one would vote for some educational splinter group calling for sickness and
degeneracy. The opposition, if there were to be any, would require in its adherents a precise and thorough
attention to detail, the pursuit of logical argument, the formulation of hypotheses as to consequences, an
underlying theory as to the means and ends of education, and some considerable knowledge of the history of
human thought. Such a constituency will never be large. There was such a constituency, of course, as there
always is, made up of thoughtful and educated people of all kinds, some of them actually in schools. But the
scholarly, academic wing of that small party was not asked to the table with the members of the Commission
on the Reorganization of Secondary Education, who didn't want to hear any more of that ``traditional training
of the reasoning faculties'' stuff in the report of the Eliot committee. And the other political dissidents, the
ones you might call the civilians in the school war, had other and far more important things to do. Most of
them had probably never heard of Cardinal Principles, and those who had would surely have found it of little
interest. The theorists of American public education, actually feeble and helpless creatures, have evolved an
amazing power to protect themselves against predators by emitting an unbearable cloud of dullness and
boredom.
If there is such a thing as an intellectual and cultural elite in America, and there may well be a far larger one
than even its detractors imagine, it is surely worthy of condemnation, for it is selfish and lazy. Jefferson and
his friends indubitably thought of themselves as an elite, a natural aristocracy of talent. So thinking, they saw
themselves not as privileged but as obliged by their gifts, obliged to serve the common good by the simple
fact of their ability to do so. This attitude is not rampant among us. It is especially unrampant in the academic
community, where those who more or less secretly do think of themselves as an elite have trained themselves
to imagine that the dull business of public education has nothing to do with their high endeavors.
The underlying attitudes and beliefs in Cardinal Principles have not been mitigated by the passage of time or
the pressure of momentous events. Quite to the contrary, they have been regularly reaffirmed and
reinvigorated, both in theory and practice. The devisers of the Seven Deadly Principles set out not to teach
certain skills and knowledge to hosts of children but to change the nature of American society. They
succeeded. They didn't, of course, make the vast mass of the people stupid and uninformed, for that happens
in the course of nature without any need for deliberate effort, but they did arrange that fewer and fewer would
reach escape velocity and rise out of the vast mass of the stupid and uninformed. As the consequences of the
deadly principles become evident, sometimes one by one and sometimes in whole hosts of troubles, the
descendants of the Gang of Twentyseven point them out as justifications for even more of the same, more
schemes to alter a society already suffering from all the earlier alterations.
The seven ``main objectives of education'' are still the main objectives of education, although one of them,
Command of Fundamental Processes, was always somewhat less main than the others and remains so now
that it has been renamed Basic Minimum Competence, in which term the important word is ``minimum.'' And
it is exactly toward the achievement of those objectives, especially the greater six, that the training and
indoctrination of schoolteachers is directed. Earnest attention to the seventh is just not possible in this
scheme, for it would require precisely those things that Cardinal Principles finds inimical to ``right'' and
``worthy'' values: stringent intellectual discipline and great stores of mere information. The professors of
education are not interested in those things, for their own training and indoctrination are no different from
what they visit upon their students. After all, what else have they to bestow? And the professors of everything
else just don't want to be bothered, and what they do have to bestow they save for a few favored students who
will in turn become the professors of everything else who just don't want to be bothered. Mencken was right.
The Graves of Academe
The Seven Deadly Principles 40
Page No 43
The Principles March On
The educationism that now informs our schools and teacher academies is an amalgam of postWundtian
misunderstanding and the Sundayschool dogoodism of Cardinal Principles. From the former it takes its
characteristically therapeutic and manipulative methods and devices, and from the latter its pious pretensions
as an agent of social harmony and guardian of the public virtue. In one way, therefore, it is pseudoscientific,
and in the other, pseudoreligious. It is the devotion to contradictory principles of dubious validity that
generates the mental climate of educationism and leads to that special fatuousness so typical of American
educational thought, a vexing blend of the illogical and the sentimental.
As recently as 1971, the National Education Association undertook a project called ``Schools for the 70's and
Beyond.'' The ensuing ``main report,'' ``written primarily [sic] by Warren T. Greenleaf and Gary A. Griffin,''
was published as a slim volume: A Call to Action. Although it was clearly written in the shadow of growing
discontent about schools, it urged at least consideration of ``the thesis that school excellence narrowly
defined, not school failure narrowly defined, has given us most of the problems that divide our nation in
1970'' an entertaining proposition, and one that would surely confirm the assertion in Cardinal
Principles that too much attention to intellectual discipline inhibits right understanding. And the ``argument''
put forth in support of that thesis is itself a dramatic example of worthy disregard for mere information:
It was not illiterate, backward men who spiked our residential skylines with steel forests of
television antennas, spoiled our rivers with the defecations of a hundred ``growth'' industries,
fouled our air with the sooty contrails of a thousand jet planes taking off daily, or choked our
cities with automobiles that cost as much to park as to buy. That work was accomplished by
men whose schooling enabled them to develop transistors, nodepositnoreturn bottles,
pressurized cabins, and a 36monthstopay economy.
You say you want to understand how a modern technological society works? Well, now you know. Men with
schooling cunningly trick the multitudes into buying television antennas and driving expensive cars.
Educated elitists force decent citizens to travel in airplanes and callously require them to dispose of bottles at
their own expense. It isn't the ``illiterate, backward men'' who visit these horrors on us; untainted by
``excellence narrowly defined,'' they can manage only rape, murder, arson, and an occasional gasstation
stickup.
This amazingly stupid oversimplification is perfectly typical of educational theory. It is typical, too, in its
confusion of ``education'' with the ability to design transistors and to pressurize cabins, which is precisely the
sort of thing Cardinal Principles had in mind when it spoke of vocational training. Such a confusion is
inevitable, however, when the pursuit of intellectual discipline is seen as hostile to right and worthy
understanding. Even a fairly elementary technology, that of the electrician or plumber, for example, depends
on certain disciplined habits of mind and a suitably large mass of information. The designing of transistors
may be more complicated, but it is essentially the same kind of enterprise as plumbing. A distrust of
intellectual discipline must eventually become a distrust of any disciplined habits of mind and any traditional
store of ``mere information.'' Logically, therefore, the writers of a Call to Action might also have indicted
plumbers and electricians, the plumbers for having connected us to sewage systems and thence to the spoiling
of rivers, and the electricians for making it easy to plug in the television sets for whose sake we have bought
all those antennas.
Antiintellectualism is like antiSemitism, which only begins with the hating of Jews. From there it goes on
to the ferreting out of hithertounsuspected manifestations of Jewishness, and antiintellectualism goes on
even to the denigration of technology, and thus of the very vocational training that schools offer as one of
many antidotes to intellectualism. One could reasonably expect, therefore, that vocational training in the
The Principles March On 41
Page No 44
schools must become a halfhearted and halfbaked enterprise, whose obvious purpose is not the teaching of
even a relatively simple technology but the segregation of students for whom even ``appreciation'' seems too
difficult. That, as it happens, is the case.
The writers of A Call to Action do not rest their case on the malefactors who brought us industrial waste and
installment payments, outrageous impositions probably dating from neolithic elitism. They go on to say that
``It was not ignorant men who designed a rifle bullet that could spin end over end to increase its fleshtearing
capacity.'' That, they remind us, was done by men with ``schooling in the far reaches of physics.'' Well,
maybe to an educationist a tumbling bullet, like the barb on a spear or the juice on an arrowhead, really
does seem to come from the far reaches of physics. That would make sense.
They name also those devious ``men sufficiently well educated to cite precedents from 200 years of
American law'' as the ones ``who juggled school boundaries...to keep black children separate from white.'' It
was not, they assure us, ``backcountry bumpkins'' who evilly studied law in order to ``manipulate city
ordinances.'' The backcountry bumpkins left that sort of thing to the overeducated gentry and just went on
about the business of beating and shooting and lynching.
It is fascinating, of course, to hear those who operate the schools argue that because there are people who can
build aircraft for profit and cite law in their own cause we may conclude that the schools have actually
provided too much ``excellence.'' What is even more fascinating is that this bewildering and ignorant line of
reasoning should find, apparently, no detractors among the vast membership of the National Education
Association, many thousands of whom must have read and taken comfort from A Call to Action.
When I still fancied that the mindless and illogical utterances so common in Academe were the results simply
of haste or carelessness, and long before I began to study the educationists' selfjustifications in works like
Cardinal Principles and A Call to Action, the following ominously suggestive article appeared in The
Underground Grammarian:
Prostrate Trouble at NJEA
There is a kind of thoughtlessness that is not exactly stupidity. It is a failing seen in ordinarily intelligent
people who, under the influence of selfinterest, prefer to evade clarity of thought in precise language, giving
themselves instead to recitation of the vague and comfortable. They write prostrate prose in which they let
themselves be walked all over by verbal inaccuracies and the failures of logic that those inaccuracies always
cause. Such prose is especially dangerous because it often sounds like common sense around the old
potbellied stove. We will consider a case of crackerbarrel cant from the ruminations of one James P.
Connerton.
Connerton is the new executive director of the New Jersey Education Association. All we know of him is
what we read in the NJEAReview of January, 1979, to wit, that he has now returned to New Jersey after ten
years spent in unspecified enterprises ``in Minnesota, North Dakota, South Dakota, Iowa, Michigan, and
other states.'' How many other states, deponent saith not, but he doth say: ``His goals are our goals. Our
aspirations are his aspirations. Our joy and our pain are his joy and pain.'' The pain probably has to do with
moving expenses.
Deponent is Frank Totten, the president of NJEA. Here's more of what he writes:
Together we are the NJEA. All of us have made us what we are today. What we will be in 10
or 20 years depends on our determination, our forsight, our hard work, and our togetherness.
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 42
Page No 45
Jim Connerton is determined, farsighted, hardworking and one of us. As in the past, we'll do
it together. We will determine our future and the future will be better because we have
worked together.
Welcome home Jim. We need you. The present and the future will be better for us because
we'll work through them together.
That has a quaint charm, no? It sounds like the language in which invocations are spoken at the firemen's
annual clambake and certificates of achievement awarded at Little League banquets. Very American.
However, we'd be readier to accept it even to applaud it if only it had begun with the traditional
Unaccustomed As I Am. In this case, though, we might feel more confident about the future of civilization if
one of the state's bestknown schoolteachers seemed more accustomed to written English, even to such trivia
as comma splices and paragraph logic.
Never mind. Totten is only a harbinger. The har that he binges is an article in which Connerton speaks
his mind: ``Our 'top' priorities.''
Strictly speaking, we can not name more than one priority, or first thing , but the plural is irresistible to those
who want to dignify anything they think they may someday prepare to begin to get ready to do something
about or even just to think about. When a word means almost anything, it means almost nothing. To name
something is to distinguish it from all the other things.
At the NJEA, they seem to have so many priorities that they have to distinguish them from one another,
calling some of them ``top'' priorities. We must assume that they have also some middle priorities and bottom
priorities. Of top priorities, Connerton explores a mere twelve. Here's what he says about a vexatious top
priority indeed:
Every reasonable person concedes that we can't hold the parent accountable for the color of a
child's hair, that we can't rate the minister by the number of parishioners who break the
Commandments, and that we can't blame the coach when a linebacker misses a tackle. Most
people also concede that we can't judge teachers by the scores their students make on tests
especially on tests approved by some state office in Trenton that does not mesh with the local
curriculum. Students should be evaluated by a variety of relevant measures, and so should
teachers.
That ``every reasonable person'' is a rhetorical gimmick similar to a speaker's promise to make no mention of
the wellknown fact that his opponent is a thief and a pederast. In this case it is less effective, for it
introduces either a shocking inanity or some hitherto unimagined cataclysm in genetics. But Connerton
knows his audience. His pains are their pains, you'll recall, and they feel an almost intractable pain whenever
they hear ``accountable.'' By using the word in this context, he deludes readers into swallowing his absurdity,
because they are predisposed to think that to hold parents ``accountable'' for attributes passed on to offspring
is to castigate them for dereliction. If Connerton had said that in plain English, he would have avoided the
absurd only to fall into the irrelevant. ``Every reasonable person,'' and even some members of the NJEA,
would have asked, So what else is new, Jim?
Having grounded his argument firmly on a proposition that is either preposterous or pointless, depending on
how we understand ``accountable,'' but having thereby won the hearts and minds of thoughtless readers,
Connerton offers two further propositions meant to be analogous to the first. However, if they were plain
statements of fact, which they are not, they could be analogous only to the irrelevant version of the first
proposition. In order to be analogous to the other possible version, the absurd one, they would have to be
obvious misrepresentations of fact, which they also are not. Therefore they are not analogous to the first
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 43
Page No 46
proposition. In one way, that's lucky for Connerton, since even schoolteachers might be able to spot three
logical monstrosities in a row. In another way, it's unlucky. His second and third propositions are analogous
to the business of evaluating the effectiveness of teachers, and they suggest the opposite of what Connerton
wants to say.
We can expect some normal amount of oxcoveting and idolatry in any congregation; but, should sinning
increase inordinately and persist obstinately, as illiteracy has in the schools, we might indeed think to ``rate''
the shepherd of the flock. Furthermore, meek as they are, ministers would probably reject the implication that
their work can be presumed to have no effect at all. Are teachers defending themselves by claiming that what
they do cannot be presumed to have any effect? Why else would Connerton imply as much about the
ministers? Maybe that's why we don't see those cute billboards anymore, the ones that used to say, ``Teachers
make the difference.''
And those hardeyed entrepreneurs who invest in football teams do indeed blame coaches and fire them,
too when more and more linebackers miss more and more tackles. It's only amateurs who want to talk
about ``how you played the game.'' Does this analogy tell us that schooling should be judged as leniently as
amateur athletics, and that we should be good sports, saying of each newly graduated illiterate, Well, that's
how the ball bounces? If we were willing to concede that, do you suppose that Connerton would then concede
that teachers should get the same salaries as those guys who coach the Little Leagues?
We have to presume, having heard of no mass defection from the NJEA, that most of the schoolteachers in
New Jersey read this passage and found no fault in it. They were apparently content to find themselves
defended in a ragged mishmash of nonsequiturs and false analogies that would earn a big fat F in any
freshman logic course in the country. It must have reminded them of the papers that always guaranteed a big
fat A, and perhaps even a cheerful, rubberstamped smiling face, in all their education courses.
Whether or not Connerton knew what he was doing, who can say? But we can say that if he did he is an
exceedingly clever writer, who knows that teachers are not too good at noticing fallacies. If he did not know
what he was doing...well, that's not our problem. He is paid for the work of his mind not by taxpayers but by
schoolteachers.
This tiny passage raises colossal questions: Does it reflect accurately the intelligent power of the average
teacher in New Jersey? If so, we have given the teaching of our children into the care of the slowwitted. Or
can it be that our teachers can see through this stuff but choose to let it stand because they like it, presuming
(oh, so correctly) that it will prove effective in persuading a slowwitted public? Must we choose between
dullness of mind and selfserving cynicism? What can we hope for where the interest of teachers is best
served by the stupidity of the people? Do you want a world in which reasoning like Connerton's is accepted
without question?
This is the most depressing text we have ever examined. It suggests a horrifying hypothesis, to wit, that, far
from failing in its intended task, our educational system is in fact succeeding magnificently, because its aim
is to keep the American people thoughtless enough to go on supporting the system. What educationists may
say or even believe that they are doing is not to the point. Their selfinterest is evident, and the cogency of
their thinking is at least questionable. A hypothesis must be tested by reference to facts and its ability to
account for the facts.
Now do your homework. Find some facts to test that dismal hypothesis. Brace yourself. You're going to have
a bad day.
It may be only a coincidence that the passage cited is the work of a man who is in charge of an affiliate of the
National Education Association, the people who brought us not only Cardinal Principles but our new
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 44
Page No 47
Department of Education, but I don't think so. His pretense at argument is remarkably like that earlier bit
about the wicked antennamongers. His audience is the same. His intention is the same: corporate
selfjustification. And, like the writers of A Call to Action, he can obviously write utter nonsense without any
fear that his fellow educationists will expose him and call him to account. He is exercising the privileges of
his membership in an extremely unusual sort of conspiracy, an unconscious conspiracy, if you can imagine
such a thing, whose members are, in a very special sense, indubitably ``innocent.'' They have no idea at all of
what they are doing.
I want to repeat now a passage that appeared earlier and that may have seemed to you a trifle rash:
We are people who imagine that we are weighing important issues when we exchange
generalizations and wellknown opinions. We decide how to vote or what to buy according
to whim or fancied selfinterest, either of which is easily engendered in us by the
manipulation of language, which we have neither the will nor the ability to analyze. We
believe that we can reach conclusions without having the faintest idea of the difference
between inferences and statements of fact, often without any suspicions that there are such
things and that they are different. We are easily persuaded and repersuaded by what seems
authoritative, without any notion of those attitudes and abilities that characterize authority.
We do not notice elementary fallacies in logic; it doesn't even occur to us to look for them;
few of us are even aware that such things exist. We make no regular distinctions between
those kinds of things that can be known and objectively verified and those that can only be
believed or not. Nor are we likely to examine, when we believe or not, the induced
predispositions that may make us do the one or the other. We are easy prey.
Well, perhaps that sweeping ``we'' was rash, but the rest of it seems to me a fair description of people who
can read about the antennamongers or Connerton's clergymen and coaches without dismay and fury. There
is no evidence whatsoever that reasoning of that sort, which can be found wherever educationism is preached,
arouses either fury or dismay or even a mild discontent. That fact, intriguing in itself, suggests some further
facts about educationism, where the blind are led about by the oneeyed king.
It can lead us to take a closer look at educationistic ``humanism,'' which, as you will remember, is the virtue
for whose sake the educationists can hold that curious article of faith that finds intellectual achievement an
inhibitor of effective teaching. In 1918 the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education
concluded, as we have seen, that the high schools had ``so exclusively sought intellectual discipline'' as to
preclude ``right emotional response.'' Although that inappropriate emphasis on intellectual discipline was
soon replaced by hundreds of easy electives intended to ensure a satisfactory adjustment to life, the writers of
A Call to Action discovered, in 1971, that there was still far too much of it. ``We have,'' they say, speaking
presumably for the NEA members who could read with gladness about those innocent backcountry
bumpkins, ``overemphasized the intellectual development of students at the expense of other capacities.''
They called for less intellectual development and more attention to ``other categories of human potential
emotional, social, aesthetic, spiritual, and physical which suggest other directions for curricular reform.''
There you have the beginnings of an understanding of the educationistic concept of ``humanism.'' It has to do
with those ``other categories of human potential,'' other than intellectual, that is. This is a drastic
transformation of a more wellknown kind of humanism, in which it was quite specifically the human mind
and its power of reason that gave the idea its name. Educationistic humanism is, in fact, so utterly unlike the
system of thought ordinarily called by that name that I prefer to call the former by the name given it, although
not exclusively in the cause of clarity, in the pages of The Underground Grammarian: ``humanisticism.'' In
humanism, it is the mind of man that is the type and discoverer at once of knowledge and understanding. In
humanisticism, various feelings, or, as Cardinal Principles called them, ``right emotional responses,'' seem to
be thought of as the quintessential signs of being human. If we say of someone that he is a humanist, we
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 45
Page No 48
suggest that he does the work of his mind in the expectation that he can devise knowledge and discover truth.
The humanisticist, on the other hand, distrusts the work of the mind and seeks rather to be a certain kind of
person than to do a certain kind of thing, expecting, it would seem, that knowledge and truth, relative things
in any case, will become visible to the right kind of person.
The passage cited above, the one about the television antennas, is a splendid example of humanisticism, but
certainly not of humanism. The humanist, too, would be repelled by filth and ugliness, but he would not find
in it evidence of the inhumanity of the intellect in the ``men whose schooling enabled them to develop
transistors.'' On the contrary, he might lament the plight of the millions in whom the inadequately schooled
intellect makes possible and profitable all those expensive automobiles and the forests of antennas. He would
find in all our ugliness and filth a sad comment on the meagerness of mind out of which we so prize material
comfort and convenience that we transform perfectly human and ingenious technological achievements into
common nuisances. He would even be able to suggest a remedy in the form of a populace sufficiently skilled
in the work of the mind so as to consider the probable consequences of materialistic appetite and thus make
such public nuisances less profitable.
The humanisticist sees that ugliness and filth as the work of those in whom the work of the mind has
engendered wrong feelings or, just as bad, an absence of feelings. In this he finds the baleful influence of
``excellence narrowly defined,'' by which he seems to mean the development of intellectual, or at least,
technical, skills without the simultaneous development of right feelings. He may also imply, but who can be
sure, that intellectual discipline is hostile to the development of right feelings. That would seem to be the
point in the later passage, where ``other categories of human potential'' are urged as an antidote to intellectual
development. In effect, where the humanist says, If only we were thoughtful, the humanisticist says, If only
we all felt the same way!
Humanisticism is sentimental, and in both senses of the word. The humanisticist sees the sentiments, or
perhaps the human propensity to feel sentiments, as the quintessentially human attribute. He also puts faith,
itself a sentiment, in what he considers either the evidence or even the conclusions of feelings, provided, of
course, that they are ``right'' feelings. The delicious glow of sated greed, for instance, which might well have
been the portion of those who sold all those antennas, although not of those who developed the theoretical
understanding out of which they come, can not be trusted. It is not, in the language of Cardinal Principles,
``worthy.''
We can now reconsider a passage cited above, in which an educationistic ``researcher'' names ``the personal
characteristics related to transpersonal teaching'':
(1) a view of man as essentially and inherently good at his core, (2) that the locus of power
and authority in one's life is within the individual, and (3) that when dealing with life
situations it is most effective to apply one's values to a solution with flexibility, and free of
preconceptions or prejudice.
Those are surely decent sentiments, and they were almost certainly accepted and even applauded as such by
the committee that granted the man who approved them a doctorate in education. They are also, of course, for
what other kind can there be, ``received'' sentiments, often expressed, often approved, and sometimes even
felt, at least in certain moods, by some human beings.
As a program for the practice of ``transpersonal teaching,'' however, they may fail to satisfy. The goodness of
man ``at his core'' needs some defining, and even some thought. Many will surely profess a belief that man is
good at his core without having any idea what they mean by those terms and without any knowledge of the
great history of human attempts to understand exactly what those terms might be taken to mean and whether
such a belief could be justified by anything more than sentiment. Nevertheless, one who holds such a belief is
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 46
Page No 49
free to hold it, of course, in a total absence of knowledge and thought. But what about one who not only holds
that belief but even recommends it to others, or, as in this case, puts it forth as a belief that teachers should
have if they want to be good, i.e., transpersonal? Or, to put it more practically, how can the teachertrainers
provide their students with ``a view of man as essentially and inherently good at his core?''
Let's leave aside for now the question of why they should want to do that and ask only how it might be done.
