Title:   Gorgias

Subject:  

Author:   Plato

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Page No 46

Page No 47

Page No 48

Page No 49

Page No 50

Page No 51

Page No 52

Page No 53

Page No 54

Page No 55

Page No 56

Page No 57

Page No 58

Page No 59

Page No 60

Page No 61

Page No 62

Page No 63

Page No 64

Page No 65

Page No 66

Page No 67

Page No 68

Page No 69

Page No 70

Page No 71

Page No 72

Page No 73

Page No 74

Page No 75

Page No 76

Page No 77

Page No 78

Page No 79

Page No 80

Page No 81

Page No 82

Page No 83

Page No 84

Page No 85

Page No 86

Page No 87

Page No 88

Page No 89

Page No 90

Page No 91

Page No 92

Page No 93

Page No 94

Page No 95

Page No 96

Page No 97

Page No 98

Page No 99

Page No 100

Bookmarks





Page No 1


Gorgias

Plato



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

Gorgias.................................................................................................................................................................1

Plato.........................................................................................................................................................1

INTRODUCTION...................................................................................................................................1

GORGIAS ..............................................................................................................................................29


Gorgias

i



Top




Page No 3


Gorgias

Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett

INTRODUCTION. 

GORGIAS  

INTRODUCTION.

In several of the dialogues of Plato, doubts have arisen among his  interpreters as to which of the various

subjects discussed in them is  the  main thesis.  The speakers have the freedom of conversation; no  severe  rules

of art restrict them, and sometimes we are inclined to  think, with  one of the dramatis personae in the

Theaetetus, that the  digressions have  the greater interest.  Yet in the most irregular of  the dialogues there is

also a certain natural growth or unity; the  beginning is not forgotten at  the end, and numerous allusions and

references are interspersed, which form  the loose connecting links of  the whole.  We must not neglect this

unity,  but neither must we  attempt to confine the Platonic dialogue on the  Procrustean bed of a  single idea.

(Compare Introduction to the Phaedrus.) 

Two tendencies seem to have beset the interpreters of Plato in this  matter.  First, they have endeavoured to

hang the dialogues upon one  another by the  slightest threads; and have thus been led to opposite  and

contradictory  assertions respecting their order and sequence.  The  mantle of  Schleiermacher has descended

upon his successors, who have  applied his  method with the most various results.  The value and use  of the

method has  been hardly, if at all, examined either by him or  them.  Secondly, they  have extended almost

indefinitely the scope of  each separate dialogue; in  this way they think that they have escaped  all difficulties,

not seeing  that what they have gained in generality  they have lost in truth and  distinctness.  Metaphysical

conceptions  easily pass into one another; and  the simpler notions of antiquity,  which we can only realize by

an effort,  imperceptibly blend with the  more familiar theories of modern philosophers.  An eye for proportion

is needed (his own art of measuring) in the study of  Plato, as well as  of other great artists.  We may hardly

admit that the  moral antithesis  of good and pleasure, or the intellectual antithesis of  knowledge and  opinion,

being and appearance, are never far off in a  Platonic  discussion.  But because they are in the background, we

should not  bring them into the foreground, or expect to discern them equally in  all  the dialogues. 

There may be some advantage in drawing out a little the main  outlines of  the building; but the use of this is

limited, and may be  easily  exaggerated.  We may give Plato too much system, and alter the  natural form  and

connection of his thoughts.  Under the idea that his  dialogues are  finished works of art, we may find a reason

for  everything, and lose the  highest characteristic of art, which is  simplicity.  Most great works  receive a new

light from a new and  original mind.  But whether these new  lights are true or only  suggestive, will depend on

their agreement with the  spirit of Plato,  and the amount of direct evidence which can be urged in  support of

them.  When a theory is running away with us, criticism does a  friendly office in counselling moderation, and

recalling us to the  indications of the text. 

Gorgias 1



Top




Page No 4


Like the Phaedrus, the Gorgias has puzzled students of Plato by the  appearance of two or more subjects.

Under the cover of rhetoric  higher  themes are introduced; the argument expands into a general view  of the

good  and evil of man.  After making an ineffectual attempt to  obtain a sound  definition of his art from

Gorgias, Socrates assumes  the existence of a  universal art of flattery or simulation having  several

branches:this is  the genus of which rhetoric is only one,  and not the highest species.  To  flattery is opposed

the true and  noble art of life which he who possesses  seeks always to impart to  others, and which at last

triumphs, if not here,  at any rate in  another world.  These two aspects of life and knowledge  appear to be  the

two leading ideas of the dialogue.  The true and the false  in  individuals and states, in the treatment of the soul

as well as of the  body, are conceived under the forms of true and false art.  In the  development of this

opposition there arise various other questions,  such as  the two famous paradoxes of Socrates (paradoxes as

they are to  the world in  general, ideals as they may be more worthily called):  (1) that to do is  worse than to

suffer evil; and (2) that when a man  has done evil he had  better be punished than unpunished; to which may

be added (3) a third  Socratic paradox or ideal, that bad men do what  they think best, but not  what they desire,

for the desire of all is  towards the good.  That pleasure  is to be distinguished from good is  proved by the

simultaneousness of  pleasure and pain, and by the  possibility of the bad having in certain  cases pleasures as

great as  those of the good, or even greater.  Not merely  rhetoricians, but  poets, musicians, and other artists, the

whole tribe of  statesmen,  past as well as present, are included in the class of  flatterers.  The  true and false

finally appear before the judgmentseat of  the gods  below. 

The dialogue naturally falls into three divisions, to which the  three  characters of Gorgias, Polus, and Callicles

respectively  correspond; and  the form and manner change with the stages of the  argument.  Socrates is

deferential towards Gorgias, playful and yet  cutting in dealing with the  youthful Polus, ironical and sarcastic

in  his encounter with Callicles.  In  the first division the question is  askedWhat is rhetoric?  To this there  is

no answer given, for  Gorgias is soon made to contradict himself by  Socrates, and the  argument is transferred

to the hands of his disciple  Polus, who rushes  to the defence of his master.  The answer has at last to  be given

by  Socrates himself, but before he can even explain his meaning to  Polus,  he must enlighten him upon the

great subject of shams or flatteries.  When Polus finds his favourite art reduced to the level of cookery, he

replies that at any rate rhetoricians, like despots, have great power.  Socrates denies that they have any real

power, and hence arise the  three  paradoxes already mentioned.  Although they are strange to him,  Polus is at

last convinced of their truth; at least, they seem to him  to follow  legitimately from the premises.  Thus the

second act of the  dialogue  closes.  Then Callicles appears on the scene, at first  maintaining that  pleasure is

good, and that might is right, and that  law is nothing but the  combination of the many weak against the few

strong.  When he is confuted  he withdraws from the argument, and  leaves Socrates to arrive at the  conclusion

by himself.  The  conclusion is that there are two kinds of  statesmanship, a higher and  a lowerthat which

makes the people better,  and that which only  flatters them, and he exhorts Callicles to choose the  higher.  The

dialogue terminates with a mythus of a final judgment, in  which there  will be no more flattery or disguise,

and no further use for  the  teaching of rhetoric. 

The characters of the three interlocutors also correspond to the  parts  which are assigned to them.  Gorgias is

the great rhetorician,  now advanced  in years, who goes from city to city displaying his  talents, and is

celebrated throughout Greece.  Like all the Sophists  in the dialogues of  Plato, he is vain and boastful, yet he

has also a  certain dignity, and is  treated by Socrates with considerable respect.  But he is no match for him  in

dialectics.  Although he has been  teaching rhetoric all his life, he is  still incapable of defining his  own art.

When his ideas begin to clear up,  he is unwilling to admit  that rhetoric can be wholly separated from justice

and injustice, and  this lingering sentiment of morality, or regard for  public opinion,  enables Socrates to detect

him in a contradiction.  Like  Protagoras,  he is described as of a generous nature; he expresses his  approbation

of Socrates' manner of approaching a question; he is quite 'one  of  Socrates' sort, ready to be refuted as well as

to refute,' and very  eager that Callicles and Socrates should have the game out.  He knows  by  experience that

rhetoric exercises great influence over other men,  but he  is unable to explain the puzzle how rhetoric can

teach  everything and know  nothing. 


Gorgias

Gorgias 2



Top




Page No 5


Polus is an impetuous youth, a runaway 'colt,' as Socrates  describes him,  who wanted originally to have taken

the place of  Gorgias under the pretext  that the old man was tired, and now avails  himself of the earliest

opportunity to enter the lists.  He is said to  be the author of a work on  rhetoric, and is again mentioned in the

Phaedrus, as the inventor of  balanced or double forms of speech  (compare Gorg.; Symp.).  At first he is

violent and illmannered, and  is angry at seeing his master overthrown.  But in the judicious hands  of

Socrates he is soon restored to goodhumour,  and compelled to  assent to the required conclusion.  Like

Gorgias, he is  overthrown  because he compromises; he is unwilling to say that to do is  fairer or  more

honourable than to suffer injustice.  Though he is  fascinated by  the power of rhetoric, and dazzled by the

splendour of  success, he is  not insensible to higher arguments.  Plato may have felt  that there  would be an

incongruity in a youth maintaining the cause of  injustice  against the world.  He has never heard the other side

of the  question,  and he listens to the paradoxes, as they appear to him, of  Socrates  with evident astonishment.

He can hardly understand the meaning  of  Archelaus being miserable, or of rhetoric being only useful in self

accusation.  When the argument with him has fairly run out, 

Callicles, in whose house they are assembled, is introduced on the  stage:  he is with difficulty convinced that

Socrates is in earnest;  for if these  things are true, then, as he says with real emotion, the  foundations of

society are upside down.  In him another type of  character is represented;  he is neither sophist nor

philosopher, but  man of the world, and an  accomplished Athenian gentleman.  He might be  described in

modern language  as a cynic or materialist, a lover of  power and also of pleasure, and  unscrupulous in his

means of attaining  both.  There is no desire on his  part to offer any compromise in the  interests of morality;

nor is any  concession made by him.  Like  Thrasymachus in the Republic, though he is  not of the same weak

and  vulgar class, he consistently maintains that might  is right.  His  great motive of action is political ambition;

in this he is  characteristically Greek.  Like Anytus in the Meno, he is the enemy of  the  Sophists; but favours

the new art of rhetoric, which he regards as  an  excellent weapon of attack and defence.  He is a despiser of

mankind as he  is of philosophy, and sees in the laws of the state only  a violation of the  order of nature, which

intended that the stronger  should govern the weaker  (compare Republic).  Like other men of the  world who

are of a speculative  turn of mind, he generalizes the bad  side of human nature, and has easily  brought down

his principles to  his practice.  Philosophy and poetry alike  supply him with  distinctions suited to his view of

human life.  He has a  good will to  Socrates, whose talents he evidently admires, while he  censures the  puerile

use which he makes of them.  He expresses a keen  intellectual  interest in the argument.  Like Anytus, again, he

has a  sympathy with  other men of the world; the Athenian statesmen of a former  generation,  who showed no

weakness and made no mistakes, such as Miltiades,  Themistocles, Pericles, are his favourites.  His ideal of

human  character  is a man of great passions and great powers, which he has  developed to the  utmost, and

which he uses in his own enjoyment and in  the government of  others.  Had Critias been the name instead of

Callicles, about whom we know  nothing from other sources, the opinions  of the man would have seemed to

reflect the history of his life. 

And now the combat deepens.  In Callicles, far more than in any  sophist or  rhetorician, is concentrated the

spirit of evil against  which Socrates is  contending, the spirit of the world, the spirit of  the many contending

against the one wise man, of which the Sophists,  as he describes them in  the Republic, are the imitators rather

than  the authors, being themselves  carried away by the great tide of public  opinion.  Socrates approaches his

antagonist warily from a distance,  with a sort of irony which touches with  a light hand both his personal  vices

(probably in allusion to some scandal  of the day) and his  servility to the populace.  At the same time, he is in

most profound  earnest, as Chaerephon remarks.  Callicles soon loses his  temper, but  the more he is irritated,

the more provoking and matter of fact  does  Socrates become.  A repartee of his which appears to have been

really  made to the 'omniscient' Hippias, according to the testimony of  Xenophon  (Mem.), is introduced.  He is

called by Callicles a popular  declaimer, and  certainly shows that he has the power, in the words of  Gorgias,

of being  'as long as he pleases,' or 'as short as he pleases'  (compare Protag.).  Callicles exhibits great ability in

defending  himself and attacking  Socrates, whom he accuses of trifling and  wordsplitting; he is scandalized

that the legitimate consequences of  his own argument should be stated in  plain terms; after the manner of

men of the world, he wishes to preserve  the decencies of life.  But he  cannot consistently maintain the bad


Gorgias

Gorgias 3



Top




Page No 6


sense  of words; and getting  confused between the abstract notions of better,  superior, stronger,  he is easily

turned round by Socrates, and only induced  to continue  the argument by the authority of Gorgias.  Once, when

Socrates  is  describing the manner in which the ambitious citizen has to identify  himself with the people, he

partially recognizes the truth of his  words. 

The Socrates of the Gorgias may be compared with the Socrates of  the  Protagoras and Meno.  As in other

dialogues, he is the enemy of  the  Sophists and rhetoricians; and also of the statesmen, whom he  regards as

another variety of the same species.  His behaviour is  governed by that of  his opponents; the least forwardness

or egotism on  their part is met by a  corresponding irony on the part of Socrates.  He must speak, for

philosophy  will not allow him to be silent.  He is  indeed more ironical and provoking  than in any other of

Plato's  writings:  for he is 'fooled to the top of his  bent' by the  worldliness of Callicles.  But he is also more

deeply in  earnest.  He  rises higher than even in the Phaedo and Crito:  at first  enveloping  his moral convictions

in a cloud of dust and dialectics, he ends  by  losing his method, his life, himself, in them.  As in the Protagoras

and  Phaedrus, throwing aside the veil of irony, he makes a speech,  but, true to  his character, not until his

adversary has refused to  answer any more  questions.  The presentiment of his own fate is  hanging over him.

He is  aware that Socrates, the single real teacher  of politics, as he ventures to  call himself, cannot safely go to

war  with the whole world, and that in the  courts of earth he will be  condemned.  But he will be justified in the

world below.  Then the  position of Socrates and Callicles will be reversed;  all those things  'unfit for ears

polite' which Callicles has prophesied as  likely to  happen to him in this life, the insulting language, the box

on  the  ears, will recoil upon his assailant.  (Compare Republic, and the  similar reversal of the position of the

lawyer and the philosopher in  the  Theaetetus). 

There is an interesting allusion to his own behaviour at the trial  of the  generals after the battle of Arginusae,

which he ironically  attributes to  his ignorance of the manner in which a vote of the  assembly should be  taken.

This is said to have happened 'last year'  (B.C. 406), and therefore  the assumed date of the dialogue has been

fixed at 405 B.C., when Socrates  would already have been an old man.  The date is clearly marked, but is

scarcely reconcilable with another  indication of time, viz. the 'recent'  usurpation of Archelaus, which

occurred in the year 413; and still less  with the 'recent' death of  Pericles, who really died twentyfour years

previously (429 B.C.) and  is afterwards reckoned among the statesmen of a  past age; or with the  mention of

Nicias, who died in 413, and is  nevertheless spoken of as a  living witness.  But we shall hereafter have  reason

to observe, that  although there is a general consistency of times  and persons in the  Dialogues of Plato, a

precise dramatic date is an  invention of his  commentators (Preface to Republic). 

The conclusion of the Dialogue is remarkable, (1) for the truly  characteristic declaration of Socrates that he is

ignorant of the true  nature and bearing of these things, while he affirms at the same time  that  no one can

maintain any other view without being ridiculous.  The  profession of ignorance reminds us of the earlier and

more exclusively  Socratic Dialogues.  But neither in them, nor in the Apology, nor in  the  Memorabilia of

Xenophon, does Socrates express any doubt of the  fundamental  truths of morality.  He evidently regards this

'among the  multitude of  questions' which agitate human life 'as the principle  which alone remains  unshaken.'

He does not insist here, any more than  in the Phaedo, on the  literal truth of the myth, but only on the

soundness of the doctrine which  is contained in it, that doing wrong  is worse than suffering, and that a  man

should be rather than seem;  for the next best thing to a man's being  just is that he should be  corrected and

become just; also that he should  avoid all flattery,  whether of himself or of others; and that rhetoric  should be

employed  for the maintenance of the right only.  The revelation  of another life  is a recapitulation of the

argument in a figure. 

(2) Socrates makes the singular remark, that he is himself the only  true  politician of his age.  In other

passages, especially in the  Apology, he  disclaims being a politician at all.  There he is  convinced that he or

any  other good man who attempted to resist the  popular will would be put to  death before he had done any

good to  himself or others.  Here he  anticipates such a fate for himself, from  the fact that he is 'the only man  of

the present day who performs his  public duties at all.'  The two points  of view are not really  inconsistent, but


Gorgias

Gorgias 4



Top




Page No 7


the difference between them is  worth noticing:  Socrates is and is not a public man.  Not in the ordinary  sense,

like  Alcibiades or Pericles, but in a higher one; and this will  sooner or  later entail the same consequences on

him.  He cannot be a  private man  if he would; neither can he separate morals from politics.  Nor  is he

unwilling to be a politician, although he foresees the dangers which  await him; but he must first become a

better and wiser man, for he as  well  as Callicles is in a state of perplexity and uncertainty.  And  yet there is  an

inconsistency:  for should not Socrates too have  taught the citizens  better than to put him to death? 

And now, as he himself says, we will 'resume the argument from the  beginning.' 

Socrates, who is attended by his inseparable disciple, Chaerephon,  meets  Callicles in the streets of Athens.

He is informed that he has  just missed  an exhibition of Gorgias, which he regrets, because he was  desirous,

not of  hearing Gorgias display his rhetoric, but of  interrogating him concerning  the nature of his art.  Callicles

proposes that they shall go with him to  his own house, where Gorgias  is staying.  There they find the great

rhetorician and his younger  friend and disciple Polus. 

SOCRATES: Put the question to him, Chaerephon. 

CHAEREPHON: What question? 

SOCRATES: Who is he?such a question as would elicit from a  man the  answer, 'I am a cobbler.' 

Polus suggests that Gorgias may be tired, and desires to answer for  him.  'Who is Gorgias?' asks Chaerephon,

imitating the manner of his  master  Socrates.  'One of the best of men, and a proficient in the  best and  noblest

of experimental arts,' etc., replies Polus, in  rhetorical and  balanced phrases.  Socrates is dissatisfied at the

length and unmeaningness  of the answer; he tells the disconcerted  volunteer that he has mistaken the  quality

for the nature of the art,  and remarks to Gorgias, that Polus has  learnt how to make a speech,  but not how to

answer a question.  He wishes  that Gorgias would answer  him.  Gorgias is willing enough, and replies to  the

question asked by  Chaerephon,that he is a rhetorician, and in Homeric  language,  'boasts himself to be a

good one.'  At the request of Socrates he  promises to be brief; for 'he can be as long as he pleases, and as  short

as  he pleases.'  Socrates would have him bestow his length on  others, and  proceeds to ask him a number of

questions, which are  answered by him to his  own great satisfaction, and with a brevity  which excites the

admiration of  Socrates.  The result of the  discussion may be summed up as follows: 

Rhetoric treats of discourse; but music and medicine, and other  particular  arts, are also concerned with

discourse; in what way then  does rhetoric  differ from them?  Gorgias draws a distinction between  the arts

which deal  with words, and the arts which have to do with  external actions.  Socrates  extends this distinction

further, and  divides all productive arts into two  classes:  (1) arts which may be  carried on in silence; and (2)

arts which  have to do with words, or in  which words are coextensive with action, such  as arithmetic,

geometry,  rhetoric.  But still Gorgias could hardly have  meant to say that  arithmetic was the same as rhetoric.

Even in the arts  which are  concerned with words there are differences.  What then  distinguishes  rhetoric from

the other arts which have to do with words?  'The words  which rhetoric uses relate to the best and greatest of

human  things.'  But tell me, Gorgias, what are the best?  'Health first, beauty  next,  wealth third,' in the words of

the old song, or how would you rank  them?  The arts will come to you in a body, each claiming precedence

and  saying that her own good is superior to that of the restHow will  you  choose between them?  'I should

say, Socrates, that the art of  persuasion,  which gives freedom to all men, and to individuals power  in the state,

is  the greatest good.'  But what is the exact nature of  this persuasion?is  the persevering retort:  You could

not describe  Zeuxis as a painter, or  even as a painter of figures, if there were  other painters of figures;  neither

can you define rhetoric simply as  an art of persuasion, because  there are other arts which persuade,  such as

arithmetic, which is an art of  persuasion about odd and even  numbers.  Gorgias is made to see the  necessity of

a further  limitation, and he now defines rhetoric as the art  of persuading in  the law courts, and in the

assembly, about the just and  unjust.  But  still there are two sorts of persuasion:  one which gives  knowledge,


Gorgias

Gorgias 5



Top




Page No 8


and another which gives belief without knowledge; and knowledge  is  always true, but belief may be either

true or false,there is  therefore  a further question:  which of the two sorts of persuasion  does rhetoric  effect

in courts of law and assemblies?  Plainly that  which gives belief  and not that which gives knowledge; for no

one can  impart a real knowledge  of such matters to a crowd of persons in a few  minutes.  And there is  another

point to be considered:when the  assembly meets to advise about  walls or docks or military expeditions,  the

rhetorician is not taken into  counsel, but the architect, or the  general.  How would Gorgias explain this

phenomenon?  All who intend  to become disciples, of whom there are several  in the company, and not

Socrates only, are eagerly asking:About what then  will rhetoric  teach us to persuade or advise the state? 

Gorgias illustrates the nature of rhetoric by adducing the example  of  Themistocles, who persuaded the

Athenians to build their docks and  walls,  and of Pericles, whom Socrates himself has heard speaking about

the middle  wall of the Piraeus.  He adds that he has exercised a  similar power over  the patients of his brother

Herodicus.  He could be  chosen a physician by  the assembly if he pleased, for no physician  could compete

with a  rhetorician in popularity and influence.  He  could persuade the multitude  of anything by the power of

his rhetoric;  not that the rhetorician ought to  abuse this power any more than a  boxer should abuse the art of

self  defence.  Rhetoric is a good  thing, but, like all good things, may be  unlawfully used.  Neither is  the

teacher of the art to be deemed unjust  because his pupils are  unjust and make a bad use of the lessons which

they  have learned from  him. 

Socrates would like to know before he replies, whether Gorgias will  quarrel  with him if he points out a slight

inconsistency into which he  has fallen,  or whether he, like himself, is one who loves to be  refuted.  Gorgias

declares that he is quite one of his sort, but fears  that the argument may  be tedious to the company.  The

company cheer,  and Chaerephon and Callicles  exhort them to proceed.  Socrates gently  points out the

supposed  inconsistency into which Gorgias appears to  have fallen, and which he is  inclined to think may arise

out of a  misapprehension of his own.  The  rhetorician has been declared by  Gorgias to be more persuasive to

the  ignorant than the physician, or  any other expert.  And he is said to be  ignorant, and this ignorance  of his is

regarded by Gorgias as a happy  condition, for he has escaped  the trouble of learning.  But is he as  ignorant of

just and unjust as  he is of medicine or building?  Gorgias is  compelled to admit that if  he did not know them

previously he must learn  them from his teacher as  a part of the art of rhetoric.  But he who has  learned

carpentry is a  carpenter, and he who has learned music is a  musician, and he who has  learned justice is just.

The rhetorician then  must be a just man, and  rhetoric is a just thing.  But Gorgias has already  admitted the

opposite of this, viz. that rhetoric may be abused, and that  the  rhetorician may act unjustly.  How is the

inconsistency to be  explained? 

The fallacy of this argument is twofold; for in the first place, a  man may  know justice and not be justhere

is the old confusion of the  arts and the  virtues;nor can any teacher be expected to counteract  wholly the

bent of  natural character; and secondly, a man may have a  degree of justice, but  not sufficient to prevent him

from ever doing  wrong.  Polus is naturally  exasperated at the sophism, which he is  unable to detect; of course,

he  says, the rhetorician, like every one  else, will admit that he knows  justice (how can he do otherwise when

pressed by the interrogations of  Socrates?), but he thinks that great  want of manners is shown in bringing  the

argument to such a pass.  Socrates ironically replies, that when old  men trip, the young set  them on their legs

again; and he is quite willing  to retract, if he  can be shown to be in error, but upon one condition,  which is

that  Polus studies brevity.  Polus is in great indignation at not  being  allowed to use as many words as he

pleases in the free state of  Athens.  Socrates retorts, that yet harder will be his own case, if he  is  compelled to

stay and listen to them.  After some altercation they  agree  (compare Protag.), that Polus shall ask and Socrates

answer. 

'What is the art of Rhetoric?' says Polus.  Not an art at all,  replies  Socrates, but a thing which in your book you

affirm to have  created art.  Polus asks, 'What thing?' and Socrates answers, An  experience or routine of

making a sort of delight or gratification.  'But is not rhetoric a fine  thing?'  I have not yet told you what  rhetoric

is.  Will you ask me another  questionWhat is cookery?  'What is cookery?'  An experience or routine of


Gorgias

Gorgias 6



Top




Page No 9


making a sort of  delight or gratification.  Then they are the same, or  rather fall  under the same class, and

rhetoric has still to be  distinguished from  cookery.  'What is rhetoric?' asks Polus once more.  A  part of a not

very creditable whole, which may be termed flattery, is the  reply.  'But what part?'  A shadow of a part of

politics.  This, as might  be  expected, is wholly unintelligible, both to Gorgias and Polus; and, in  order to

explain his meaning to them, Socrates draws a distinction  between  shadows or appearances and realities; e.g.

there is real  health of body or  soul, and the appearance of them; real arts and  sciences, and the  simulations of

them.  Now the soul and body have two  arts waiting upon  them, first the art of politics, which attends on  the

soul, having a  legislative part and a judicial part; and another  art attending on the  body, which has no generic

name, but may also be  described as having two  divisions, one of which is medicine and the  other gymnastic.

Corresponding  with these four arts or sciences there  are four shams or simulations of  them, mere experiences,

as they may  be termed, because they give no reason  of their own existence.  The  art of dressing up is the sham

or simulation  of gymnastic, the art of  cookery, of medicine; rhetoric is the simulation  of justice, and  sophistic

of legislation.  They may be summed up in an  arithmetical  formula: 

Tiring : gymnastic :: cookery : medicine :: sophistic :  legislation. 

And, 

Cookery : medicine :: rhetoric : the art of justice. 

And this is the true scheme of them, but when measured only by the  gratification which they procure, they

become jumbled together and  return  to their aboriginal chaos.  Socrates apologizes for the length  of his

speech, which was necessary to the explanation of the subject,  and begs  Polus not unnecessarily to retaliate

on him. 

'Do you mean to say that the rhetoricians are esteemed flatterers?'  They  are not esteemed at all.  'Why, have

they not great power, and  can they not  do whatever they desire?'  They have no power, and they  only do what

they  think best, and never what they desire; for they  never attain the true  object of desire, which is the good.

'As if  you, Socrates, would not envy  the possessor of despotic power, who can  imprison, exile, kill any one

whom  he pleases.'  But Socrates replies  that he has no wish to put any one to  death; he who kills another,  even

justly, is not to be envied, and he who  kills him unjustly is to  be pitied; it is better to suffer than to do

injustice.  He does not  consider that going about with a dagger and putting  men out of the  way, or setting a

house on fire, is real power.  To this  Polus  assents, on the ground that such acts would be punished, but he is

still of opinion that evildoers, if they are unpunished, may be happy  enough.  He instances Archelaus, son of

Perdiccas, the usurper of  Macedonia.  Does not Socrates think him happy?Socrates would like to  know

more about him; he cannot pronounce even the great king to be  happy, unless  he knows his mental and moral

condition.  Polus explains  that Archelaus was  a slave, being the son of a woman who was the slave  of Alcetas,

brother of  Perdiccas king of Macedonand he, by every  species of crime, first  murdering his uncle and then

his cousin and  halfbrother, obtained the  kingdom.  This was very wicked, and yet all  the world, including

Socrates,  would like to have his place.  Socrates  dismisses the appeal to numbers;  Polus, if he will, may

summon all the  rich men of Athens, Nicias and his  brothers, Aristocrates, the house  of Pericles, or any other

great family  this is the kind of evidence  which is adduced in courts of justice, where  truth depends upon

numbers.  But Socrates employs proof of another sort;  his appeal is to  one witness only,that is to say, the

person with whom he  is  speaking; him he will convict out of his own mouth.  And he is prepared  to show,

after his manner, that Archelaus cannot be a wicked man and  yet  happy. 

The evildoer is deemed happy if he escapes, and miserable if he  suffers  punishment; but Socrates thinks him

less miserable if he  suffers than if he  escapes.  Polus is of opinion that such a paradox  as this hardly deserves

refutation, and is at any rate sufficiently  refuted by the fact.  Socrates  has only to compare the lot of the

successful tyrant who is the envy of the  world, and of the wretch who,  having been detected in a criminal

attempt  against the state, is  crucified or burnt to death.  Socrates replies, that  if they are both  criminal they are


Gorgias

Gorgias 7



Top




Page No 10


both miserable, but that the unpunished  is the more  miserable of the two.  At this Polus laughs outright, which

leads  Socrates to remark that laughter is a new species of refutation.  Polus  replies, that he is already refuted;

for if he will take the votes of  the company, he will find that no one agrees with him.  To this  Socrates  rejoins,

that he is not a public man, and (referring to his  own conduct at  the trial of the generals after the battle of

Arginusae) is unable to take  the suffrages of any company, as he had  shown on a recent occasion; he can  only

deal with one witness at a  time, and that is the person with whom he  is arguing.  But he is  certain that in the

opinion of any man to do is  worse than to suffer  evil. 

Polus, though he will not admit this, is ready to acknowledge that  to do  evil is considered the more foul or

dishonourable of the two.  But what is  fair and what is foul; whether the terms are applied to  bodies, colours,

figures, laws, habits, studies, must they not be  defined with reference to  pleasure and utility?  Polus assents to

this  latter doctrine, and is easily  persuaded that the fouler of two things  must exceed either in pain or in  hurt.

But the doing cannot exceed  the suffering of evil in pain, and  therefore must exceed in hurt.  Thus doing is

proved by the testimony of  Polus himself to be worse or  more hurtful than suffering. 

There remains the other question:  Is a guilty man better off when  he is  punished or when he is unpunished?

Socrates replies, that what  is done  justly is suffered justly:  if the act is just, the effect is  just; if to  punish is

just, to be punished is just, and therefore  fair, and therefore  beneficent; and the benefit is that the soul is

improved.  There are three  evils from which a man may suffer, and  which affect him in estate, body,  and

soul;these are, poverty,  disease, injustice; and the foulest of these  is injustice, the evil of  the soul, because

that brings the greatest hurt.  And there are three  arts which heal these evilstrading, medicine,  justiceand

the  fairest of these is justice.  Happy is he who has never  committed  injustice, and happy in the second degree

he who has been healed  by  punishment.  And therefore the criminal should himself go to the judge  as he

would to the physician, and purge away his crime.  Rhetoric will  enable him to display his guilt in proper

colours, and to sustain  himself  and others in enduring the necessary penalty.  And similarly  if a man has  an

enemy, he will desire not to punish him, but that he  shall go unpunished  and become worse and worse, taking

care only that  he does no injury to  himself.  These are at least conceivable uses of  the art, and no others  have

been discovered by us. 

Here Callicles, who has been listening in silent amazement, asks  Chaerephon  whether Socrates is in earnest,

and on receiving the  assurance that he is,  proceeds to ask the same question of Socrates  himself.  For if such

doctrines are true, life must have been turned  upside down, and all of us  are doing the opposite of what we

ought to  be doing. 

Socrates replies in a style of playful irony, that before men can  understand one another they must have some

common feeling.  And such a  community of feeling exists between himself and Callicles, for both of  them  are

lovers, and they have both a pair of loves; the beloved of  Callicles  are the Athenian Demos and Demos the

son of Pyrilampes; the  beloved of  Socrates are Alcibiades and philosophy.  The peculiarity of  Callicles is  that

he can never contradict his loves; he changes as his  Demos changes in  all his opinions; he watches the

countenance of both  his loves, and repeats  their sentiments, and if any one is surprised  at his sayings and

doings,  the explanation of them is, that he is not  a free agent, but must always be  imitating his two loves.  And

this is  the explanation of Socrates'  peculiarities also.  He is always  repeating what his mistress, Philosophy,  is

saying to him, who unlike  his other love, Alcibiades, is ever the same,  ever true.  Callicles  must refute her, or

he will never be at unity with  himself; and  discord in life is far worse than the discord of musical  sounds. 

Callicles answers, that Gorgias was overthrown because, as Polus  said, in  compliance with popular prejudice

he had admitted that if his  pupil did not  know justice the rhetorician must teach him; and Polus  has been

similarly  entangled, because his modesty led him to admit  that to suffer is more  honourable than to do

injustice.  By custom  'yes,' but not by nature, says  Callicles.  And Socrates is always  playing between the two

points of view,  and putting one in the place  of the other.  In this very argument, what  Polus only meant in a

conventional sense has been affirmed by him to be a  law of nature.  For convention says that 'injustice is


Gorgias

Gorgias 8



Top




Page No 11


dishonourable,' but  nature  says that 'might is right.'  And we are always taming down the  nobler  spirits among

us to the conventional level.  But sometimes a great  man  will rise up and reassert his original rights, trampling

under foot all  our formularies, and then the light of natural justice shines forth.  Pindar says, 'Law, the king of

all, does violence with high hand;' as  is  indeed proved by the example of Heracles, who drove off the oxen of

Geryon  and never paid for them. 

This is the truth, Socrates, as you will be convinced, if you leave  philosophy and pass on to the real business

of life.  A little  philosophy  is an excellent thing; too much is the ruin of a man.  He  who has not  'passed his

metaphysics' before he has grown up to manhood  will never know  the world.  Philosophers are ridiculous

when they take  to politics, and I  dare say that politicians are equally ridiculous  when they take to  philosophy:

'Every man,' as Euripides says, 'is  fondest of that in which  he is best.'  Philosophy is graceful in  youth, like the

lisp of infancy,  and should be cultivated as a part of  education; but when a grownup man  lisps or studies

philosophy, I  should like to beat him.  None of those  overrefined natures ever come  to any good; they avoid

the busy haunts of  men, and skulk in corners,  whispering to a few admiring youths, and never  giving

utterance to any  noble sentiments. 

For you, Socrates, I have a regard, and therefore I say to you, as  Zethus  says to Amphion in the play, that you

have 'a noble soul  disguised in a  puerile exterior.'  And I would have you consider the  danger which you and

other philosophers incur.  For you would not know  how to defend yourself if  any one accused you in a

lawcourt,there  you would stand, with gaping  mouth and dizzy brain, and might be  murdered, robbed,

boxed on the ears  with impunity.  Take my advice,  then, and get a little common sense; leave  to others these

frivolities; walk in the ways of the wealthy and be wise. 

Socrates professes to have found in Callicles the philosopher's  touchstone;  and he is certain that any opinion

in which they both  agree must be the  very truth.  Callicles has all the three qualities  which are needed in a

criticknowledge, goodwill, frankness; Gorgias  and Polus, although  learned men, were too modest, and

their modesty  made them contradict  themselves.  But Callicles is welleducated; and  he is not too modest to

speak out (of this he has already given  proof), and his goodwill is shown  both by his own profession and by

his giving the same caution against  philosophy to Socrates, which  Socrates remembers hearing him give long

ago  to his own clique of  friends.  He will pledge himself to retract any error  into which he  may have fallen,

and which Callicles may point out.  But he  would like  to know first of all what he and Pindar mean by natural

justice.  Do  they suppose that the rule of justice is the rule of the stronger or of  the better?'  'There is no

difference.'  Then are not the many  superior to  the one, and the opinions of the many better?  And their  opinion

is that  justice is equality, and that to do is more  dishonourable than to suffer  wrong.  And as they are the

superior or  stronger, this opinion of theirs  must be in accordance with natural as  well as conventional justice.

'Why  will you continue splitting words?  Have I not told you that the superior  is the better?'  But what do  you

mean by the better?  Tell me that, and  please to be a little  milder in your language, if you do not wish to drive

me away.  'I mean  the worthier, the wiser.'  You mean to say that one man  of sense ought  to rule over ten

thousand fools?  'Yes, that is my meaning.'  Ought the  physician then to have a larger share of meats and

drinks? or the  weaver to have more coats, or the cobbler larger shoes, or the farmer  more  seed?  'You are

always saying the same things, Socrates.'  Yes,  and on the  same subjects too; but you are never saying the

same  things.  For, first,  you defined the superior to be the stronger, and  then the wiser, and now  something

else;what DO you mean?  'I mean  men of political ability, who  ought to govern and to have more than  the

governed.'  Than themselves?  'What do you mean?'  I mean to say  that every man is his own governor.  'I  see

that you mean those dolts,  the temperate.  But my doctrine is, that a  man should let his desires  grow, and take

the means of satisfying them.  To  the many this is  impossible, and therefore they combine to prevent him.  But

if he is a  king, and has power, how base would he be in submitting to  them!  To  invite the common herd to be

lord over him, when he might have  the  enjoyment of all things!  For the truth is, Socrates, that luxury and

selfindulgence are virtue and happiness; all the rest is mere talk.' 


Gorgias

Gorgias 9



Top




Page No 12


Socrates compliments Callicles on his frankness in saying what  other men  only think.  According to his view,

those who want nothing  are not happy.  'Why,' says Callicles, 'if they were, stones and the  dead would be

happy.'  Socrates in reply is led into a halfserious,  halfcomic vein of  reflection.  'Who knows,' as Euripides

says,  'whether life may not be  death, and death life?'  Nay, there are  philosophers who maintain that even  in

life we are dead, and that the  body (soma) is the tomb (sema) of the  soul.  And some ingenious  Sicilian has

made an allegory, in which he  represents fools as the  uninitiated, who are supposed to be carrying water  to a

vessel, which  is full of holes, in a similarly holey sieve, and this  sieve is their  own soul.  The idea is fanciful,

but nevertheless is a  figure of a  truth which I want to make you acknowledge, viz. that the life  of  contentment

is better than the life of indulgence.  Are you disposed to  admit that?  'Far otherwise.'  Then hear another

parable.  The life of  selfcontentment and selfindulgence may be represented respectively  by two  men, who

are filling jars with streams of wine, honey,  milk,the jars of  the one are sound, and the jars of the other

leaky;  the first fils his  jars, and has no more trouble with them; the second  is always filling them,  and would

suffer extreme misery if he  desisted.  Are you of the same  opinion still?  'Yes, Socrates, and the  figure

expresses what I mean.  For  true pleasure is a perpetual  stream, flowing in and flowing out.  To be  hungry and

always eating,  to be thirsty and always drinking, and to have  all the other desires  and to satisfy them, that, as I

admit, is my idea of  happiness.'  And  to be itching and always scratching?  'I do not deny that  there may be

happiness even in that.'  And to indulge unnatural desires, if  they  are abundantly satisfied?  Callicles is

indignant at the introduction  of such topics.  But he is reminded by Socrates that they are  introduced,  not by

him, but by the maintainer of the identity of  pleasure and good.  Will Callicles still maintain this?  'Yes, for the

sake of consistency, he  will.'  The answer does not satisfy Socrates,  who fears that he is losing  his touchstone.

A profession of  seriousness on the part of Callicles  reassures him, and they proceed  with the argument.

Pleasure and good are  the same, but knowledge and  courage are not the same either with pleasure  or good, or

with one  another.  Socrates disproves the first of these  statements by showing  that two opposites cannot

coexist, but must alternate  with one  anotherto be well and ill together is impossible.  But pleasure  and  pain

are simultaneous, and the cessation of them is simultaneous; e.g.  in the case of drinking and thirsting,

whereas good and evil are not  simultaneous, and do not cease simultaneously, and therefore pleasure  cannot

be the same as good. 

Callicles has already lost his temper, and can only be persuaded to  go on  by the interposition of Gorgias.

Socrates, having already  guarded against  objections by distinguishing courage and knowledge  from pleasure

and good,  proceeds:The good are good by the presence  of good, and the bad are bad  by the presence of

evil.  And the brave  and wise are good, and the cowardly  and foolish are bad.  And he who  feels pleasure is

good, and he who feels  pain is bad, and both feel  pleasure and pain in nearly the same degree, and  sometimes

the bad man  or coward in a greater degree.  Therefore the bad man  or coward is as  good as the brave or may

be even better. 

Callicles endeavours now to avert the inevitable absurdity by  affirming  that he and all mankind admitted

some pleasures to be good  and others bad.  The good are the beneficial, and the bad are the  hurtful, and we

should  choose the one and avoid the other.  But this,  as Socrates observes, is a  return to the old doctrine of

himself and  Polus, that all things should be  done for the sake of the good. 

Callicles assents to this, and Socrates, finding that they are  agreed in  distinguishing pleasure from good,

returns to his old  division of empirical  habits, or shams, or flatteries, which study  pleasure only, and the arts

which are concerned with the higher  interests of soul and body.  Does  Callicles agree to this division?

Callicles will agree to anything, in  order that he may get through  the argument.  Which of the arts then are

flatteries?  Fluteplaying,  harpplaying, choral exhibitions, the  dithyrambics of Cinesias are all  equally

condemned on the ground that they  give pleasure only; and  Meles the harpplayer, who was the father of

Cinesias, failed even in  that.  The stately muse of Tragedy is bent upon  pleasure, and not upon  improvement.

Poetry in general is only a rhetorical  address to a  mixed audience of men, women, and children.  And the

orators  are very  far from speaking with a view to what is best; their way is to  humour  the assembly as if they

were children. 


Gorgias

Gorgias 10



Top




Page No 13


Callicles replies, that this is only true of some of them; others  have a  real regard for their fellowcitizens.

Granted; then there are  two species  of oratory; the one a flattery, another which has a real  regard for the

citizens.  But where are the orators among whom you  find the latter?  Callicles admits that there are none

remaining, but  there were such in the  days when Themistocles, Cimon, Miltiades, and  the great Pericles were

still  alive.  Socrates replies that none of  these were true artists, setting  before themselves the duty of  bringing

order out of disorder.  The good man  and true orator has a  settled design, running through his life, to which he

conforms all his  words and actions; he desires to implant justice and  eradicate  injustice, to implant all virtue

and eradicate all vice in the  minds  of his citizens.  He is the physician who will not allow the sick man  to

indulge his appetites with a variety of meats and drinks, but  insists on  his exercising selfrestraint.  And this is

good for the  soul, and better  than the unrestrained indulgence which Callicles was  recently approving. 