The intellectual study of the history of that belief will not suffice, for it is simply a fact that many who have
pondered the proposition have concluded that it was either false or meaningless. In any case, the
teachertrainers are little likely to turn to intellectual study, which they already know to interdict right
emotional response and to encourage the skepticism out of which men design transistors with no concern at
all for the fact that transistors can be used in weapons. Where study will not serve, only precept and example
remain. That's why the teachers of teachers, and then, of course, the teachers themselves, give much attention
to the skill of ``exhibiting behavior'' of a certain kind. (That girl in the bunny outfit, whom you have probably
forgotten, but I have not, was practicing just that exhibiting a behavior calculated to arouse appropriate
sentiments in little children.) If you behave like one who believes in man's good core, although exactly what
deeds that might require I can't begin to imagine, then your students will come to believe, or at least come to
believe that you believe. The behavior by itself, of course, will be ambiguous, perhaps even baffling, and
unless you also tell your students what your behavior means they may well conclude that you're just a bit
smarmy. Your acts and demeanor are ``reinforcement'' of the precept, the assertion that man's core is good.
See?
The intrusion of the intellect at any point in this process is disastrous. Even a simple question, ``Miss Jones,
why exactly do you view man's core as essentially good?'' will undo many months of exhibited behavior and
reiterated precept. Notice, please, that the disaster lies in the question, not in the answer, although that would
surely make things even worse. It is the asking of the question that marks the intrusion of the intellect, and it
is no less devastating to humanisticism when the question is, as in fact it usually is, unspoken.
The inevitable collision of intellect and sentiment has even more frightful consequences. In a Sunday school
it would be a simple demonstration either of dogmatism or typical grownup hypocrisy, either of which
children can easily recognize and shrug off. But classes in school, although they are in fact dedicated to the
inculcation of beliefs, are often ostensibly devoted to some small work of the mind. In a biology class,
therefore, intellectual inquiries are sometimes appropriate and sometimes not. The resultant confusion
between what is knowable and what is not, and between statement of fact and assertion of belief, is usually
sufficient to last any schoolchild for the rest of his life. And, for all the recitation of precepts and exhibitions
of behavior, the lesson that he learns best is that his teachers could not make such distinctions either. Nor
could their teachers.
To the incipient transpersonal teacher's view of man's core as good, we must also add, if we are
teachertrainers, the belief that ``the locus of power and authority in one's life is within the individual.'' This
curious proposition bristles with terms that are going to need very precise and narrow definitions if we are to
find it credible. We will probably find that its very attractiveness as a sentiment will be drastically diminished
when definitions are provided, and it is only in the absence of such definitions that anyone can recommend it
as a major virtue. It becomes ludicrous when we imagine how the precept must be translated into practice in
the teacher academy. Gumchewing girls, still troubled by acne and addicted to movie magazines, will be
persuaded that their chubby frames are loci of power and authority, notwithstanding the fact that their skills,
the instruments of power, are minimal, and their knowledge, the root of authority, is meager. And, thus
persuaded, they will go forth to exhibit the appropriate behaviors and recite the appropriate precepts in order
to persuade poor and wretched children into the same sad delusion.
Now that we have given our wouldbe transpersonal teachers the belief, contrary to all evidence, that they
are selfsufficient loci of power and authority and that man's core is inherently good, it remains only to see
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 47
Page No 50
that they apply these values in ``life situations'' ``with flexibility, and free of preconceptions of prejudice.''
Decisions, decisions. Well, what the hell. Let us by all means hold unalterably to that value about man's good
core, until we flex it in a life situation, that is. On the other hand, though, can it be that that very belief, that
is, the belief that we must be flexible about out beliefs, is one of those preconceptions and prejudices of
which we must be free? Or can it be that the value out of which we flex our values is itself flexible, thus
permitting us, in certain life situations, to be flexible enough not to be flexible and to free ourselves from
that preconception about being free from preconceptions? Or can we just lie down and forget the whole damn
thing? Such absurdities must always occur when the mouth runs off in the recitation of precepts couched in
vague generalizations and undefined terms. But they do not trouble the educationistic humanisticists, who
never seem to notice them. The important thing is that the precept sounds good. And it does quite good
enough, in fact, to be elevated into a principle of teacher education, where the disruptive questions of the
intellect will never intrude.
I have been talking, of course, not of the specific program of any teachertraining academy but of
Waterman's notions of ``the personal characteristics related to transpersonal teaching.'' It may be, I admit, that
there is somewhere in America a teacher academy that rejects such notions and also the notion that such
notions have anything at all to do with effective teaching, but I don't think so. Waterman's ``characteristics''
are painfully familiar to anyone who has paid attention to the loudly proclaimed humanisticism of
teachertraining. That's exactly the sort of thing they all say, and that they all champion as our only
protection against the unbridled ruthlessness of intellectual discipline, also known as ``excellence narrowly
defined.''
Excellence broadly defined, however, is a mild master. It can be anything you like. And when broadly
defined excellence is understood as the goal of a pious and humanisticist education, any sanctimonious
amateur can fancy himself a teacher of anything at all. In the teacher academies this permits some startling
but not at all uncommon courses, in which ``appreciation'' is the aim, in despite of knowledge.
A splendid example of the hokum thus generated came in the mail one day to the editorial offices of The
Underground Grammarian. It was a mimeographed sheet, headed by one of those silly smiling faces and
announcing a course in the Department of Educational Curriculum and Instruction at the University of
Tennessee. The course, ``The Existential Student,'' was for seniors and graduate students, and the ``teacher,''
who billed himself as ``Seminar Coordinator,'' was a certain Anand Kumar Malik. His powers must be
unbounded; here's what he proposes:
OBJECTIVES: Aim is to introduce the students in an informal situation to the major themes
in existentialism and humanism; to make them aware of their basic inner freedom to lead an
authentic life, to sing their own song, to dance their way through life, to relate themselves to
themselves through selfunderstanding, to relate themselves to others through nonego love,
to accept their complete academic responsibility to their own growth and to enrich their own
educational curriculum and life experiences. All in harmony with their basic responsibilities
to others in the world.
There follows a description of the intended ``Learning Experiences,'' on which I would like to comment, but
cannot. My power of language is just not sufficient. Fortunately, however, a letter was enclosed with the
announcement. It was printed in its entirety in The Underground Grammarian thus:
Song and Dance in Tennessee
Dear Underground, I have been reading and studying you magazine for sometime and I truly
do enjoy reading it. The onliest thing is, is that it is hard to study out what it means. A least
always. I don't mean the Latin or whatever it is in the ``headlines'' which I can skip them
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 48
Page No 51
anyway but it seems to me that folks up North make things out harder than they have to be
some time and you could learn from us as well. You take Philosophy, as any one would call
it a hard ``subject'' (but not in Knoxville) because you would want to read about the material
dialects and the rational. Still, I think you would very seriously do it but end up finally with
book learning that is alright in its place, however, life must go on as they say. You will see
from the ``enclosed'' that Philosophy does not have to be hard, and not even Existentialism
that is the hardest known Philosophy. It tells about Anand Kumar Malik and his course he is
teaching called The Existential Student, and very well put by the ``headline.'' ``You are
hereby invited to become no one but yourself.'' It gives a good feeling and the smiling face
picture really gets the message across. Any one who could get themselves down to the
University of Tennessee, in Knoxville this summer, could learn Existentialism
and Humanism thrown in as the flyer says in only four (4) weeks in the dept. of Education,
and that's what it is about after all. If I may give some quotes from the flier you will see that
school can be fun, when the students learn ``to sing their own song'' and ``to dance their way
through life.'' It gives some selected writings too, and as I said there is not a thing wrong with
book learning, but I have to admit that I don't recognize the names, except Elizabeth Lacey
tells me that a friend of hers has a whole book of Philosophy by that Mr. Kahlil Gibran, or
probably Prof. Gibran, and she says that he is ``very good.'' ( Exact quote!) They will have
existential music and existential art slides, and ``making your own existential painting.'' Best
of all is they will ``relate themselves to themselves through selfunderstanding'' and that
makes good sense if you ask me in my humble opinion. Maybe you shouldn't think school
should be all that hard as you seem to think some times, because here is Mr. Malik whose not
only an education teacher but he can teach Existentialism too, and he even lets the students
figure up their grades so there won't be all that worry about flunking (failing.) Now that is the
whole difference right there between the teachers and the others, and I bet you you won't find
any cheerful smiling face picture drawn up at the top of any fancy medical school flyer. You
take doctors and lawyers and even I hope you don't mind my saying so some of your college
professors and you will find there is more than just one stuffed shirt between them. That is
because all those ``subjects'' they study they make them so serious as though somebody's or
other life depended on it. Life isn't all a rose colored glass, you know, and it is good to have
faith that our school teachers can learn Existentialism and dance through it with a song in
their heart nevertheless. I know you hate mistakes, so I looked up the hard words.
To that breathtaking commentary I can add only a few trivial footnotes: The writers whose ``existential
themes'' are to be studied in four weeks are eighteen in number and range from Kierkegaard to Susan Polis
Schutz, and include Carlos Castaneda as well as that celebrated existentialist, Kahlil Gibran. The students,
who will, of course, determine their own grades, even as they sing their own songs and dance their own ways,
will also keep ``a small diary of...brief reactions to some existential ideas.'' Small. Brief. Some. And
naturally, reactions. Knowledge is not at issue. Each student is promised ``an annotated bibliography on
existentialism and humanism (for...continuous selfdevelopment after the seminar is over.)'' Continuous
selfdevelopment. As to how (or whether) existentialism and humanism are distinguished I cannot say.
The ordinary citizen, contemplating such a juvenile parody of scholarship, is inclined to protect his sanity by
assuming that such a course is a freakish anomaly. That, alas, cannot be so. This instructor, after all, is not an
independent entrepreneur peddling selfhelp and uplift down at the Community Center on Tuesday evenings
from seven to nine. This course is offered with the approval and connivance of his colleagues and
coconspirators in that Department of Educational Curriculum and Instruction and the entire administrative
apparatus of the University of Tennessee. And that means, dear citizen, that not one of all those professors,
committee members, chairmen, deans, vicepresidents, and who can say how many other functionaries,
probably including legislative committees and the governor himself, had either enough knowledge or concern
to suggest that the king was naked.
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 49
Page No 52
It would probably be a mistake to assume that the students enrolled in such a course were taken in by it,
although there will be a few in any teachertraining program slow and gullible enough to mistake a small
diary of brief reactions for the work of the mind. Students take those courses precisely because they are silly
and easy, and you would do the same. Those credits are worth money. And on the other side of the
transaction, the existence of such a course is also worth money and professional respectability, and job
security to the one who teaches it and the system that permits it. That makes me suspicious. Although I
think that I can understand why those seniors and graduate students, in search of certificates and raises, might
gladly take courses like ``The Existential Student,'' I find it less easy to be tolerant of those who teach and
sponsor them and of what can only be called the corporate complicity of the entire system of public education
in America.
Furthermore, it is discouraging to notice that the graduates of our teachers' colleges do not, as you might
think, all forswear the nonsense to which they have been subjected once they have their certificates in hand.
Or, if they do, they are remarkably secretive about it. In the kingdom of educationism, outspoken dissidents
are rare. This is because those few who do dissent and shake off the childish humanisticism of their education
courses have good reason to know that nothing can be done about anything. But it must also be because there
are in any teachers' college enough of the slow and gullible to form a permanent population of committed
humanisticists who will never change. I conclude that this must be so, for there is no other way to account for
the existence and growing numbers of institutions like the Connecticut Teachers' Center for Humanistic
Education, which was described thus in the pages of The Underground Grammarian:
The Black Whole of Connecticut ``Mistah Kurtz he transpersonalized.''
The center cannot hold, you say? Poo. Come with us now, up some tranquil New England waterway leading
to the uttermost ends of the earth and into the heart of an immense darkness. There, we will come at last to
the Connecticut Teachers' Center for Humanistic Education, and it's holding very well indeed, thank you.
Dark humanistic shapes we will make out in the distance, flitting indistinctly against the gloomy border of the
forest, and, chief among them, brooding over some inscrutable purpose, Emily, the Assistant Director. All we
know of her is what we read in Centering, the Center's little newsletter. Here it is sic:
Emily has experience training in the areas of Bioenergetics, Psychosynthesis, Gestalt
Therapy, Arica Psychocalesthenics, Yoga and Tai Chi. Emily has been a consultant to
Connecticut Public Schools...in selfawareness training, confluent education, and
organization development...Emily is committed to working with individuals wholistically
facilitating the integration of their emotional, intellectual, physical and transpersonal aspects.
In the hush that falls suddenly upon the whole (or ``hole,'') sorrowful land, do remember that Emily is only
the Assistant Director. What must he be, who can direct the labors of such an assistant? And whose heads are
those, their transpersonal aspects hideously integrated on selfawareness training poles, that fence these
murky precincts? They look so small.
We are lost, lost in an area. Is it the area of Psychosynthesis or the area of Tai Chi? Could we be in the
neighborhood of Bioenergetics or even in the immediate environs of Arica Psychocalesthenics? Who knows?
They look so much alike. That's why we all need Assistant Directors, real professionals of education, with
rigorous ``experience training'' in areas. Oh, what a mistake we made studying junk like geography when
what we ought to have had was experience training somewhere in the areaawareness area. Now we just can't
seem to facilitate the integration of any of our aspects. The horror, the horror.
We have, of course, no idea at all of what teachers do in a teachers' center, and we obviously never will, for
the gravity of the Black Whole of Connecticut is so enormous that no light escapes. We can only guess,
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 50
Page No 53
therefore, that teachers hie themselves there to have their Gestalten therapized in the lotus position,
performing the while, quietly within the psyche, synthesizing calesthenics, whatever those may be,
interspersed with an occasional aspectintegrating and bigenergizing round of Tai Chi, perhaps a confluent
form of Parcheesi for individuals. That would explain a lot.
That's all we can tell you. Like that other cryptic screed, our source gave ``no practical hints to interpret [or
even to understand] the magic current of its phrases...unless a kind of note...scrawled evidently much later,
may be regarded as the exposition of a method,'' or, at least, of a course in methodology. ``It was very simple,
and at the end of that moving appeal to every altruistic sentiment it blazed...luminous and terrifying, like a
flash of lightning in a serene sky: 'Excruciate the brats!' '' And that, of course, would explain everything.
Maybe I'm wrong. Maybe it isn't out of cynicism but something worse that students in teachers' colleges take
courses in selfrelating through life experiences. Maybe it's folly. Maybe stupidity. Maybe it's just the
paralysis of the mind that may well befall anyone who has taken enough of such courses and listened to such
cant and endured, bored and thus uncritical, the foolish circular arguments, generalizations, and non sequiturs
of educationistic vaporizing. The teachers who frequent that Connecticut Teachers' Center for Humanistic
Education, and there must be some, perhaps many, go there of their own free will. They must
want Psychosynthesis and Tai Chi. They must want to be worked with ``wholistically'' in the cause of the
facilitation of the integration of their aspects. And the educationist bureaucrats who take our money for the
support of the Connecticut Teachers' Center for Humanistic Education must want the teachers to want such
things. And the schools must have wanted to consult with Emily, again at our expense, on selfawareness
training and organization development. In a world where all of that is not only possible but even usual,
cynicism seems a refreshing virtue.
But it is precisely in such a climate, where selfhelp facilitations and puerile popularizations can blossom,
that the pseudoscience and pseudoreligion of educationism can spread and flourish. In a climate of hard
knowledge and rational analysis such flamboyant weeds would wither and die in a season. But that won't
happen. To their unique blend of the illogical and the sentimental, the educationists have added the
techniques of a man to whom they owe far more than they do to Horace Mann, or John Dewey, or even
Wundt, poor Wundt. The guiding spirit of the methods of educationism, if not the ideology, is, of course,
Dale Carnegie.
The Graves of Academe
The Principles March On 51
Page No 54
The Pygmies' Revenge
Peter's wellknown Principle was obviously discovered by a man who knew nothing at all about schools. In
schools it just isn't true that the people who can actually do their jobs get promoted until they find themselves,
at last and forever, in the jobs they can't do. This is because the most difficult and demanding jobs in
education are what industry calls ``entrylevel positions,'' teaching in classrooms. That's the bottom rung of
the school ladder, and there are many people who just can't do that work. It isn't, in itself, very difficult work;
all it takes is intelligence, diligence, talent, and a little bit of luck. Those who have some of the first three,
however, often run clean out of the fourth when they start taking education courses and start worrying more
about enhancing their personological variables than about collecting more knowledge. (Furthermore, teaching
obviously has to be done in a school, and many of our schools, after decades of eschewing ``mere
information'' in the cause of ``worthy citizenship,'' have turned into lawless encampments of armed barbarians
where no one can teach and no one can learn.) Those who are short on intelligence, diligence, and talent,
however, find their luck much improved by the fact that the teachers' colleges are designed for just such
people.
Thus, partly because so many have incompetence thrust upon them, and partly because so many are born to
incompetence, in every faculty there will be people who just can't handle the entrylevel position. In
industry, or even in a fastfood restaurant, they would be washed out; but we don't do that kind of thing in
the schools, especially since public school teaching is more and more used by government as a jobs program
for the less able. In the schools, those who cannot do the work at the lowest rank are simply promoted into
higher ranks. Weirdly enough, given the nature of the educational enterprise, this makes perfect sense.
In those realms where the Peter Principle prevails, it is often true that higher rank and higher pay do go along
with harder work. In the schools, where there is no harder work than teaching in a classroom, exactly the
opposite is true. In fact, it is not at all absurd to imagine a perfectly splendid school in which there are only
teachers and one clever and industrious handyman who can also type. On the other hand, think for a moment
about the school toward which, as all the statistics suggest, we might be moving, a school made up almost
entirely of administrators and their own ``support services.'' (They usually call them that.) In such a school
we would see clearly what we now can see only darkly, through the frosted glass of governmental mandate
and educationistic dogma: that almost all of the work done by those above the rank of teacher is contrived so
that there may be more workers. Thus it is that so much of the administrative work done in schools is
intended not to do work, as a physicist would use the term, but to occupy time and justify the existence of
some administrative post.
It turns out, not surprisingly therefore, that the mindless and inflated jargon, superbly suited to the darkening
of logic and the interminable belaboring of the obvious, is exactly the language that an educationistic
administrator needs in order to conceal the fact that the work he does simply doesn't need doing. If you want
to rise in the school business, you have to master the lingo. This is another reason why good teachers don't
become principals and superintendents: The very attributes that make them good teachers also make it
impossible for them to talk about experiential remediation enhancement strategies with straight faces. And if
there is one attribute a principal or superintendent needs, it's a perfectly straight face. You have to believe.
Solemnly.
When those who can't teach want to improve themselves by becoming supervisors of those who can teach,
they must go through, once again, the strait gate of the teachers' college. Outside of that church, there is no
salvation. They must return, perhaps on Monday and Thursday evenings, to the study, if that's the word, of
such arcana as Curriculum Development and Supervision, Career and Guidance Counseling, and Educational
Administration/Management. Since there is little to be learned about such matters, the courses are easy,
requiring mostly the ability to tolerate ponderous recitations of the trivial and obvious and a mind just weak
The Pygmies' Revenge 52
Page No 55
enough to fall without a struggle into an habitual inanity in language. These are the very proclivities that have
made the poorer teachers what they are, so there is no shortage of suitable candidates for graduate study in
the schools of education. While the steady stream of aspirants to lofty (nonteaching) rank assures perpetual
public funding for the teachers' colleges and pleasant, permanent employment for professors of education, it
has some even more unhappy consequences. It assures that the antiintellectual climate of the public high
schools will prevail in the colleges and universities as well. Except for the uncharacteristically depraved,
professors of chemistry or history, or of any traditional discipline with a concrete and growing body of
knowledge, simply don't want to do the boring and empty work of administration. They gladly leave that to
the educationists and other nonacademic arrivistes in higher education, who gladly take it. Thus it comes to
pass that in most of our colleges and universities policy decisions about academic matters are regularly made
by direct descendants of the Commission on the Reorganization of Secondary Education, to whom
intellectual discipline and mere information are pesky impediments to worthy ethical character and right
emotional response.
The work of school administration, therefore, usually has two typical attributes: Because it must justify the
very existence of school administration, it must seem timeconsuming and difficult. Because it is an
instrument of educationistic ideology, it must be ``humanistic'' and ``democratic,'' as the educationists
understand those terms, which is to say emotional and collective rather than coldly knowledgeable and
authoritarian. You can recognize in the typical administrative committee, therefore, a longtrouser version of
the social studies class envisioned in Cardinal Principles, where it is imagined that ignorant but rightfeeling
children will corporately hatch out wisdom.
Here, from the pages of The Underground Grammarian, is an example of how the administrative work of an
institution of higher education is actually done:
Ask a Stupid Question...
Glassboro has so many lowranking, junior administrators that it's hard to find them useful work. We don't
even try, in fact; we just find them things to play with.
George Wildman and Robert Harris are cochairmen of the Task Force on Recruitment, Retention, and
Image. We don't know how they produce their prose whether by one as told to the other or by taking turns
word by word but here's how it comes out:
In the first two sessions of the Task Force, the group explored the task facing them.
Discussion ensued during these sessions concerning the goals and objectives to be
accomplished. The Committee began the task of gathering supporting data by virtue of
reports supplied by the offices of Admissions, Counseling, and the Registrar. Considerable
time was spent attempting to define terminology as a basis for functioning, and much thought
was given in an attempt to identify some of the major concerns which the Task Force would
be facing in its work.
The first, second, and fourth sentences of that paragraph say the same thing, although the fourth does add that
bit about defining ``terminology [terms?] as a basis for functioning.'' The third sentence actually has its own
thing to say, but only that they ``began the task of gathering.'' Does that mean that they began gathering or
that they began getting ready to gather? This sentence also uses ``by virtue of'' as though it meant ``from.''
Never ask a junior administrator to say something straight out. He'd rather be knocked flat in an airport by O.
J. Simpson. (Good idea.)
Since the combined salaries of the twenty members of the Task Force must be more than half a million
dollars a year we're glad to report that their labor has had some results. As early as their second meeting, they
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 53
Page No 56
divided themselves into three ``interestarea subcommittees'' (shouldn't that be subTask Forces or Task
Forcelets?), one each for Recruitment, Retention, and Image.
They did more. Each interestarea subcommittee undertook to ``define its term.''
Now you would think that any fool could define recruitment, retention, and even image, although why that
should be necessary is not clear. We have to guess that many members of the Task Force were unacquainted
with those words and needed remediational input.
Discussion ensued by virtue of input, and tasks were explored. Thought was given in an attempt, and time
was spent attempting.
By the next meeting, each ``interestarea'' subcommittee had defined ``its term.'' Here's what they found
as a basis for functioning:
recruitment: the institution's philosophy and procedures by which we attempt to attract
students to continue their education...
retention: the ability of the college to hold students who are pursuing a degree program
(B.A., M.A., including certification) .
image: the reflection of reality and substance.
The language of these administrators is symbolic, as language always is, although in this case not consciously
symbolic. They do on the page exactly what they do in their jobs. They say over and over again a thing that
needs no saying in the first place. They set themselves, at public expense, to the silly task of defining, in
groups no less, terms (or, as they prefer, terminology) that need no defining. If their labors were successful,
they would learn at great expense of time and money what any thoughtful person could have told them at
their first meeting, and they will inevitably propose the obvious. They will urge more recruitment and
retention along with imageenhancement.
It is important for the ordinary citizen to realize that such committees, through whose agency almost
everything is done in Academe, are not composed entirely of administrators. There will always be some
members who are only incipient administrators making themselves useful and noteworthy, some junior
professors bucking for promotion and not at all reluctant to be parties to a lengthy and arduous reinvention of
the wheel, and other faculty members somewhat less than passionately devoted to their chosen disciplines.
The latter, of course, are usually from an education department, where a passionate devotion to discipline is
precluded not only by the questionable nature and content of what is taught but by the traditional animosity to
discipline itself.
If you can assemble enough such people and assign them an especially ambiguous errand, neither of which is
at all difficult in a school, you can easily devise an educationistic enterprise that can go on, literally, forever:
The Future Lies Ahead!
Early in the Fall, the Needs Assessment Task Force was asked to study the process of
Academic Planning as it presently exists at Southwest Texas State University and determine
whether we should implement a different process. (From the works of Joseph Caputo, VP for
AcAff.)
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 54
Page No 57
As the time for dinner approaches, the standard American amateur looks in the refrigerator. He notices some
food. He takes some of it out and cooks it. Then he eats it. It's so crude; any savage could do it. Here in
Academe, we are ``professionals,'' and we have better ways of doing things.
First we establish a committee to consider whether or not there should be any dinner, and, if so, whether or
not it should actually be eaten, and, if again so, where, and when, and by whom. Then we form a
subcommittee to decide what, if anything, to cook, and how. Now we discover that we need a study group to
consider whether or not dinnerplanning is, in fact, all that simple, and to establish its parameters and to
explore the implications of fiscal, curricular, and societal restraints that may be perceived as existing. Or
maybe not. But the study group cannot do its work until we have definitive findings from the Needs
Assessment Task Force, which is ``to study the process of Academic Planning as it presently exists...and
determine whether we should implement a different process.''
The Needs Assessment Task Force down at Southwest Texas State University, where the squirrels also rush
around the brush, has done its work. Here's some of it:
An Academic Planning Model must involve a futures planning component. Goals should be
set for some time in the future. These goals should be translated into shorterterm objectives
for which the degree of detail and concreteness varies inversely with the lead time. There
should also be reasonable suspense dates for implementation of plans and a definitive
methodology for evaluation and feedback. The interfacing of longterm...and shortterm
planning should result.
So, you thought that only a herd of nerds would set themselves to wondering whether or not to plan how to
plan, eh? No siree! It takes some of the sharpest thinkers in Academe to discover and announce that plans are
about the ``future,'' not the past!
They're even smart enough to call for the involvement of a component, which would never occur to an
ordinary human being, and a definitive methodology, where any simpleminded taxpayer would have settled
for a mere method.
That's not all, of course. The Task Forcers also urge ``update features,'' prudently left unspecified so that yet
another task can be forced on yet another task force, and warn against the ``counterproductive hurdle,'' the
worst kind. One of their main conclusions, solemnly pronounced, probably after much deliberation and
searching of heart, is that an Academic Planning Model (they always capitalize it) should actually work, or,
as they put it, ``be functional.'' They further opine, cutting right to the bone, that any plan that will work, will
in fact work: ``Any Academic Planning Model to be considered...would positively impact [wham!] our
decisionmaking process to the extent that it accomplishes its designed purpose.''
To proclaim the obvious in language that is odious is, of course, the regular practice of the educationists, who
love to serve on task forces (they put that kind of stuff in their resumes and grant applications), and have no
moral or intellectual objections to writing at length about nothing. However, at least one member of this task
force was not an educationist, but an agent provocateur and a subtle ironist. On his backward colleagues he
foisted the one sentence that says it all: ``An Academic Planning process must not become viewed by the
participants as activity to be finished so that they may return to the real business of the university.''
Then again, to be sure, the revelation of that last sentence may have been due simply to ineptitude. But the
revelation is a true one, for, as far as the educationist is concerned, ``the real business of the university'' is not
what you probably think.
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 55
Page No 58
For years, I have been looking around for the key, the master metaphor, the one striking analogy that would
clarify and dramatize the nature of our schools. They are, of course, something like the asylum where the
inmates have taken over, but that doesn't do the whole job. They are more like some island nation in which
the traditional, mild, but inefficient governance once exercised by a genteel but effete and distracted
aristocracy has been taken over, without any bloodshed at all, by bands of persistent pygmies from the
unexplored interior. The less than worldly aristocrats, far more interested in watching for comets and
collecting Lepidoptera than in zoning rules and customs control, were not displeased to accede when the
pygmies drifted in and offered to do all the hard work. It seemed such a good idea at the time, but by now the
pygmies are in charge of everything, and the bemused aristocrats, whose ancestral estates have been
converted to miniature golf courses, find that they are sipping their soup out of very small spoons.
But that metaphor isn't enough either, for it does not provide a place for the only slightly rationalized
vengefulness that characterizes the educationists' almost complete governance of what was once an academic
and intellectual confederation of semiautonomous principalities. We might do better to think of Bolsheviks in
the Winter Palace, or the moneychangers in the temple who have it in mind not only to do a flourishing
business but to preach the doctrine as well, thus ensuring that business will always flourish. I think that latter
analogy especially good, but not very entertaining. The former, however, while even less entertaining, may
be even better, for educationism is in fact an ideological collectivism devoted to social change through
institutionalized thought control, but of that more later.
Perhaps the best metaphor, although unfortunately the nastiest, is that of racism. If we could divide the world
of schools roughly, and it would be very roughly at best, into two ``races,'' the academicians and the
educationists, we would find some useful analogies. The educationists, although long released from slavery,
have indubitably been treated like secondclass citizens and kept in the ghettos. From the point of view of the
academicians, the department of education, where not even the educationists have been able to identify a
concrete body of knowledge out of which to make a ``subject,'' is as much a ghetto as any local public school.
The educationists, although they eagerly do the scutwork of administration, have never been admitted into the
society of the ``learned,'' and they have had to make their own subsociety complete with its own subPhi
Beta Kappa and countless subjournals of subscholarship. (It is an interesting irony that the learned journals
of literary criticism, for example, are often as pretentiously impenetrable as anything you can find in any one
of those apparently countless journals of educationistic research into perceived personological variables, but
the diction is more noble and the verbs almost always agree with the subjects.) In faculty dining rooms all
over the country, historians and biologists and professors of Renaissance literature happily lunch together, but
the educationists usually keep to themselves. The very degrees that educationists award one another are held
to be inferior to the degrees that the academicians award one another. Although the traditional ``original
contribution to scholarship'' expected of the academic doctoral dissertation is often ludicrously picayune, the
dissertation in education, often nothing more than a report on the results of some questionnaire, ordinarily
deals with either the obvious, like the conclusion that children who want to learn will learn more than those
who don't; or the trivial, like the mechanics of pencil distribution; or the utterly ineffable, like the perceived
personological existential variables. Furthermore, the doctorate in education almost never requires that signal
cachet of the learned scholar, competence in foreign languages. This often cited distinction is enough by itself
to ``prove'' to the academicians the innate inferiority of the race of educationists.
The prejudice is real, and the educationists, naturally, resent it. Much of what they do, therefore, can be
understood as an expectably hostile thirst for revenge. Cardinal Principles is only superficially a plan for
secondary education; it is essentially a Summa contra gentiles, a stickittotheintellectuals manifesto. The
pronouncements of Cardinal Principles must be read in two ways.
Consider, for example, the proposition that a disciplined academic study of literature, whatever that might
mean, precludes ``right emotional response.'' On the one hand, that shows the ``humane'' intention to provide
students with the ``best'' that literature has to offer, certain feelings, presumably good to have. It asserts, and
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 56
Page No 59
who would deny, that the pity and terror of tragedy will strike even those who are utterly ignorant of the
textual variants, although it also provides the possibility that pity or terror might not be included among the
``right'' emotional responses. On the other hand, it makes clear that the ``teachers'' of literature in the
secondary schools can do their jobs without having to go through all that disciplined scholarship by which
those lofty academicians make their livings. From that notion it is not far to the next, to wit, that the
academicians are in fact preventing right emotional response with their footnotes and critical editions and
that the only path to right emotional response is the deliberate neglect of such things. With the next step we
can see that ignorance is better than knowledge, an idea singularly attractive to those who have not read any
of the footnotes or critical editions.
The dream of putting down the scornful mighty from their chairs also informs another cardinal tenet of
educationism: the notion widely held in the teacher academies that all a teacher needs is training in how to
teach, with which he can teach anything at all, perhaps with a little boning up. Thus it is that the high school
social studies teacher, already inoculated against the dehumanizing effects of the ``mere information''
associated with the disciplined study of history, can readily be retreaded into a teacher of English. After all,
we all speak English, don't we? In any case, what is important is not what a teacher knows but how he relates
to the students. Such ideas are impossible where academic subjects are held important in themselves, but
where they are seen only as the devices by which to generate feelings it is inevitable that existentialism (
and humanism, in the same package deal) boils down to singing your own song and dancing your way
through life in a twoweek summer session.
Such Jackofalltradesism, although long a regular practice in the public schools, is a little harder to get
away with in colleges and universities. But just a little. Anand Kumar Malik, you must have noticed, seems
to have had no trouble at all in setting up shop as a teacher of philosophy and even of painting at the same
time. Here we can see the mighty consequences of the fact that educationists are eager to serve on committees
and to undertake the dull labors of administration. Without powerful coconspirators in the superstructure at
the University of Tennessee, Malik would have been laughed off the campus and sent to sing and dance for a
much smaller supper in the Thursday evening class at the YMCA.
It probably isn't exactly true that we become what we hate. It seems more likely that we become a parody of
what we hate. Certainly the oppressed and scorned educationists, driven in part by oppression and scorn to
denigrate the very intellectual powers they are said to lack, are pathetically eager nevertheless to lay claim to
those powers for themselves, and also to the expertise that such powers can provide. Thus they put
themselves forth aswell, not exactly professors of philosophy, but at least as easy professors of easy
philosophy. Students like that, of course, but it makes professors of philosophy glum.
Given the principle that any subject matter is a useful device for the generation of socially desirable feeling,
and given also the fact that policymaking in colleges and universities has been conceded to the educationists
who proclaim that given principle, it follows that ``higher'' education will have its analogues of the phys. ed.
teacher who takes over when the biology teacher gets pregnant, of course. But it also follows, even more
ominously, that there is really no need for a biology teacher in the first place. And in college, where the
biology teacher is firmly entrenched in tradition and tenure, it further follows that the study of biology itself
might just as well be replaced with something else, something that can be ``taught'' by one who knows little
of biology but who has been trained as a teacher and whose eye is on not the biology itself but on whatever
worthy attitudes that may, or should, arise from the study of biology. Since those attitudes are the worth of
the study, why bother with the study when one can jump right into the attitudes?
Here is an example of exactly such a leap of faith, which legitimizes a startling educationistic Anschluss of a
host of traditional and concretely identifiable academic studies:
Long Underdue
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 57
Page No 60
The Department of Foundations of Education has proposed a workshop in ``intercultural education'' to tack
three more hours onto a course in the same thing, if that is a thing. From reading the proposal, we guess that
both course and workshop call for lots of ``relating'' and ``interacting,'' and, naturally, ``problemsolving,''
with ``foci on direct field experience'' and ``working on real school or/and community problems.'' (That sure
beats indirect field experience and fake problems; but these folk are into ``professional'' matters, not amateur
dabbling like math or history.) As far as we can tell, there will be no study of any identifiable body of
knowledge, just rapping, preferably with someone who says Mama mia! now and then.
This workshop is not expected to have results; it anticipates ``outcomes,'' outcomes of some ``nature.'' One
anticipated outcome is:
of the nature of...development of ability to anticipate factors likely to influence proposals for
changes in human relations...
What this means, of course, is that they hope the student will be informed, rational, and prudent. So hope we
all; but to suggest that there are forms of rationality and prudence specifically germane to ``intercultural
relations'' is fatuous. To suggest further that someone knows how to instill those virtues is patently absurd, if
not mendacious. Who is rational and prudent needs no workshop to teach him how to be rational and prudent
about Bulgarians any more than a man who can find the diameter of circle needs to be schooled in the
methodology of finding the diameter of a pizza; and who is neither prudent nor rational will scarcely be
helped through chatting with Bulgarians. Furthermore, who would become knowledgeable about Bulgarians
will do better to study their history or language or literature than to pursue
[d]evelopment of ability to apply selected tools or procedures for analyzing, assessing, and
surveying school and/or community provisions for intercultural education.
And how will students show that they have (get? interact with? what?) these outcomes? The proposal looks
for ``taped evidence of interaction with other cultures'' (they probably mean a person from another culture),
``oral presentations that exemplify good intercultural education practices,'' ``peer performance assessments,''
``records of participation'' (in what, would you guess?), and even ``practical written tools'' (try to figure
that one out).
We must put aside small questions (how, for instance, is a good intercultural education practice different
from other good education practices?) to explore the central question: What, exactly, is the subject matter
here? Is it information about diverse cultures? That is availableinescapable, in factin the study of
anthropology, art, economics, geography, history, language, literature, philosophy, religion, and many other
traditional disciplines. Is this the study of the collisions of cultures and their effects upon one another? Ditto.
Is this a study of tolerance and love?
The proposers cannot intend either of the first two, for if they do, there is no need to propose anything. Let's
hope they don't mean that third possibility. There must be some limits to what they can teach.
If intercultural education is in truth some new subject matter not yet widely known, it must have been
described somewhere in clear English and with concrete reference to things in the real world. We deserve to
hear such a description, since the language of the proposal tells us little (that's often the aim of this kind of
jargon) and makes us suspect much.
We must in fairness say that the proposal has been given comprehensive, penetrating scrutiny and analysis by
the very Dean of Professional Studies, so it seems only honest to print her commentary in full:
A good idealong overdue.
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 58
Page No 61
The background of that proposal is instructive: In the State of New Jersey, as in many other states, students in
teachertraining programs are required to have some instruction in what is generally called the
``appreciation'' of other cultures. This seems to be all the more important as the public schools, especially in
the cities, fill up with children of recently arrived immigrants from many different lands. I say that it ``seems''
important, because I'm not sure that it is really necessary to ``appreciate'' Bulgarian culture, whatever that
means, in order to teach arithmetic to children whose parents came from Bulgaria, although it would
obviously do a math teacher no harm to have knowledge about Bulgarian culture. But the mandate, in any
case, is not for knowledge. The incipient teacher is to appreciate other cultures so that he can relate and
interact.
Here we see again we see it everywhere the shadow of Cardinal Principles. Knowledge, generally a
matter of mere information, is untrustworthy as a generator of right response, so that intercultural
appreciation can be taught through learning some folk dances and sampling the traditional cookies of many
lands. But it must be taught, for those who award teaching certificates require it. They require it because their
cousins in the teacher academies, whose enrollments are falling, need some more required courses with which
to justify their continued employment. In the same cause, and with the great weight of the tradition of
Cardinal Principles, the teachertrainers must hold that such academic studies as anthropology, history,
literature, or language can not provide a worthy appreciation of other cultures. Since the teachertrainers, and
the certifiers, and the managers and bureaucrats of entire systems of state education are all from the same
litter, and since legislators all have more important things than education to think about, especially in New
Jersey, where someone has to pay attention to casinos, basic minimum intercultural appreciation speedily
becomes the law of the land. And the professors of education who get to ``teach'' it have assured their
continued employment and proved yet again that a teacher can teach anything, anything at all.
Educationists can say that, of course, only when ``anything'' means ``anything that should be taught,'' in the
system of worthiness enunciated in Cardinal Principles, and when ``taught'' means ``produced as a response
to stimulus,'' as defined in the methodology of behavior modification. You will notice that the
statesupported monopoly in intercultural education does not concede that a professor of anthropology can
teach ``the appreciation of other cultures.'' Far from it, he is all too likely to teach mere information, which
may or may not lead to what should be taught, appreciation, the worthy response.
That's why the word ``appreciation'' is so important both in Cardinal Principles and in all educationistic
theorizing thereafter. First, it sounds good. Who can be against it? More important, it is a code word with
which to indicate, without having to be concrete and specific, any or all of the ``worthy'' attributes that we
may expect as the student outcomes of anything that is done in school, however trivial or trendy. In one
sense, ``appreciation'' is familiar to anyone who has been through ``Music Appreciation,'' a course that
usually does not require any study or knowledge of harmony, counterpoint, or even the classification of
elementary forms, although it often does provide uplifting or entertaining vignettes from the lives of
composers. In another and far more important sense, the meaning of ``appreciation'' is what is embedded in
the notion that when we have learned some Bulgarian folk dances we will better ``appreciate'' Bulgarian
culture, and that that will be good. ``Appreciation'' seems to be used to suggest an amiable tolerance of that
which someone thinks we ought to tolerate but probably wouldn't if we were left alone.
A student outcome of the order of appreciation has another tremendous value in an antiintellectual
education: No one can measure it. No one can measure ``right emotional response'' or ``worthy ethical
character'' either. The value of such student outcomes is in fact double. They make it impossible to check up
on the effectiveness of a curriculum, and they permit the bogus ``research'' of educationistic theorizing, in
which such things as existentiality and commitment to the goodness of man at his core are put forth as
measurable quantities. Who is to say, after all, exactly which students, and with what ardor, are indeed
singing their own songs and dancing their ways through life after two weeks of harmony and smallgroup
discussions at the University of Tennessee? Unfortunately, someone probably will undertake to do just that,
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 59
Page No 62
perhaps the very chappie who told us all about the ``values, attitudes, and teaching philosophy pertinent to
transpersonally oriented nonpublic school teachers.''
The Student Outcomes Principle (it seems to deserve capitals) is the Prime Mover of American education. It
is our equivalent of the Death of God, after which everything is permitted. It arises inevitably from the
intersection of that sentimental humanisticism that has made the schools into virtuenurseries where guards
patrol the corridors, and the iron law of behavior modification that has made them laboratories where all the
experiments fail. But that's all right. As schools, and consequently the rest of society, become more anarchic,
the educationists can point to an ever greater need for the inculcation of values, and every failed experiment
makes room for new devils in the guise of faddish innovations.
But the Student Outcomes Principle has brought us even worse abominations than the fads and gimmicks that
have been tripping over each other's heels for the last sixty years. Since the proponents of that principle have
become the makers of policy at all levels of public education, they have been able to refashion even the most
traditional courses of study into exercises in the inculcation of right emotional response and the clarification
of values. Such was proposed, of course, in Cardinal Principles and in some cases easily effected by the
ouster of history for the sake of social studies, for instance, in which the especially civic virtues, whatever
they happen to be at any given time, are fostered by idle gossip about current events and some illinformed
generalizations about remote tribes.
The process, however, has only begun when social studies are implanted in the secondary public schools.
Imagine what happens thereafter: At first, of course, the history teachers must be the social studies teachers.
The less committed they are to the traditional study of history, the more likely they are to welcome this
opportunity to escape the tyranny of mere information and develop instead an ``appreciation and...a clear
conception of right relations.'' History itself now becomes nothing more than a social study, and by no means
primus inter pares but rather an aging and demanding relative less and less acceptable in a rapidly growing
family of trendy issues. The next generation of social studies teachers cannot be students of history, or
certainly not merely students of history. This means that whatever is to be done in the high schools in the
name of social studies must also be done in the teachers' colleges where the social studies teachers are to
learn their trade. The professors of such things as history and economics, therefore, have to be reeducated.
They must welcome into partnership the sociologists, who are cousins to the educationists both in language
and ideology, and learn to appreciate the priority of values over mere information. This is done in the name of
``meeting the needs of the students,'' which is another way of expressing the Student Outcomes Principle, and
which can have any practical effect you please depending only on the ``needs'' chosen.
Imagine that you are a bright young history scholar who has become an instructor in a college where there is
a school of teacher education. After a year or two of teaching the basic freshman course in Western
Civilization, which is already a social studies course, devoted to a little bit of everything and anything that
probably ought to be appreciated, you discover that you would like to spend more time in teaching about the
Renaissance in Italy, a body of knowledge in which you are especially well informed. Since the history
department is small and offers no course in the Italian Renaissance, you write a description and a syllabus and
send off a course proposal to the curriculum committee, with the blessing of your fellow history professors,
who believe that the Italian Renaissance is worth studying.
Now your proposal comes before the curriculum committee, where the educationists and wouldbe
administrators are serving with gladness and where the rules and procedures, as well as the ideology, have
long been established by others of their kind. When they look at your proposal, they do not think about the
intrinsic value of the study of the Renaissance in Italy; they ask rather about the projected student outcomes
and the measurable behavioral objectives. They don't really want to hear what you could probably tell them:
that those who study the Italian Renaissance can come to have knowledge. They want to know what kind of
people your students will become, what they will appreciate, and whether they will be able to relate the
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 60
Page No 63
Renaissance in Italy to the goals of selffulfillment. In short, they will want to know, although the chances
are good that no single member of the curriculum committee has ever heard of Cardinal Principles, exactly
what it is that makes your course ``worthy'' in spite of its distinctly academic taint.
In response, you can, of course, lie. You can trump up some noble and plausible outcomes and objectives.
That would probably work, for it is standard practice in any case, especially in the courses in education, and
your interlocutors would be receptive to loose talk about appreciation of cultural heritage and the relating of
self to self and others both as groups and individuals. You can say such things about the study of anything or
even about dabbling in anything, cookery or karate, for that matter. But such a maneuver has, for you at least,
two nasty consequences. First, you become either a fool or a liar. You may actually come to believe your
concoctions, in which case you become a fool, but you can escape folly only by knowing yourself a liar, or,
as we in the academic world prefer, a pragmatist. You lie in good cause, naturally, and in the company of all
the other pragmatists who devise student outcomes and behavioral objectives in order to get past the
curriculum committee, but still you lie. Lying and scholarship cannot live together, but Iying and
indoctrination are made for each other. Where scholarship is not practiced for its own sake but only in the
service of doctrine, everybody has to lie or be a fool and your proposed course in Renaissance Italy
must be put forth only as a means to some higher (and socially more acceptable) end than the mere learning
of some knowledge.
And there is the other nasty consequence. If you do lie and cook up some lovely student outcomes and
behavioral objectives that can justify the study of the Italian Renaissance, you explicitly admit that the higher
end is more important than the means, since the latter can be justified only because of the former. That being
so, your cunningly devised outcomes and objectives, which sound amazingly like the outcomes and
objectives of many other courses, are obviously ends that might be achieved by many other means. Thus,
whatever it is that makes your proposed course ``worthy'' also makes it unnecessary. But that fact doesn't
doom your proposed course, although it may doom you. If you have lied well enough, your course will be
approved, since the continuous multiplication of courses is a profitable practice in any case, because it is now
an admission by a humbled elitist academic that disciplined study is no more than a means to certain student
outcomes. And once you have admitted that, you have become a de facto educationist. If you are willing to
teach the history of the Renaissance in Italy as a way of engendering right appreciation of a cultural heritage
and an exercise in relating self to self and others, then you must admit the academic validity of any other
course, including cookery, that can make the same claims. You must also admit that students might just as
well take cookery as your history course, for the student outcomes are the same. And, worse yet, you may
someday have to admit, since, by your own confession, knowledge, or mere information, is not in fact the
main point of your course, that it could just as well be taught by someone who is not a scholar of the
Renaissance in Italy. And that is why it is that educationists can find permanent work teaching tencentstore
equivalents of anything in the catalog, and, far worse, why onceserious scholars can end up doing the same
thing without even knowing it.