Here Callicles, who had been with difficulty brought to this point,  turns  restive, and suggests that Socrates

shall answer his own  questions.  'Then,' says Socrates, 'one man must do for two;' and  though he had hoped  to

have given Callicles an 'Amphion' in return for  his 'Zethus,' he is  willing to proceed; at the same time, he

hopes  that Callicles will correct  him, if he falls into error.  He  recapitulates the advantages which he has

already won: 

The pleasant is not the same as the goodCallicles and I are  agreed about  that,but pleasure is to be

pursued for the sake of the  good, and the good  is that of which the presence makes us good; we and  all things

good have  acquired some virtue or other.  And virtue,  whether of body or soul, of  things or persons, is not

attained by  accident, but is due to order and  harmonious arrangement.  And the  soul which has order is better

than the  soul which is without order,  and is therefore temperate and is therefore  good, and the intemperate  is

bad.  And he who is temperate is also just and  brave and pious, and  has attained the perfection of goodness

and therefore  of happiness,  and the intemperate whom you approve is the opposite of all  this and  is wretched.

He therefore who would be happy must pursue  temperance  and avoid intemperance, and if possible escape

the necessity of  punishment, but if he have done wrong he must endure punishment.  In  this  way states and

individuals should seek to attain harmony, which,  as the  wise tell us, is the bond of heaven and earth, of gods

and men.  Callicles  has never discovered the power of geometrical proportion in  both worlds; he  would have

men aim at disproportion and excess.  But  if he be wrong in  this, and if selfcontrol is the true secret of

happiness, then the paradox  is true that the only use of rhetoric is  in selfaccusation, and Polus was  right in

saying that to do wrong is  worse than to suffer wrong, and Gorgias  was right in saying that the  rhetorician

must be a just man.  And you were  wrong in taunting me  with my defenceless condition, and in saying that I

might be accused  or put to death or boxed on the ears with impunity.  For I  may repeat  once more, that to

strike is worse than to be strickento do  than to  suffer.  What I said then is now made fast in adamantine

bonds.  I  myself know not the true nature of these things, but I know that no  one can  deny my words and not

be ridiculous.  To do wrong is the  greatest of evils,  and to suffer wrong is the next greatest evil.  He  who

would avoid the last  must be a ruler, or the friend of a ruler;  and to be the friend he must be  the equal of the

ruler, and must also  resemble him.  Under his protection  he will suffer no evil, but will  he also do no evil?

Nay, will he not  rather do all the evil which he  can and escape?  And in this way the  greatest of all evils will

befall  him.  'But this imitator of the tyrant,'  rejoins Callicles, 'will kill  any one who does not similarly imitate

him.'  Socrates replies that he  is not deaf, and that he has heard that repeated  many times, and can  only reply,

that a bad man will kill a good one.  'Yes,  and that is  the provoking thing.'  Not provoking to a man of sense

who is  not  studying the arts which will preserve him from danger; and this, as you  say, is the use of rhetoric

in courts of justice.  But how many other  arts  are there which also save men from death, and are yet quite

humble in their  pretensionssuch as the art of swimming, or the art  of the pilot?  Does  not the pilot do men

at least as much service as  the rhetorician, and yet  for the voyage from Aegina to Athens he does  not charge

more than two  obols, and when he disembarks is quite  unassuming in his demeanour?  The  reason is that he is

not certain  whether he has done his passengers any  good in saving them from death,  if one of them is

diseased in body, and  still more if he is diseased  in mindwho can say?  The engineer too will  often save

whole cities,  and yet you despise him, and would not allow your  son to marry his  daughter, or his son to

marry yours.  But what reason is  there in  this?  For if virtue only means the saving of life, whether your  own  or


Gorgias

Gorgias 11



Top




Page No 14


another's, you have no right to despise him or any practiser of  saving arts.  But is not virtue something

different from saving and  being  saved?  I would have you rather consider whether you ought not  to disregard

length of life, and think only how you can live best,  leaving all besides  to the will of Heaven.  For you must

not expect to  have influence either  with the Athenian Demos or with Demos the son of  Pyrilampes, unless

you  become like them.  What do you say to this? 

'There is some truth in what you are saying, but I do not entirely  believe  you.' 

That is because you are in love with Demos.  But let us have a  little more  conversation.  You remember the

two processesone which  was directed to  pleasure, the other which was directed to making men  as good as

possible.  And those who have the care of the city should  make the citizens as good as  possible.  But who

would undertake a  public building, if he had never had a  teacher of the art of building,  and had never

constructed a building  before? or who would undertake  the duty of statephysician, if he had never  cured

either himself or  any one else?  Should we not examine him before we  entrusted him with  the office?  And as

Callicles is about to enter public  life, should we  not examine him?  Whom has he made better?  For we have

already  admitted that this is the statesman's proper business.  And we must  ask the same question about

Pericles, and Cimon, and Miltiades, and  Themistocles.  Whom did they make better?  Nay, did not Pericles

make  the  citizens worse?  For he gave them pay, and at first he was very  popular  with them, but at last they

condemned him to death.  Yet  surely he would be  a bad tamer of animals who, having received them  gentle,

taught them to  kick and butt, and man is an animal; and  Pericles who had the charge of man  only made him

wilder, and more  savage and unjust, and therefore he could  not have been a good  statesman.  The same tale

might be repeated about  Cimon, Themistocles,  Miltiades.  But the charioteer who keeps his seat at  first is not

thrown out when he gains greater experience and skill.  The  inference  is, that the statesman of a past age were

no better than those of  our  own.  They may have been cleverer constructors of docks and harbours,  but they

did not improve the character of the citizens.  I have told  you  again and again (and I purposely use the same

images) that the  soul, like  the body, may be treated in two waysthere is the meaner  and the higher  art.  You

seemed to understand what I said at the time,  but when I ask you  who were the really good statesmen, you

answeras  if I asked you who were  the good trainers, and you answered, Thearion,  the baker, Mithoecus,

the  author of the Sicilian cookerybook,  Sarambus, the vintner.  And you would  be affronted if I told you that

these are a parcel of cooks who make men  fat only to make them thin.  And those whom they have fattened

applaud  them, instead of finding  fault with them, and lay the blame of their  subsequent disorders on  their

physicians.  In this respect, Callicles, you  are like them; you  applaud the statesmen of old, who pandered to

the vices  of the  citizens, and filled the city with docks and harbours, but neglected  virtue and justice.  And

when the fit of illness comes, the citizens  who in  like manner applauded Themistocles, Pericles, and others,

will  lay hold of  you and my friend Alcibiades, and you will suffer for the  misdeeds of your  predecessors.  The

old story is always being  repeated'after all his  services, the ungrateful city banished him,  or condemned

him to death.'  As  if the statesman should not have  taught the city better!  He surely cannot  blame the state for

having  unjustly used him, any more than the sophist or  teacher can find fault  with his pupils if they cheat

him.  And the sophist  and orator are in  the same case; although you admire rhetoric and despise  sophistic,

whereas sophistic is really the higher of the two.  The teacher  of the  arts takes money, but the teacher of virtue

or politics takes no  money, because this is the only kind of service which makes the  disciple  desirous of

requiting his teacher. 

Socrates concludes by finally asking, to which of the two modes of  serving  the state Callicles invites

him:'to the inferior and  ministerial one,' is  the ingenuous reply.  That is the only way of  avoiding death,

replies  Socrates; and he has heard often enough, and  would rather not hear again,  that the bad man will kill

the good.  But  he thinks that such a fate is  very likely reserved for him, because he  remarks that he is the only

person  who teaches the true art of  politics.  And very probably, as in the case  which he described to  Polus, he

may be the physician who is tried by a jury  of children.  He  cannot say that he has procured the citizens any

pleasure,  and if any  one charges him with perplexing them, or with reviling their  elders,  he will not be able to

make them understand that he has only been  actuated by a desire for their good.  And therefore there is no


Gorgias

Gorgias 12



Top




Page No 15


saying  what  his fate may be.  'And do you think that a man who is unable to  help  himself is in a good

condition?'  Yes, Callicles, if he have the  true self  help, which is never to have said or done any wrong to

himself or others.  If I had not this kind of selfhelp, I should be  ashamed; but if I die for  want of your

flattering rhetoric, I shall  die in peace.  For death is no  evil, but to go to the world below  laden with offences

is the worst of  evils.  In proof of which I will  tell you a tale: 

Under the rule of Cronos, men were judged on the day of their  death, and  when judgment had been given

upon them they departedthe  good to the  islands of the blest, the bad to the house of vengeance.  But as they

were  still living, and had their clothes on at the time  when they were being  judged, there was favouritism, and

Zeus, when he  came to the throne, was  obliged to alter the mode of procedure, and  try them after death,

having  first sent down Prometheus to take away  from them the foreknowledge of  death.  Minos,

Rhadamanthus, and Aeacus  were appointed to be the judges;  Rhadamanthus for Asia, Aeacus for  Europe, and

Minos was to hold the court  of appeal.  Now death is the  separation of soul and body, but after death  soul and

body alike  retain their characteristics; the fat man, the dandy,  the branded  slave, are all distinguishable.  Some

prince or potentate,  perhaps  even the great king himself, appears before Rhadamanthus, and he  instantly

detects him, though he knows not who he is; he sees the  scars of  perjury and iniquity, and sends him away to

the house of  torment. 

For there are two classes of souls who undergo punishmentthe  curable and  the incurable.  The curable are

those who are benefited by  their  punishment; the incurable are such as Archelaus, who benefit  others by

becoming a warning to them.  The latter class are generally  kings and  potentates; meaner persons, happily for

themselves, have not  the same power  of doing injustice.  Sisyphus and Tityus, not  Thersites, are supposed by

Homer to be undergoing everlasting  punishment.  Not that there is anything  to prevent a great man from  being

a good one, as is shown by the famous  example of Aristeides, the  son of Lysimachus.  But to Rhadamanthus

the  souls are only known as  good or bad; they are stripped of their dignities  and preferments; he  despatches

the bad to Tartarus, labelled either as  curable or  incurable, and looks with love and admiration on the soul of

some just  one, whom he sends to the islands of the blest.  Similar is the  practice of Aeacus; and Minos

overlooks them, holding a golden  sceptre, as  Odysseus in Homer saw him 

'Wielding a sceptre of gold, and giving laws to the dead.' 

My wish for myself and my fellowmen is, that we may present our  souls  undefiled to the judge in that day;

my desire in life is to be  able to meet  death.  And I exhort you, and retort upon you the  reproach which you

cast  upon me,that you will stand before the  judge, gaping, and with dizzy  brain, and any one may box you

on the  ear, and do you all manner of evil. 

Perhaps you think that this is an old wives' fable.  But you, who  are the  three wisest men in Hellas, have

nothing better to say, and no  one will  ever show that to do is better than to suffer evil.  A man  should study to

be, and not merely to seem.  If he is bad, he should  become good, and avoid  all flattery, whether of the many

or of the  few. 

Follow me, then; and if you are looked down upon, that will do you  no harm.  And when we have practised

virtue, we will betake ourselves  to politics,  but not until we are delivered from the shameful state of

ignorance and  uncertainty in which we are at present.  Let us follow  in the way of virtue  and justice, and not

in the way to which you,  Callicles, invite us; for  that way is nothing worth. 

We will now consider in order some of the principal points of the  dialogue.  Having regard (1) to the age of

Plato and the ironical  character of his  writings, we may compare him with himself, and with  other great

teachers,  and we may note in passing the objections of his  critics.  And then (2)  casting one eye upon him, we

may cast another  upon ourselves, and endeavour  to draw out the great lessons which he  teaches for all time,

stripped of  the accidental form in which they  are enveloped. 


Gorgias

Gorgias 13



Top




Page No 16


(1)  In the Gorgias, as in nearly all the other dialogues of Plato,  we are  made aware that formal logic has as yet

no existence.  The old  difficulty  of framing a definition recurs.  The illusive analogy of  the arts and the  virtues

also continues.  The ambiguity of several  words, such as nature,  custom, the honourable, the good, is not

cleared up.  The Sophists are  still floundering about the distinction  of the real and seeming.  Figures  of speech

are made the basis of  arguments.  The possibility of conceiving a  universal art or science,  which admits of

application to a particular  subjectmatter, is a  difficulty which remains unsolved, and has not  altogether

ceased to  haunt the world at the present day (compare  Charmides).  The defect of  clearness is also apparent in

Socrates himself,  unless we suppose him  to be practising on the simplicity of his opponent,  or rather perhaps

trying an experiment in dialectics.  Nothing can be more  fallacious  than the contradiction which he pretends to

have discovered in  the  answers of Gorgias (see above).  The advantages which he gains over  Polus are also

due to a false antithesis of pleasure and good, and to  an  erroneous assertion that an agent and a patient may be

described by  similar  predicates;a mistake which Aristotle partly shares and  partly corrects in  the

Nicomachean Ethics.  Traces of a 'robust  sophistry' are likewise  discernible in his argument with Callicles. 

(2)  Although Socrates professes to be convinced by reason only,  yet the  argument is often a sort of dialectical

fiction, by which he  conducts  himself and others to his own ideal of life and action.  And  we may  sometimes

wish that we could have suggested answers to his  antagonists, or  pointed out to them the rocks which lay

concealed  under the ambiguous terms  good, pleasure, and the like.  But it would  be as useless to examine his

arguments by the requirements of modern  logic, as to criticise this ideal  from a merely utilitarian point of

view.  If we say that the ideal is  generally regarded as unattainable,  and that mankind will by no means agree

in thinking that the criminal  is happier when punished than when  unpunished, any more than they  would

agree to the stoical paradox that a  man may be happy on the  rack, Plato has already admitted that the world is

against him.  Neither does he mean to say that Archelaus is tormented by  the stings  of conscience; or that the

sensations of the impaled criminal  are more  agreeable than those of the tyrant drowned in luxurious

enjoyment.  Neither is he speaking, as in the Protagoras, of virtue as a  calculation of  pleasure, an opinion

which he afterwards repudiates in  the Phaedo.  What  then is his meaning?  His meaning we shall be able  to

illustrate best by  parallel notions, which, whether justifiable by  logic or not, have always  existed among

mankind.  We must remind the  reader that Socrates himself  implies that he will be understood or  appreciated

by very few. 

He is speaking not of the consciousness of happiness, but of the  idea of  happiness.  When a martyr dies in a

good cause, when a soldier  falls in  battle, we do not suppose that death or wounds are without  pain, or that

their physical suffering is always compensated by a  mental satisfaction.  Still we regard them as happy, and

we would a  thousand times rather have  their death than a shameful life.  Nor is  this only because we believe

that  they will obtain an immortality of  fame, or that they will have crowns of  glory in another world, when

their enemies and persecutors will be  proportionably tormented.  Men  are found in a few instances to do what

is  right, without reference to  public opinion or to consequences.  And we  regard them as happy on  this ground

only, much as Socrates' friends in the  opening of the  Phaedo are described as regarding him; or as was said of

another,  'they looked upon his face as upon the face of an angel.'  We are  not  concerned to justify this idealism

by the standard of utility or public  opinion, but merely to point out the existence of such a sentiment in  the

better part of human nature. 

The idealism of Plato is founded upon this sentiment.  He would  maintain  that in some sense or other truth

and right are alone to be  sought, and  that all other goods are only desirable as means towards  these.  He is

thought to have erred in 'considering the agent only,  and making no  reference to the happiness of others, as

affected by  him.'  But the  happiness of others or of mankind, if regarded as an  end, is really quite  as ideal and

almost as paradoxical to the common  understanding as Plato's  conception of happiness.  For the greatest

happiness of the greatest number  may mean also the greatest pain of  the individual which will procure the

greatest pleasure of the  greatest number.  Ideas of utility, like those of  duty and right, may  be pushed to

unpleasant consequences.  Nor can Plato in  the Gorgias be  deemed purely selfregarding, considering that

Socrates  expressly  mentions the duty of imparting the truth when discovered to  others.  Nor must we forget


Gorgias

Gorgias 14



Top




Page No 17


that the side of ethics which regards others is  by  the ancients merged in politics.  Both in Plato and Aristotle,

as well  as in the Stoics, the social principle, though taking another form, is  really far more prominent than in

most modern treatises on ethics. 

The idealizing of suffering is one of the conceptions which have  exercised  the greatest influence on mankind.

Into the theological  import of this, or  into the consideration of the errors to which the  idea may have given

rise,  we need not now enter.  All will agree that  the ideal of the Divine  Sufferer, whose words the world would

not  receive, the man of sorrows of  whom the Hebrew prophets spoke, has  sunk deep into the heart of the

human  race.  It is a similar picture  of suffering goodness which Plato desires to  pourtray, not without an

allusion to the fate of his master Socrates.  He  is convinced that,  somehow or other, such an one must be

happy in life or  after death.  In the Republic, he endeavours to show that his happiness  would be  assured here

in a wellordered state.  But in the actual condition  of  human things the wise and good are weak and

miserable; such an one is  like a man fallen among wild beasts, exposed to every sort of wrong  and  obloquy. 

Plato, like other philosophers, is thus led on to the conclusion,  that if  'the ways of God' to man are to be

'justified,' the hopes of  another life  must be included.  If the question could have been put to  him, whether a

man dying in torments was happy still, even if, as he  suggests in the  Apology, 'death be only a long sleep,' we

can hardly  tell what would have  been his answer.  There have been a few, who,  quite independently of

rewards and punishments or of posthumous  reputation, or any other influence  of public opinion, have been

willing to sacrifice their lives for the good  of others.  It is  difficult to say how far in such cases an unconscious

hope of a future  life, or a general faith in the victory of good in the  world, may have  supported the sufferers.

But this extreme idealism is not  in  accordance with the spirit of Plato.  He supposes a day of retribution,  in

which the good are to be rewarded and the wicked punished.  Though,  as  he says in the Phaedo, no man of

sense will maintain that the  details of  the stories about another world are true, he will insist  that something of

the kind is true, and will frame his life with a  view to this unknown  future.  Even in the Republic he

introduces a  future life as an  afterthought, when the superior happiness of the  just has been established  on

what is thought to be an immutable  foundation.  At the same time he  makes a point of determining his main

thesis independently of remoter  consequences. 

(3)  Plato's theory of punishment is partly vindictive, partly  corrective.  In the Gorgias, as well as in the Phaedo

and Republic, a  few great  criminals, chiefly tyrants, are reserved as examples.  But  most men have  never had

the opportunity of attaining this preeminence  of evil.  They are  not incurable, and their punishment is

intended for  their improvement.  They are to suffer because they have sinned; like  sick men, they must go to

the physician and be healed.  On this  representation of Plato's the  criticism has been made, that the  analogy of

disease and injustice is  partial only, and that suffering,  instead of improving men, may have just  the opposite

effect. 

Like the general analogy of the arts and the virtues, the analogy  of  disease and injustice, or of medicine and

justice, is certainly  imperfect.  But ideas must be given through something; the nature of  the mind which is

unseen can only be represented under figures derived  from visible objects.  If these figures are suggestive of

some new  aspect under which the mind may  be considered, we cannot find fault  with them for not exactly

coinciding  with the ideas represented.  They  partake of the imperfect nature of  language, and must not be

construed  in too strict a manner.  That Plato  sometimes reasons from them as if  they were not figures but

realities, is  due to the defective logical  analysis of his age. 

Nor does he distinguish between the suffering which improves and  the  suffering which only punishes and

deters.  He applies to the  sphere of  ethics a conception of punishment which is really derived  from criminal

law.  He does not see that such punishment is only  negative, and supplies  no principle of moral growth or

development.  He is not far off the higher  notion of an education of man to be  begun in this world, and to be

continued in other stages of existence,  which is further developed in the  Republic.  And Christian thinkers,

who have ventured out of the beaten  track in their meditations on the  'last things,' have found a ray of light  in


Gorgias

Gorgias 15



Top




Page No 18


his writings.  But he has  not explained how or in what way punishment is  to contribute to the  improvement of

mankind.  He has not followed out the  principle which  he affirms in the Republic, that 'God is the author of

evil  only with  a view to good,' and that 'they were the better for being  punished.'  Still his doctrine of a future

state of rewards and punishments  may  be compared favourably with that perversion of Christian doctrine

which  makes the everlasting punishment of human beings depend on a brief  moment  of time, or even on the

accident of an accident.  And he has  escaped the  difficulty which has often beset divines, respecting the  future

destiny of  the meaner sort of men (Thersites and the like), who  are neither very good  nor very bad, by not

counting them worthy of  eternal damnation. 

We do Plato violence in pressing his figures of speech or chains of  argument; and not less so in asking

questions which were beyond the  horizon  of his vision, or did not come within the scope of his design.  The

main  purpose of the Gorgias is not to answer questions about a  future world, but  to place in antagonism the

true and false life, and  to contrast the  judgments and opinions of men with judgment according  to the truth.

Plato  may be accused of representing a superhuman or  transcendental virtue in the  description of the just man

in the  Gorgias, or in the companion portrait of  the philosopher in the  Theaetetus; and at the same time may be

thought to  be condemning a  state of the world which always has existed and always will  exist  among men.

But such ideals act powerfully on the imagination of  mankind.  And such condemnations are not mere

paradoxes of  philosophers,  but the natural rebellion of the higher sense of right  in man against the  ordinary

conditions of human life.  The greatest  statesmen have fallen very  far short of the political ideal, and are

therefore justly involved in the  general condemnation. 

Subordinate to the main purpose of the dialogue are some other  questions,  which may be briefly

considered: 

a.  The antithesis of good and pleasure, which as in other  dialogues is  supposed to consist in the permanent

nature of the one  compared with the  transient and relative nature of the other.  Good  and pleasure, knowledge

and sense, truth and opinion, essence and  generation, virtue and pleasure,  the real and the apparent, the

infinite and finite, harmony or beauty and  discord, dialectic and  rhetoric or poetry, are so many pairs of

opposites,  which in Plato  easily pass into one another, and are seldom kept perfectly  distinct.  And we must

not forget that Plato's conception of pleasure is  the  Heracleitean flux transferred to the sphere of human

conduct.  There is  some degree of unfairness in opposing the principle of good, which is  objective, to the

principle of pleasure, which is subjective.  For the  assertion of the permanence of good is only based on the

assumption of  its  objective character.  Had Plato fixed his mind, not on the ideal  nature of  good, but on the

subjective consciousness of happiness, that  would have  been found to be as transient and precarious as

pleasure. 

b.  The arts or sciences, when pursued without any view to truth,  or the  improvement of human life, are called

flatteries.  They are all  alike  dependent upon the opinion of mankind, from which they are  derived.  To  Plato

the whole world appears to be sunk in error, based  on selfinterest.  To this is opposed the one wise man

hardly  professing to have found truth,  yet strong in the conviction that a  virtuous life is the only good,

whether  regarded with reference to  this world or to another.  Statesmen, Sophists,  rhetoricians, poets,  are alike

brought up for judgment.  They are the  parodies of wise men,  and their arts are the parodies of true arts and

sciences.  All that  they call science is merely the result of that study of  the tempers of  the Great Beast, which

he describes in the Republic. 

c.  Various other points of contact naturally suggest themselves  between  the Gorgias and other dialogues,

especially the Republic, the  Philebus, and  the Protagoras.  There are closer resemblances both of  spirit and

language  in the Republic than in any other dialogue, the  verbal similarity tending  to show that they were

written at the same  period of Plato's life.  For the  Republic supplies that education and  training of which the

Gorgias suggests  the necessity.  The theory of  the many weak combining against the few  strong in the

formation of  society (which is indeed a partial truth), is  similar in both of them,  and is expressed in nearly the


Gorgias

Gorgias 16



Top




Page No 19


same language.  The  sufferings and fate  of the just man, the powerlessness of evil, and the  reversal of the

situation in another life, are also points of similarity.  The poets,  like the rhetoricians, are condemned because

they aim at  pleasure  only, as in the Republic they are expelled the State, because they  are  imitators, and

minister to the weaker side of human nature.  That  poetry is akin to rhetoric may be compared with the

analogous notion,  which  occurs in the Protagoras, that the ancient poets were the  Sophists of their  day.  In

some other respects the Protagoras rather  offers a contrast than a  parallel.  The character of Protagoras may be

compared with that of  Gorgias, but the conception of happiness is  different in the two dialogues;  being

described in the former,  according to the old Socratic notion, as  deferred or accumulated  pleasure, while in

the Gorgias, and in the Phaedo,  pleasure and good  are distinctly opposed. 

This opposition is carried out from a speculative point of view in  the  Philebus.  There neither pleasure nor

wisdom are allowed to be the  chief  good, but pleasure and good are not so completely opposed as in  the

Gorgias.  For innocent pleasures, and such as have no antecedent  pains, are  allowed to rank in the class of

goods.  The allusion to  Gorgias' definition  of rhetoric (Philebus; compare Gorg.), as the art  of persuasion, of

all  arts the best, for to it all things submit, not  by compulsion, but of their  own free willmarks a close and

perhaps  designed connection between the  two dialogues.  In both the ideas of  measure, order, harmony, are

the  connecting links between the  beautiful and the good. 

In general spirit and character, that is, in irony and antagonism  to public  opinion, the Gorgias most nearly

resembles the Apology,  Crito, and portions  of the Republic, and like the Philebus, though  from another point

of view,  may be thought to stand in the same  relation to Plato's theory of morals  which the Theaetetus bears

to his  theory of knowledge. 

d.  A few minor points still remain to be summed up:  (1) The  extravagant  irony in the reason which is

assigned for the pilot's  modest charge; and in  the proposed use of rhetoric as an instrument of

selfcondemnation; and in  the mighty power of geometrical equality in  both worlds.  (2) The reference  of the

mythus to the previous  discussion should not be overlooked:  the  fate reserved for incurable  criminals such as

Archelaus; the retaliation of  the box on the ears;  the nakedness of the souls and of the judges who are  stript of

the  clothes or disguises which rhetoric and public opinion have  hitherto  provided for them (compare Swift's

notion that the universe is a  suit  of clothes, Tale of a Tub).  The fiction seems to have involved Plato  in the

necessity of supposing that the soul retained a sort of  corporeal  likeness after death.  (3) The appeal of the

authority of  Homer, who says  that Odysseus saw Minos in his court 'holding a golden  sceptre,' which  gives

verisimilitude to the tale. 

It is scarcely necessary to repeat that Plato is playing 'both  sides of the  game,' and that in criticising the

characters of Gorgias  and Polus, we are  not passing any judgment on historical individuals,  but only

attempting to  analyze the 'dramatis personae' as they were  conceived by him.  Neither is  it necessary to

enlarge upon the obvious  fact that Plato is a dramatic  writer, whose real opinions cannot  always be assumed

to be those which he  puts into the mouth of  Socrates, or any other speaker who appears to have  the best of the

argument; or to repeat the observation that he is a poet as  well as a  philosopher; or to remark that he is not to

be tried by a modern  standard, but interpreted with reference to his place in the history  of  thought and the

opinion of his time. 

It has been said that the most characteristic feature of the  Gorgias is the  assertion of the right of dissent, or

private judgment.  But this mode of  stating the question is really opposed both to the  spirit of Plato and of

ancient philosophy generally.  For Plato is not  asserting any abstract  right or duty of toleration, or advantage

to be  derived from freedom of  thought; indeed, in some other parts of his  writings (e.g. Laws), he has  fairly

laid himself open to the charge of  intolerance.  No speculations had  as yet arisen respecting the  'liberty of

prophesying;' and Plato is not  affirming any abstract  right of this nature:  but he is asserting the duty  and right

of the  one wise and true man to dissent from the folly and  falsehood of the  many.  At the same time he

acknowledges the natural  result, which he  hardly seeks to avert, that he who speaks the truth to a  multitude,


Gorgias

Gorgias 17



Top




Page No 20


regardless of consequences, will probably share the fate of  Socrates. 

... 

The irony of Plato sometimes veils from us the height of idealism  to which  he soars.  When declaring truths

which the many will not  receive, he puts  on an armour which cannot be pierced by them.  The  weapons of

ridicule are  taken out of their hands and the laugh is  turned against themselves.  The  disguises which Socrates

assumes are  like the parables of the New  Testament, or the oracles of the Delphian  God; they half conceal,

half  reveal, his meaning.  The more he is in  earnest, the more ironical he  becomes; and he is never more in

earnest  or more ironical than in the  Gorgias.  He hardly troubles himself to  answer seriously the objections of

Gorgias and Polus, and therefore he  sometimes appears to be careless of the  ordinary requirements of  logic.

Yet in the highest sense he is always  logical and consistent  with himself.  The form of the argument may be

paradoxical; the  substance is an appeal to the higher reason.  He is  uttering truths  before they can be

understood, as in all ages the words of  philosophers, when they are first uttered, have found the world

unprepared  for them.  A further misunderstanding arises out of the  wildness of his  humour; he is supposed not

only by Callicles, but by  the rest of mankind,  to be jesting when he is profoundly serious.  At  length he makes

even Polus  in earnest.  Finally, he drops the  argument, and heedless any longer of the  forms of dialectic, he

loses  himself in a sort of triumph, while at the  same time he retaliates  upon his adversaries.  From this

confusion of jest  and earnest, we may  now return to the ideal truth, and draw out in a simple  form the main

theses of the dialogue. 

First Thesis: 

It is a greater evil to do than to suffer injustice. 

Compare the New Testament 

'It is better to suffer for well doing than for evil doing.'1  Pet. 

And the Sermon on the Mount 

'Blessed are they that are persecuted for righteousness'  sake.'Matt. 

The words of Socrates are more abstract than the words of Christ,  but they  equally imply that the only real

evil is moral evil.  The  righteous may  suffer or die, but they have their reward; and even if  they had no

reward,  would be happier than the wicked.  The world,  represented by Polus, is  ready, when they are asked, to

acknowledge  that injustice is dishonourable,  and for their own sakes men are  willing to punish the offender

(compare  Republic).  But they are not  equally willing to acknowledge that injustice,  even if successful, is

essentially evil, and has the nature of disease and  death.  Especially  when crimes are committed on the great

scalethe crimes  of tyrants,  ancient or modernafter a while, seeing that they cannot be  undone,  and have

become a part of history, mankind are disposed to forgive  them, not from any magnanimity or charity, but

because their feelings  are  blunted by time, and 'to forgive is convenient to them.'  The  tangle of  good and evil

can no longer be unravelled; and although they  know that the  end cannot justify the means, they feel also that

good  has often come out  of evil.  But Socrates would have us pass the same  judgment on the tyrant  now and

always; though he is surrounded by his  satellites, and has the  applauses of Europe and Asia ringing in his

ears; though he is the  civilizer or liberator of half a continent, he  is, and always will be, the  most miserable of

men.  The greatest  consequences for good or for evil  cannot alter a hair's breadth the  morality of actions

which are right or  wrong in themselves.  This is  the standard which Socrates holds up to us.  Because politics,

and  perhaps human life generally, are of a mixed nature  we must not allow  our principles to sink to the level

of our practice. 


Gorgias

Gorgias 18



Top




Page No 21


And so of private individualsto them, too, the world occasionally  speaks  of the consequences of their

actions:if they are lovers of  pleasure, they  will ruin their health; if they are false or dishonest,  they will

lose  their character.  But Socrates would speak to them, not  of what will be,  but of what isof the present

consequence of  lowering and degrading the  soul.  And all higher natures, or perhaps  all men everywhere, if

they were  not tempted by interest or passion,  would agree with himthey would rather  be the victims than

the  perpetrators of an act of treachery or of tyranny.  Reason tells them  that death comes sooner or later to all,

and is not so  great an evil  as an unworthy life, or rather, if rightly regarded, not an  evil at  all, but to a good

man the greatest good.  For in all of us there  are  slumbering ideals of truth and right, which may at any time

awaken and  develop a new life in us. 

Second Thesis: 

It is better to suffer for wrong doing than not to suffer. 

There might have been a condition of human life in which the  penalty  followed at once, and was proportioned

to the offence.  Moral  evil would  then be scarcely distinguishable from physical; mankind  would avoid vice as

they avoid pain or death.  But nature, with a view  of deepening and  enlarging our characters, has for the most

part  hidden from us the  consequences of our actions, and we can only  foresee them by an effort of  reflection.

To awaken in us this habit  of reflection is the business of  early education, which is continued  in maturer years

by observation and  experience.  The spoilt child is  in later life said to be unfortunatehe  had better have

suffered when  he was young, and been saved from suffering  afterwards.  But is not  the sovereign equally

unfortunate whose education  and manner of life  are always concealing from him the consequences of his  own

actions,  until at length they are revealed to him in some terrible  downfall,  which may, perhaps, have been

caused not by his own fault?  Another  illustration is afforded by the pauper and criminal classes, who  scarcely

reflect at all, except on the means by which they can compass  their immediate ends.  We pity them, and make

allowances for them; but  we  do not consider that the same principle applies to human actions  generally.  Not

to have been found out in some dishonesty or folly,  regarded from a  moral or religious point of view, is the

greatest of  misfortunes.  The  success of our evil doings is a proof that the gods  have ceased to strive  with us,

and have given us over to ourselves.  There is nothing to remind  us of our sins, and therefore nothing to

correct them.  Like our sorrows,  they are healed by time; 

'While rank corruption, mining all within,  Infects unseen.' 

The 'accustomed irony' of Socrates adds a corollary to the  argument:  'Would you punish your enemy, you

should allow him to  escape unpunished'  this is the true retaliation.  (Compare the  obscure verse of

Proverbs,  'Therefore if thine enemy hunger, feed  him,' etc., quoted in Romans.) 

Men are not in the habit of dwelling upon the dark side of their  own lives:  they do not easily see themselves

as others see them.  They  are very kind  and very blind to their own faults; the rhetoric of  selflove is always

pleading with them on their own behalf.  Adopting  a similar figure of  speech, Socrates would have them use

rhetoric, not  in defence but in  accusation of themselves.  As they are guided by  feeling rather than by  reason,

to their feelings the appeal must be  made.  They must speak to  themselves; they must argue with themselves;

they must paint in eloquent  words the character of their own evil  deeds.  To any suffering which they  have

deserved, they must persuade  themselves to submit.  Under the figure  there lurks a real thought,  which,

expressed in another form, admits of an  easy application to  ourselves.  For do not we too accuse as well as

excuse  ourselves?  And  we call to our aid the rhetoric of prayer and preaching,  which the  mind silently

employs while the struggle between the better and  the  worse is going on within us.  And sometimes we are too

hard upon  ourselves, because we want to restore the balance which selflove has  overthrown or disturbed;

and then again we may hear a voice as of a  parent  consoling us.  In religious diaries a sort of drama is often

enacted by the  consciences of men 'accusing or else excusing them.'  For all our life long  we are talking with

ourselves:What is thought  but speech?  What is  feeling but rhetoric?  And if rhetoric is used on  one side


Gorgias

Gorgias 19



Top




Page No 22


only we shall be  always in danger of being deceived.  And so  the words of Socrates, which at  first sounded

paradoxical, come home  to the experience of all of us. 

Third Thesis: 

We do not what we will, but what we wish. 

Socrates would teach us a lesson which we are slow to learnthat  good  intentions, and even benevolent

actions, when they are not  prompted by  wisdom, are of no value.  We believe something to be for  our good

which we  afterwards find out not to be for our good.  The  consequences may be  inevitable, for they may

follow an invariable law,  yet they may often be  the very opposite of what is expected by us.  When we

increase pauperism by  almsgiving; when we tie up property  without regard to changes of  circumstances;

when we say hastily what  we deliberately disapprove; when we  do in a moment of passion what  upon

reflection we regret; when from any  want of selfcontrol we give  another an advantage over uswe are

doing not  what we will, but what  we wish.  All actions of which the consequences are  not weighed and

foreseen, are of this impotent and paralytic sort; and the  author of  them has 'the least possible power' while

seeming to have the  greatest.  For he is actually bringing about the reverse of what he  intended.  And yet the

book of nature is open to him, in which he who  runs  may read if he will exercise ordinary attention; every

day offers  him  experiences of his own and of other men's characters, and he  passes them  unheeded by.  The

contemplation of the consequences of  actions, and the  ignorance of men in regard to them, seems to have led

Socrates to his  famous thesis:'Virtue is knowledge;' which is not so  much an error or  paradox as a half

truth, seen first in the twilight  of ethical philosophy,  but also the half of the truth which is  especially needed

in the present  age.  For as the world has grown  older men have been too apt to imagine a  right and wrong

apart from  consequences; while a few, on the other hand,  have sought to resolve  them wholly into their

consequences.  But Socrates,  or Plato for him,  neither divides nor identifies them; though the time has  not yet

arrived either for utilitarian or transcendental systems of moral  philosophy, he recognizes the two elements

which seem to lie at the  basis  of morality.  (Compare the following:  'Now, and for us, it is a  time to  Hellenize

and to praise knowing; for we have Hebraized too  much and have  overvalued doing.  But the habits and

discipline  received from Hebraism  remain for our race an eternal possession.  And  as humanity is constituted,

one must never assign the second rank  today without being ready to restore  them to the first tomorrow.'  Sir

William W. Hunter, Preface to Orissa.) 

Fourth Thesis: 

To be and not to seem is the end of life. 

The Greek in the age of Plato admitted praise to be one of the  chief  incentives to moral virtue, and to most

men the opinion of their  fellows is  a leading principle of action.  Hence a certain element of  seeming enters

into all things; all or almost all desire to appear  better than they are,  that they may win the esteem or

admiration of  others.  A man of ability can  easily feign the language of piety or  virtue; and there is an

unconscious  as well as a conscious hypocrisy  which, according to Socrates, is the worst  of the two.  Again,

there  is the sophistry of classes and professions.  There are the different  opinions about themselves and one

another which  prevail in different  ranks of society.  There is the bias given to the mind  by the study of  one

department of human knowledge to the exclusion of the  rest; and  stronger far the prejudice engendered by a

pecuniary or party  interest  in certain tenets.  There is the sophistry of law, the sophistry  of  medicine, the

sophistry of politics, the sophistry of theology.  All of  these disguises wear the appearance of the truth; some

of them are  very  ancient, and we do not easily disengage ourselves from them; for  we have  inherited them,

and they have become a part of us.  The  sophistry of an  ancient Greek sophist is nothing compared with the

sophistry of a religious  order, or of a church in which during many  ages falsehood has been  accumulating,

and everything has been said on  one side, and nothing on the  other.  The conventions and customs which  we

observe in conversation, and  the opposition of our interests when  we have dealings with one another  ('the


Gorgias

Gorgias 20



Top




Page No 23


buyer saith, it is noughtit  is nought,' etc.), are always obscuring  our sense of truth and right.  The sophistry

of human nature is far more  subtle than the deceit of  any one man.  Few persons speak freely from their  own

natures, and  scarcely any one dares to think for himself:  most of us  imperceptibly  fall into the opinions of

those around us, which we partly  help to  make.  A man who would shake himself loose from them, requires

great  force of mind; he hardly knows where to begin in the search after  truth.  On every side he is met by the

world, which is not an  abstraction  of theologians, but the most real of all things, being  another name for

ourselves when regarded collectively and subjected to  the influences of  society. 

Then comes Socrates, impressed as no other man ever was, with the  unreality  and untruthfulness of popular

opinion, and tells mankind  that they must be  and not seem.  How are they to be?  At any rate they  must have

the spirit  and desire to be.  If they are ignorant, they  must acknowledge their  ignorance to themselves; if they

are conscious  of doing evil, they must  learn to do well; if they are weak, and have  nothing in them which they

can  call themselves, they must acquire  firmness and consistency; if they are  indifferent, they must begin to

take an interest in the great questions  which surround them.  They  must try to be what they would fain appear

in  the eyes of their  fellowmen.  A single individual cannot easily change  public opinion;  but he can be true

and innocent, simple and independent; he  can know  what he does, and what he does not know; and though

not without an  effort, he can form a judgment of his own, at least in common matters.  In  his most secret

actions he can show the same high principle  (compare  Republic) which he shows when supported and

watched by public  opinion.  And  on some fitting occasion, on some question of humanity  or truth or right,

even an ordinary man, from the natural rectitude of  his disposition, may be  found to take up arms against a

whole tribe of  politicians and lawyers, and  be too much for them. 

Who is the true and who the false statesman? 

The true statesman is he who brings order out of disorder; who  first  organizes and then administers the

government of his own  country; and  having made a nation, seeks to reconcile the national  interests with those

of Europe and of mankind.  He is not a mere  theorist, nor yet a dealer in  expedients; the whole and the parts

grow  together in his mind; while the  head is conceiving, the hand is  executing.  Although obliged to descend

to  the world, he is not of the  world.  His thoughts are fixed not on power or  riches or extension of  territory, but

on an ideal state, in which all the  citizens have an  equal chance of health and life, and the highest education  is

within  the reach of all, and the moral and intellectual qualities of  every  individual are freely developed, and

'the idea of good' is the  animating principle of the whole.  Not the attainment of freedom  alone, or  of order

alone, but how to unite freedom with order is the  problem which he  has to solve. 

The statesman who places before himself these lofty aims has  undertaken a  task which will call forth all his

powers.  He must  control himself before  he can control others; he must know mankind  before he can manage

them.  He  has no private likes or dislikes; he  does not conceal personal enmity under  the disguise of moral or

political principle:  such meannesses, into which  men too often fall  unintentionally, are absorbed in the

consciousness of  his mission, and  in his love for his country and for mankind.  He will  sometimes ask  himself

what the next generation will say of him; not because  he is  careful of posthumous fame, but because he

knows that the result of  his life as a whole will then be more fairly judged.  He will take  time for  the execution

of his plans; not hurrying them on when the  mind of a nation  is unprepared for them; but like the Ruler of the

Universe Himself, working  in the appointed time, for he knows that  human life, 'if not long in  comparison

with eternity' (Republic), is  sufficient for the fulfilment of  many great purposes.  He knows, too,  that the work

will be still going on  when he is no longer here; and he  will sometimes, especially when his  powers are

failing, think of that  other 'city of which the pattern is in  heaven' (Republic). 