It is interesting to notice that there are some studies that are by nature resistant to this process, and even more
interesting to discover that they are the very studies where the failures of public education are most obvious.
No amount of prattle about ``right emotional response'' to literature can for long disguise the fact that students
can't read literature, and worthy appreciation of the logic of mathematics rarely assures the ability to cipher.
The failure of the schools to teach these and other ``fundamental processes'' briefly mentioned and dismissed
in Cardinal Principles is nowadays well known, but we have not yet given enough thought to the reason for
that failure. It is not sufficient, although it is more and more true, to say that the children cannot read and
write and cipher because their teachers cannot read and write and cipher. That just puts the question off one
more step and leaves us to wonder how the teachers came to suffer that disability. The answer is to be found
in that intellectual miasma emitted by the Student Outcomes Principle, which always holds, remember, that
the truly desirable outcomes of any study at all are attitudes or values of some sort and not mere skill or
information. Because they insist on teaching what is unteachable, educationists must denigrate the teaching of
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 61
Page No 64
what is teachable. Where the pygmies rule, everybody else has to crouch.
Having seized power from the wicked elitists, the pygmy educationists are always busy stamping out vestiges
of the old regime and its discredited ideals and practices. If you want to make an educationist wince, all you
have to do is cite some ``facts and dates,'' which you could know only as the result of ``rote learning.'' Such
things are all characterized in Cardinal Principles as notorious impediments to the true goals of education.
They are not only elitist but oppressive and antidemocratic as well, and it may even be that a detailed
knowledge of the constitution, for instance, would prevent the proper appreciation of our institutions and their
values. It follows inevitably that those studies that depend heavily on memorization, mere ``rote learning,''
will be given very short shrift indeed in our schools and the same in our teacher academies. Just as the
instructor of Renaissance Italian history forswears himself by proposing anything other than knowledge as
the goal of study, the educationist forswears himself and all that he stands for in permitting the suggestion
that the goal of study is just knowledge. Thus it is that the educationists just don't know what to do with
subjects that cannot, like history or literature, for example, be diluted for the sake of noncognitive student
outcomes. And when they can't dilute a subject, they just neglect it.
It is for that reason, in fact, that along with reading and writing and ciphering, another equally ``basic'' study
has fallen out of favor in the schools, and that is the study of foreign languages. We make a virtue of
ignorance and sloth by claiming that a distaste for foreign languages is an American attribute, and while
perhaps lamentable, nevertheless a tribute to the tough independence of our pioneer forebears. Many of those
forebears, however, obviously saw the knowledge of other languages as an elementary part of an education
and nothing more esoteric than literacy itself. Our supposed distaste for foreign language has in fact been
fabricated in the schools. Foreign language study is not mentioned in Cardinal Principles, and it must be
precisely what is excluded when that document, asserting that the language skills of elementary school
children are ``not yet sufficient,'' points out that ``this is particularly true of the mother tongue.'' And foreign
language is, no doubt, one of those ``provisions'' that might be made for ``those having distinctively academic
interests and needs.'' What we think of now as the lack of interest in foreign languages, and the obvious and
unpleasant social and economic effects of that lack, to say nothing of the intellectual, is simply the inevitable
consequence of the antiintellectual educationism that informed Cardinal Principles.
The ideological distortion that can twist the study of literature into the inculcation of right emotional response
just won't work with the study of irregular verbs. And, while any halfbaked teacher of social studies can
peddle appreciation of institutions without any tiresome concern for facts and dates, a teacher of German
actually has to know the prepositions that take the dative. Furthermore, the results of foreign language study,
and thus perhaps even the efficacy of teaching, can be measured concretely and objectively. Either you have
learned those prepositions, and ``by rote'' at that, or you haven't. The Student Outcomes Principle just won't
stretch far enough to cover the study of foreign languages. The only thing left is neglect, which is made all
the more acceptable by the implication, already visible in Cardinal Principles, that a knowledge of French or
God forbid! Greek is an esoteric dabbling in the arcane and nothing more than an antiquated social
adornment suitable only for elitists. (Indeed, something very much like that same judgment is nowadays
made of expertise in ``the mother tongue'' as well, which makes it much easier to apply the Student Outcomes
Principle to the study of reading and writing English, where creativity and selfexpression are held more
important than spelling and punctuation, mere ``rote learning.'')
Because of the educationistic hegemony in public ``higher'' education, which is more often than not a clumsy
apparatus built around a teachertraining academy, the neglect of foreign language study is just as common
in the colleges as in the high schools. The neglect of foreign language, in fact, is a splendid case in point out
of which to show that whatever happens in the realm of educationism must eventually have an effect not only
everywhere in education itself but everywhere in our society.
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 62
Page No 65
As foreign languages are less and less studied in the public schools, fewer and fewer language teachers are
needed, and enrollments decline in foreign language departments in teachers' colleges. As enrollments
decline, the numbers of language professors decline, and some languages disappear entirely from the
curriculum. That's not bad; it's good. It justifies still further neglect in the high schools, where, when the last
old Latin teacher finally retires, the principal can replace her with an auto mechanics teacher since, whatever
the students may want, you can't find a Latin teacher nowadays. At the same time, there are fewer and fewer
students enrolling in foreign language courses even in those colleges that are not teacher academies, and
there, too, faculties will shrink. One of the first to go and you can believe that the pygmies will be damn
glad to get rid of him will be the the only surviving professor of Attic Greek, a notoriously
unreconstructed elitist. He will be replaced by a woman with a rightsounding surname who will teach
remedial English as a second language, and she, just as soon as the doddering professor of Old English packs
it in, will be joined by another of the same, and a new department will be born.
While all of that has been happening, foreign language study has been continually a victim of propaganda.
Because it is not reducible to appreciation, and especially because it requires such antihumanistic behavior as
memorization, it has become widely known as a ``hard'' subject, which is furthermore tainted with elitism. As
a result, high school graduates who go to college are less and less likely to choose a foreign language. Where
such requirements were once common in anything from English to political science, they must be abolished,
lest enrollments shrink, which is the worst thing that can happen in any department. This leads, of course, to
further shrinking in the already embattled language department, but what can we do? Surely it is better for the
few to suffer than the many. But it also leads to one more abandonment of an intellectual standard and one
more submission to the lifeadjustment ideology of Cardinal Principles, and after all, those now
forgotten language requirements have to be replaced to one more lie about student outcomes and
behavioral objectives for a course in the appreciation of foreignlanguagespeaking cultures. And, when we
have finally reached something like our present condition, when the bad name of language study has provided
that few college graduates can even speak English, never mind German or French, and when businesses find
that their memo writers can't understand each other, and when thousands of workers are driven out of jobs by
foreign competition, then we discover that every Japanese salesman speaks fluent English, and we wonder if
that means something.
To whatever other woes it may bring us, of which diminished ability to compete in international trade is only
one, we must add another step in the general decline of the intellectual enterprise as a whole, which ought to
be the principal business of the schools. This decline, which we can see in science and technology just as well
as in the study of the humanities and languages, must continue as long as the inheritors of Cardinal
Principles continue in all the committees and administrative posts and in all the centers, both public and
private, of educationistic``research.'' Even when they are unaware of it, as indeed they often are, all their
notions and theories and programs have an underlying theme, the theme that is sounded when the ineffective
and thus discontented social studies teacher decides that he would rather go to those evening classes in
educationism and become, instead of a mere teacher, a curriculum facilitator or a guidance counselor or even,
oh joy, an assistant principal. That theme is compounded partly of a distaste for the work of the intellect,
which he has never been able to do with pleasure, and partly of the desire to take some revenge on those who
do seem to find that pleasure and in whose eyes he is a secondclass citizen. And the whole apparatus of
theory and governance established in the shadow of Cardinal Principles and now in complete control of
public education in America makes it not only possible but even easy for the failed social studies teacher to
rise above his more intellectual colleagues and tell them what and how to teach or, even better, find a place in
the eternal task force where needs are assessed within the parameters of planning whether to plan. The
soughtafter jobs in education are the ones that take you as far as possible from the classroom.
That, by itself, would be splendid, for it would take the silliest people in the education business away from
the places where they can do the most harm. Unfortunately, however, all the follies they commit in offices
and meeting rooms and administration buildings and taxsupported agencies are visited not on their own
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 63
Page No 66
heads they pay each other to think up new follies but on the heads of the students and teachers whom
they have gladly left behind. Thus it is that, after about sixty years of organized and militant
antiintellectualism in the schools, every disorder in education brings power and profit to those who have
made that disorder, and every problem is given for solution into the hands of the only people who cannot
possibly solve it. The pygmies have been in charge for so long now that we are all cracking our skulls on the
doorways of the public buildings; when we go to them for remedy, they urge on us the value of crawling.
The Graves of Academe
The Pygmies' Revenge 64
Page No 67
ProblemSolving in the Content Area
When we find ourselves wondering about the meaning of conditions and events, it is always useful to ask,
who profits? The problems and disorders in education have become more and more visible in the last few
years, of course, and even the ordinary citizen who happens to have no children in the schools suspects that
something is very wrong, but he will never understand exactly what is wrong until he realizes that all our
educational problems and disorders, none of which are new, although they are more obvious, provide endless
and growing employment for the people who made them. Barely literate children may be suffering and facing
whole lives of deprivation, but consultants and remediationists and professors of reading education and
taxsupported researchers and the editors and publishers of workbooks and handsome packets of materials
are doing very well indeed and looking for even better days to come. It is important to note, too, that all those
profitmakers have not suddenly appeared among us like the wandering bands of looters who can reasonably
be expected to show up after the earthquake. They've been around a long time, diligently turning the wheel,
professing what must be remediated and remediating what has been professed and enlarging in our society
the role of what can only be called the educationistindustrial complex. Anything that may seem to us a
disorder in education is for them a golden opportunityindeed, since they live by tax money, they cannot
make their profits until we do see a disorder in education and thus feel obliged to shell out.
Curiously enough, therefore, it is very much in the interest of the policymakers and theoreticians of public
schooling that there be problems and failures and that we know about them and also, even more curiously,
that any kind of social disorder at all be made the business of the schools. We are encouraged thus to hand
over to the educationists not only the problem of widespread illiteracy but also the notorious disinclination of
the American voter to trouble himself by going to the polls, the fear and hatred of each race for the others,
and the epidemic of venereal disease among thirteenyearolds.
Sometimes, especially when defending themselves against the charge that they just don't know how to teach
reading and writing and ciphering, the educationists complain that they are unfairly burdened by ``public
demand'' for all sorts of social but nonacademic services and instruction. But, in fact, as any reader of
Cardinal Principles would know, they chose long ago to be social engineers rather than academicians,
claiming, too, that they had chosen the nobler calling. It would be interesting to put them to the test, offering
them the opportunity to give up all that thankless inculcation of right and worthy feelings and habits and stick
to teaching only what can be objectively taught and measured. It would, however, take an enlightened and
thoughtful public to make that offer, and the influence of Cardinal Principles makes an enlightened and
thoughtful public impossible. For all their occasional whimpers, therefore, the educationists are delighted to
take upon themselves the right ordering of society, which is, in any case, even more profitable than the cycle
of professing and remediating general public illiteracy.
Now here is an interesting and suggestive fact: The seven cardinal principles can be divided, and were in fact
divided by their propounders, into two categories. In one category, the category that the educationists
themselves have come to call the ``cognitive domain,'' we can put only one principle, the Command of
Fundamental Processes, or Basic Minimum Competence. You will recall that once the principlemakers had
named the Command of Fundamental Processes they could think of little more to say about it. There is a
fascinating truth hidden in that fact: Educationistic research flourishes where it is possible to say a lot about
what is vague and withers where there is little or nothing to say about the concrete. About right emotional
response to literature you can natter forever; about adding numbers to each other, what else is there to do but
teach it? It is partly for that reason, of course, that all the other six principles are in what they now call the
``affective domain,'' where there is no limit to talk. Even vocational education, which you might think would
be very concrete indeed, is to be a vehicle for various worthy responses, ``right relationships toward fellow
workers and society,'' and even that ``clear conception of right relations'' between employer and employee,
the sort of thing thought useful in East Germany, too. And it is perfectly clear, from Cardinal Principles itself
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 65
Page No 68
and from educationistic theory and practice thereafter, that educationists are much more interested in the six
other principles than in the Commend of Fundamental Processes. This is so not only because the Six can
generate more verbiage than the One, but because the consequences of schooling in the One are
embarrassingly measurable, while the consequences of schooling in the Six are not only impossible to
measure but usually not even discernible for so many years that, when they do begin to appear, the people
who caused them will all be dead, or at least retired. Thus it is that our educationists are far readier to offer
solutions to disorders in their affective domain than in their cognitive.
Consider, as a trendy example, sex. In a sane civilization, to be sure, the citizens would tell the school people
that the sexual attitudes and values of the young were none of the school's damn business and that they ought
to stick to facts, but we don't do it that way. Our schools have been granted the sex concession by virtue of
those cardinal principles that put them in charge of Health, in one context, and Worthy Homemembership,
in another. And then there is also the Worthy Use of Leisure. Thus chartered, the educationists who have long
dabbled in what they call sex education have now, now that unabashed and selfindulgent libertinism has
brought upon us great plagues of divorce, illegitimate births, venereal diseases, and all the social and
economic and personal disorders attendant on such things, come into their kingdom. Sex education is in
bloom in America.
And what form does it take? What form can it possibly take when it is devised by the inheritors of the
cardinal principles and the manipulators of stimulus and response? We can, for the sake of convenience
although not in any absolute sense, partition the study of sex, and especially human sexuality, into the
educationists' own categories, the cognitive and the affective. In the one category we can put everything that
we can name and know, all that is objectively demonstrable and subject to reasonable hypothesis and
prediction. In the other category we will have to put the other things, the feelings, attitudes, values, and
responses, worthy or not, that so fascinated the makers of the cardinal principles. Thus, while the latter
considerations can be included with the Six, the former must go with the One. The teaching of certain facts
about sex and sexuality is like the teaching of reading and writing and ciphering. Knowledge about sex is like
any other knowledge, publicly available and publicly verifiable and not variable in accordance with attitudes
or emotional responses, however worthy. It is what educationists call ``subject matter''often ``mere subject
matter''and can easily be learned without the help of any teacher at all. Most of it is in books, to which a
good teacher can, of course, provide useful footnotes in the form of newer knowledge, further description,
and the devising of analogies by which facts can be seen as functions of one another and from which
hypotheses and principles can be formed. The books do exist, and if students had the habit of reading books
there would be no shortage of knowledge about sex. But, because of decades of neglect of the mere subject
matter of those fundamental processes, they do not have the habit of reading books any more than the schools
have the habit of using books as the primary medium of what is called an education.
The books used in the public schools are almost exclusively books designed specifically to be used in the
public schools. This is in keeping with the mandate of Cardinal Principles that every course is ``in need of
extensive reorganization in order that it may contribute more effectively to the objectives outlined herein.'' A
history written by a historian is therefore disqualified unless, by some extraordinary coincidence, it happens
to foster the approved responses and appreciations, and that without dependence on mere information. Even
should that be so, the book probably would have to be rewritten and simplified for students in whom the
Command of Fundamental Processes is meager. A scientist's book on biology, furthermore, would find no
place in the schools because it will not be ``properly focused upon personal and community hygiene [and] the
principles of sanitation, and their applications.'' To find a welcome in the schools, a book must be simply
written``childishly'' might be the better wordand carefully designed to elicit worthy responses, in which
cause mere information can be not only dismissed but even distorted. Because it must meet those standards, a
schoolbook can never be a mere book, as we ordinarily understand the term, a record of the controlled and
thoughtful discourse of a knowledgeable, individual mind. To guard against every possible occasion of
unworthy response and to root out every appearance of mere information displayed in no cause other than
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 66
Page No 69
that of mere knowledge requires the diligent labor of a committee in collusion with rightminded consultants
and editorial assistants.
In America Revised (AtlanticLittle, Brown, 1979) by Frances FitzGerald, you will find a full and
demoralizing description of how school history books come to be the perversions that they are. And more
recently there was a littlenoticed but illuminating example of the nature of school ``learning materials'' in a
Hilton Kramer essay in The New York Times on the aftermath of the great Picasso retrospective. The schools
are just as good at teaching the right appreciation of art as they are at teaching worthy sexual attitudes, and
the Picasso show brought forth not only an ``educational'' film in which the painter was portrayed, surely to
the stupefaction of those with some mere information, as an exemplary parent and role model, but also a
teachers' guide in which Picasso is identified as a Fauve playing with bright colors. That's bad enough, but his
imaginary enlistment in fauvism is also said to have been a result of his abandonment of experimentation
with bright colors. And the cover of the teachers' guide bore a large ``Picasso'' signature superimposed on a
lovely photograph of a studio littered with painter's paraphernalia and handsome canvases, certainly
appreciable, but, to anyone having a little knowledge, easily identifiable as the work of Miró.
As bad as this ludicrous display of ignorance is, there is something worse, which Hilton Kramer probably
doesn't suspect any more than you do, and that is that no one in the schools is likely to be troubled or
embarrassed by such a display. Well, so what? Looking at Miró's studio is also a worthy use of leisure, and a
niggling attention to trivial details is exactly the kind of elitism that has always inhibited right emotional
response. So there. It is in the same spirit that educationists can blithely justify the omission, in an American
history text, of any reference to the Civil War.
The making of a schoolbook is analogous to the classroom rap session in which the illinformed are
supposed to reach understanding through the recitation of slogans and notions and by relating to one another.
There are differences, however. For the captive children pretending to formulate ``good judgment as to means
and methods'' for the promotion of some worthy social end and developing ``habits of cordial cooperation in
social undertakings,'' as prescribed in Cardinal Principles, the whole thing is obviously a game. Only a
teacher, or an especially dull or cowed student, could take it seriously. But the committees and task forces
that devise (you cannot say ``write'') those nonbooks used in the school take their work very seriously
indeed. There is profit in it Even prestige. So we can be confident that the ``books,'' and all the other
wondrously diverse and cunningly packaged ``learning materials'' out of which sex education will be taught,
will be acceptable to the ideology of educationism both simplified and tendentious, careless of mere
information and careful in the elicitation of right response in the cause of social adjustment. In other words,
this ``new'' campaign intended to remedy whole hosts of social and personal disorders is different from the
old program of education as social manipulation only in extentand, of course, expense. In both cases, much
greater.
As our schools now embark on a massive campaign of sexual rehabilitation for all of American youth, we can
naturally expect that they will give it all they have, which means, of course, that what they don't have they
won't give it. What they do have, all they have, is that earnest devotion to the power of suggestion in the
cause of social and psychological manipulation, and, although their decades of devotion to pious social
adjustment may not be the only cause of our present disorders, they have certainly not prevented them. Now
the necessary concomitant of the social adjustment theory of education is the denigration of intellectual
discipline, for the sake of which the command of fundamental processes was slighted in Cardinal
Principles. Perhaps it is a bit rash, however tempting, to say it is exactly because the schools have been
preaching vapid and sentimental sermons for sixty years that hosts of our newborn children and their mothers
will become permanent wards of the state, but it is not a bit rash to suspect that widespread and crippling
social disorders of all kinds are directly caused by ignorance an thoughtlessness. There is only one remedy
for ignorance an thoughtlessness, and that is literacy. Millions and million of American children would today
stand in no need of sex education, or consumer education or intercultural education or any of those fake
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 67
Page No 70
educations, if they had had in the first place an education.
We have seen above, for instance, that what is called intercultural education is a shabby dodge by which
students and teachers may be excused from the study of history, anthropology, geography, language,
literature, philosophy, and who can count what else. That all makes for a long and detailed discussion, but an
equivalent and simpler model of the genesis of fake educations can be seen in the trendy and popular
consumer education. We are told that we need consumer education because people are easily duped by
misleading advertising, cannot figure out the perounce price of ketchup, and imagine that they can live on
Twinkies and CocaCola. (When teenaged mothers raise their illegitimate children on Twinkies and
CocaCola, that reinforces the need for sex education and also family living education.) The consumer who
is duped by misleading advertising does not need consumer education; he needs to know how to read. The
housewife who can't figure out what ketchup costs does not need consumer education; she needs to know
how to cipher. And as to those who want to live on Twinkies and CocaCola, frankly that's their own damn
business and we ought to leave them alone, but we might legitimately provide them with knowledge about
biology and chemistry first and then leave them alone. Our problems come not from ignorance and
thoughtlessness about sex any more than from ignorance and thoughtlessness about ketchup, they just come
from ignorance and thoughtlessness, which are preserved and nourished in our schools by those whose profits
lie in ``solving'' the problems they have created.
Literacy is like the kingdom of Heaven. Those who seek it first will find that other things are added unto
them. Literacy is not the same as Basic Minimum Competence, but, if we provide an emphasis that seems not
to have occurred to the principlemakers, it might indeed be described as the command of the fundamental
processes of word and number. The power of number, to be sure, is not usually included in ``literacy,'' but it
should be, for it is through the ability to command the techniques both of word and number that we can
know and think. There is no other way. To say that we can ``know'' or ``think'' in other ways is to blur those
words into uselessness so that rather than making fine distinctions they can point vaguely in the direction of
any events at all that seem to take place invisibly in the mind. It is exactly that reluctance to seek or even
tolerate fine distinctions that makes the muddled jargon of the educationists what it is, and it is not surprising,
therefore, that those who have neglected literacy should look for some presumed other ways of knowing and
thinking. This makes it possible to excuse or even to justify the failure to teach literacy by claiming that it
doesn't have to be taught anyway. Consider the following, a brief and unfortunately oversimplified piece
from The Underground Grammarian:
The Idea of Expressing Feelings In New Mexico
It had to happen. Last month we granted the world's first DEd, horroris causa, and now everybody wants
one. Two new candidates present themselves, and they are not some silly educationists but bona
fide associate professors of English out at what they call Eastern New Mexico University.
Laidback folk. Arlene Zekowski, Stanley Berne. Hate apostrophes. Rules. Arbitrary. Down sentences! Up
feelings expressing! Up Zekowski! Up Berne! Right on!
Or, if you prefer, On right! ``We're professors of English,'' says Berne. (Hm. Shouldn't that be ``Were
professors of English''?) ``We are concerned with the idea of expressing feelings. Arbitrary rules of grammar
prohibit that.'' (Cmon, be patient. Sure he talks that tired old grammar, but only because he has to get to we
elitists.) Hes wright. No, thats not expressing feelings. He rite! Wordsworth feelingexpressing fouledup by
verbsubject agreement. Shakespeare shot downDonne undone by nonrestrictive clauses. Whitman
comatose from commas.