The false politician is the servingman of the state.  In order to  govern  men he becomes like them; their

'minds are married in  conjunction;' they  'bear themselves' like vulgar and tyrannical  masters, and he is their

obedient servant.  The true politician, if he  would rule men, must make  them like himself; he must 'educate his

party' until they cease to be a  party; he must breathe into them the  spirit which will hereafter give form  to


Gorgias

Gorgias 21



Top




Page No 24


their institutions.  Politics  with him are not a mechanism for seeming  what he is not, or for  carrying out the

will of the majority.  Himself a  representative man,  he is the representative not of the lower but of the  higher

elements  of the nation.  There is a better (as well as a worse)  public opinion  of which he seeks to lay hold; as

there is also a deeper  current of  human affairs in which he is borne up when the waves nearer the  shore  are

threatening him.  He acknowledges that he cannot take the world  by  forcetwo or three moves on the

political chess board are all that he  can fore seetwo or three weeks moves on the political chessboard are

all  that he can foreseetwo or three weeks or months are granted to  him in  which he can provide against a

coming struggle.  But he knows  also that  there are permanent principles of politics which are always  tending

to the  wellbeing of statesbetter administration, better  education, the  reconciliation of conflicting

elements, increased  security against external  enemies.  These are not 'of today or  yesterday,' but are the same

in all  times, and under all forms of  government.  Then when the storm descends and  the winds blow, though

he knows not beforehand the hour of danger, the  pilot, not like  Plato's captain in the Republic, halfblind and

deaf, but  with  penetrating eye and quick ear, is ready to take command of the ship  and guide her into port. 

The false politician asks not what is true, but what is the opinion  of the  worldnot what is right, but what is

expedient.  The only  measures of  which he approves are the measures which will pass.  He  has no intention of

fighting an uphill battle; he keeps the roadway of  politics.  He is  unwilling to incur the persecution and enmity

which  political convictions  would entail upon him.  He begins with  popularity, and in fair weather  sails

gallantly along.  But  unpopularity soon follows him.  For men expect  their leaders to be  better and wiser than

themselves:  to be their guides  in danger, their  saviours in extremity; they do not really desire them to  obey all

the  ignorant impulses of the popular mind; and if they fail them  in a  crisis they are disappointed.  Then, as

Socrates says, the cry of  ingratitude is heard, which is most unreasonable; for the people, who  have  been

taught no better, have done what might be expected of them,  and their  statesmen have received justice at their

hands. 

The true statesman is aware that he must adapt himself to times and  circumstances.  He must have allies if he

is to fight against the  world; he  must enlighten public opinion; he must accustom his  followers to act

together.  Although he is not the mere executor of  the will of the  majority, he must win over the majority to

himself.  He is their leader and  not their follower, but in order to lead he  must also follow.  He will  neither

exaggerate nor undervalue the power  of a statesman, neither  adopting the 'laissez faire' nor the 'paternal

government' principle; but  he will, whether he is dealing with  children in politics, or with full  grown men,

seek to do for the  people what the government can do for them,  and what, from imperfect  education or

deficient powers of combination, they  cannot do for  themselves.  He knows that if he does too much for them

they  will do  nothing; and that if he does nothing for them they will in some  states  of society be utterly

helpless.  For the many cannot exist without  the  few, if the material force of a country is from below, wisdom

and  experience are from above.  It is not a small part of human evils  which  kings and governments make or

cure.  The statesman is well aware  that a  great purpose carried out consistently during many years will  at last

be  executed.  He is playing for a stake which may be partly  determined by some  accident, and therefore he

will allow largely for  the unknown element of  politics.  But the game being one in which  chance and skill are

combined,  if he plays long enough he is certain  of victory.  He will not be always  consistent, for the world is

changing; and though he depends upon the  support of a party, he will  remember that he is the minister of the

whole.  He lives not for the  present, but for the future, and he is not at all sure  that he will be  appreciated

either now or then.  For he may have the  existing order of  society against him, and may not be remembered by

a  distant posterity. 

There are always discontented idealists in politics who, like  Socrates in  the Gorgias, find fault with all

statesmen past as well as  present, not  excepting the greatest names of history.  Mankind have an  uneasy

feeling  that they ought to be better governed than they are.  Just as the actual  philosopher falls short of the one

wise man, so  does the actual statesman  fall short of the ideal.  And so partly from  vanity and egotism, but

partly  also from a true sense of the faults of  eminent men, a temper of  dissatisfaction and criticism springs up

among those who are ready enough  to acknowledge the inferiority of  their own powers.  No matter whether a


Gorgias

Gorgias 22



Top




Page No 25


statesman makes high  professions or none at allthey are reduced sooner or  later to the  same level.  And

sometimes the more unscrupulous man is better  esteemed than the more conscientious, because he has not

equally  deceived  expectations.  Such sentiments may be unjust, but they are  widely spread;  we constantly find

them recurring in reviews and  newspapers, and still  oftener in private conversation. 

We may further observe that the art of government, while in some  respects  tending to improve, has in others a

tendency to degenerate,  as institutions  become more popular.  Governing for the people cannot  easily be

combined  with governing by the people:  the interests of  classes are too strong for  the ideas of the statesman

who takes a  comprehensive view of the whole.  According to Socrates the true  governor will find ruin or death

staring him  in the face, and will  only be induced to govern from the fear of being  governed by a worse  man

than himself (Republic).  And in modern times,  though the world  has grown milder, and the terrible

consequences which  Plato foretells  no longer await an English statesman, any one who is not  actuated by a

blind ambition will only undertake from a sense of duty a  work in  which he is most likely to fail; and even if

he succeed, will  rarely  be rewarded by the gratitude of his own generation. 

Socrates, who is not a politician at all, tells us that he is the  only real  politician of his time.  Let us illustrate

the meaning of  his words by  applying them to the history of our own country.  He  would have said that  not

Pitt or Fox, or Canning or Sir R. Peel, are  the real politicians of  their time, but Locke, Hume, Adam Smith,

Bentham, Ricardo.  These during  the greater part of their lives  occupied an inconsiderable space in the  eyes of

the public.  They were  private persons; nevertheless they sowed in  the minds of men seeds  which in the next

generation have become an  irresistible power.  'Herein is that saying true, One soweth and another  reapeth.'

We may  imagine with Plato an ideal statesman in whom practice  and speculation  are perfectly harmonized;

for there is no necessary  opposition between  them.  But experience shows that they are commonly

divorcedthe  ordinary politician is the interpreter or executor of the  thoughts of  others, and hardly ever

brings to the birth a new political  conception.  One or two only in modern times, like the Italian  statesman

Cavour, have created the world in which they moved.  The  philosopher is  naturally unfitted for political life;

his great ideas  are not understood  by the many; he is a thousand miles away from the  questions of the day.

Yet perhaps the lives of thinkers, as they are  stiller and deeper, are also  happier than the lives of those who

are  more in the public eye.  They have  the promise of the future, though  they are regarded as dreamers and

visionaries by their own  contemporaries.  And when they are no longer here,  those who would  have been

ashamed of them during their lives claim kindred  with them,  and are proud to be called by their names.

(Compare Thucyd.) 

Who is the true poet? 

Plato expels the poets from his Republic because they are allied to  sense;  because they stimulate the

emotions; because they are thrice  removed from  the ideal truth.  And in a similar spirit he declares in  the

Gorgias that  the stately muse of tragedy is a votary of pleasure  and not of truth.  In  modern times we almost

ridicule the idea of  poetry admitting of a moral.  The poet and the prophet, or preacher, in  primitive antiquity

are one and  the same; but in later ages they seem  to fall apart.  The great art of  novel writing, that peculiar

creation  of our own and the last century,  which, together with the sister art  of review writing, threatens to

absorb  all literature, has even less  of seriousness in her composition.  Do we not  often hear the novel  writer

censured for attempting to convey a lesson to  the minds of his  readers? 

Yet the true office of a poet or writer of fiction is not merely to  give  amusement, or to be the expression of

the feelings of mankind,  good or bad,  or even to increase our knowledge of human nature.  There  have been

poets  in modern times, such as Goethe or Wordsworth, who  have not forgotten their  high vocation of

teachers; and the two  greatest of the Greek dramatists owe  their sublimity to their ethical  character.  The

noblest truths, sung of in  the purest and sweetest  language, are still the proper material of poetry.  The poet

clothes  them with beauty, and has a power of making them enter  into the hearts  and memories of men.  He has

not only to speak of themes  above the  level of ordinary life, but to speak of them in a deeper and  tenderer


Gorgias

Gorgias 23



Top




Page No 26


way than they are ordinarily felt, so as to awaken the feeling of  them  in others.  The old he makes young

again; the familiar principle he  invests with a new dignity; he finds a noble expression for the  common

places of morality and politics.  He uses the things of sense  so as to  indicate what is beyond; he raises us

through earth to  heaven.  He  expresses what the better part of us would fain say, and  the halfconscious

feeling is strengthened by the expression.  He is  his own critic, for the  spirit of poetry and of criticism are not

divided in him.  His mission is  not to disguise men from themselves,  but to reveal to them their own  nature,

and make them better  acquainted with the world around them.  True  poetry is the remembrance  of youth, of

love, the embodiment in words of the  happiest and holiest  moments of life, of the noblest thoughts of man, of

the greatest deeds  of the past.  The poet of the future may return to his  greater calling  of the prophet or

teacher; indeed, we hardly know what may  not be  effected for the human race by a better use of the poetical

and  imaginative faculty.  The reconciliation of poetry, as of religion,  with  truth, may still be possible.  Neither

is the element of pleasure  to be  excluded.  For when we substitute a higher pleasure for a lower  we raise  men

in the scale of existence.  Might not the novelist, too,  make an ideal,  or rather many ideals of social life, better

than a  thousand sermons?  Plato, like the Puritans, is too much afraid of  poetic and artistic  influences.  But he

is not without a true sense of  the noble purposes to  which art may be applied (Republic). 

Modern poetry is often a sort of plaything, or, in Plato's  language, a  flattery, a sophistry, or sham, in which,

without any  serious purpose, the  poet lends wings to his fancy and exhibits his  gifts of language and metre.

Such an one seeks to gratify the taste of  his readers; he has the 'savoir  faire,' or trick of writing, but he  has not

the higher spirit of poetry.  He has no conception that true  art should bring order out of disorder; that  it should

make provision  for the soul's highest interest; that it should be  pursued only with a  view to 'the improvement

of the citizens.'  He  ministers to the weaker  side of human nature (Republic); he idealizes the  sensual; he sings

the strain of love in the latest fashion; instead of  raising men above  themselves he brings them back to the

'tyranny of the  many masters,'  from which all his life long a good man has been praying to  be  delivered.  And

often, forgetful of measure and order, he will express  not that which is truest, but that which is strongest.

Instead of a  great  and noblyexecuted subject, perfect in every part, some fancy of  a heated  brain is worked

out with the strangest incongruity.  He is  not the master  of his words, but his wordsperhaps borrowed from

anotherthe faded  reflection of some French or German or Italian  writer, have the better of  him.  Though we

are not going to banish the  poets, how can we suppose that  such utterances have any healing or  lifegiving

influence on the minds of  men? 

'Let us hear the conclusion of the whole matter:'  Art then must be  true,  and politics must be true, and the life

of man must be true and  not a  seeming or sham.  In all of them order has to be brought out of  disorder,  truth

out of error and falsehood.  This is what we mean by  the greatest  improvement of man.  And so, having

considered in what  way 'we can best  spend the appointed time, we leave the result with  God.' Plato does not

say  that God will order all things for the best  (compare Phaedo), but he  indirectly implies that the evils of this

life will be corrected in  another.  And as we are very far from the  best imaginable world at present,  Plato here,

as in the Phaedo and  Republic, supposes a purgatory or place of  education for mankind in  general, and for a

very few a Tartarus or hell.  The myth which  terminates the dialogue is not the revelation, but rather,  like all

similar descriptions, whether in the Bible or Plato, the veil of  another life.  For no visible thing can reveal the

invisible.  Of this  Plato, unlike some commentators on Scripture, is fully aware.  Neither  will  he dogmatize

about the manner in which we are 'born again'  (Republic).  Only he is prepared to maintain the ultimate

triumph of  truth and right,  and declares that no one, not even the wisest of the  Greeks, can affirm any  other

doctrine without being ridiculous. 

There is a further paradox of ethics, in which pleasure and pain  are held  to be indifferent, and virtue at the

time of action and  without regard to  consequences is happiness.  From this elevation or  exaggeration of

feeling  Plato seems to shrink:  he leaves it to the  Stoics in a later generation to  maintain that when impaled or

on the  rack the philosopher may be happy  (compare Republic).  It is  observable that in the Republic he raises

this  question, but it is not  really discussed; the veil of the ideal state, the  shadow of another  life, are allowed

to descend upon it and it passes out of  sight.  The  martyr or sufferer in the cause of right or truth is often


Gorgias

Gorgias 24



Top




Page No 27


supposed to  die in raptures, having his eye fixed on a city which is in  heaven.  But if there were no future,

might he not still be happy in the  performance of an action which was attended only by a painful death?  He

himself may be ready to thank God that he was thought worthy to do  Him the  least service, without looking

for a reward; the joys of  another life may  not have been present to his mind at all.  Do we  suppose that the

mediaeval  saint, St. Bernard, St. Francis, St.  Catharine of Sienna, or the Catholic  priest who lately devoted

himself  to death by a lingering disease that he  might solace and help others,  was thinking of the 'sweets' of

heaven?  No;  the work was already  heaven to him and enough.  Much less will the dying  patriot be  dreaming

of the praises of man or of an immortality of fame:  the sense  of duty, of right, and trust in God will be

sufficient, and as  far as  the mind can reach, in that hour.  If he were certain that there  were  no life to come, he

would not have wished to speak or act otherwise  than he did in the cause of truth or of humanity.  Neither, on

the  other  hand, will he suppose that God has forsaken him or that the  future is to be  a mere blank to him.  The

greatest act of faith, the  only faith which  cannot pass away, is his who has not known, but yet  has believed.  A

very  few among the sons of men have made themselves  independent of  circumstances, past, present, or to

come.  He who has  attained to such a  temper of mind has already present with him eternal  life; he needs no

arguments to convince him of immortality; he has in  him already a principle  stronger than death.  He who

serves man  without the thought of reward is  deemed to be a more faithful servant  than he who works for hire.

May not  the service of God, which is the  more disinterested, be in like manner the  higher?  And although only

a  very few in the course of the world's history  Christ himself being  one of themhave attained to such a

noble  conception of God and of  the human soul, yet the ideal of them may be  present to us, and the

remembrance of them be an example to us, and their  lives may shed a  light on many dark places both of

philosophy and theology. 

THE MYTHS OF PLATO. 

The myths of Plato are a phenomenon unique in literature.  There  are four  longer ones:  these occur in the

Phaedrus, Phaedo, Gorgias,  and Republic.  That in the Republic is the most elaborate and finished  of them.

Three of  these greater myths, namely those contained in the  Phaedo, the Gorgias and  the Republic, relate to

the destiny of human  souls in a future life.  The  magnificent myth in the Phaedrus treats  of the immortality, or

rather the  eternity of the soul, in which is  included a former as well as a future  state of existence.  To these

may be added, (1) the myth, or rather fable,  occurring in the  Statesman, in which the life of innocence is

contrasted  with the  ordinary life of man and the consciousness of evil:  (2) the  legend of  the Island of Atlantis,

an imaginary history, which is a fragment  only, commenced in the Timaeus and continued in the Critias:  (3)

the  much  less artistic fiction of the foundation of the Cretan colony  which is  introduced in the preface to the

Laws, but soon falls into  the background:  (4) the beautiful but rather artificial tale of  Prometheus and

Epimetheus  narrated in his rhetorical manner by  Protagoras in the dialogue called  after him:  (5) the speech at

the  beginning of the Phaedrus, which is a  parody of the orator Lysias; the  rival speech of Socrates and the

recantation of it.  To these may be  added (6) the tale of the grasshoppers,  and (7) the tale of Thamus and  of

Theuth, both in the Phaedrus:  (8) the  parable of the Cave  (Republic), in which the previous argument is

recapitulated, and the  nature and degrees of knowledge having been  previously set forth in  the abstract are

represented in a picture:  (9) the  fiction of the  earthborn men (Republic; compare Laws), in which by the

adaptation of  an old tradition Plato makes a new beginning for his society:  (10) the  myth of Aristophanes

respecting the division of the sexes, Sym.:  (11)  the parable of the noble captain, the pilot, and the mutinous

sailors  (Republic), in which is represented the relation of the better part of  the  world, and of the philosopher,

to the mob of politicians:  (12)  the  ironical tale of the pilot who plies between Athens and Aegina  charging

only a small payment for saving men from death, the reason  being that he is  uncertain whether to live or die

is better for them  (Gor.):  (13) the  treatment of freemen and citizens by physicians and  of slaves by their

apprentices,a somewhat laboured figure of speech  intended to illustrate  the two different ways in which the

laws speak  to men (Laws).  There also  occur in Plato continuous images; some of  them extend over several

pages,  appearing and reappearing at  intervals:  such as the bees stinging and  stingless (paupers and  thieves) in

the Eighth Book of the Republic, who are  generated in the  transition from timocracy to oligarchy:  the sun,

which is  to the  visible world what the idea of good is to the intellectual, in the  Sixth Book of the Republic:


Gorgias

Gorgias 25



Top




Page No 28


the composite animal, having the form of  a  man, but containing under a human skin a lion and a

manyheaded  monster  (Republic):  the great beast, i.e. the populace:  and the wild  beast within  us, meaning

the passions which are always liable to break  out:  the  animated comparisons of the degradation of philosophy

by the  arts to the  dishonoured maiden, and of the tyrant to the parricide,  who 'beats his  father, having first

taken away his arms':  the dog,  who is your only  philosopher:  the grotesque and rather paltry image  of the

argument  wandering about without a head (Laws), which is  repeated, not improved,  from the Gorgias:  the

argument personified as  veiling her face (Republic),  as engaged in a chase, as breaking upon  us in a first,

second and third  wave:on these figures of speech the  changes are rung many times over.  It  is observable

that nearly all  these parables or continuous images are found  in the Republic; that  which occurs in the

Theaetetus, of the midwifery of  Socrates, is  perhaps the only exception.  To make the list complete, the

mathematical figure of the number of the state (Republic), or the  numerical  interval which separates king

from tyrant, should not be  forgotten. 

The myth in the Gorgias is one of those descriptions of another  life which,  like the Sixth Aeneid of Virgil,

appear to contain  reminiscences of the  mysteries.  It is a vision of the rewards and  punishments which await

good  and bad men after death.  It supposes the  body to continue and to be in  another world what it has become

in  this.  It includes a Paradiso,  Purgatorio, and Inferno, like the  sister myths of the Phaedo and the  Republic.

The Inferno is reserved  for great criminals only.  The argument  of the dialogue is frequently  referred to, and

the meaning breaks through  so as rather to destroy  the liveliness and consistency of the picture.  The  structure

of the  fiction is very slight, the chief point or moral being  that in the  judgments of another world there is no

possibility of  concealment:  Zeus has taken from men the power of foreseeing death, and  brings  together the

souls both of them and their judges naked and  undisguised  at the judgmentseat.  Both are exposed to view,

stripped of  the veils  and clothes which might prevent them from seeing into or being  seen by  one another. 

The myth of the Phaedo is of the same type, but it is more  cosmological,  and also more poetical.  The

beautiful and ingenious  fancy occurs to Plato  that the upper atmosphere is an earth and heaven  in one, a

glorified earth,  fairer and purer than that in which we  dwell.  As the fishes live in the  ocean, mankind are

living in a lower  sphere, out of which they put their  heads for a moment or two and  behold a world beyond.

The earth which we  inhabit is a sediment of  the coarser particles which drop from the world  above, and is to

that  heavenly earth what the desert and the shores of the  ocean are to us.  A part of the myth consists of

description of the  interior of the  earth, which gives the opportunity of introducing several  mythological

names and of providing places of torment for the wicked.  There is no  clear distinction of soul and body; the

spirits beneath the  earth are  spoken of as souls only, yet they retain a sort of shadowy form  when  they cry for

mercy on the shores of the lake; and the philosopher  alone is said to have got rid of the body.  All the three

myths in  Plato  which relate to the world below have a place for repentant  sinners, as well  as other homes or

places for the very good and very  bad.  It is a natural  reflection which is made by Plato elsewhere,  that the two

extremes of human  character are rarely met with, and that  the generality of mankind are  between them.  Hence

a place must be  found for them.  In the myth of the  Phaedo they are carried down the  river Acheron to the

Acherusian lake,  where they dwell, and are  purified of their evil deeds, and receive the  rewards of their good.

There are also incurable sinners, who are cast into  Tartarus, there  to remain as the penalty of atrocious

crimes; these suffer  everlastingly.  And there is another class of hardlycurable sinners  who  are allowed from

time to time to approach the shores of the  Acherusian  lake, where they cry to their victims for mercy; which

if  they obtain they  come out into the lake and cease from their torments. 

Neither this, nor any of the three greater myths of Plato, nor  perhaps any  allegory or parable relating to the

unseen world, is  consistent with  itself.  The language of philosophy mingles with that  of mythology;  abstract

ideas are transformed into persons, figures of  speech into  realities.  These myths may be compared with the

Pilgrim's  Progress of  Bunyan, in which discussions of theology are mixed up with  the incidents of  travel, and

mythological personages are associated  with human beings:  they  are also garnished with names and phrases

taken out of Homer, and with  other fragments of Greek tradition. 


Gorgias

Gorgias 26



Top




Page No 29


The myth of the Republic is more subtle and also more consistent  than  either of the two others.  It has a

greater verisimilitude than  they have,  and is full of touches which recall the experiences of  human life.  It will

be noticed by an attentive reader that the twelve  days during which Er lay  in a trance after he was slain

coincide with  the time passed by the spirits  in their pilgrimage.  It is a curious  observation, not often made,

that  good men who have lived in a  wellgoverned city (shall we say in a  religious and respectable  society?)

are more likely to make mistakes in  their choice of life  than those who have had more experience of the

world  and of evil.  It  is a more familiar remark that we constantly blame others  when we have  only ourselves

to blame; and the philosopher must acknowledge,  however  reluctantly, that there is an element of chance in

human life with  which it is sometimes impossible for man to cope.  That men drink more  of  the waters of

forgetfulness than is good for them is a poetical  description  of a familiar truth.  We have many of us known

men who,  like Odysseus, have  wearied of ambition and have only desired rest.  We should like to know  what

became of the infants 'dying almost as  soon as they were born,' but  Plato only raises, without satisfying,  our

curiosity.  The two companies of  souls, ascending and descending  at either chasm of heaven and earth, and

conversing when they come out  into the meadow, the majestic figures of the  judges sitting in heaven,  the

voice heard by Ardiaeus, are features of the  great allegory which  have an indescribable grandeur and power.

The remark  already made  respecting the inconsistency of the two other myths must be  extended  also to this:  it

is at once an orrery, or model of the heavens,  and a  picture of the Day of Judgment. 

The three myths are unlike anything else in Plato.  There is an  Oriental,  or rather an Egyptian element in them,

and they have an  affinity to the  mysteries and to the Orphic modes of worship.  To a  certain extent they are

unGreek; at any rate there is hardly anything  like them in other Greek  writings which have a serious

purpose; in  spirit they are mediaeval.  They  are akin to what may be termed the  underground religion in all

ages and  countries.  They are presented in  the most lively and graphic manner, but  they are never insisted on

as  true; it is only affirmed that nothing better  can be said about a  future life.  Plato seems to make use of them

when he  has reached the  limits of human knowledge; or, to borrow an expression of  his own,  when he is

standing on the outside of the intellectual world.  They are  very simple in style; a few touches bring the

picture home to the  mind, and make it present to us.  They have also a kind of authority  gained  by the

employment of sacred and familiar names, just as mere  fragments of  the words of Scripture, put together in

any form and  applied to any  subject, have a power of their own.  They are a  substitute for poetry and

mythology; and they are also a reform of  mythology.  The moral of them may  be summed up in a word or

two:  After death the Judgment; and 'there is  some better thing remaining  for the good than for the evil.' 

All literature gathers into itself many elements of the past:  for  example,  the tale of the earthborn men in the

Republic appears at  first sight to be  an extravagant fancy, but it is restored to  propriety when we remember

that  it is based on a legendary belief.  The art of making stories of ghosts and  apparitions credible is said  to

consist in the manner of telling them.  The  effect is gained by  many literary and conversational devices, such

as the  previous raising  of curiosity, the mention of little circumstances,  simplicity,  picturesqueness, the

naturalness of the occasion, and the like.  This  art is possessed by Plato in a degree which has never been

equalled. 

The myth in the Phaedrus is even greater than the myths which have  been  already described, but is of a

different character.  It treats of  a former  rather than of a future life.  It represents the conflict of  reason aided  by

passion or righteous indignation on the one hand, and  of the animal  lusts and instincts on the other.  The soul

of man has  followed the company  of some god, and seen truth in the form of the  universal before it was born

in this world.  Our present life is the  result of the struggle which was  then carried on.  This world is  relative to

a former world, as it is often  projected into a future.  We ask the question, Where were men before birth?  As

we likewise  enquire, What will become of them after death?  The first  question is  unfamiliar to us, and

therefore seems to be unnatural; but if  we  survey the whole human race, it has been as influential and as

widely  spread as the other.  In the Phaedrus it is really a figure of speech  in  which the 'spiritual combat' of this

life is represented.  The  majesty and  power of the whole passageespecially of what may be  called the theme

or  proem (beginning 'The mind through all her being  is immortal')can only be  rendered very inadequately


Gorgias

Gorgias 27



Top




Page No 30


in another  language. 

The myth in the Statesman relates to a former cycle of existence,  in which  men were born of the earth, and by

the reversal of the  earth's motion had  their lives reversed and were restored to youth and  beauty:  the dead

came  to life, the old grew middleaged, and the  middleaged young; the youth  became a child, the child an

infant, the  infant vanished into the earth.  The connection between the reversal of  the earth's motion and the

reversal  of human life is of course verbal  only, yet Plato, like theologians in  other ages, argues from the

consistency of the tale to its truth.  The new  order of the world was  immediately under the government of

God; it was a  state of innocence  in which men had neither wants nor cares, in which the  earth brought  forth

all things spontaneously, and God was to man what man  now is to  the animals.  There were no great estates,

or families, or  private  possessions, nor any traditions of the past, because men were all  born  out of the earth.

This is what Plato calls the 'reign of Cronos;' and  in like manner he connects the reversal of the earth's motion

with  some  legend of which he himself was probably the inventor. 

The question is then asked, under which of these two cycles of  existence  was man the happier,under that of

Cronos, which was a  state of innocence,  or that of Zeus, which is our ordinary life?  For  a while Plato

balances  the two sides of the serious controversy, which  he has suggested in a  figure.  The answer depends on

another question:  What use did the children  of Cronos make of their time?  They had  boundless leisure and

the faculty  of discoursing, not only with one  another, but with the animals.  Did they  employ these advantages

with  a view to philosophy, gathering from every  nature some addition to  their store of knowledge? or, Did

they pass their  time in eating and  drinking and telling stories to one another and to the  beasts?in  either case

there would be no difficulty in answering.  But  then, as  Plato rather mischievously adds, 'Nobody knows what

they did,' and  therefore the doubt must remain undetermined. 

To the first there succeeds a second epoch.  After another natural  convulsion, in which the order of the world

and of human life is once  more  reversed, God withdraws his guiding hand, and man is left to the  government

of himself.  The world begins again, and arts and laws are  slowly and  painfully invented.  A secular age

succeeds to a  theocratical.  In this  fanciful tale Plato has dropped, or almost  dropped, the garb of mythology.

He suggests several curious and  important thoughts, such as the possibility  of a state of innocence,  the

existence of a world without traditions, and  the difference  between human and divine government.  He has

also carried a  step  further his speculations concerning the abolition of the family and of  property, which he

supposes to have no place among the children of  Cronos  any more than in the ideal state. 

It is characteristic of Plato and of his age to pass from the  abstract to  the concrete, from poetry to reality.

Language is the  expression of the  seen, and also of the unseen, and moves in a region  between them.  A great

writer knows how to strike both these chords,  sometimes remaining within  the sphere of the visible, and then

again  comprehending a wider range and  soaring to the abstract and universal.  Even in the same sentence he

may  employ both modes of speech not  improperly or inharmoniously.  It is  useless to criticise the broken

metaphors of Plato, if the effect of the  whole is to create a picture  not such as can be painted on canvas, but

which is full of life and  meaning to the reader.  A poem may be contained  in a word or two,  which may call up

not one but many latent images; or half  reveal to us  by a sudden flash the thoughts of many hearts.  Often the

rapid  transition from one image to another is pleasing to us:  on the other  hand, any single figure of speech if

too often repeated, or worked out  too  much at length, becomes prosy and monotonous.  In theology and

philosophy  we necessarily include both 'the moral law within and the  starry heaven  above,' and pass from one

to the other (compare for  examples Psalms xviii.  and xix.).  Whether such a use of language is  puerile or noble

depends upon  the genius of the writer or speaker, and  the familiarity of the  associations employed. 

In the myths and parables of Plato the ease and grace of  conversation is  not forgotten:  they are spoken, not

written words,  stories which are told  to a living audience, and so well told that we  are more than

halfinclined  to believe them (compare Phaedrus).  As in  conversation too, the striking  image or figure of

speech is not  forgotten, but is quickly caught up, and  alluded to again and again;  as it would still be in our


Gorgias

Gorgias 28



Top




Page No 31


own day in a genial  and sympathetic  society.  The descriptions of Plato have a greater life and  reality  than is

to be found in any modern writing.  This is due to their  homeliness and simplicity.  Plato can do with words

just as he  pleases; to  him they are indeed 'more plastic than wax' (Republic).  We are in the  habit of opposing

speech and writing, poetry and prose.  But he has  discovered a use of language in which they are united;

which gives a  fitting expression to the highest truths; and in which  the trifles of  courtesy and the familiarities

of daily life are not  overlooked. 

GORGIAS

PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE:  Callicles, Socrates, Chaerephon, Gorgias,  Polus. 

SCENE:  The house of Callicles. 

CALLICLES: The wise man, as the proverb says, is late for a  fray, but not  for a feast. 

SOCRATES: And are we late for a feast? 

CALLICLES: Yes, and a delightful feast; for Gorgias has just  been  exhibiting to us many fine things. 

SOCRATES: It is not my fault, Callicles; our friend  Chaerephon is to  blame; for he would keep us loitering

in the Agora. 

CHAEREPHON: Never mind, Socrates; the misfortune of which I  have been the  cause I will also repair; for

Gorgias is a friend of  mine, and I will make  him give the exhibition again either now, or, if  you prefer, at

some other  time. 

CALLICLES: What is the matter, Chaerephondoes Socrates  want to hear  Gorgias? 

CHAEREPHON: Yes, that was our intention in coming. 

CALLICLES: Come into my house, then; for Gorgias is staying  with me, and  he shall exhibit to you. 

SOCRATES: Very good, Callicles; but will he answer our  questions? for I  want to hear from him what is the

nature of his art,  and what it is which  he professes and teaches; he may, as you  (Chaerephon) suggest, defer

the  exhibition to some other time. 

CALLICLES: There is nothing like asking him, Socrates; and  indeed to  answer questions is a part of his

exhibition, for he was  saying only just  now, that any one in my house might put any question  to him, and that

he  would answer. 

SOCRATES: How fortunate! will you ask him, Chaerephon? 

CHAEREPHON: What shall I ask him? 

SOCRATES: Ask him who he is. 

CHAEREPHON: What do you mean? 

SOCRATES: I mean such a question as would elicit from him,  if he had been  a maker of shoes, the answer

that he is a cobbler.  Do  you understand? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 29



Top




Page No 32


CHAEREPHON: I understand, and will ask him:  Tell me,  Gorgias, is our  friend Callicles right in saying

that you undertake to  answer any questions  which you are asked? 

GORGIAS: Quite right, Chaerephon:  I was saying as much only  just now; and  I may add, that many years

have elapsed since any one  has asked me a new  one. 

CHAEREPHON: Then you must be very ready, Gorgias. 

GORGIAS: Of that, Chaerephon, you can make trial. 

POLUS: Yes, indeed, and if you like, Chaerephon, you may  make trial of me  too, for I think that Gorgias,

who has been talking a  long time, is tired. 

CHAEREPHON: And do you, Polus, think that you can answer  better than  Gorgias? 

POLUS: What does that matter if I answer well enough for  you? 

CHAEREPHON: Not at all:and you shall answer if you like. 

POLUS: Ask: 

CHAEREPHON: My question is this:  If Gorgias had the skill  of his brother  Herodicus, what ought we to

call him?  Ought he not to  have the name which  is given to his brother? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

CHAEREPHON: Then we should be right in calling him a  physician? 

POLUS: Yes. 

CHAEREPHON: And if he had the skill of Aristophon the son of  Aglaophon, or  of his brother Polygnotus,

what ought we to call him? 

POLUS: Clearly, a painter. 

CHAEREPHON: But now what shall we call himwhat is the art  in which he is  skilled. 

POLUS: O Chaerephon, there are many arts among mankind which  are  experimental, and have their origin

in experience, for experience  makes the  days of men to proceed according to art, and inexperience  according

to  chance, and different persons in different ways are  proficient in different  arts, and the best persons in the

best arts.  And our friend Gorgias is one  of the best, and the art in which he is  a proficient is the noblest. 

SOCRATES: Polus has been taught how to make a capital  speech, Gorgias; but  he is not fulfilling the

promise which he made to  Chaerephon. 

GORGIAS: What do you mean, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I mean that he has not exactly answered the  question which he  was asked. 

GORGIAS: Then why not ask him yourself? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 30



Top




Page No 33


SOCRATES: But I would much rather ask you, if you are  disposed to answer:  for I see, from the few words

which Polus has  uttered, that he has attended  more to the art which is called rhetoric  than to dialectic. 

POLUS: What makes you say so, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: Because, Polus, when Chaerephon asked you what was  the art which  Gorgias knows, you

praised it as if you were answering  some one who found  fault with it, but you never said what the art was. 

POLUS: Why, did I not say that it was the noblest of arts? 

SOCRATES: Yes, indeed, but that was no answer to the  question:  nobody  asked what was the quality, but

what was the nature,  of the art, and by  what name we were to describe Gorgias.  And I would  still beg you

briefly  and clearly, as you answered Chaerephon when he  asked you at first, to say  what this art is, and what

we ought to call  Gorgias:  Or rather, Gorgias,  let me turn to you, and ask the same  question,what are we to

call you,  and what is the art which you  profess? 

GORGIAS: Rhetoric, Socrates, is my art. 

SOCRATES: Then I am to call you a rhetorician? 

GORGIAS: Yes, Socrates, and a good one too, if you would  call me that  which, in Homeric language, 'I

boast myself to be.' 

SOCRATES: I should wish to do so. 

GORGIAS: Then pray do. 

SOCRATES: And are we to say that you are able to make other  men  rhetoricians? 

GORGIAS: Yes, that is exactly what I profess to make them,  not only at  Athens, but in all places. 

SOCRATES: And will you continue to ask and answer questions,  Gorgias, as  we are at present doing, and

reserve for another occasion  the longer mode  of speech which Polus was attempting?  Will you keep  your

promise, and  answer shortly the questions which are asked of you? 

GORGIAS: Some answers, Socrates, are of necessity longer;  but I will do my  best to make them as short as

possible; for a part of  my profession is that  I can be as short as any one. 

SOCRATES: That is what is wanted, Gorgias; exhibit the  shorter method now,  and the longer one at some

other time. 

GORGIAS: Well, I will; and you will certainly say, that you  never heard a  man use fewer words. 

SOCRATES: Very good then; as you profess to be a  rhetorician, and a maker  of rhetoricians, let me ask you,

with what is  rhetoric concerned:  I might  ask with what is weaving concerned, and  you would reply (would

you not?),  with the making of garments? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And music is concerned with the composition of  melodies? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 31



Top




Page No 34


GORGIAS: It is. 

SOCRATES: By Here, Gorgias, I admire the surpassing brevity  of your  answers. 

GORGIAS: Yes, Socrates, I do think myself good at that. 

SOCRATES: I am glad to hear it; answer me in like manner  about rhetoric:  with what is rhetoric concerned? 

GORGIAS: With discourse. 

SOCRATES: What sort of discourse, Gorgias?such discourse  as would teach  the sick under what

treatment they might get well? 

GORGIAS: No. 

SOCRATES: Then rhetoric does not treat of all kinds of  discourse? 

GORGIAS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: And yet rhetoric makes men able to speak? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And to understand that about which they speak? 

GORGIAS: Of course. 

SOCRATES: But does not the art of medicine, which we were  just now  mentioning, also make men able to

understand and speak about  the sick? 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then medicine also treats of discourse? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Of discourse concerning diseases? 

GORGIAS: Just so. 

SOCRATES: And does not gymnastic also treat of discourse  concerning the  good or evil condition of the

body? 

GORGIAS: Very true. 

SOCRATES: And the same, Gorgias, is true of the other  arts:all of them  treat of discourse concerning the

subjects with  which they severally have  to do. 

GORGIAS: Clearly. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 32



Top




Page No 35


SOCRATES: Then why, if you call rhetoric the art which  treats of  discourse, and all the other arts treat of

discourse, do you  not call them  arts of rhetoric? 

GORGIAS: Because, Socrates, the knowledge of the other arts  has only to do  with some sort of external

action, as of the hand; but  there is no such  action of the hand in rhetoric which works and takes  effect only

through  the medium of discourse.  And therefore I am  justified in saying that  rhetoric treats of discourse. 

SOCRATES: I am not sure whether I entirely understand you,  but I dare say  I shall soon know better; please

to answer me a  question:you would allow  that there are arts? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: As to the arts generally, they are for the most  part concerned  with doing, and require little or

no speaking; in  painting, and statuary,  and many other arts, the work may proceed in  silence; and of such arts

I  suppose you would say that they do not  come within the province of  rhetoric. 

GORGIAS: You perfectly conceive my meaning, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: But there are other arts which work wholly through  the medium of  language, and require either

no action or very little,  as, for example, the  arts of arithmetic, of calculation, of geometry,  and of playing

draughts;  in some of these speech is pretty nearly  coextensive with action, but in  most of them the verbal

element is  greaterthey depend wholly on words for  their efficacy and power:  and I take your meaning to be

that rhetoric is  an art of this latter  sort? 

GORGIAS: Exactly. 

SOCRATES: And yet I do not believe that you really mean to  call any of  these arts rhetoric; although the

precise expression which  you used was,  that rhetoric is an art which works and takes effect  only through the

medium of discourse; and an adversary who wished to  be captious might say,  'And so, Gorgias, you call

arithmetic  rhetoric.'  But I do not think that  you really call arithmetic  rhetoric any more than geometry would

be so  called by you. 

GORGIAS: You are quite right, Socrates, in your apprehension  of my  meaning. 

SOCRATES: Well, then, let me now have the rest of my  answer:seeing that  rhetoric is one of those arts

which works mainly  by the use of words, and  there are other arts which also use words,  tell me what is that

quality in  words with which rhetoric is  concerned:Suppose that a person asks me  about some of the arts

which  I was mentioning just now; he might say,  'Socrates, what is  arithmetic?' and I should reply to him, as

you replied  to me, that  arithmetic is one of those arts which take effect through  words.  And  then he would

proceed to ask:  'Words about what?' and I should  reply,  Words about odd and even numbers, and how many

there are of each.  And  if he asked again:  'What is the art of calculation?' I should say,  That also is one of the

arts which is concerned wholly with words.  And if  he further said, 'Concerned with what?' I should say, like

the  clerks in  the assembly, 'as aforesaid' of arithmetic, but with a  difference, the  difference being that the art

of calculation considers  not only the  quantities of odd and even numbers, but also their  numerical relations to

themselves and to one another.  And suppose,  again, I were to say that  astronomy is only wordshe would

ask,  'Words about what, Socrates?' and I  should answer, that astronomy  tells us about the motions of the stars

and  sun and moon, and their  relative swiftness. 

GORGIAS: You would be quite right, Socrates. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 33



Top




Page No 36


SOCRATES: And now let us have from you, Gorgias, the truth  about rhetoric:  which you would admit

(would you not?) to be one of  those arts which act  always and fulfil all their ends through the  medium of

words? 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: Words which do what? I should ask.  To what class  of things do  the words which rhetoric uses

relate? 

GORGIAS: To the greatest, Socrates, and the best of human  things. 

SOCRATES: That again, Gorgias is ambiguous; I am still in  the dark:  for  which are the greatest and best of

human things?  I  dare say that you have  heard men singing at feasts the old drinking  song, in which the

singers  enumerate the goods of life, first health,  beauty next, thirdly, as the  writer of the song says, wealth

honestly  obtained. 

GORGIAS: Yes, I know the song; but what is your drift? 

SOCRATES: I mean to say, that the producers of those things  which the  author of the song praises, that is to

say, the physician,  the trainer, the  moneymaker, will at once come to you, and first the  physician will say:  'O

Socrates, Gorgias is deceiving you, for my art  is concerned with the  greatest good of men and not his.'  And

when I  ask, Who are you? he will  reply, 'I am a physician.'  What do you  mean? I shall say.  Do you mean  that

your art produces the greatest  good?  'Certainly,' he will answer,  'for is not health the greatest  good?  What

greater good can men have,  Socrates?'  And after him the  trainer will come and say, 'I too, Socrates,  shall be

greatly  surprised if Gorgias can show more good of his art than I  can show of  mine.'  To him again I shall say,

Who are you, honest friend,  and what  is your business?  'I am a trainer,' he will reply, 'and my  business  is to

make men beautiful and strong in body.'  When I have done  with  the trainer, there arrives the moneymaker,

and he, as I expect, will  utterly despise them all.  'Consider Socrates,' he will say, 'whether  Gorgias or any one

else can produce any greater good than wealth.'  Well,  you and I say to him, and are you a creator of wealth?

'Yes,'  he replies.  And who are you?  'A moneymaker.'  And do you consider  wealth to be the  greatest good of

man?  'Of course,' will be his  reply.  And we shall  rejoin:  Yes; but our friend Gorgias contends  that his art

produces a  greater good than yours.  And then he will be  sure to go on and ask, 'What  good?  Let Gorgias

answer.'  Now I want  you, Gorgias, to imagine that this  question is asked of you by them  and by me; What is

that which, as you say,  is the greatest good of  man, and of which you are the creator?  Answer us. 

GORGIAS: That good, Socrates, which is truly the greatest,  being that  which gives to men freedom in their

own persons, and to  individuals the  power of ruling over others in their several states. 

SOCRATES: And what would you consider this to be? 