Zekowski: ``Grammar is elitism. I wish to destroy what is dead, lifeless and snobbish.'' Hows that for boring
from within? ``Arbitrary sentence structure is logical,'' she complains, ``but the brain isn't logical. [How
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 68
Page No 71
true!] You don't think in sentences. You think in terms of patterns and images. It's random association.'' And
further: ``Many advertisements don't use sentences or grammar. They use words to create images.'' (Exactly
how they use the words she doesn't say. Could be they sprinklem here and there, collagewise. Cool. Just
think. If Das Kapital had been done like that, we wouldn't have all this damn trouble now. There's nothing
more dangerous than a bunch of logical sentences, but what would you expect from an elitist like Marx?)
If there's one thing we love around here, it's the classing of icons, and we support the idea of expressing
feelings 1,000 percent. That's exactly what we should be teaching these kids. For one thing, it's a cinch, like
playing tennis with the net down, as Frost put it. Another: if we let them in on the secrets of logical sentences
and coherent discourse, the ignorant little bastards will go on to take away some of our cushiest jobs, perhaps
even as associate professors of English, and that will be the end of lifeless elitism as we know it.
However, while we applaud Zekowski and Berne for their cunning subterfuge, and while we admit that it
is the first duty of a DEd to cook up schemes for job security, we cannot give them their degrees just yet.
Their plan sounds good off paper, but when they write their grammarless English, we read: ``Once upon a
time ago. But now nevermore.'' Cute and expressive of feeling, sure, but clogged up with grammar. Maybe
next year.
Following the appearance of that article, I heard from many readers who accused me of inventing Berne and
Zekowski. How silly. Bernes and Zekowskis are generated spontaneously out of the primordial nutrient broth
of Cardinal Principles. If you find them unbelievable, you might be sobered to know that they have written
many books for the guidance of public school English teachers and are said to go about holding workshops
and training sessions for same.
The ``thought'' of Berne and ZekowskiI know that's not the right word, but we may not even have the right
word in Englishrepays study. Consider: ``You don't think in sentences. You think in terms of patterns and
images. It's random association.'' All of that is true, of course, if you happen to be an imbecile, or maybe a
gnu. All of it is also true even for conscious human beings if the verb to think refers to anything, anything at
all, that takes place invisibly in the mind. The mind does indeed, from time to time and often with dismal
consequences when there is a certain kind of work to be done, find itself occupied with patterns and images
and random associations. And it does many things that have no need of sentences: it regrets, it exults, it
yearns, it wonders, it fears, it expects, it dreams (perchance to sleep), it wanders, it sees, it hears...you can
make your own list. The very fact that there are so many words for the invisible acts of the mind reveals that
our language can and regularly does make, as Berne and Zekowski do not, countless fine and subtle
distinctions among those acts. And the act in which we do , if we have a command of fundamental processes,
make such distinctions may be called thinking; and, in fact, we do that thinking in sentences, in which we say
to ourselves that yearning and thinking are different for such and such reasons. We may perform any number
of mental acts ``in terms of,'' whatever that means, patterns and images, but thinking is not one of them.
Thinking is done in sentences, logical sentences. Principia mathematica is not random association. Nor, for
that matter, is poetry, which Berne and Zekowski are said to write, and which they seem to confuse with
``expressing feelings,'' which could also include smashing urinals in the boys' room. It is one of the great
wonders of poetry that it can be supremely free and individual in spite of countless traditional and arbitrary
restraints, and even in spite of the often greater restraints that poets usually choose to impose on themselves.
Berne and Zekowski, I admit, are probably an extreme case of educationistic antiintellectualism, but they
are, don't forget, professors of English at a state university where English teachers are trained. Their notions
are right at home in the context of Cardinal Principles. They are concerned with expressing feeling, or, as
they put it, with the ``idea'' of expressing feelings. (I don't know what that might mean, but I suspect that it is
not some fine distinction between ``expressing'' and ``the idea of expressing.'') They wish to destroy elitism,
which, although dead and lifeless, somehow manages to remain snobbish. They characterize rules as
``arbitrary'' rules, as though no one had ever put modifiers near what they modify until the rule had been
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 69
Page No 72
devised, and assert that the arbitrary rules prohibit the expression of feelings, against which assertion some
evidence could be adduced. They turn, for example, to the demotic, the advertisements that ``use words to
create images,'' as though that were some startling new use of language and especially to be prized because of
its commercial quality. They differ from gardenvariety educationists only in detail (and perhaps in their
taste for the dramaticnotably absent in educationists) but not in principle. They prefer emotional response
to knowledge; they equate technical proficiency with elitism; they imagine grammar as a set of rules, mere
information, and the stuff of rote learning; and they depend for their lessons on the popular or practical, to
which students can presumably ``relate.''
When we look around America, we notice, of course, what seems to be a general decline in our young people
of the powers of observation and discrimination and the habits of accuracy and precision that we might
expect in the literate. This is an illusion born of the fact that it is only the young people who are occasionally
tested or measured. The same disabilities are to be found in all groups, because they have been fostered for so
many years now. And those many years of malpractice have fostered the same disabilities within the ranks of
the educationists themselves that we can see in the public at large. The nowretired professors of education
who learned their appreciation of the ``command'' of fundamental processes in the shadow of Cardinal
Principles taught it to the professors of education, who taught the same to all the teachers and supervisors and
facilitators now in the schools, who in their turn can pass on to their students nothing but more of the same.
It follows, therefore, that the formulation and direction of the currently faddish fervor for those fundamental
processes are given into the hands of those who lack the skills of those processes and who have grown up in
the climate of opinion out of which Berne and Zekowski have formulated their principles. The enterprise
cannot succeed any more than pygmies can grow tall by pulling upward on their ears.
Here is how one state system of teacher academies plans to solve the problem:
The Missouri Compromise
You will not be astonished to learn that there are some people in Missouri who cannot manage commas,
cannot avoid sentence fragments, cannot regularly make verbs agree with subjects and pronouns with
antecedents, and cannot help sounding like literal translations from Bulgarian. If you are a regular reader of
this journal, you'll also be unastonished to hear that those pitiable illiterates are members of the Missouri
Association of Colleges of Teacher Education.
These poor saps have finally noticed that lots of irate citizens ``have indicated concern of [yes, of ] the
decreasing standardized test scores of students.'' They even know that a ``sensitivity has become quite
manifest in the development in state wide [yes, two words] assessment systems.'' But they don't seem too
worried. They've cleared up the whole mess in a ``position statement'' called Assessment of Basic Skills
Competencies of Potential Teachers.
The Missouri educationists have also just discovered, or have at least come to suspect that they might perhaps
decide to assume tentatively, what the rest of us have always known. They put it thus: ``Although many
factors may intervene the teacher is viewed by many as a critical variable in the teachinglearning process
and, therefore, the key to the improvement in the basic skills of students.''
``The teacher,'' they say, ``must have a high degree of proficiency in the basic skills. They are expected to
transmit to their students through precept and example.''
Yeah. And here are some of the precepts and examples through which these Missouri Teachertraining
Turkeys transmit:
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 70
Page No 73
``The latter ['field experiences'] being principally in student teaching with a major emphasis on institutional
planning, execution, and evaluation of subject matter to be presented.'' And, ``Utilizing the assumption that
the measuring/ascertaining of the competencies of potential teachers should be done on or about the end of
the traditional sophomore year.'' For the Turkeys, those are sentences. So why should they care? It's the
taxpayers and children who'll have to serve them.
Those, of course, are just supersaturated, freebooting participles, but this one passes understanding: ``If the
student does not meet the prescribed standards of basic skills and the student, before they are formally
admitted into teacher education and certainly before graduation, should have remediation and reevaluation.''
(Wow, these people are tough! Before graduation, no less.) Any competent sixthgrade teacher would flunk
such rubbish, but the Turkeys aren't worried. As long as they're in charge, there will be damned few
competent sixthgrade teachers in Missouri.
``Also,'' say the Turkeys, ``there is a question of the relationship of secondary and cosecondary schools in
terms of relationships. The authors [ ! ] of this position paper agreed that such an assessment process can
have a significant impact [they never discuss insignificant or mere impacts] on secondary school curriculum
in turning to an assessment instrument to which the public schools might be inclined to reach toward.''
Why do the good people of Missouri suffer such humbug, without turning to some blunt instrument to which
they might be inclined to reach toward? We can tell you why. It's because these ugly crimes against nature
are committed in private among consenting Turkeys. How many ``authors,'' do you suppose, conspired to
write, rewrite, edit, and finally to approve all that gibberish? How many of Missouri's teachertrainers,
would you guess, have read it? Was not one of them embarrassed or outraged by this sleazy display of
ignorance and ineptitude? And if there was one, what do you think he did? He kept his mouth shut. It's better
to suffer a momentary discontent than to attract the taxpayers`` attention.
So, unhampered by pesky public outcry, people who cannot devise sentences or make sense or even
punctuate will get on with the business of providing Missouri with teachers. And they don't want
any interference, if you please, as they make, well, not ''clear,`` to be sure, but at least ''quite manifest,`` in
their ghastly and ungrammatical peroration:
''There is an advantage to each institution in Missouri preparing teachers to have an institutional level
responsibility rather than a state wide...responsibility for assurance of proficiency of basic skills. Alternate
assessment processes allow for diversity of response by each institution. It [?] allows for diversity of response
loads [?] by students, it allows for diversity of interpretation of what is basic [that's the part they like best]
for that institution's student population, and it eliminates conflicts of perogatives [typo?] and rights of
faculties of institution to set curriculum in means of assessing a testing or assuring of competencies.``
We have some advice for the good people of Missouri. Turn those rascals out. Pension them off for life at full
pay, requiring only that the never again set foot on a campus. Don't worry about the cost. In fifty years or so,
there won't be any cost. As it is, you're planning to pay more and more of them for ever and ever. Once
they're gone, on the day they go, in fact, your schools and colleges will become the best in the land.
A knowledge of history is one of the basic skills of which we have been deprived by the educationists' fervor
for shabby social studies and smug civics. We have forgotten that the storekeeper used to pay miscreants to
stay away. It worked We've gotten it backward. We pay them to hang around and smash the windows. Let's
be realistic and pay the miscreants to do that one thing the we most need them to donothing, nothing at all.
I am very sorry to have to award any points at all to the compromisers of Missouri, who are contentedly
unconscious of their own ignorance and the ludicrous pathos of their determination to ensure the
''measuring/ascertaining`` of that ''high degree of proficiency in the basic skills,`` but they do deserve a few.
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 71
Page No 74
In the first place, if this is an exculpation, their ignorance was visited upon them by the system in whose
service they labor, and, in the next place, there is much justice in the educationists' routine disclaimer of
responsibility for the literacy of incipient teachers. That, they happily point out, is supposed to be the
business of the English departments. And they are right, although, if literacy is a fundamental process, it
ought to be a concern in every department. But there is no doubt that English departments must be charged
with teaching everything that can be taught about the technical skills that provide a command of literacy. And
Berne and Zekowski, you will surely remember, are professors not of education but of English, who ply their
trade in a school where teachertraining happens. Although it is, to be sure, the very existence of the articles
of educationistic faith that makes Bernes and Zekowskis possible, professors of English are supposed to have
some of their own articles of faith, which ought to double them up with hysterical laughter when Bernes and
Zekowskis appear at department meetings. So the poor professors of education are put in the sad position of
having to lament aloud that even the professors of English have swallowed the potion bottled by the
professors of education. There's a satisfying sort of justice in that, but it still means that there is not much
hope of breaking the cycle in which illiteracy is passed on from generation to generation.
The story of what has happened to English departments in the last few decades, especially in English
departments attached to teachertraining academies, would make a fat and dull book. In brief, that history
can be seen as a conditioned response to the dual role of the study of English as imagined in Cardinal
Principles, where the command of fundamental processes on the one hand and the right emotional response
to literature on the other were obviously assigned to the same people. Since a fervid dedication to the former
has not exactly been a hallmark of the schools, and since the latter can more or less be ''taught`` by anyone,
the teaching of English has evolved into a curious creature that now looks something like a pair of wings with
no bird between them. There is the Right Wing, devoted to the study of literature (pronounced in four
syllables and without any trace of a ''ch``), which has handed over the muchhated and laborious teaching of
composition to graduate assistants and junior department members panting after promotion, who look upon
the work as a necessary apprenticeship to be swiftly accomplished so that they might go on to teaching
seminars in the early Elizabethan dramatists.
The Left Wing is more complicated, because it is divided into two persuasions or parties, the democrats and
the technocrats. The democrats are really true inheritors of Cardinal Principles, for they propose literature as
a vehicle of social and ''interpersonal`` understanding and an incentive to the appreciation of the brotherhood
of all mankind and the human condition. It is the democrats of the Left Wing who have multiplied the
offerings in the catalog by cooking up courses in everything from the Urban Experience to Adolescence in
America and Female Problems in an Age of Lowered Expectations. Such courses all have, inevitably, their
analogues in the high schools, where the study of literature comes down to minicourses in ghost, sport, or
animal stories adapted from popular magazines.
However, while the democrats hold large tracts in the kingdom of government education, the broadest acres
are being deeded to the technocrats of the Left Wing, who have prudently provided for themselves and their
progeny by reconstruing reading and writing as ''communication.`` Communication is socially acceptable.
Even the desultory deliberations of the uninterested ignorant can be called ''communication.`` And the
eighthgrade rap session on free abortions for eighth graders suddenly becomes a skill to be taught as a
legitimate ''fundamental process.`` All the presumed skills of communication, including filmmaking and
taperecorder operation and even (this is true) televisionwatching, become precincts of the great realm of
communications, where writing itself, only one precinct, is subdivided into utilitarian fragments. The study of
writing thus gives way to courses in Personal Writing, Creative Writing, Journalistic Writing, Technical
Writingwell, however long the list, it will be longer tomorrow.
The innumerable offerings of the communicationiststhey sometimes call themselves
''communicologists`` recommend themselves in the world of educationism by virtue not only of their
collectivist aims but also because of their technical flavor. Idle chatter finds respectability and curricular
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 72
Page No 75
justification when it becomes Interpersonal Group Communication Methodology. Furthermore, while a
course in writing needs only some paper and pencils, courses in communicology can generate some very
impressive budgets.
Here is a case in point, indeed, a case in several points, for whose sake I must provide some background. The
Communications Department in question does its business at the college where I do mine, and it is famous
here for having announced its withdrawal from the division of arts and sciences, as we call them. The
announcement, a portion of which is quoted, was neither preceded nor accompanied nor followed by any
action at all. That in itself was a splendid display of the paramountcy of communication over substance.
Now, however, there is some substance at issue, specifically, a proposal to establish what was then called a
''Flagship`` program of great excellence in the ''field`` of communications. (The word ''Flagship`` cannot be
printed out in full in The Underground Grammarian):
The Works of Scriblerus X. Machina
When the Communications Department blasted off into the unknown regions of interdivisional space, its
chairman left us to mull over his now famous Farewell (sans Hail):
But in the sober light of day after the intoxicating elixirs of selfdelusion have begun to fade,
after the sonorous tones of your voices have begun to sound hollow, after the technicolor
hues of your dreams have begun to mute into the blacks and whites of realitythen you may
perhaps face these details of reality.
He was reminding us that we had not yet entered the twentieth century, so he must have chosen that quaint
and antiquated tone of purple fustian for ironic emphasisdon't you think? How subtly he reminds us of our
enslavement to outworn tradition by his innovative use of ''mute`` as an intransitive verb and that multimedia
metaphor in which our elixirs ''fade`` before our very eyes!
Now the Communications Department reenters our atmosphere, blazing like another Kohoutek, and
bringing no faded elixirs but a heady draft proposal for a F of its very own.
We looked at the part where they tell all about the teaching of writing, twentiethcentury style. Here's the
plan:
The communications Department proposes to establish an ideal classroom for the teaching of
the basic writing course...While there is no single classroom prototype that could be
considered ideal for all circumstances, there is a concern that different approaches be taken.
One of the keys in suggesting an ideal classroom is that traditional classrooms have a way of
perpetuating traditional approaches...By bringing together in one room a large variety of
audiovisual implements, creating a relaxed atmosphere by having the room carpeted with
pictures on the walls and easy chairs and tables and by having duplicating equipment and a
variety of newspapers and magazines readily available, we can encourage attempts to change
both students' perceptions and teachers' approaches to the task of learning how to write.
Now why couldn't we have thought of all that neat stuff? Because we've been hung up perpetuating
traditional approachesthings like drill and practice, writing and rewritingthat's why. Even desks! Now
we see. What we need is a dentist's waiting room redone by Radio Shack, magazines and Muzak, comfy
chairs, and a shiny new Xerox so the scholars won't have to fight over the latest number of Popular
Mechanics.
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 73
Page No 76
Notice a refreshing absence of flat, empty surfaces where a thoughtless student might accidentally write
words on a piece of paper and set the whole class back a century. That's the hard part, all right, putting the
words on the paper. That's why hardly anyone was able to write before the advent of that large variety of
audiovisual implements. (Implements?)
The proposal itself seems to have been put together in just such an innovative, relaxing setting. Notice, for
instance, the creative (or easy chair) treatment of punctuation in that bit about the pictures. The room is
carpeted with pictures on the walls. The pictures are on the walls and easy chairs and tables. It's a
splitscreen effect. Elec tron ic!
Elsewhere we find:
A second prong in the outreach of the department would come from a Communication
Consultancy Center. This would be created as an umbrella from which many different kinds
of services could be offered to the community.
Stunning. No fuddyduddy of the age of paper and pencil could ever have accomplished prose like that. The
secret is ''vision.`` Only a writer who has learned his craft from long hours of assiduous (but relaxed) scrutiny
of a twentyinch color implement could hope to develop a vision modern enough to see that outreaches have
prongs, prongs coming from their Centers, and that a prong, or maybe a Center, can be created as an
umbrella, an umbrella from which services can be dispensed, services that can help us all to learn how to
communicate in just this fashion.
Well, you can just bet your Bearcat scanner against a busted quill pen that all our staff writers will be
standing at the door the day they open that Communications Consultancy Center. We're mired in traditions.
We could never, for instance, have come up with these spiffy structures that go the tired old passive at least
one bettermaybe two:
...[the] Department can provide leadership that will cause it to be viewed as a resource .
...few of the courses...have been able to be offered on a regular basis....needs should be able
to be filled...
You just can't hope to master that smooth modern style without spending hours, whole seasons probably, in
the old easy chair, beer and pretzels at hand, studying the styles of the greatest playbyplay and color men
to be found on the audiovisual implement.
And just look at these daring departures from stodgy tradition. We're so oldfashioned that we almost
thought they were mistakes:
...the advantages the computer offers...lies in continuous availability....the equipment
needs...is appended. ...there needs to be provisions made...
All of this is encouraging for anybody who worries about the teaching of writing here at Glassboro. It shows
that the Communications Department is perfectly willing to put some of the taxpayers' money where
somebody's mouth isin a collection of machines. Time was when your basic model communications
teacher would rather watch reruns of ''Washington Week in Review`` than teach a writing course. Now they'll
be clamoring to twiddle the dials and leaf through Cosmopolitan and rap about nontraditional approaches to
interpersonal communication in the easy chair.
So not to worry. We can all go down to the launching in good conscience, sing in our hollow tones one
chorus of ''Anchors Aweigh,`` smash a fifth of faded elixir on the prow of the refitted Starship Triad, newly
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 74
Page No 77
home from one uncharted deep, sallying forth into yet another, carrying our hopes and dreams, ere they mute,
our tuners and amplifiers and, of course, the prongs of our outreach.
In that blazing display of furniture and equipment, you may have missed the fact that the ''ideal classroom``
(certainly ideal for some lucky contractors) is for ''the teaching of the basic writing course.`` Advanced
courses in various ''writings`` will require yet more specialized doodads. The implicit suggestion of all the
paraphernalia and even the carefully designed environment will be the same, to wit, that writing is just one of
many ''skills`` of communication, similar in kind to the making of television commercials and the
grammarless collages that so pleased Berne and Zewokski. And it follows that ''reading`` is the skill of
receiving and registering ''communication,`` which, accordingly, may or may not come in the form of
writing. And it further follows, therefore, that what the schools mean by ''literacy`` is not what you think it is.
Literacy may be ''visual literacy`` or the ability to program computers, although it is hard to imagine how
people who are not interested in punctuation or spelling can meet the even more stringent demands of
computer programs.
But the greatest achievement of the communicationists, and the one that best assures their prosperity, is that
they have transformed writing from a private act into a public one, from a solitary search for understanding
into a public display of some communication. This suggests some deeper reasons, deeper than their obvious
distaste for the mere information required in the teaching of writing, for the pro forma mention and
subsequent neglect of those fundamental processes in Cardinal Principles. Everywhere in that pamphlet, we
can find exhortations to socialization through group efforts, group discussions, group thinking, and even
games and dances. We find specific condemnations of too much knowledge of mere facts and too much
attention to intellectual discipline, characteristic foreshadowings of that later indictment of ''excellence
narrowly defined.`` In an even more recent policy statement from the National Education Association,
Curriculum Change Toward the 21st Century (1977), a reappraisal and expanded reaffirmation of Cardinal
Principles, we read:
Imbedded in the question of freedom is an educational dilemmathe longstanding enigma
of how to obtain the important output of superior minds without creating an elite of
scientists, politicians, social planners and commentators, military specialists, business
executives, and so on.
Or, in other words, how can we manage to muzzle the ox while he treadeth out the corn?
The supposed love of democracy out of which the commissioners devised their principles is really just a
hatred of those ''superior minds,`` from which, notice, we can profit not by the study and practice of superior
mindfulness but by ''obtaining their output.`` While we will discourage students from a painful retracing of
the path of Newton's logic, for instance, we will take profit and pleasure from the fact that Newton has made
it possible (for some few of us, who do have to be watched carefully for signs of incipient elitism) to
construct devices that work.
But we mustn't forget that bullet, the one that ''spins`` end over end in perfect but antisocial obedience to the
laws of motion. (A thoughtful writer would have written ''tumbles,`` but, having done that out of
thoughtfulness, he would probably, out of that same thoughtfulness, have understood that the point of the
example was utterly irrelevant.) Of the output that we might obtain from those superior minds, some must
prove unworthy, which is to say, antihumanistic, which in turn is to say, the work of an individual mind
heedless of collective values. It is thus a primary aim of social adjustment educationism to disarm and
overwhelm the individual mind and replace it with a comprehensive data bank of received and unexamined
attitudes, values, opinions, and worthy emotional responses. All of the curricular dilutions and manipulations
prescribed in Cardinal Principles are means to that end. And, to that end, there is only one certain
impediment. It is the one ''student outcome`` that our schools simply cannot afford to provide, even if they
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 75
Page No 78
could, which, out of thoughtless acceptance of their own principles, they can't. It is, of course, literacy.
''Literacy`` needs some redefining. When Jefferson spoke of that literacy that would provide ''informed
discretion,`` he did not mean the ability to read the instructions for assembling a swing set or even for
assembling a nuclear power generating plant. He did not mean the ability to write a correctly punctuated
letter of application for a job. He did not mean the ability to devise, or even to ''appreciate,`` advertisements
that ''use words to create images.`` He did not mean the habit of worthy emotional response to literature. In
short, he did not mean any, or even all taken together, of those ''skills`` that we now put forth as studies in
communications or language arts. He did mean certain habits and powers of the individual mind, habits and
powers that can be learned and refined only by long practice in reading and writing.