GORGIAS: What is there greater than the word which persuades  the judges in  the courts, or the senators in

the council, or the  citizens in the  assembly, or at any other political meeting?if you  have the power of

uttering this word, you will have the physician your  slave, and the trainer  your slave, and the moneymaker

of whom you  talk will be found to gather  treasures, not for himself, but for you  who are able to speak and to

persuade the multitude. 

SOCRATES: Now I think, Gorgias, that you have very  accurately explained  what you conceive to be the art

of rhetoric; and  you mean to say, if I am  not mistaken, that rhetoric is the artificer  of persuasion, having this

and  no other business, and that this is her  crown and end.  Do you know any  other effect of rhetoric over and

above that of producing persuasion? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 34



Top




Page No 37


GORGIAS: No:  the definition seems to me very fair,  Socrates; for  persuasion is the chief end of rhetoric. 

SOCRATES: Then hear me, Gorgias, for I am quite sure that if  there ever  was a man who entered on the

discussion of a matter from a  pure love of  knowing the truth, I am such a one, and I should say the  same of

you. 

GORGIAS: What is coming, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I will tell you:  I am very well aware that I do  not know what,  according to you, is the exact

nature, or what are the  topics of that  persuasion of which you speak, and which is given by  rhetoric; although

I  have a suspicion about both the one and the  other.  And I am going to ask  what is this power of

persuasion which  is given by rhetoric, and about  what?  But why, if I have a suspicion,  do I ask instead of

telling you?  Not for your sake, but in order that  the argument may proceed in such a  manner as is most likely

to set  forth the truth.  And I would have you  observe, that I am right in  asking this further question:  If I asked,

'What sort of a painter is  Zeuxis?' and you said, 'The painter of figures,'  should I not be right  in asking, 'What

kind of figures, and where do you  find them?' 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And the reason for asking this second question  would be, that  there are other painters besides,

who paint many other  figures? 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: But if there had been no one but Zeuxis who  painted them, then  you would have answered

very well? 

GORGIAS: Quite so. 

SOCRATES: Now I want to know about rhetoric in the same  way;is rhetoric  the only art which brings

persuasion, or do other  arts have the same  effect?  I mean to sayDoes he who teaches  anything persuade

men of that  which he teaches or not? 

GORGIAS: He persuades, Socrates,there can be no mistake  about that. 

SOCRATES: Again, if we take the arts of which we were just  now speaking:  do not arithmetic and the

arithmeticians teach us the  properties of number? 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And therefore persuade us of them? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then arithmetic as well as rhetoric is an  artificer of  persuasion? 

GORGIAS: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: And if any one asks us what sort of persuasion,  and about what,  we shall answer, persuasion

which teaches the  quantity of odd and even;  and we shall be able to show that all the  other arts of which we

were just  now speaking are artificers of  persuasion, and of what sort, and about  what. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 35



Top




Page No 38


GORGIAS: Very true. 

SOCRATES: Then rhetoric is not the only artificer of  persuasion? 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: Seeing, then, that not only rhetoric works by  persuasion, but  that other arts do the same, as in

the case of the  painter, a question has  arisen which is a very fair one:  Of what  persuasion is rhetoric the

artificer, and about what?is not that a  fair way of putting the question? 

GORGIAS: I think so. 

SOCRATES: Then, if you approve the question, Gorgias, what  is the answer? 

GORGIAS: I answer, Socrates, that rhetoric is the art of  persuasion in  courts of law and other assemblies, as

I was just now  saying, and about the  just and unjust. 

SOCRATES: And that, Gorgias, was what I was suspecting to be  your notion;  yet I would not have you

wonder if byandby I am found  repeating a  seemingly plain question; for I ask not in order to  confute you,

but as I  was saying that the argument may proceed  consecutively, and that we may not  get the habit of

anticipating and  suspecting the meaning of one another's  words; I would have you  develope your own views

in your own way, whatever  may be your  hypothesis. 

GORGIAS: I think that you are quite right, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Then let me raise another question; there is such  a thing as  'having learned'? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And there is also 'having believed'? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And is the 'having learned' the same as 'having  believed,' and  are learning and belief the same

things? 

GORGIAS: In my judgment, Socrates, they are not the same. 

SOCRATES: And your judgment is right, as you may ascertain  in this way:  If a person were to say to

you, 'Is there, Gorgias, a  false belief as well  as a true?'you would reply, if I am not  mistaken, that there is. 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Well, but is there a false knowledge as well as a  true? 

GORGIAS: No. 

SOCRATES: No, indeed; and this again proves that knowledge  and belief  differ. 

GORGIAS: Very true. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 36



Top




Page No 39


SOCRATES: And yet those who have learned as well as those  who have  believed are persuaded? 

GORGIAS: Just so. 

SOCRATES: Shall we then assume two sorts of persuasion,one  which is the  source of belief without

knowledge, as the other is of  knowledge? 

GORGIAS: By all means. 

SOCRATES: And which sort of persuasion does rhetoric create  in courts of  law and other assemblies about

the just and unjust, the  sort of persuasion  which gives belief without knowledge, or that which  gives

knowledge? 

GORGIAS: Clearly, Socrates, that which only gives belief. 

SOCRATES: Then rhetoric, as would appear, is the artificer  of a persuasion  which creates belief about the

just and unjust, but  gives no instruction  about them? 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: And the rhetorician does not instruct the courts  of law or other  assemblies about things just

and unjust, but he  creates belief about them;  for no one can be supposed to instruct such  a vast multitude

about such  high matters in a short time? 

GORGIAS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Come, then, and let us see what we really mean  about rhetoric;  for I do not know what my

own meaning is as yet.  When  the assembly meets  to elect a physician or a shipwright or any other  craftsman,

will the  rhetorician be taken into counsel?  Surely not.  For at every election he  ought to be chosen who is most

skilled; and,  again, when walls have to be  built or harbours or docks to be  constructed, not the rhetorician but

the  master workman will advise;  or when generals have to be chosen and an order  of battle arranged, or  a

position taken, then the military will advise and  not the  rhetoricians:  what do you say, Gorgias?  Since you

profess to be a  rhetorician and a maker of rhetoricians, I cannot do better than learn  the  nature of your art

from you.  And here let me assure you that I  have your  interest in view as well as my own.  For likely enough

some  one or other of  the young men present might desire to become your  pupil, and in fact I see  some, and a

good many too, who have this  wish, but they would be too modest  to question you.  And therefore  when you

are interrogated by me, I would  have you imagine that you are  interrogated by them.  'What is the use of

coming to you, Gorgias?'  they will say'about what will you teach us to  advise the  state?about the just

and unjust only, or about those other  things  also which Socrates has just mentioned?'  How will you answer

them? 

GORGIAS: I like your way of leading us on, Socrates, and I  will endeavour  to reveal to you the whole

nature of rhetoric.  You  must have heard, I  think, that the docks and the walls of the  Athenians and the plan of

the  harbour were devised in accordance with  the counsels, partly of  Themistocles, and partly of Pericles, and

not  at the suggestion of the  builders. 

SOCRATES: Such is the tradition, Gorgias, about  Themistocles; and I myself  heard the speech of Pericles

when he  advised us about the middle wall. 

GORGIAS: And you will observe, Socrates, that when a  decision has to be  given in such matters the

rhetoricians are the  advisers; they are the men  who win their point. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 37



Top




Page No 40


SOCRATES: I had that in my admiring mind, Gorgias, when I  asked what is  the nature of rhetoric, which

always appears to me, when  I look at the  matter in this way, to be a marvel of greatness. 

GORGIAS: A marvel, indeed, Socrates, if you only knew how  rhetoric  comprehends and holds under her

sway all the inferior arts.  Let me offer  you a striking example of this.  On several occasions I  have been with

my  brother Herodicus or some other physician to see one  of his patients, who  would not allow the physician

to give him  medicine, or apply the knife or  hot iron to him; and I have persuaded  him to do for me what he

would not do  for the physician just by the  use of rhetoric.  And I say that if a  rhetorician and a physician were

to go to any city, and had there to argue  in the Ecclesia or any other  assembly as to which of them should be

elected  statephysician, the  physician would have no chance; but he who could speak  would be chosen  if he

wished; and in a contest with a man of any other  profession the  rhetorician more than any one would have the

power of  getting himself  chosen, for he can speak more persuasively to the multitude  than any  of them, and

on any subject.  Such is the nature and power of the  art  of rhetoric!  And yet, Socrates, rhetoric should be used

like any other  competitive art, not against everybody,the rhetorician ought not to  abuse  his strength any

more than a pugilist or pancratiast or other  master of  fence;because he has powers which are more than a

match  either for friend  or enemy, he ought not therefore to strike, stab, or  slay his friends.  Suppose a man to

have been trained in the palestra  and to be a skilful  boxer,he in the fulness of his strength goes and  strikes

his father or  mother or one of his familiars or friends; but  that is no reason why the  trainers or

fencingmasters should be held  in detestation or banished from  the city;surely not.  For they  taught their art

for a good purpose, to be  used against enemies and  evildoers, in selfdefence not in aggression, and  others

have  perverted their instructions, and turned to a bad use their own  strength and skill.  But not on this account

are the teachers bad,  neither  is the art in fault, or bad in itself; I should rather say  that those who  make a bad

use of the art are to blame.  And the same  argument holds good  of rhetoric; for the rhetorician can speak

against  all men and upon any  subject,in short, he can persuade the multitude  better than any other man  of

anything which he pleases, but he should  not therefore seek to defraud  the physician or any other artist of his

reputation merely because he has  the power; he ought to use rhetoric  fairly, as he would also use his  athletic

powers.  And if after having  become a rhetorician he makes a bad  use of his strength and skill, his  instructor

surely ought not on that  account to be held in detestation  or banished.  For he was intended by his  teacher to

make a good use of  his instructions, but he abuses them.  And  therefore he is the person  who ought to be held

in detestation, banished,  and put to death, and  not his instructor. 

SOCRATES: You, Gorgias, like myself, have had great  experience of  disputations, and you must have

observed, I think, that  they do not always  terminate in mutual edification, or in the  definition by either party

of  the subjects which they are discussing;  but disagreements are apt to arise  somebody says that another

has  not spoken truly or clearly; and then they  get into a passion and  begin to quarrel, both parties conceiving

that their  opponents are  arguing from personal feeling only and jealousy of  themselves, not  from any interest

in the question at issue.  And sometimes  they will  go on abusing one another until the company at last are

quite  vexed at  themselves for ever listening to such fellows.  Why do I say this?  Why, because I cannot help

feeling that you are now saying what is not  quite consistent or accordant with what you were saying at first

about  rhetoric.  And I am afraid to point this out to you, lest you should  think  that I have some animosity

against you, and that I speak, not  for the sake  of discovering the truth, but from jealousy of you.  Now  if you

are one of  my sort, I should like to crossexamine you, but if  not I will let you  alone.  And what is my sort?

you will ask.  I am  one of those who are very  willing to be refuted if I say anything  which is not true, and very

willing  to refute any one else who says  what is not true, and quite as ready to be  refuted as to refute; for I

hold that this is the greater gain of the two,  just as the gain is  greater of being cured of a very great evil than

of  curing another.  For I imagine that there is no evil which a man can endure  so great  as an erroneous opinion

about the matters of which we are  speaking;  and if you claim to be one of my sort, let us have the discussion

out,  but if you would rather have done, no matter;let us make an end of  it. 

GORGIAS: I should say, Socrates, that I am quite the man  whom you  indicate; but, perhaps, we ought to

consider the audience,  for, before you  came, I had already given a long exhibition, and if we  proceed the


Gorgias

GORGIAS 38



Top




Page No 41


argument  may run on to a great length.  And therefore I  think that we should  consider whether we may not be

detaining some  part of the company when they  are wanting to do something else. 

CHAEREPHON: You hear the audience cheering, Gorgias and  Socrates, which  shows their desire to listen

to you; and for myself,  Heaven forbid that I  should have any business on hand which would take  me away

from a discussion  so interesting and so ably maintained. 

CALLICLES: By the gods, Chaerephon, although I have been  present at many  discussions, I doubt whether

I was ever so much  delighted before, and  therefore if you go on discoursing all day I  shall be the better

pleased. 

SOCRATES: I may truly say, Callicles, that I am willing, if  Gorgias is. 

GORGIAS: After all this, Socrates, I should be disgraced if  I refused,  especially as I have promised to

answer all comers; in  accordance with the  wishes of the company, then, do you begin.  and  ask of me any

question  which you like. 

SOCRATES: Let me tell you then, Gorgias, what surprises me  in your words;  though I dare say that you

may be right, and I may have  misunderstood your  meaning.  You say that you can make any man, who  will

learn of you, a  rhetorician? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Do you mean that you will teach him to gain the  ears of the  multitude on any subject, and this

not by instruction but  by persuasion? 

GORGIAS: Quite so. 

SOCRATES: You were saying, in fact, that the rhetorician  will have greater  powers of persuasion than the

physician even in a  matter of health? 

GORGIAS: Yes, with the multitude,that is. 

SOCRATES: You mean to say, with the ignorant; for with those  who know he  cannot be supposed to have

greater powers of persuasion. 

GORGIAS: Very true. 

SOCRATES: But if he is to have more power of persuasion than  the  physician, he will have greater power

than he who knows? 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Although he is not a physician:is he? 

GORGIAS: No. 

SOCRATES: And he who is not a physician must, obviously, be  ignorant of  what the physician knows. 

GORGIAS: Clearly. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 39



Top




Page No 42


SOCRATES: Then, when the rhetorician is more persuasive than  the  physician, the ignorant is more

persuasive with the ignorant than  he who  has knowledge?is not that the inference? 

GORGIAS: In the case supposed:yes. 

SOCRATES: And the same holds of the relation of rhetoric to  all the other  arts; the rhetorician need not

know the truth about  things; he has only to  discover some way of persuading the ignorant  that he has more

knowledge  than those who know? 

GORGIAS: Yes, Socrates, and is not this a great  comfort?not to have  learned the other arts, but the art of

rhetoric  only, and yet to be in no  way inferior to the professors of them? 

SOCRATES: Whether the rhetorician is or not inferior on this  account is a  question which we will hereafter

examine if the enquiry  is likely to be of  any service to us; but I would rather begin by  asking, whether he is or

is  not as ignorant of the just and unjust,  base and honourable, good and evil,  as he is of medicine and the

other  arts; I mean to say, does he really know  anything of what is good and  evil, base or honourable, just or

unjust in  them; or has he only a way  with the ignorant of persuading them that he not  knowing is to be

esteemed to know more about these things than some one  else who knows?  Or must the pupil know these

things and come to you  knowing them  before he can acquire the art of rhetoric?  If he is ignorant,  you who  are

the teacher of rhetoric will not teach himit is not your  business; but you will make him seem to the

multitude to know them,  when he  does not know them; and seem to be a good man, when he is not.  Or will

you  be unable to teach him rhetoric at all, unless he knows  the truth of these  things first?  What is to be said

about all this?  By heavens, Gorgias, I  wish that you would reveal to me the power of  rhetoric, as you were

saying  that you would. 

GORGIAS: Well, Socrates, I suppose that if the pupil does  chance not to  know them, he will have to learn of

me these things as  well. 

SOCRATES: Say no more, for there you are right; and so he  whom you make a  rhetorician must either know

the nature of the just  and unjust already, or  he must be taught by you. 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Well, and is not he who has learned carpentering a  carpenter? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And he who has learned music a musician? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And he who has learned medicine is a physician, in  like manner?  He who has learned anything

whatever is that which his  knowledge makes him. 

GORGIAS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And in the same way, he who has learned what is  just is just? 

GORGIAS: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And he who is just may be supposed to do what is  just? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 40



Top




Page No 43


GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And must not the just man always desire to do what  is just? 

GORGIAS: That is clearly the inference. 

SOCRATES: Surely, then, the just man will never consent to  do injustice? 

GORGIAS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: And according to the argument the rhetorician must  be a just  man? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And will therefore never be willing to do  injustice? 

GORGIAS: Clearly not. 

SOCRATES: But do you remember saying just now that the  trainer is not to  be accused or banished if the

pugilist makes a wrong  use of his pugilistic  art; and in like manner, if the rhetorician  makes a bad and unjust

use of  his rhetoric, that is not to be laid to  the charge of his teacher, who is  not to be banished, but the

wrongdoer himself who made a bad use of his  rhetoriche is to be  banishedwas not that said? 

GORGIAS: Yes, it was. 

SOCRATES: But now we are affirming that the aforesaid  rhetorician will  never have done injustice at all? 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: And at the very outset, Gorgias, it was said that  rhetoric  treated of discourse, not (like

arithmetic) about odd and  even, but about  just and unjust?  Was not this said? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: I was thinking at the time, when I heard you  saying so, that  rhetoric, which is always

discoursing about justice,  could not possibly be  an unjust thing.  But when you added, shortly  afterwards, that

the  rhetorician might make a bad use of rhetoric I  noted with surprise the  inconsistency into which you had

fallen; and I  said, that if you thought,  as I did, that there was a gain in being  refuted, there would be an

advantage in going on with the question,  but if not, I would leave off.  And in the course of our  investigations,

as you will see yourself, the  rhetorician has been  acknowledged to be incapable of making an unjust use  of

rhetoric, or  of willingness to do injustice.  By the dog, Gorgias, there  will be a  great deal of discussion, before

we get at the truth of all this. 

POLUS: And do even you, Socrates, seriously believe what you  are now  saying about rhetoric?  What!

because Gorgias was ashamed to  deny that the  rhetorician knew the just and the honourable and the  good, and

admitted  that to any one who came to him ignorant of them he  could teach them, and  then out of this

admission there arose a  contradictionthe thing which you  dearly love, and to which not he,  but you,

brought the argument by your  captious questions(do you  seriously believe that there is any truth in  all

this?)  For will any  one ever acknowledge that he does not know, or  cannot teach, the  nature of justice?  The

truth is, that there is great  want of manners  in bringing the argument to such a pass. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 41



Top




Page No 44


SOCRATES: Illustrious Polus, the reason why we provide  ourselves with  friends and children is, that when

we get old and  stumble, a younger  generation may be at hand to set us on our legs  again in our words and in

our actions:  and now, if I and Gorgias are  stumbling, here are you who  should raise us up; and I for my part

engage to retract any error into  which you may think that I have  fallenupon one condition: 

POLUS: What condition? 

SOCRATES: That you contract, Polus, the prolixity of speech  in which you  indulged at first. 

POLUS: What! do you mean that I may not use as many words as  I please? 

SOCRATES: Only to think, my friend, that having come on a  visit to Athens,  which is the most freespoken

state in Hellas, you  when you got there, and  you alone, should be deprived of the power of  speechthat

would be hard  indeed.  But then consider my case:shall  not I be very hardly used, if,  when you are making

a long oration, and  refusing to answer what you are  asked, I am compelled to stay and  listen to you, and may

not go away?  I  say rather, if you have a real  interest in the argument, or, to repeat my  former expression, have

any  desire to set it on its legs, take back any  statement which you  please; and in your turn ask and answer,

like myself  and  Gorgiasrefute and be refuted:  for I suppose that you would claim to  know what Gorgias

knowswould you not? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And you, like him, invite any one to ask you about  anything  which he pleases, and you will

know how to answer him? 

POLUS: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And now, which will you do, ask or answer? 

POLUS: I will ask; and do you answer me, Socrates, the same  question which  Gorgias, as you suppose, is

unable to answer:  What is  rhetoric? 

SOCRATES: Do you mean what sort of an art? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: To say the truth, Polus, it is not an art at all,  in my opinion. 

POLUS: Then what, in your opinion, is rhetoric? 

SOCRATES: A thing which, as I was lately reading in a book  of yours, you  say that you have made an art. 

POLUS: What thing? 

SOCRATES: I should say a sort of experience. 

POLUS: Does rhetoric seem to you to be an experience? 

SOCRATES: That is my view, but you may be of another mind. 

POLUS: An experience in what? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 42



Top




Page No 45


SOCRATES: An experience in producing a sort of delight and  gratification. 

POLUS: And if able to gratify others, must not rhetoric be a  fine thing? 

SOCRATES: What are you saying, Polus?  Why do you ask me  whether rhetoric  is a fine thing or not, when

I have not as yet told  you what rhetoric is? 

POLUS: Did I not hear you say that rhetoric was a sort of  experience? 

SOCRATES: Will you, who are so desirous to gratify others,  afford a slight  gratification to me? 

POLUS: I will. 

SOCRATES: Will you ask me, what sort of an art is cookery? 

POLUS: What sort of an art is cookery? 

SOCRATES: Not an art at all, Polus. 

POLUS: What then? 

SOCRATES: I should say an experience. 

POLUS: In what?  I wish that you would explain to me. 

SOCRATES: An experience in producing a sort of delight and  gratification,  Polus. 

POLUS: Then are cookery and rhetoric the same? 

SOCRATES: No, they are only different parts of the same  profession. 

POLUS: Of what profession? 

SOCRATES: I am afraid that the truth may seem discourteous;  and I hesitate  to answer, lest Gorgias should

imagine that I am making  fun of his own  profession.  For whether or no this is that art of  rhetoric which

Gorgias  practises I really cannot tell:from what he  was just now saying, nothing  appeared of what he

thought of his art,  but the rhetoric which I mean is a  part of a not very creditable  whole. 

GORGIAS: A part of what, Socrates?  Say what you mean, and  never mind me. 