Literacy is not, as it is considered in our schools, a portion of education. It is education. It is at once the
ability and the inclination of the mind to find knowledge, to pursue understanding, and, out of knowledge
and understanding, not out of received attitudes and values or emotional responses, however ''worthy,`` to
make judgments. Literate people are not easy prey. They do know an inference from a statement of fact.
They are not easily persuaded by pretended authority. They are attentive to the natural requirements of logic.
They can make distinctions, very fine distinctions, and are able both to notice and to examine their own
predispositions and even their only presumably ''right emotional responses.`` To say that young human beings
are incapable of such powers is elitism.
But our schools do say that. And thus they not only preclude those powers in the students but in the whole
system. Today's teachers and the teachers of today's teachers are all the inevitable results of the system. They
simply don't know what literacy is. This accounts for one of the most bewildering contradictions to be found
in the current pandemonium of bold, innovative thrusts in basic minimum competencies. On the one hand,
our educationists fancy that literacy is something you achieve when you have developed enough ''skills.`` But
it turns out that many of those skills are in fact the results of much practice and hard knowledge and habits of
rote learning and mere information, things in short supply not only among the hapless students but also
among the teachers and the teachers of the teachers. Therefore, on some other hand, having discovered how
hard it is to teach those skills in a system where no one is very good at them, the educationists can also fancy
that literacy is not simply a matter of skills, which now become ''mere`` skills, and that it might just as well
be achieved in their absence.
''Problemsolving in the content area`` is a favorite pastime of educationists. In the case of literacy, it works
this way: Literacy, whatever it is, must be a student outcome. So let's try to teach those basic skills and offer
minicourses and interesting electives in all sorts of communications and language arts and let the students
express themselves and improve their selfesteem. Then we'll find out what the student outcomes are and call
them ''literacy.`` Put in those terms, the proposition sounds too preposterous to win approval even among
educationists, unless you happen to be one of millions of American parents who have wondered how
compositions full of uncorrected and perhaps unnoticed mechanical errors could earn such good grades.
The convenient redefinition of literacy, however, is not merely a happy dodge for teachers. It is national
policy in the realm of educationism, which embraces even those outlying provinces that we mistakenly deem
buffer states between us and the traditional expansionism of governmental social adjustment. The same
comfortable and undemanding redefinition is a matter of policy at the Educational Testing Service:
The Holistic Hustle
Fortunately for American educationists, there is never any dearth of trashy and popular fads, the raw material
of curricular novelty. The halflife of most bold innovative thrusts is less than that of the pet rock or the nude
encounter group, and pedagogical gimmicks have to be cooked up more often than situation comedies. But,
thanks to the fertile inventiveness always inspired by exuberant greed, the master schlockmongers will
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 76
Page No 79
always provide the educationists with full measures of readily adaptable inanities.
Of course, there is a difference between the peddlers of pop and the educationists. The peddlers of pop are
skillful. When promoters have deposited the take from Woodstocks and Earth Days, the educationists come
limping behind with minicourses in the ''poetry`` of rock and roll, and environmental awareness. In a frantic
scramble after what crumbs may fall from the merchants' tables, they rush to ''teach`` soapoperawatching,
the casting of horoscopes, and the throwing of the Frisbee. Coming soon: Elvis, the copper bracelet, and the
Tshirt as literature.
Future historians of education (how's that for a dreary calling?) will understand better than we that the most
powerful influence on education in our time was not new knowledge of the psychology of learning, not the
rise and dominance of the electronic media, not the fervor for democratization that followed the civil rights
movements, not even the newly awakened public recognition of the tensions between the demands of an
increasingly automated society and a reinvigorated and often antimaterialistic individualism, but, purely and
simply, the Big Mac. Our schools are, in almost every respect, analogues of the fastfood industry, although
there probably is some nourishment in the Big Mac. Even the slogans are the same: Have it your way; We do
it all for yoooooo.
It's not surprising, therefore, that educationists respond to public discontent not by trying to improve what
they do, but by trying to ''educate`` the public into some other ''perception`` of what they do. In education, as
in the fastfood business, it's called ''image enhancement,`` and, like all flackery, it's done with slogans and
buzz words. When the public finally noticed, for instance, that fewer and fewer children were learning to
read, the educationists quickly discovered that ''learning disabilities`` were far more common than anyone
had ever suspected. Therefore, we ought in fact to praise the schools for doing such a great job with swarms
of undernourished, disaffected imbeciles, many of whom were also myopic, hard of hearing, hyperactive (if
not lethargic), or even lacking in selfesteem.
Now, pestered by complaints about student writing, the educationists have drawn from the bottomless pit of
mindless pop a bucket of inspiration, the Whatever Turns You On Plan for the Enhancement of Public
Perceptions Concerning Student Writing. They call it ''holistic`` grading. It will improve grades dramatically
without requiring any improvement in the teaching of writing. It will work even in schools where there is
no teaching of writing. Now that's educationism.
Most of what we've heard about holistic grading has come from the horse's mouth, the National Council of
Teachers of English. We now have a report from another part of the horse, the Educational Testing Service,
which is offering ''workshops`` in holistic grading:
With this method, the essay is read for a total impression of its quality rather than for such
separate aspects of writing skill as organization, punctuation, diction, or spelling. The
method takes a positive approach to the rating of compositions by asking the reader to
concentrate on what the student has accomplished rather than on what the student has failed
to do or has done badly. Holistic scoring is both efficient and accurate. The standards by
which compositions are judged are those that the readers have developed from their training
and from their experiences with student writing.
We have to presume that the written parts of tests given by ETS will be ''rated`` in this ''efficient and
accurate`` fashion from now on. In a few years, we'll hear that the writing crisis, if indeed there ever was one,
is over.
This, you see, is a ''positive approach.`` To fuss about organization, punctuation, diction, and spelling is the
bad old negative approach that caused the whole flap to begin with.
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 77
Page No 80
To judge writing by this ''holistic`` method is like judging a musical performance without reference to
rhythm, tempo, or dynamics, and taking no heed of false notes or of ''organization.`` What could we say of a
performance in which all of those things were wrong? We could certainly not judge it as a musical
performance if we choose to give no weight to the attributes of musical performance. If we could consider
things without regarding their attributes, which we can't, we wouldn't even know what the hell they were. It is
only by their attributes that we can distinguish a musical performance from a billiard ball. It is by just such
attributes as organization and diction, dismissed above as presumably optional ''aspects,`` that we can
distinguish between written composition and the egg stains on an educationist's face.
And that is a distinction that we had better learn to make. There will never be good, universal, public
education in America until we learn, from their own words, that the people in charge of it are badly in need of
an education. Educated people will not be deceived by such nonsense. Some knowledge of the history of
thought and some skill in logical language can be expected of the educated, but they are not required for a
degree in ''education.``
Educated people are likely to know what ''holistic`` means. They know, simply because they have the power
of language and thought, that if something is more than the sum of its parts, it cannot be less than the sum of
its parts. They even know what ''aspects`` are, and that to call punctuation, spelling, diction, and even
organization, ''separate aspects`` of writing suggests either ignorance or mendacity. They know, too, that this
slick hustle, designed not only to deceive the taxpayers about the state of student writing but also to make the
grading of compositions one hell of a lot easier, may appropriately be called many things, but ''holistic`` isn't
one of them.
''Contemptuous,`` however, is one of them. It is not out of kindness but out of contempt (and sloth) that
educationists design ways to excuse students from the demands of good work. To tell a student that ''what he
has accomplished,`` however little that may be, is an adequate substitute for ''what he has failed to do or has
done badly,`` however much that may be, is not ''humanistic`` (they don't know the meaning of that word,
either) or even humane. It is arrogant.
It is also unmistakably to imply that the mastery of good writing is not important. Do you suppose that those
educationists would want their dentists or even their electricians ''rated`` by their ''holistic`` method? When
pilots and flight engineers are licensed by ''positive approaches`` without regard for all those trivial ''separate
aspects`` of their crafts, will the loyal members of the National Council of Teachers of English fly to the
annual convention anyway, just to demonstrate their faith in a ''total impression of quality``? Will they
consult physicians whose diplomas have been granted in spite of ''what the student has failed to do or has
done badly``?
One thing must be said in fairness to the educationists who have packaged and touted the Holistic Hot 'n'
Juicy: The standards by which they propose to measure students' work are no more rigorous than those by
which they judge their own work. After all, the ability to write good English isn't required for a doctorate in
education, so why bother high school kids about it? Of course, there may be some kids who aim higher and
would like to do useful and respectable work that calls for the habits of accuracy and clear thought that come
from the mastery of written composition, but the fastfood business doesn't work that way. When ETS serves
up the Holistic Hot 'n' Juicy, everybody eats it.
And the educationists all get to do a little something for themselves toooooo.
In a school where ''holistic rating`` is accepted orthodoxy, will a student's understanding of the mere facts of
human sexuality be measured, and applauded, out of a total impression of its quality? Will the mindless
appreciation of expressed feelings in grammarless (and successful) advertisements have some consequence in
the classroom next door where children are learning to be canny consumers? Having completed their courses
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 78
Page No 81
in sex and consumer education, will students be every bit as knowledgeable and thoughtful in their sex lives
and their ketchup selection as they are in the separate aspects of writing skills? Will it come to pass with them
in the world according to whatever little they may have ''accomplished`` rather than according to what they
have done badly or failed to do?
In the absence of literacy and the habits of mind that it both induces and permits, no one can understand
anything, for understanding is not the same as knowing. What we know can be expressed in statements about
the world. What we understand has to be expressed in statements about statements about the world.
Understanding calls for classification and organization, fine distinctions, and logical testing, all related to
knowledge. All of those things can be taught in schools to very young children, but they can not be taught
where an ''impression`` of overall quality supersedes the measurement of ''separate aspects of writing skills,``
which are precisely the devices of classification and organization, fine distinctions, and logical testing. There
is thus an absolute limit imposed on what the schools can do in the zany ''educations.`` Even should the
schools be able to provide some knowledge about human sexuality, for instanceand that itself is not to be
counted on in an atmosphere hostile to mere information and rote learningthey will never be able to
provide understanding until they have first provided literacy.
That absolute limit can also be understood in social and political terms, terms of the educationists' own
devising. We have seen that even the technically skillful and ingenious, to say nothing of the educated (not
always the same thing), are beheld by the educationists with wary suspicion. They may well be the products
of that ''excellence narrowly defined`` that has fouled the air and water, and they are certainly the incipient
elitists who constitute that ''dilemma`` in the form of a ''longstanding enigma.`` Is there perhaps some
danger in a program of sex education that gets too close to ''excellence narrowly definedż` Will some lurking
''superior minds`` seize the opportunity to become more knowledgeable and thoughtful than most of their
classmates and become as skillful and effective in matters sexual as they are in designing those demonic
transistors? Will they become a sexual elite, leading prudent and orderly lives in stable families, from which
privilege the great mass of Americans is unjustly excluded? And from such a privileged elite, which uses its
thoughtfulness and knowledge exclusively in its own private interests, how can we obtain any useful output?
Since our educational system thrives on the disorders it causes, such questions are not as farfetched as they
may sound. A case in point is the new and muchtalkedof ''awareness`` among educationists of a looming
and promising problem that will bring hosts of new programs, research grants, administrators, counselors,
facilitators, and specialists: the fact that children who live with only one parent don't, as a group, do as well in
school as children from what is coming more and more to be thought of as a special case, an ''intact family.``
That is, at least in part, a problem of sexual values, attitudes, and habits. While the children who live with
only one parent may be in some personal distress, their growing numbers are good for business. The
workshops alone will provide employment for thousands. On the other hand, any significant diminution in
their numbers would be bad for business. It is not realistic to suppose that a massive governmental institution
will do anything that will someday give it less to do.
There is, in fact, no ''problemsolving in the content area,`` although there are certainly problems ''in the
content area.`` But in a government institution, there is only one area in which problems are taken seriously,
and that is the political. Many of the strange things done in American educationism suddenly become
perfectly understandable when we see them not as educational methods but as political maneuvers. We must
understand illiteracy, therefore, the root of ignorance and thoughtlessness, as not some inadvertent failure to
accomplish what was intended but simply a political arrangement of great value to somebody.
The Graves of Academe
ProblemSolving in the Content Area 79
Page No 82
Every Three Second
Educationists are entertaining. We can always find a good laugh in their prose, with its special, ludicrous
combination of ignorance and pretentiousness. It's always amusing to watch them reinventing the wheel
every few years and announcing, for instance, as some of them recently have, that children who know the
sounds of letters can actually read words they've never seen before, by golly. It's fun to consider the systems
of Lilliputian leaping and creeping by which they better their lots and advance from humble teaching to
exalted posts as curriculum facilitators, and the superintendent's speech at the athletic awards banquet usually
has that rarest of literary qualities, absolute immunity to parody. Indeed, the first thing you see when you
consider thoughtfully and in some detail the ways of American educationism is that it is funny. It's usually
the last thing you see, too, and since education is not one of the truly serious enterprises of American
civilization, like petrochemicals or banking, it doesn't seem to matter much. True, clowns and kooks seem
common in the education business, especially at the higher managerial levels, but so what? The whole
business is about nothing more than children, who don't count yet, and who can't be expected to do any
important work. We are quite ready to tolerate in curriculum and governance the same clumsy amateurism
that we find so engaging in the school play and the marching band. After all, weren't we all taught in our own
time in the schools that what really counts is the effort? And it is only when we go to the home games that
we hope to see excellence.
We tolerate the educational establishment the same way that we tolerate the children themselves, and we
therefore extend to the guidance counselors and curriculum facilitators the same immunities that we extend to
the children, the harmless children. They are all togetherover there aside from the mainstream of real life.
But anyone who will look long and carefully at what happens ''over there`` will sooner or later notice
something that doesn't seem funny. He may begin to suspect that perhaps there are some consequences to
child's play, and that maybe the children aren't so harmless after all, to say nothing of the counselors and
facilitators. It may begin to dawn on such an observer that the children in school actually are people and not
merely yettobeformed raw materials who will start to be people after the last blackboard has been
washed. Where once he tolerated the silliness of the schools as a temporary and sectarian custom in a small
fragment of real life, he now sees that the habits and attitudes so earnestly inculcated in children by silly
people will almost certainly not evaporate on commencement day. And why should they? Habits and
attitudes never evaporate. We may sometimes change them consciously, but only after skillful observation
and controlled thoughtfulness, which are generally not among the habits and attitudes that children acquire in
school. Those are the habits of literacy. The attentive and patient observer, therefore, must come to see at last
that school is not ''something else over there.`` School is America. If you want to predict the future of our
land, go to school and look around.
Schools do not fail. They succeed. Children always learn in school. Always and every day. When their rare
and tiny compositions are ''rated holistically`` without regard for separate ''aspects`` like spelling,
punctuation, capitalization, or even organization, they learn. They learn that mistakes bring no consequences.
They learn that their teachers were only pretending in all those lessons on spelling and punctuation. They
learn that there are no rewards for good work, and that they who run the race all win. They learn that
what they win is a rubberstamped smiling face, exactly as valuable as what they might lose, which is
nothing, nothing at all. They learn that the demands of life are easily satisfied with little labor, if any, and that
a show of effort is what really counts. They learn to pay attention to themselves, their wishes and fears, their
likes and dislikes, their idle whims and temperamental tendencies, all of which, idolized as ''values`` and
personological variables, are far more important than ''mere achievement`` in subject matter. The ''whole
child`` comes first, and no one learns that lesson better than the children. Just as you can predict the future by
going to school, you can decipher the past by lookingaround. All those thoughtless, unskilled, unproductive,
selfindulgent, and eminently dupable Americanswhere have they been and what did they learn there?
Every Three Second 80
Page No 83
What is done to children in schools is not inconsequential. It is not even the ''fun and games`` that might be
deplored for its own sake. It is permanent and deadly serious. Sometimes, it is simply deadly:
The Royko Papers
When you talked us in your paper you called us barbarians. It is even more rude than when
you call us delinquents. You cant compare us to 50 years ago because we dont wear knickers'
and deliver newspapers. All you Old Farts are the same. At Cominsky Park we were just
expressing our feelings about disco, because disco sucks. If you write another column like
that you will have to answer to me in person.
A letter to Mike Royko from a high school student
I was struck by a manifest shallowness in the doer [Eichmann] that made it impossible to
trace the incontestable evil of his deeds to any deeper level of roots or motives. The deeds
were monstrous, but the doer...was quite ordinary, commonplace, and neither demonic nor
monstrous. There was no sign in him of firm ideological convictions or of specific evil
motives, and the only notable characteristic one could detect in his past behavior as well as in
his behavior during the trial and throughout the pretrial police examination was something
entirely negative: it was not stupidity but thoughtlessness... Is wickedness, however we may
define it, this being ''determined to prove a villain,`` not a necessary condition for
evildoing? Might the problem of good and evil, our faculty for telling right from wrong, be
connected with our faculty of thought?
Hannah Arendt, in The Life of the Mind
Mike Royko is a columnist at the SunTimes of Chicago. His essays appear in many newspapers throughout
the country, thank goodness, for he has the habit of clear language and thought. Mike Royko wrote a column
about those eleven people who were trampled to death at a rock concert in Cincinnati. He suggested, by no
means injudiciously, that ''those who would climb over broken bodies to reach a seat in an auditorium could
be called 'the new barbarians.' `` That suggestion must have seemed less than humanistic and perhaps even
somewhat unselfesteemenhancing to a certain Robert Maszak, a teacher of English at Bloom Township
in Chicago Heights. Maszak, probably remembering his training in the teacher academy, seized for his
students this marvelous opportunity for a relevant and experiential exercise in the integration of
selfawareness aspects and the clarification of values. He had them all write letters telling Royko where to
head in, and proving, since they could write, that some teenagers were not barbarians. In fact, they couldn't,
and they are.
Royko, to be sure, had said nothing about teenagersor about the worth of rock music, which was stridently
championed in many of the letters. Maszak, however, may well be a member of the National Council of
Teachers of English, and thus both a proponent and a practitioner of ''holistic`` reading, in which the reader
must scrupulously refuse to consider what the writer actually says, a mere ''aspect`` of writing.
Maszak may also be a holistic grader, for he was not reluctant to display the fruits of his teaching, which look
like this:
Dear Tenage hater I was disapointed by what you writen on the Who concert. From what you
said I can see you have know so called barbarism. You used some strong words in there with
very little fact, you say everyone was numbed in the brain. I will say from concert experience
maybe half or three forties were high on something or nether but I allso know that theres not
one forth to half that weren't. You say everyone was pushing and throwing elbows, did you
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 81
Page No 84
ever think that some of the thrown elbows were from people who didn't like getting pushed.
You said something about when you were a kid, well times have change...
Yes. The times indeed have change. Well, let's try to be holistic. Let's ignore failures of technique and, as we
were instructed in last month's quotation from ETS, concentrate on ''what the student has accomplished rather
than on what the student has failed to do or has done badly.`` Let's remember as well the aggrieved whimpers
of the educationists who beseech us to believe that skill in writing is obviously, while useful, much less
important than humanistic things like the encouragement of selfexpression, the enhancement of selfesteem,
and the clarification of values.
Now we can understand why Maszak was untroubled by such a piece of work. It is, in fact, a testimony to the
triumph of educationism over education. That poor student, not a villain but a victim, has indeed expressed
nothing more than himself. His esteem for that forlorn and meager self is firm and truculent. And his values
are perfectly clear.
Perfectly clear, too, are the values of the few students who actually mentioned Royko's topic, the death of
eleven people. One saw it as a perfectly expectable concomitant of everybody's inalienable right to have what
he wants when he wants it. Here's his clarification of values:
If there were someone yer looked up to and yer went to see them in person and thier were
thousands of peopl just like you and wanted to see him up close would you fight yer way in?
Another shows an even keener sense of values; he gives us the very numbers by which we can reconcile
ourselves to death in Cincinnati: ''People die every three second. What would you do if you paid $15 for a
ticketż`
Eichmann must have said as much in the still watches of the night, if he ever did say anything to himself.
Jews die anyway, don't they? And Eichmann had even more than fifteen dollars at stake.
You can be sure that the humanisticists in our schools will make a profit from that last letter. They will
transform it into a ''values clarification module``: You have paid for a ticket to hear a concert by the Walking
Dead, whom yer look up to. How cheap does it have to be for you to decide that getting to your seat just isn't
worth the hassle of trampling a few people to death, people who may in any case die every three second? The
ensuing rap session will be quite long enough to provide yet another day's respite from the tedious and
dehumanizing study of language and thought.
The children who wrote the Royko papers are juniors and seniors in high school. They are probably from
sixteen to nineteen years old. They have spent eleven, twelve, or more, years in our ''humanistic,``
''valuesoriented,`` schools. What their teachers have praised as ''creativity`` looks remarkably like anarchic
selfindulgence, which is what creativity must always be in the want of discipline and skill. Their
muchencouraged ''selfexpression`` cannot be distinguished from dissolute libertinism, a virulent form of
selfexpression where there is no selfknowledge. Their ''enhanced selfesteem`` has blossomed into an
arrogant narcissism, a perversion of selfesteem where there is no idea of what is estimable.
Can we hope that Maszak's few students are unique, or at least unusual? We cannot. We know that there are
millions, millions of children who have in effect been dehumanized by the ''humanistic`` education that
smugly dismisses the mastery of knowledge and skills and the discipline of the intellect as elitist adornments
accessible, if they will have them, only to the few, and eagerly peddles to the many the mindless claptrap of
environmental awareness and career orientation and ethnic sensitivity and doing your own thing and letting it
all hang out.
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 82
Page No 85
Human beings only, of all living creatures, can know what Hannah Arendt has described as ''the claim on our
thinking attention that all events and facts make by virtue of their existence.`` She said of Eichmann ''that he
clearly knew of no such claim,`` although she does not say of him, as we might have to of Maszak's students,
that even had he known of such a claim he would have proved incapable of paying it thinking attention.
Thinking attention can be paid only in skillful language. And, for those who want to be humanistic, there is
no more distinctly human attribute than the power of language and no more distinctly human accomplishment
than thinking attention.
Go and learn those things, you humanismmongers, before you presume to instruct our children in values.
And do it fast. There isn't much time. We have read the Royko papers, and we know what you have been
doing. We have seen the future that you have fashioned for us, and, in words that even your victims will
understand, it sucks, humanisticists, and all the young farts are the same.
It is possible, of course, to make too much of what seems a smoldering savagery in the students of Robert
Maszak. But when we seek mitigation of that ominous threat to the future of an already disintegrating
civilization, we discover yet other threats. For instance, it is probably true that Maszak's teenagers are in part
striking poses designed to disturb grownups, pour épater, no doubt, le bourgeois. That is not only a child's
inalienable right, but an important part of the training of the mind. Rational thoughtfulness, after all, is not
and should not be the ordinary condition of daily human life; it is a stance that we assume, if we can, when
appropriate. Even if we are able to do the work of logical thinking, we do not, unless we are John Stuart Mill,
perhaps, do it except in response to a summons, exactly the summons that Hannah Arendt has in mind when
she speaks of ''the claim...that all events and facts make by virtue of their existence.`` Attentive
thoughtfulness is an aberration, an act not only rare in human experience but also an act requiring cultivation.
Thinking is not unlike playing the violin; it isn't simply natural. Even if we can do it, we don't often do it.
Very well, then. We admit that those teenagers are, in part at least, striking stances. But why these and only
these stances? What stance, we wonder, has their teacher himself chosen, so that they can so obviously expect
his approval? Their chosen stance is (just like their teacher's?) tiresomely ordinary and predictable; even its
virulent truculence is exactly what ''tough`` teenagers suppose ''stylish.`` It pretends to express an
independence, especially an independence of the outworn values of grownups who wore knickers and
delivered newspapers, but it in fact expresses the opposite, for it is nothing but a recitation of attitudes and
emotions as generally received and accepted in that milieu. ''That milieu`` includes the classroom, obviously,
and the school. It includes principally, however, the world out there, the popular, the ideology of the streets
and the movies and the music. In that sense, Maszak's classroom is the world, only less so, for it repeats what
is uttered first in the world. The agents of American educationism do not lead their students anywhere, they
follow them, and always downstream, always in the way they would go even if there were no schools.
An education, which requires the training of the mind in rational thoughtfulness, goes against the grain. It
isn't easy. It isn't even ''natural,`` as we usually mean that word. To live, even to live an ordinary and
comfortable life, requires the practice of rational thoughtfulness no more than it requires practice on the
violin. You can come and go, get and spend, work and play, choose and reject, rise and fall, live and die,
entirely in response to the suggestions without and the appetites within. You need never feel, never mind
answer, that claim that facts and events make on the thinking attention. For any value you share, any
''worthy`` emotional response to which you are led, any received opinion that you think to call ''yours,`` there
is always the justification of some fifteendollar ticket.
Furthermore, a whole culture composed of people just like you would be a very stable and peaceful one.
While the socialadjustment educationists may seem silly and ignorant, at the heart of all they do there is an
important and correctly understood truth: thoughtfulness is disruptive, and the work of an individual mind is
seldom likely to contribute to the consistent harmony of a collective social system. Therefore, while you, as
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 83
Page No 86
an individual mind, may judge that the children who wrote to Royko suggest some failure in schooling, and
while such might even be the judgment of individual minds who actually do the schooling, those same
children represent a mighty success in principle. Whatever else they might be, they are not individual minds
that will fall into the anticollective habit of thoughtful attention. They may indeed make a ruckus at a rock
concert, which is ironically only a part of the ''consistent harmony of a collective social system,`` but they
will not examine and reexamine the ideas and values that have been delivered unto them.
Those students represent another kind of success. Their schools have undertaken, at the expense of skills and
knowledge, to instill in them values. And they have values. They know what a fifteendollar ticket is worth
and that disco sucks. Those are values. They are not determinations from evidence, not descriptions of
phenomena, not conclusions from argument. They are assertions of worth. Values. They are neither unusual
nor eccentric, however repellent some may find them. But even the most intemperate critic of American
educationism cannot accuse the schools of intending to teach such values, and the people in the schools will
themselves protest that such reprehensible values are picked up not in the schools, which struggle bravely
and perhaps hopelessly against them, but from ''the society.`` They are right, and they are wrong. Certainly
the resort to violence, hedonistic selfindulgence, and the supposed worth of whatever is popular are
celebrated in ''the society.`` But why is that so? It must be because we are in the habit of accepting values out
of suggestion and example rather than of formulating them out of knowledge and thoughtfulness. And
that must be so because we have been schooled into that habit, for whose sake we have been unschooled in
the habit of thoughtful judgment, which would preclude the habit of accepting values out of suggestion and
example and make impossible the social adjustment that is the principal aim of the schools. Thoughtful
judgment is a specific antibody against uncritical susceptibility to suggestion, so it must be repressed if
schooling is to succeed. And when it is repressed successfully, through willful neglect of intellectual
discipline and mere information, schoolchildren will form their ''values`` not from the transparent
preachments of teachers who are obviously trying to con them into putting on knickers and delivering
newspapers, but from the dramatic and stylish examples of the world of the demotic.
Many pernicious consequences flow from the fact that the schools have appointed themselves inculcators of
values and that the American public, itself ''adjusted`` by the schools, has come to believe that the inculcation
of values is a legitimate aim of education. One of the worst of those consequences is now made manifest in
the current wave of sectarian demands that the schools, since they are in the values business anyway, ought
to teach not just the nonsense they have been teaching but whatever other nonsense any sufficiently noisy
group of citizens may prefer. After all, if the schools can ''teach`` doing your own thing or going with the
flow ( both of which, curiously enough, can justify any particular belief or deed), why can't they ''teach`` that
the universe is just as well described in Genesis as in geology, astronomy, paleontology, physics, biology,
and chemistry? While they preach, from one side of the mouth, a humanistic contempt for that ''excellence
narrowly defined`` that brought us all those ugly antennas, why can't they prate, from the other, about the
glories of the profit system? There is no good answer to such questions. If a taxsupported government
school system devotes itself to any values at all, it can always be made to do exactly that for any
other values at all.
One of the inevitable consequences of sixty years of antiintellectualism in the government schools is the
automatic assumption of most Americans that things like spelling and punctuation are political and
ideological badges. Those who are fussy about spelling and punctuation, and other such devices, are assumed
to be oldfashioned, conservative, and elitist, while those who care little for such traditional trivia must be
with it, liberal, and democratic. (This accords ill with another article of American folklore, according to
which it is the ''educated`` who become liberals and abandon the oldtime religion of this or that, but the
American public has been trained not to see such contradictions.) Because The Underground
Grammarian often ridicules academicians who cannot spell or punctuate or even make sense, readers
occasionally assume that it must also be against gun control and in favor of prayer in schools and a return to
McGuffey's Readers. I often had letters from strange people asking aid and comfort in such causes, all of
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 84
Page No 87
them unwitting testimony to the distress and confusion of mind that automatically equates schooling with
education and indoctrination with learning. Eventually it seemed good to write a general answer to all such
solicitations:
Guarding the Guardians of the Guards
We have been hearing both from and about groups of citizens who have organized themselves as guardians of
education and monitors of texts and techniques. Those who have written to us have praised our efforts,
claiming a common cause and expecting that we will praise, and promote, their efforts. We will not. They are
decent and wellmeaning people disturbed about the obvious disorders of education, no doubt, but their
understanding of ''education`` is as thoughtless and selfserving as that of the selfstyled professionals of
education who brought those disorders upon us.
These guardians of education, while they differ in some ways, all seem proponents of the backtobasics
frenzy, in which we find no merit. We champion mastery, and we mean mastery, not minimum competence,
in language and number not because it is the goal of education but because it is absurd to imagine an
educated person who lacks it. Having that mastery, we can make of knowledge the raw material of
thoughtfulness and judgment. Lacking it, we can make of knowledge nothing more than the substance of
training and the content of indoctrination.
The backtobasics enthusiasts, who never fail to note the paramount importance of being able to read
wantads and to write letters of application, treat the skills of number and language as subdivisions of
vocational training to be imparted and done with, as though reading a micrometer and reading a paragraph
were acts of the same nature. In one sense, literacy is a trivial skill, easily acquired and neither more nor less
valuable than those darlings of the schools, the ''life skills,`` things like shoetying and crossing at the corner.
In another sense, it is an endless and demanding enterprise that is also the ground of our knowledge and
understanding, but an enterprise little likely to entice the minds of those taught literacy as a life skill.
All unwittingly, therefore, the guardians preach the same degradation of literacy that the educationists have
so long practiced, and, strange as it might seem at first, for the same reason. The greatest mischief done in the
schools is the attempt to inculcate certain presumed ''values,`` but the guardians understand that less than
perfectly. They fancy that the mischief lies not in the inculcation of values but in the inculcation of the
educationists' values rather than the guardians' values. All would be well, they imagine, if only the school
would foster the ''right`` values. And that is why they must make of literacy a ''basic`` life skill rather than a
way of life. If you want to foster in children certain values and preclude others, you must take care that they
do not develop an appetite for knowledge and the skill to make of it the raw material of thoughtfulness and
judgment. Jefferson's words are an assertion of faith, not fact; fact may be ''selfevident,`` but ''truth`` is not.
If it were, earth would be fair, and all men glad and wise.
There is a momentous difference between coming to believe what we have often been told and deciding, as
Jefferson did, out of knowledge and thoughtful judgment, to ''hold`` something true. The former is a kind of
slavery and easy to achieve; the latter is difficult, for it requires knowledge and governed intellect, in other
words, an education, but it is freedom.
Freedom is, to be sure, frightening. There is no telling what values free people will choose to hold. Decent
and wellmeaning guardians of values were horrified by the monstrous principles of the Declaration of
Independence. It is, of course, out of fear that the guardians preach the inculcation of values, fear of
knowledge and thought.
Most of the guardians urge things like the study of history and economics ''emphasizing the benefits of the
free enterprise system.`` We wholeheartedly share the guardians' devotion to the free enterprise system, but
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 85
Page No 88
they obviously don't share our equal devotion to the study of history and economics, which will inevitably
bring the knowledge of some facts, events, and ideas that are not at all conducive to our wholehearted
devotion to the free enterprise system. When we study history from a certain point of view, we do not study
history. If our students someday discover, as in fact they will, that we were sometimes mistaken in our
knowledge of history, they will probably forgive us. But if they discover, as in fact they do, that we have
misrepresented or omitted knowledge in the service of some values, they will learn to distrust both us and
those values, as indeed they shouldand apparently do.
If our values are grounded, as we usually imagine they are, in evidence and reason, then those who can see
the evidence and who know the ways of reason are likely to adopt them. However, if we find ourselves
tampering with the evidence and tempering the power of language, the medium of reason, then perhaps we
ought to reevaluate our values. Should that prove unacceptable, we should at least be able to see that our
interest would be best served not by asking the state to promulgate our values but by forbidding the state to
promulgate any values at all. If the state can espouse some value that we love, it can, with equal justice,
espouse others that we do not love.
The guardians do differ in one important way from the educationists. The guardians have lost their nerve,
while the educationists still have plenty. The guardians, although they often wave the flag, do not truly hold
the most basic value of a free society: the belief that, given the choice, knowing and thoughtful people will
choose to continue in a free society. Those who do hold that value must guard against the guardians. But not
in the classroom.
We misunderstand the dangers of schooling. We fancy that what is at stake is some obviously needed
widespread level of competence and ability, a large population of people able to cope with the demands of a
complicated and technical system. And there is, to be sure, some danger that we will have fewer effective
people than we need. But we have at stake in the schools something far more important than that, for what is
effectively precluded by the essential and pervasive ideology of the government school system is nothing less
than individual freedom.
We could probably say many things about the unhappy schoolboy who knows the value of a ticket and even
that ''people die every three second,`` but of them all the most important is that he is not free. His beliefs and
values are not his; he is theirs. He is possessed, as anyone must be possessed who knows nothing of the claim
that all things make on our thinking attention and who lacks in any case the perfectly learnable powers and
skills of thinking attention. Which is to say that that schoolboy, in company with countless millions of other
Americans, is held captive by illiteracy, and that we have in effect voted in favor of Proposition 3, which
requires that the ignorant must be unfree if civilization is to endure. But Jefferson warned us that that might
happen. What he did not foresee, unfortunately, was that we would find a way to make it happen.
Literacy is not a skill or a collection of skills, although it surely does provide many evergrowing skills; it is
rather a way of the mind, the individual mind, for there is no other, the habit of thinking attention paid in
language in the search for understanding. It is the only guarantee of freedom and the essential attribute of
knowing and thoughtful people who can choose. For free people, basic minimum competency won't do, and
that our schools now propose that shabby substitute for literacy is clear evidence that their collectivist
ideology has nothing to do with the goal of the freedom of the individual.
A government institution serves the aims of government. The aims of even the best government, as Jefferson
warned us, are not the same as the aims of free individuals nor can they be. Free individuals, capable of
thoughtful discretion, are the necessary check to the natural propensities of what Jefferson so aptly named the
''functionaries`` of government. It must follow, therefore, that if education provides us with free individuals,
it is not in the interest of government functionaries to provide education. They must provide something else,
but they must call it ''education.`` In this respect, no government is different from any other, and in the
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 86
Page No 89
following article The Underground Grammarian explored a frightening parallel:
The Answering of Kautski
Why should we bother to reply to Kautski? He would reply to us, and we would have to reply to his reply.
There's no end to that. It will be quite enough for us to announce that Kautski is a traitor to the working class,
and everyone will understand everything. V. I. Lenin
Tyranny is always and everywhere the same, while freedom is always various. The well and truly enslaved
are dependable; we know what they will say and think and do. The free are quirky. Tyrannies may be overt
and violent or covert and insidious, but they all require the same thing, a subject population in which the
power of thought is occluded and the power of deed brought low. That's why Lenin's bolshevism and
American educationism have so much in common.
''Give me four years to teach the children,`` said Lenin, ''and the seed I have sown will never be uprooted.``
He wasn't talking about reading, writing, and arithmetic. He wanted only enough of such skills so that the
workers could puzzle out their quotas and so that a housebroken bureaucracy could get on with the business
of rural electrification. Our educationists call it Basic Minimum Competency, and they hope that we'll settle
for it as soon as they can cook up some way of convincing us that they can provide it. For Lenin, as for our
educationists, to ''teach the children`` is to ''adjust`` them into some ideology.
Lenin understood the power of that ready refuge from logical thought that is called in our schools the
''affective domain,`` the amiable Nevernever Land of the halfbaked, to whom anything they name
''humanistic`` is permitted, and of whom skillful scholarship and large knowledge are not required. Lenin
approved the ''teaching`` of values and the display, with appropriate captions, of socially acceptable ''role
models.`` He knew all too well the worth of behavior modification. He knew that indoctrination in
''citizenship`` is safer than the study of history, and that a familiarity with literature is not conducive to the
wholehearted pursuit of career objectives in the reallife situation, or arena.
On the other hand, Lenin knew that there was little risk that coherent thought would erupt in minds besieged
by endless prattle about the clarification of values. He knew that reiterated slogans can dull even a good mind
into a stupor out of which it will never arise to overthrow the sloganmakers. In this, our educationists have
followed him assiduously, justifying every new crime against freedom of language and thought by mouthing
empty slogans about ''quality education.``
''Most of the people,`` Lenin wrote, not in public, of course, but in a letter, ''just aren't capable of thinking.
The best they can do is learn the words.`` If that reminds you of those bleating sheep in Animal Farm, try to
forget them, and think instead of the lowing herds of pitiable teachertrainees, many of whom began with
good intentions and even with brains, singing for their certificates dull dirges of interpersonal interaction
outcomes enhancement and of change agent skills developed in timeaction line. Lenin's contempt was
reserved for the masses. These educationists, pretenders to egalitarianism, hold even their own students in
contempt, offering them nothing but words.
If you think it too rash to charge our educationists even as unwitting agents of tyranny and thought control,
consider these lines from a recent proclamation of the Association of California School Administrators:
''Parent choice`` proceeds from the belief that the purpose of education is to provide
individual students with an education. In fact, educating the individual is but a means to the
true end of education, which is to create a viable social order to which individuals contribute
and by which they are sustained. ''Family choice`` is, therefore, basically selfish and
antisocial in that it focuses on the ''wants`` of a single family rather than the ''needs`` of
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 87
Page No 90
society.
So what do you think? Would it suit Lenin?
And if you'd like to object, you'll see that these people also know how to answer Kautski. They'll just
pronounce you an elitist, and everybody will understand everything.
Thoughtful people will discover some reservations about the voucher system, against which the California
administrators direct their strange homily. It does assume, contrary to evidence, that the ordinary American
parent knows what an education is and prizes it, and it will provide lucrative opportunities for even more
fools and charlatans than the schools now harbor. In fact, the best thing that can be said for the voucher
system is that it clearly terrifies the educationists and drives them to admit, out of a mindless frenzy,
apparently, for the admission is most damning, that ''educating the individual is but a means to the true end
of education, which is to create a viable social order to which individuals contribute and by which they are
sustained.`` They almost certainly say exactly the same thing in the schools of Albania.
It was the American promise that free individuals would be more important than any ''social order,`` and that
it was for them to choose how best it might be formed and sustained. Nor is it suggested in the Declaration of
Independence that the individual's pursuit of his ''wants`` is ''basically selfish and antisocial`` and
antithetical to the ''needs`` of the society. But then the chances are very good that no member of the
Association of California School Administrators has pondered the meanings of the Declaration of
Independence. Indeed, as inheritors of the ideology of Cardinal Principles, the California principals have
probably never so much as read it, since ''civics should concern itself less with constitutional questions and
remote governmental functions, and should direct attention to social agencies close at hand and to the
informal activities of daily life that regard and seek the common good.``
The common good. How splendid that sounds. But when William Blake once gave his thinking attention to
the perennial cry of those who justified their deeds in the name of the common good, he had to conclude:
He who would do good to another must do it in Minute Particulars. General Good is the plea
of the scoundrel, hypocrite, flatterer; for Art and Science cannot exist but in minutely
organized Particulars.
The deepest, most pervasive theme of American educationism is the rejection of minutely organized
particulars for the sake of vaguely appreciated generalities. If the former are the substance of Art and Science,
of what are the latter the substance?
I can't think of any pat answer to that question, but I cannot help believing that those whose minds wander in
the work of vaguely appreciated generalities and who cannot give themselves to the organization of minute
particulars cannot in any sense be free, and may not, in some special sense, be fully human. If the direction of
thinking attention to the claim of events and facts is the essentially human act, performed in the essentially
human medium of language, what can we say of those who are unable to perform that act, but that they are
unfree in a state of civilization?
Rousseau had it backward. We are not born free. We are born in the chains of the random and reflexive, and
are ignorant and unreasonable by simple nature. We must learn to be free, to organize the random and detect
the reflexive, to acquire the knowledge of particulars and the powers of reason. The examined life is
impossible if we cannot examine, order, classify, define, distinguish, always in minute particulars. It was a
premise of the founders of American educationism that what they called ''ethical character`` could be
instilled, indeed, might better be instilled, without attention to intellectual discipline. Out of that premise
they devised their ''affective domain`` and set it over against the merely ''cognitive domain`` as a somewhat
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 88
Page No 91
more than equal and independent principality, where they might wander comfortably among the
unmeasurables, the feelings and sentiments and values and ''worthy emotional responses.`` Of that affective
domain I must now say four things, which, although I have to put them in some order, are equally important:
>
It is out of resort to the affective domain that educationists can palm off as ''education`` everything
from folk dancing to bulletin board decoration and visits to nursing homes, and, at the same time, so
neglect the merely cognitive disciplines that they can spend twelve whole years in the teaching of
something as simple as conventional punctuation and still fail to teach it.
>
The affective domain is a logical absurdity. Feelings, sentiments, values, and responses have causes,
attributes, and consequences. We can know nothing of them, we can neither understand nor judge
them, without the work of the intellect in the organization of minute particulars. You may call
''affective`` whatever you please, but you cannot deal with it unless you are cognitive.
>
The feelings, sentiments, values, and responses of our children, or of any citizens, are none of the
government's damned business. That we must support a government agency that gives itself to the
emotional and ideological manipulation of citizens is infamous. That it should, out of that intrusive
manipulation, provide us with who can say how many young citizens who cannot think coherently
but who do ''appreciate`` the value of a fifteendollar ticket to a rock concert is an unspeakable
outrage.
>
It is the supposed existence and paramountcy of the affective domain that have made the teachers'
colleges what they are, nurseries of selfindulgence, unskilled ''creativity,`` and halfbaked
pseudometaphysical incantation. Silly as it may seem, training in the efficient storage of chalk and
erasers would actually be of more value to the incipient schoolteacher than a whole experiential
continuum of intercultural awarenessenhancement, but if teachertraining were devoted only to the
cognitive it could be very quickly accomplished by very few people. The professionals of education
can justify their continued employment in great numbers only if they can convince us that they alone
can initiate supplicants into the mysteries. It is only in the cognitive domain, which they scorn, that
charlatanism is readily unmasked.
Nevertheless, and although the colonists could hardly have been more oppressed by the king than we are by
the schools, there seems to be no hope of a Declaration of Independence, to say nothing of a revolution. This
time, the people, already massively indoctrinated by the values teaching of the schools, are willing parties to
their own oppression. We want the schools to teach values, and we believe what they have told us, that
concrete knowledge and strict intellectual discipline are not only separate from ''ethical character`` but
perhaps actually impediments to that lofty goal.
The makers of Cardinal Principles were true prophets when they said that, where the formation of ''ethical
character`` was intended, the school was ''the one agency that [could] be controlled definitely and
consciously.`` And they did it. The national ''ethical character,`` whatever it may be, didn't just happen; it is
the result of definite and conscious control. Nor can we free ourselves from that control, not only accepted
but even approved by most Americans, without an enormous change in many millions of individual minds.
Such a change could be wrought only through universal public education, which is exactly what we do not
have. We have universal public schooling, which is not even close to education. The confusion between
schooling and education, which suffuses every one of the Seven Deadly Principles, and out of which the
principlemakers did their work, is what the schools have by now taught us all. It is their only triumph, the
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 89
Page No 92
only lesson they have taught universally and with complete effectiveness; but it is enough. It took them a bit
more than four years, to be sure, but they do seem to have planted a seed that can never be uprooted. Lenin
would be envious.
The Graves of Academe
Every Three Second 90
Page No 93
Afterword: Plus Ça Change
As I was approaching what I hoped would be the end of this book, I received a fat manila envelope from a
highranking staff officer in the educationistic bureaucracy of the State of New York. His letter, clipped to a
great wad of that slick and grimylooking paper that comes out of copying machines covered with that
medium gray print that always makes you want to polish your glasses, read:
Your advice and example are among the influences on the attached grant proposal to the
National Endowment for the Humanities for ''A Program of Renew Education in Basic
Humanities Disciplines.`` Because of your influence, I thought you ought to get a copy of the
proposal while we are still awaiting the results of NEH's peer review, which we should have
in March and April. I would like to hear your reaction to the proposal (which, you will note,
includes a fieldtest in New Jersey), and I hope that we will be able to call on you for advice
on the project if it is funded. Please don't hesitate to write or call me with questions or
advice.
Although the writer was not unknown to me, and although I had actually once spent a day pattering about this
and that at the headquarters of his vast bureaucracy, I could think of no way to justify calling that ''advice and
example,`` to say nothing of ''influence.`` Furthermore, I felt vaguely discomfited to be even a putative party
to that process in which one educationistic bureaucracy solicits a slice of our money from another
educationistic bureaucracy in order to remedy some newly visible deficiency caused by a third educationistic
bureaucracy. If the teachertraining academies of America had not devoted themselves for more than half a
century to militant antiintellectualism, there would now be no need for the National Endowment for the
Humanities to take some of our money and give it to the New York State Department of Education, which
will thereupon set about beginning to start to prepare to do what it damn well ought to have been doing all
along. Accordingly, in spite of my correspondent's advice not to hesitate with questions or advice, I hesitated.
As I hesitated, it dawned on me. Of course. I was looking at the latest Great Lurch Forward. The whole
history of American educationism can be told in Great Lurches Forward. When we recently noticed that even
the taxpayers had noticed that astonishingly few high school graduates could read or write, we made the
Great Lurch Forward into Basic Minimum Competency. Well, all right, said our educationists, now we know
what to do. That was what they had said when we were all so dispirited by the dread Sputnik, which Clifton
Fadiman reminded us, although in vain, was simply a flying dog in a metal box, but which frightened most of
us enough to make us turn for succor to the educationists, probably the only people around who couldn't
provide any. Aha! they said; now we know what to do. And they lurched forward. Since the day of the Great
Primal Lurch, the life adjustmentism of Cardinal Principles, they have lurched from one bold innovative
thrust to another. They have lurched out of ''selfcontained`` classrooms right back into them, lurching in the
meanwhile in and out of pods and modules. They have lurched from the old math to the new math to the
balancing of checkbooks instead of math. And now they are going to lurch into The Humanities.
The lurchers, notably imperceptive of irony in any case, see no irony at all in proposing that those who
couldn't even make us a minimally literate nation will now make us the possessors of the ''thoughtful
discretion`` of which Jefferson dreamed. Since I do know something about these lurchers in Albany who
claim my influence, I can testify that they are not cynical opportunists booking themselves cushy berths on
the next great lurch, but that is no consolation. In fact, I could wish they were cynical opportunists, for it may
well be that the false and mercenary preacher will convert, out of wellpretended zeal, more souls than will
ever be moved by decent, ineffectual honesty. And the Albany lurchers, surely decent and honest, will just as
surely prove ineffectual.
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 91
Page No 94
Like all those who imagine that it is possible to change or reform the government education system, they
seem to have a mistaken metaphor in their heads. I think they see ''the schools`` as an apparatus of some sort,
even, as many educationists unhappily call it, a ''delivery system,`` something like UPS. There are the trucks.
They exist. They even run. You can put in them and then deliver anything you choose. All we have to do is
choose. If we choose some nice humanities, we'll deliver them. But government education is not a neutral
vessel into which and out of which diverse fluids can be poured. It is not even an apparatus that can be set or
programmed to do whatever we want of it. It is more like an elaborate and complicated organism that has
inevitably evolved into exactly and only the creature that can do exactly and only what it must do to survive.
It is even more like an extensive, interlocking ecosystem, something like the Great Dismal Swamp, in which
every plant and creature, and even the air and earth and water, are what they are and do what they do because
that's the way it must be. You can shoot the tiger, or you can stay out of his way, but you cannot pronounce
him a vegetarian.
Here is just one of the objectives of the ''Language Arts/English Syllabi`` as put forth in the proposal from the
New York State Education Department, already tainted, you probably noticed, by that slash, which reveals
that no one has paid any thoughtful attention to the conjunction, and thus to the exact nature of the
relationship, between those hokey Language Arts, already infamous, and mere English:
Instruction in critical thinking will be integrated into the classroom activities of reading,
discussion, and writing about literature and other writing of recognized high quality. The
complexity and difficulty of the reading, writing, and discussion will increase progressively
from kindergarten through grade twelve.
That certainly sounds great. But, for anyone who knows something of what is done in our schools and teacher
academies, who has seen how the work of the mind is done by the theoreticians who design programs, who
has an inkling of how education is governed and directed, some questions arise. Who will provide all that
instruction in critical thinking? Will they be the teachers who have themselves been exhaustively trained in
values clarification and in relating? Will those who carried signs promoting ''Quality Educacion`` and
''Descent Wages for Teachers`` cast light on ''literature and other writing of recognized high quality``? Will
the assistant superintendent for instruction, the exshop teacher with a small real estate business on the side,
devise the parameters of the plan to integrate the instruction in critical thinking into the various classroom
activities? Will that instruction be also integrated into the making of collages for the bulletin board and the
appreciation of other cultures at the Christmas party featuring the cookies of many lands? Who will decide,
and how, exactly what ''complexity`` is suitable for the fourth grade and what for the sixth? An exguidance
counselor turned principal? An exprincipal turned coordinator in Albany? Will the publishers and legislators
and professors of education disband their Triple Entente and leave the choice of ''literature and other writing
of recognized high quality`` to the critically thinking teachers? Will the parents, themselves unthinking
products of long years of values indoctrination and helpless against the random suggestions of any and all
indoctrinators, be tickled pink when their children bring all that critical thinking home? And you can
probably devise for yourself dozens of other depressing questions about what is in fact one tiny entry in thirty
singlespaced pages of similar ''objectives`` and schemes and devices.
Furthermore, we can see that in the schools history becomes social studies, writing becomes a communication
skill, literature becomes propaganda, and even science becomes brushing after meals. What will
''humanities`` become? I am sad to say that I have a clue, for in my own school I have seen recently a
supposed attempt to cash in on the next Great Lurch Forward, which, fortunately, failed. I say ''fortunately``
because had it succeeded we would in fact have been further than ever from the education of ''informed
discretion.``
To see why that failure was fortunate, you must first know some generally hidden things about a public
college. By ''humanities,`` for instance, we mean those studies that do not lead to clearly identifiable paying
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 92
Page No 95
jobs, and in fact we hardly ever use the word except when we have to distinguish those few and antique
disciplines from such things as teachertraining or business education, which are the routine enterprises of
the college. Furthermore, we never speak of ''the liberal arts``; we are prevented by a superstitious dread of
the kind that would prevent the surviving peasants from uttering aloud the name of Count Dracula. When we
do have to admit that all our students ought to share some body of knowledge, and can thus be passed off as
members in good standing of Western Culture, we call that what almost every other school in America calls it
''general education.`` General education, of course, is to education exactly what general science is to
science, a smattering of this and that. Nor is ''general education`` a euphemism for the liberal arts, and
certainly not for the humanities. It is, in fact, not an intellectual entity but a political device, the result of a
reluctant compromise among the teachers of everything from puppetmaking to selfawareness through
massage. It has neither center nor theme, and everyone, although for purely sectarian reasons, agrees that it is
simply a mess.
One of our subcommittees undertook to reform general education. After many months of arduous labor, the
subcommittee brought forth well, certainly not a mouse, but something more like a hydra as big as the
Ritz a hydra as it might be designed by a subcommittee, however. Its details were only mildly interesting,
but its theme was fascinating.
It derived all of its recommendations from something that you will recognize: the Student Outcomes
Principle. It began by saying, and said again and again throughout, that the ''aims`` of courses of study were
certain student outcomes, which might well be achieved which, indeed, might best be achieved not by
any traditionally practiced studies but by the ad hoc invention of innovative interdisciplinary studies and
other gimmicks.
One of the desired student outcomes, for instance, was ''an appreciation of the role of science and technology
in the modern world.`` (Yes, ''appreciation.`` Plus Ça change.) While the proposal did concede that such an
appreciation might have something to do with ''a course oriented toward [my italics, and well merited, too]
the discipline of physics, chemistry, biology, geology, or astronomy,`` it quite specifically and emphatically
rejected the quaint and elitist notion that a student ought to take a basic course in one of those disciplines.
Such a course is neither innovative nor interdisciplinary and cannot be expected, therefore, to provide that
appreciation which is the desirable student outcome. Furthermore, a basic course in some hard science
provides no opening at all for some nervous member of a shrinking education department who is also a
skillful tinkerer with automobiles and motorcycles and who could surely, as teachertrainee enrollments
decline, impart in a reallife situation a worthy appreciation of the role of science and technology in the
modern world. (Since I myself do all the typesetting and printing for The Underground Grammarian, I
suggested that I too might teach a course in the appreciation of science and technology. My printing press
itself exemplifies all of the cunning embodiments of the principles of mechanics that made the Industrial
Revolution, and every single one of Newton's famous, but now unknown, Laws of Motion can be seen at
work in that machine. And appreciated. The subcommittee members nodded emphatically, pleased to see that
a notorious slow learner was coming around. You cannot, in fact, dream up anything so preposterous that you
will not find it being taught in some school.)
The ''humanities`` are not mentioned in the proposal, although ''the human environment`` is. And there are the
''integrative studies,`` in which ''innovation and experimentation are strongly encouraged,`` and which ought
to include things like Racism, Sexism in the United States Today, or New Directions in the Search for
Meaning. For obvious reasons, the study of foreign languages is not to be considered a necessary part of
every student's general education, although there would be little harm in teaching a student to appreciate the
fact that there are foreign languages. In every respect, even in its call for a massive new bureaucracy to serve
the needs of general education, the proposal derives directly from the ideology, and often even from the very
text, of Cardinal Principles.
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 93
Page No 96
That's ominous, because there couldn't have been more than two or three members of that subcommittee who
had ever even heard of Cardinal Principles. Indeed, some of those members are so clearly devoted to things
like intellectual discipline and all that mere information that they would recoil in dismay from a clear
statement of the ideology of Cardinal Principles. This must mean that that ideology has so thoroughly seeped
into American schooling at every level that it has become the ground of who can say how many rarely
noticed and therefore rarely examined assumptions. Those assumptions are dangerous, and there can never be
the education that Jefferson intended while they are the daily food and drink of the schools. And they are.
Even the academically disciplined members of the subcommittee signed their names (what were they
thinking? were they thinking?) to this:
The realization that study areas refer to desirable outcomes and that these may be met in a
variety of ways, ways that may at times deny the customestablished claims to coveted
provinces of instruction, broadens the possibilities of curricular offerings immeasurably.
The ideologues of educationism (fortunately for us, if we will pay thoughtful attention) have so thoroughly
given themselves to their disdain of intellectual discipline that they always , and always inadvertently, reveal
some truth when they pretend to do the work of the mind in writing. It isn't true, as popular opinion fancies,
that the unskilled writer fails to make himself clear; he is far more likely to make himself all too clear. While
there is no clear meaning in the assertion that areas ''refer to`` outcomes and that outcomes can be ''met,``
there is a clear meaning in the fact that the assertion is made in such a murky way. The very use of the word
''realization`` is a mindless twitch of longing, for in no way can the Student Outcomes Principle be put forth
as some fact to be ''realized`` but only as an assertion to be believed. It is simply true that he who pauses to
choose the right word will find out what he means to mean, and he who can't will make it clear to his reader
that he is ignorant and thoughtless.
But the most unsettling revelation of that passage is of the automatic assumption that underlies the
characterization of the ''claims of disciplines`` as ''customestablished`` and ''provinces of instruction`` as
''coveted.`` What else must be true of one who automatically assumes that it is out of custom that we turn to
the scholar of history for knowledge and understanding of history? Would he also assume that it is out of
nothing more than custom that we take our shoes to the cobbler or our teeth to the dentist? What can you
guess about devotion to discipline and the love of learning in one who airily presumes that it is out of
covetousness that the physicists greedily demand the privilege of teaching the physics courses? When the
outcome seeker suggests that we might do better to teach the appreciation of history and physics by devising
innovative interdisciplinary courses to replace the customary and coveted work of the physicists and
historians, who is covetous? Such bizarre notions are not only possible but inevitable in a world where there
really are no academic disciplines, where this year's general science teacher may just as well be next year's
guidance counselor and then another year's assistant principal for instruction, where this year's professor of
curriculum facilitation will probably be next year's grants proposal coordinator and another year's supervisor
of preservice handson experiential continua. Among the educationists, who make policy and devise theory,
there is so little experience of academic discipline that they probably really can't imagine any reason other
than ''custom`` for giving the teaching of physics into the hands of the physicists. Physics, for them, is not a
concrete and complicated body of real knowledge and understanding but just one of many vaguely similar
vehicles for the enhancement of appreciation. Nor is it surprising that those who have, because the mere
teaching of general science or social studies did not arise from or command love and devotion, indeed
coveted the nobler and more lucrative work of the guidance counselor should imagine that the scholar of
history has seized his chair, in which he seems so disturbingly and unaccountably content, out of
covetousness.
What can we hope for now that such people have boldly announced their intention to devise new programs of
emphasis on the great role of the humanities in the development of Western Civilization and the powers of
knowledge and critical thought as the necessary virtues of a free society?
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 94
Page No 97
Nothing.
Or, more precisely, nothing but more of the same.
The state of American government education is simply not a ''problem`` that can be solved. It is rather an
enormous fact of life, a selfperpetuating institution elaborated from within by principle, not caprice,
governed by collective assent, not individual talent. It easily absorbs the shock of every criticism by
pretending to ''reform`` itself, only to transform and dilute whatever it claims to embrace into nothing but
more of the same. It easily swallows and digests and incorporates into its substance everything in the world
around it, popular fads and fancies just as readily as appropriately diluted new knowledge in genetics or
psychology or in any of the disciplines that it will not teach. Whatever there is in our society fastfood
merchandizing, militant homosexualism, disco dancing, supplyside economics, weird religious cultism,
futurology through computers, jogging, astrology, est, you name it will find its analogue in the schools.
The Commission for the Reorganization of Secondary Education set out to adjust the ordinary American
child, whatever that might be, to life in American society, whatever that might be. It did not clearly and fully
understand either, but who does? It nevertheless succeeded prodigiously, if only by a roundabout way. By
now the children and the children of the children of those children whom they ''adjusted`` have
become American society. In strictest truth, therefore, it may not be correct to say that the educational
system absorbs and replicates the mindless fads and the manipulative practices of society and commerce. It
may be just the other way around. After more than half a century of preparing children for life, our
government education system has prepared a life for children.
That system is a tiger that we can neither kill nor evade. To shoot the tiger is unthinkable; the consequent
social and economic upheaval would turn us from a nation of children into a nation of crazy and desperate
children, a condition from which we are now (more or less) protected not by the good offices of the schools
but by their mere existence as employers and purchasers of goods and services. Furthermore, the ideologues
and leaders of teachers' unions are indisputably correct when they recite, to the thunderous applause of
millions of government employees, the assertion that a free society's impossible without a free, public, and
universal system of education, although they are absolutely wrong in imagining that an education is what
that system in fact provides. Curiously enough, therefore, that assertion is actually an incitement to the
abolition of the public school system, for we will never find that universal education, which we do in very
fact require in a free society, in these schools.
If we do want to ''do something`` about the schools, we must begin by giving up forever the futile hope that
the educationists will do it for us if only we ask them often enough. Governmental agencies do not change
from within except for their own purposes, and their ''responses`` to external cries for change, even when well
meant, are inevitably subterfuges. However, while public education is best understood as simply another
government agency, it does differ from the IRS and the Marine Corps in one supremely important detail: it
harbors hosts of dissidents, dissidents who are themselves sick to death of what they see in the system that
demeans and subverts their best efforts. The plight of dissidents in the soviet of educationism embodies
precisely the principal thematic tension that engendered Cardinal Principles: They are individual minds and
talents caught in a system of collective ideologies and values.
Consider, for instance, the case of a certain tenthgrade English teacher in a Maryland high school. This
audacious fellow had his students read the Poetics of Aristotle and The Prince of Machiavelli as obviously
useful and thoughtprovoking adjuncts to the study of Julius Caesar. Since Aristotle and Machiavelli are not
approved by the local curriculum facilitators, the teacher, who refused to recant, was suspended without pay
for insubordination and misconduct in office. (At this writing, he is still awaiting trial, and I have no idea
what will become of him.) The superintendent of the school system where this outrage occurred was quoted
in Time (December 15, 1980) as follows:
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 95
Page No 98
I don't know whether [he] is right or wrong about the books. But in a public school system,
you have to have reasonable procedures to determine what is to be used, and the
superintendent has to uphold them...What if a teacher decided to use Playboy or Hustler? I
think the school system has an obligation to set standards and to set curriculum.
Forgive me, reader, if I fear that you may have missed the main point of this little story. If you are
exasperated at yet another suggestion that we have put the yahoos in charge of the schools, then you
have missed the main point. That superintendent, yahoo or not and it doesn't really matter is absolutely
right. He recites with perfect accuracy the principles of an ideological collectivism. Now you might say,
speaking as an individual mind that can know, understand, and judge, that the difference between
Playboy and the Poetics is obvious. It is, quite simply, a matter of worth. But a superintendent is not an
individual mind but rather a functionary of a collective ideology. It is not his function to know, understand,
and judge, but only to function appropriately according to his place in the apparatus. (That sort of ''worker``
seems superbly characterized by the word ''apparatchik,`` the best possible job description for most of the
people who ''educate`` our children.) The apparatus is not intended to distinguish what is worthy from what is
not, but what is approved from what is not. That distinction requires only knowledge of the list, and it
absolutely precludes understanding and judgment. Therefore, from the point of view of the apparatus of
which the superintendent is simply a component, there is no difference between Playboy and the Poetics. We
have thus an educational system that, exactly because it is ''values oriented,`` can by its intrinsic nature have
no values whatsoever, but only collectively derived ''standards.``
Now, if you still dream that education can be changed by the people who work in it, imagine yourself trying
to discuss that little matter with that superintendent, the man in charge of the life and work of the intellect in a
whole school system, and who says, ''I don't know whether he is right or wrong about the books.``
Remember, he speaks the truth. He doesn't know. In that imagined conference you will see a miniature but
perfectly accurate paradigm of all intentions to change the government schools.
It is instructive to notice that when dissidents are unmasked in the schools, it is usually because of a book. I
mean, of course, a book, not a textbook. A book is the permanent record of the work of a solitary human
mind, to be read, marked, learned, and inwardly digested by another solitary human mind. A committee can
no more make a book than it can play the violin, but almost every ''book`` used in schools and in
teachertraining academies is written collectively and for collective purposes. The makers of schoolbooks
are ''writers`` only in the sense that the sign painter who labels bathroom doors is a ''writer,`` or the pilot who
draws in the sky slogans in smoke. Such messages enormously dignified in schools as ''communications``
can never, however long and seemingly complex they become, provide the substance of anything more
than collective training. Education comes from books. And it goes into books. Education arises when one
mind ponders the work of another. Thus, since the elements and circumstances of an education are beyond
number, since all minds are different not only from one another but even from their earlier selves, there is no
end to understanding, no final judgment. And that is why books are so scarce in schools and why a teacher
can find himself a pariah in the ''academic`` enterprise because of an essay by Aristotle. The schools are
devoted to collective conclusions, what that superintendent calls ''standards,`` and not to the interminable
(and to educationists ''selfish and antisocial") ruminations of understanding and judgment.
A magnificent education, as countless examples attest, can come from nothing more than reading and writing.
In the one we behold the work of the solitary mind, in the other we do it, but we do it in such a way that we
can behold again, and understand, and judge, the work of a solitary mindour own. In the cause of education,
there are no substitutes for reading and writing, nor do they require any supplements. Filmstrips and
flipcharts and all the countless gimmicks and gadgets that clutter our classrooms which are, by the way,
every bit as profitable as the antennas and jet exhaust fumes so righteously deplored by our humanisticist
educationists are the trash and pollution of education and reveal the schools' corporate belief that children
are mentally crippled and must be cajoled into learning anything at all. But the gimmickry of the schools is
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 96
Page No 99
more than simple cajolery, which most students see quite clearly as something between condescension and
contempt; it is an integral and large portion of a general program designed to prevent solitude. And while the
children themselves are pestered with values clarification modules and relating sessions and group activities
lest they fall into solitude, they are also protected from dangerous exposure to the fruits of solitary thinking in
others. Committees and commissions and teaching teams and curriculum standard setters make the
filmstrips and movies and tapes and slideshows and packets of learning materials. Their very teachers,
raised in the same tradition and then doubly indoctrinated in the teacher training academies, are not solitary
minds but collective spokesmen, not minds that pursue understanding but only mouths that transmit
communications. The system will find no fault in any teacher, no matter how scant his knowledge, who is
ever mindful of awareness enhancement and the parameters of remediational strategies in meeting the felt
needs of the whole child, but it will suspend without pay a teacher who brings into class a nonstandard work
of a solitary mind.
Still, some dissidents do survive. And, because they are themselves solitary minds, some few lucky students
will find, even in the worst school, the beginnings of an education. The dissidents are those teachers we all
remember, the Miss Morrisons and the Mr. Martins who made we don't know just how some important
difference. And they will always make that important difference, although our schools of education make it
harder and harder for a solitary mind to emerge intact and independent. But they will save only a few other
solitary minds here and there. They cannot save, or reform, or even change the system. Two facts prevent
them: They are almost always teachers, privates in the ranks, the least powerful and influential people in the
schools; and, for all the good that they do now and then, their selfinterest is best served by the same
establishment that harbors and rewards the guidance counselors and curriculum facilitators and the
supervisors and superintendents and all the whole host of fools and frauds who could probably not make a
living in anything other than a government agency. They are the dissidents also government agents.
We have reached a point at which even Mencken's sound advice would be no help. Sure, we could probably
burn down all the colleges and hang all the professors, but that would still leave us with fifty state
departments of education, and a federal one, hundreds of educationistic research institutes and curriculum
development outfits, a like number of publishers and learning materials designers and manufacturers, who
knows how many awarenessorientated teachers' centers, and who can count what else, including the
National Education Association and the American Federation of Teachers. Unfortunately, burning the
colleges and hanging the professors just won't do it. Our schools, a parody of education, are impervious to
anything less than revolutionobliteration and reconstitution. But that is impossible.
In the first place, nobody cares that much. It just isn't worth the trouble. The only ones who care, although not
that much, might be the dissidents, but they can never make a revolution. In America we have rules for
revolution, and obviously good rules at that. Who would make a revolution among us is expected to pledge
thereto life, fortune, and sacred honor. Some of us dissidents (I think I can speak for them) would like no
doubt to imagine pledging our lives in some great cause, but when you get right down to it there is nothing
more at stake here than the freedom of somebody else's children. Besides, we have contracts. Whether we can
pledge our lives or not they do not specify, but they do make it clear that there is to be no tampering with the
terms and conditions of our employment. As to our fortunes, well, you know very well that we have none.
Most unaccountably, the wise and happy society of ethical characters and worthy citizens that we have
fostered for so long in our schools now seems to value us less than it values bus drivers and trash collectors.
So we can pledge no fortunes, not even our guaranteed annual increments. And as to that sacred honor, which
sounds suspiciously antiquated and elitist, you do have to admit that it is a value notoriously difficult to
clarify in group discussions. On that we must pass. The closest we might come is to pledge our tenure, but we
can't. It sounds noble, of course, but it would simply erode the standards of the profession.
But maybe things will change.
The Graves of Academe
Afterword: Plus Ça Change 97
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. The Graves of Academe, page = 4
3. Richard Mitchell, page = 4
4. Contents, page = 5
5. Foreword, page = 6
6. Propositions Three and Seven, page = 7
7. The End of the String, page = 14
8. The Wundter of It All, page = 23
9. The Seven Deadly Principles, page = 35
10. The Principles March On, page = 44
11. The Pygmies' Revenge, page = 55
12. Problem-Solving in the Content Area, page = 68
13. Every Three Second, page = 83
14. Afterword: Plus Ça Change, page = 94