SOCRATES: In my opinion then, Gorgias, the whole of which  rhetoric is a  part is not an art at all, but the

habit of a bold and  ready wit, which  knows how to manage mankind:  this habit I sum up  under the word

'flattery'; and it appears to me to have many other  parts, one of which is  cookery, which may seem to be an

art, but, as I  maintain, is only an  experience or routine and not an art:another  part is rhetoric, and the  art of

attiring and sophistry are two  others:  thus there are four  branches, and four different things  answering to

them.  And Polus may ask,  if he likes, for he has not as  yet been informed, what part of flattery is  rhetoric:  he

did not see  that I had not yet answered him when he proceeded  to ask a further  question:  Whether I do not

think rhetoric a fine thing?  But I shall  not tell him whether rhetoric is a fine thing or not, until I  have  first

answered, 'What is rhetoric?'  For that would not be right,  Polus; but I shall be happy to answer, if you will ask

me, What part  of  flattery is rhetoric? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 43



Top




Page No 46


POLUS: I will ask and do you answer?  What part of flattery  is rhetoric? 

SOCRATES: Will you understand my answer?  Rhetoric,  according to my view,  is the ghost or counterfeit of

a part of  politics. 

POLUS: And noble or ignoble? 

SOCRATES: Ignoble, I should say, if I am compelled to  answer, for I call  what is bad ignoble:  though I

doubt whether you  understand what I was  saying before. 

GORGIAS: Indeed, Socrates, I cannot say that I understand  myself. 

SOCRATES: I do not wonder, Gorgias; for I have not as yet  explained  myself, and our friend Polus, colt by

name and colt by  nature, is apt to  run away.  (This is an untranslatable play on the  name 'Polus,' which means

'a colt.') 

GORGIAS: Never mind him, but explain to me what you mean by  saying that  rhetoric is the counterfeit of a

part of politics. 

SOCRATES: I will try, then, to explain my notion of  rhetoric, and if I am  mistaken, my friend Polus shall

refute me.  We  may assume the existence of  bodies and of souls? 

GORGIAS: Of course. 

SOCRATES: You would further admit that there is a good  condition of either  of them? 

GORGIAS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Which condition may not be really good, but good  only in  appearance?  I mean to say, that

there are many persons who  appear to be in  good health, and whom only a physician or trainer will  discern at

first  sight not to be in good health. 

GORGIAS: True. 

SOCRATES: And this applies not only to the body, but also to  the soul:  in  either there may be that which

gives the appearance of  health and not the  reality? 

GORGIAS: Yes, certainly. 

SOCRATES: And now I will endeavour to explain to you more  clearly what I  mean:  The soul and body

being two, have two arts  corresponding to them:  there is the art of politics attending on the  soul; and another

art  attending on the body, of which I know no single  name, but which may be  described as having two

divisions, one of them  gymnastic, and the other  medicine.  And in politics there is a  legislative part, which

answers to  gymnastic, as justice does to  medicine; and the two parts run into one  another, justice having to do

with the same subject as legislation, and  medicine with the same  subject as gymnastic, but with a difference.

Now,  seeing that there  are these four arts, two attending on the body and two on  the soul for  their highest

good; flattery knowing, or rather guessing their  natures, has distributed herself into four shams or simulations

of  them;  she puts on the likeness of some one or other of them, and  pretends to be  that which she simulates,

and having no regard for  men's highest interests,  is ever making pleasure the bait of the  unwary, and

deceiving them into the  belief that she is of the highest  value to them.  Cookery simulates the  disguise of

medicine, and  pretends to know what food is the best for the  body; and if the  physician and the cook had to


Gorgias

GORGIAS 44



Top




Page No 47


enter into a competition in  which  children were the judges, or men who had no more sense than children,  as

to which of them best understands the goodness or badness of food,  the  physician would be starved to death.

A flattery I deem this to be  and of  an ignoble sort, Polus, for to you I am now addressing myself,  because it

aims at pleasure without any thought of the best.  An art I  do not call it,  but only an experience, because it is

unable to  explain or to give a reason  of the nature of its own applications.  And I do not call any irrational

thing an art; but if you dispute my  words, I am prepared to argue in  defence of them. 

Cookery, then, I maintain to be a flattery which takes the form of  medicine; and tiring, in like manner, is a

flattery which takes the  form of  gymnastic, and is knavish, false, ignoble, illiberal, working  deceitfully  by the

help of lines, and colours, and enamels, and  garments, and making  men affect a spurious beauty to the neglect

of  the true beauty which is  given by gymnastic. 

I would rather not be tedious, and therefore I will only say, after  the  manner of the geometricians (for I think

that by this time you  will be able  to follow) 

as tiring : gymnastic :: cookery : medicine; 

or rather, 

as tiring : gymnastic :: sophistry : legislation; 

and 

as cookery : medicine :: rhetoric : justice. 

And this, I say, is the natural difference between the rhetorician  and the  sophist, but by reason of their near

connection, they are apt  to be jumbled  up together; neither do they know what to make of  themselves, nor do

other  men know what to make of them.  For if the  body presided over itself, and  were not under the guidance

of the  soul, and the soul did not discern and  discriminate between cookery  and medicine, but the body was

made the judge  of them, and the rule of  judgment was the bodily delight which was given by  them, then the

word  of Anaxagoras, that word with which you, friend Polus,  are so well  acquainted, would prevail far and

wide:  'Chaos' would come  again, and  cookery, health, and medicine would mingle in an indiscriminate  mass.

And now I have told you my notion of rhetoric, which is, in relation  to the soul, what cookery is to the body.

I may have been  inconsistent in  making a long speech, when I would not allow you to  discourse at length.

But I think that I may be excused, because you  did not understand me, and  could make no use of my answer

when I spoke  shortly, and therefore I had to  enter into an explanation.  And if I  show an equal inability to

make use of  yours, I hope that you will  speak at equal length; but if I am able to  understand you, let me have

the benefit of your brevity, as is only fair:  And now you may do what  you please with my answer. 

POLUS: What do you mean? do you think that rhetoric is  flattery? 

SOCRATES: Nay, I said a part of flattery; if at your age,  Polus, you  cannot remember, what will you do

byandby, when you get  older? 

POLUS: And are the good rhetoricians meanly regarded in  states, under the  idea that they are flatterers? 

SOCRATES: Is that a question or the beginning of a speech? 

POLUS: I am asking a question. 

SOCRATES: Then my answer is, that they are not regarded at  all. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 45



Top




Page No 48


POLUS: How not regarded?  Have they not very great power in  states? 

SOCRATES: Not if you mean to say that power is a good to the  possessor. 

POLUS: And that is what I do mean to say. 

SOCRATES: Then, if so, I think that they have the least  power of all the  citizens. 

POLUS: What! are they not like tyrants?  They kill and  despoil and exile  any one whom they please. 

SOCRATES: By the dog, Polus, I cannot make out at each  deliverance of  yours, whether you are giving an

opinion of your own,  or asking a question  of me. 

POLUS: I am asking a question of you. 

SOCRATES: Yes, my friend, but you ask two questions at once. 

POLUS: How two questions? 

SOCRATES: Why, did you not say just now that the  rhetoricians are like  tyrants, and that they kill and

despoil or exile  any one whom they please? 

POLUS: I did. 

SOCRATES: Well then, I say to you that here are two  questions in one, and  I will answer both of them.  And

I tell you,  Polus, that rhetoricians and  tyrants have the least possible power in  states, as I was just now saying;

for they do literally nothing which  they will, but only what they think  best. 

POLUS: And is not that a great power? 

SOCRATES: Polus has already said the reverse. 

POLUS: Said the reverse! nay, that is what I assert. 

SOCRATES: No, by the greatwhat do you call him?not you,  for you say  that power is a good to him

who has the power. 

POLUS: I do. 

SOCRATES: And would you maintain that if a fool does what he  thinks best,  this is a good, and would you

call this great power? 

POLUS: I should not. 

SOCRATES: Then you must prove that the rhetorician is not a  fool, and that  rhetoric is an art and not a

flatteryand so you will  have refuted me; but  if you leave me unrefuted, why, the rhetoricians  who do what

they think  best in states, and the tyrants, will have  nothing upon which to  congratulate themselves, if as you

say, power be  indeed a good, admitting  at the same time that what is done without  sense is an evil. 

POLUS: Yes; I admit that. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 46



Top




Page No 49


SOCRATES: How then can the rhetoricians or the tyrants have  great power in  states, unless Polus can refute

Socrates, and prove to  him that they do as  they will? 

POLUS: This fellow 

SOCRATES: I say that they do not do as they will;now  refute me. 

POLUS: Why, have you not already said that they do as they  think best? 

SOCRATES: And I say so still. 

POLUS: Then surely they do as they will? 

SOCRATES: I deny it. 

POLUS: But they do what they think best? 

SOCRATES: Aye. 

POLUS: That, Socrates, is monstrous and absurd. 

SOCRATES: Good words, good Polus, as I may say in your own  peculiar style;  but if you have any

questions to ask of me, either  prove that I am in error  or give the answer yourself. 

POLUS: Very well, I am willing to answer that I may know  what you mean. 

SOCRATES: Do men appear to you to will that which they do,  or to will that  further end for the sake of

which they do a thing?  when they take medicine,  for example, at the bidding of a physician,  do they will the

drinking of  the medicine which is painful, or the  health for the sake of which they  drink? 

POLUS: Clearly, the health. 

SOCRATES: And when men go on a voyage or engage in business,  they do not  will that which they are

doing at the time; for who would  desire to take  the risk of a voyage or the trouble of business?But  they

will, to have  the wealth for the sake of which they go on a  voyage. 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And is not this universally true?  If a man does  something for  the sake of something else, he

wills not that which he  does, but that for  the sake of which he does it. 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And are not all things either good or evil, or  intermediate and  indifferent? 

POLUS: To be sure, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Wisdom and health and wealth and the like you  would call goods,  and their opposites evils? 

POLUS: I should. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 47



Top




Page No 50


SOCRATES: And the things which are neither good nor evil,  and which  partake sometimes of the nature of

good and at other times  of evil, or of  neither, are such as sitting, walking, running,  sailing; or, again, wood,

stones, and the like:these are the things  which you call neither good nor  evil? 

POLUS: Exactly so. 

SOCRATES: Are these indifferent things done for the sake of  the good, or  the good for the sake of the

indifferent? 

POLUS: Clearly, the indifferent for the sake of the good. 

SOCRATES: When we walk we walk for the sake of the good, and  under the  idea that it is better to walk,

and when we stand we stand  equally for the  sake of the good? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And when we kill a man we kill him or exile him or  despoil him  of his goods, because, as we

think, it will conduce to our  good? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Men who do any of these things do them for the  sake of the good? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And did we not admit that in doing something for  the sake of  something else, we do not will

those things which we do,  but that other  thing for the sake of which we do them? 

POLUS: Most true. 

SOCRATES: Then we do not will simply to kill a man or to  exile him or to  despoil him of his goods, but we

will to do that which  conduces to our  good, and if the act is not conducive to our good we  do not will it; for

we  will, as you say, that which is our good, but  that which is neither good  nor evil, or simply evil, we do not

will.  Why are you silent, Polus?  Am I  not right? 

POLUS: You are right. 

SOCRATES: Hence we may infer, that if any one, whether he be  a tyrant or a  rhetorician, kills another or

exiles another or deprives  him of his  property, under the idea that the act is for his own  interests when really

not for his own interests, he may be said to do  what seems best to him? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But does he do what he wills if he does what is  evil?  Why do  you not answer? 

POLUS: Well, I suppose not. 

SOCRATES: Then if great power is a good as you allow, will  such a one have  great power in a state? 

POLUS: He will not. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 48



Top




Page No 51


SOCRATES: Then I was right in saying that a man may do what  seems good to  him in a state, and not have

great power, and not do  what he wills? 

POLUS: As though you, Socrates, would not like to have the  power of doing  what seemed good to you in the

state, rather than not;  you would not be  jealous when you saw any one killing or despoiling or  imprisoning

whom he  pleased, Oh, no! 

SOCRATES: Justly or unjustly, do you mean? 

POLUS: In either case is he not equally to be envied? 

SOCRATES: Forbear, Polus! 

POLUS: Why 'forbear'? 

SOCRATES: Because you ought not to envy wretches who are not  to be envied,  but only to pity them. 

POLUS: And are those of whom I spoke wretches? 

SOCRATES: Yes, certainly they are. 

POLUS: And so you think that he who slays any one whom he  pleases, and  justly slays him, is pitiable and

wretched? 

SOCRATES: No, I do not say that of him:  but neither do I  think that he is  to be envied. 

POLUS: Were you not saying just now that he is wretched? 

SOCRATES: Yes, my friend, if he killed another unjustly, in  which case he  is also to be pitied; and he is not

to be envied if he  killed him justly. 

POLUS: At any rate you will allow that he who is unjustly  put to death is  wretched, and to be pitied? 

SOCRATES: Not so much, Polus, as he who kills him, and not  so much as he  who is justly killed. 

POLUS: How can that be, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: That may very well be, inasmuch as doing injustice  is the  greatest of evils. 

POLUS: But is it the greatest?  Is not suffering injustice a  greater evil? 

SOCRATES: Certainly not. 

POLUS: Then would you rather suffer than do injustice? 

SOCRATES: I should not like either, but if I must choose  between them, I  would rather suffer than do. 

POLUS: Then you would not wish to be a tyrant? 

SOCRATES: Not if you mean by tyranny what I mean. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 49



Top




Page No 52


POLUS: I mean, as I said before, the power of doing whatever  seems good to  you in a state, killing,

banishing, doing in all things  as you like. 

SOCRATES: Well then, illustrious friend, when I have said my  say, do you  reply to me.  Suppose that I go

into a crowded Agora, and  take a dagger  under my arm.  Polus, I say to you, I have just acquired  rare power,

and  become a tyrant; for if I think that any of these men  whom you see ought to  be put to death, the man

whom I have a mind to  kill is as good as dead; and  if I am disposed to break his head or  tear his garment, he

will have his  head broken or his garment torn in  an instant.  Such is my great power in  this city.  And if you do

not  believe me, and I show you the dagger, you  would probably reply:  Socrates, in that sort of way any one

may have great  powerhe may  burn any house which he pleases, and the docks and triremes  of the

Athenians, and all their other vessels, whether public or private  but can you believe that this mere doing as

you think best is great  power? 

POLUS: Certainly not such doing as this. 

SOCRATES: But can you tell me why you disapprove of such a  power? 

POLUS: I can. 

SOCRATES: Why then? 

POLUS: Why, because he who did as you say would be certain  to be punished. 

SOCRATES: And punishment is an evil? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And you would admit once more, my good sir, that  great power is  a benefit to a man if his

actions turn out to his  advantage, and that this  is the meaning of great power; and if not,  then his power is an

evil and is  no power.  But let us look at the  matter in another way:do we not  acknowledge that the things of

which  we were speaking, the infliction of  death, and exile, and the  deprivation of property are sometimes a

good and  sometimes not a good? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: About that you and I may be supposed to agree? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Tell me, then, when do you say that they are good  and when that  they are evilwhat principle

do you lay down? 

POLUS: I would rather, Socrates, that you should answer as  well as ask  that question. 

SOCRATES: Well, Polus, since you would rather have the  answer from me, I  say that they are good when

they are just, and evil  when they are unjust. 

POLUS: You are hard of refutation, Socrates, but might not a  child refute  that statement? 

SOCRATES: Then I shall be very grateful to the child, and  equally grateful  to you if you will refute me and

deliver me from my  foolishness.  And I  hope that refute me you will, and not weary of  doing good to a friend. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 50



Top




Page No 53


POLUS: Yes, Socrates, and I need not go far or appeal to  antiquity; events  which happened only a few days

ago are enough to  refute you, and to prove  that many men who do wrong are happy. 

SOCRATES: What events? 

POLUS: You see, I presume, that Archelaus the son of  Perdiccas is now the  ruler of Macedonia? 

SOCRATES: At any rate I hear that he is. 

POLUS: And do you think that he is happy or miserable? 

SOCRATES: I cannot say, Polus, for I have never had any  acquaintance with  him. 

POLUS: And cannot you tell at once, and without having an  acquaintance  with him, whether a man is

happy? 

SOCRATES: Most certainly not. 

POLUS: Then clearly, Socrates, you would say that you did  not even know  whether the great king was a

happy man? 

SOCRATES: And I should speak the truth; for I do not know  how he stands in  the matter of education and

justice. 

POLUS: What! and does all happiness consist in this? 

SOCRATES: Yes, indeed, Polus, that is my doctrine; the men  and women who  are gentle and good are also

happy, as I maintain, and  the unjust and evil  are miserable. 

POLUS: Then, according to your doctrine, the said Archelaus  is miserable? 

SOCRATES: Yes, my friend, if he is wicked. 

POLUS: That he is wicked I cannot deny; for he had no title  at all to the  throne which he now occupies, he

being only the son of a  woman who was the  slave of Alcetas the brother of Perdiccas; he  himself therefore in

strict  right was the slave of Alcetas; and if he  had meant to do rightly he would  have remained his slave, and

then,  according to your doctrine, he would  have been happy.  But now he is  unspeakably miserable, for he has

been  guilty of the greatest crimes:  in the first place he invited his uncle and  master, Alcetas, to come  to him,

under the pretence that he would restore  to him the throne  which Perdiccas has usurped, and after entertaining

him  and his son  Alexander, who was his own cousin, and nearly of an age with  him, and  making them drunk,

he threw them into a waggon and carried them  off by  night, and slew them, and got both of them out of the

way; and when  he  had done all this wickedness he never discovered that he was the most  miserable of all

men, and was very far from repenting:  shall I tell  you  how he showed his remorse? he had a younger brother,

a child of  seven years  old, who was the legitimate son of Perdiccas, and to him  of right the  kingdom

belonged; Archelaus, however, had no mind to  bring him up as he  ought and restore the kingdom to him; that

was not  his notion of happiness;  but not long afterwards he threw him into a  well and drowned him, and

declared to his mother Cleopatra that he had  fallen in while running after  a goose, and had been killed.  And

now  as he is the greatest criminal of  all the Macedonians, he may be  supposed to be the most miserable and

not  the happiest of them, and I  dare say that there are many Athenians, and you  would be at the head  of them,

who would rather be any other Macedonian than  Archelaus! 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 51



Top




Page No 54


SOCRATES: I praised you at first, Polus, for being a  rhetorician rather  than a reasoner.  And this, as I

suppose, is the  sort of argument with  which you fancy that a child might refute me,  and by which I stand

refuted  when I say that the unjust man is not  happy.  But, my good friend, where is  the refutation?  I cannot

admit  a word which you have been saying. 

POLUS: That is because you will not; for you surely must  think as I do. 

SOCRATES: Not so, my simple friend, but because you will  refute me after  the manner which rhetoricians

practise in courts of  law.  For there the one  party think that they refute the other when  they bring forward a

number of  witnesses of good repute in proof of  their allegations, and their adversary  has only a single one or

none  at all.  But this kind of proof is of no  value where truth is the aim;  a man may often be sworn down by a

multitude  of false witnesses who  have a great air of respectability.  And in this  argument nearly every  one,

Athenian and stranger alike, would be on your  side, if you should  bring witnesses in disproof of my

statement;you may,  if you will,  summon Nicias the son of Niceratus, and let his brothers, who  gave the

row of tripods which stand in the precincts of Dionysus, come with  him; or you may summon Aristocrates,

the son of Scellius, who is the  giver  of that famous offering which is at Delphi; summon, if you will,  the

whole  house of Pericles, or any other great Athenian family whom  you choose;  they will all agree with

you:  I only am left alone and  cannot agree, for  you do not convince me; although you produce many  false

witnesses against  me, in the hope of depriving me of my  inheritance, which is the truth.  But  I consider that

nothing worth  speaking of will have been effected by me  unless I make you the one  witness of my words; nor

by you, unless you make  me the one witness of  yours; no matter about the rest of the world.  For  there are two

ways  of refutation, one which is yours and that of the world  in general;  but mine is of another sortlet us

compare them, and see in  what they  differ.  For, indeed, we are at issue about matters which to know  is

honourable and not to know disgraceful; to know or not to know  happiness  and miserythat is the chief of

them.  And what knowledge  can be nobler?  or what ignorance more disgraceful than this?  And  therefore I will

begin  by asking you whether you do not think that a  man who is unjust and doing  injustice can be happy,

seeing that you  think Archelaus unjust, and yet  happy?  May I assume this to be your  opinion? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: But I say that this is an impossibilityhere is  one point about  which we are at issue:very

good.  And do you mean to  say also that if he  meets with retribution and punishment he will  still be happy? 

POLUS: Certainly not; in that case he will be most  miserable. 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, if the unjust be not punished,  then,  according to you, he will be happy? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But in my opinion, Polus, the unjust or doer of  unjust actions  is miserable in any case,more

miserable, however, if  he be not punished  and does not meet with retribution, and less  miserable if he be

punished  and meets with retribution at the hands of  gods and men. 

POLUS: You are maintaining a strange doctrine, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: I shall try to make you agree with me, O my  friend, for as a  friend I regard you.  Then these are

the points at  issue between usare  they not?  I was saying that to do is worse than  to suffer injustice? 

POLUS: Exactly so. 

SOCRATES: And you said the opposite? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 52



Top




Page No 55


POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: I said also that the wicked are miserable, and you  refuted me? 

POLUS: By Zeus, I did. 

SOCRATES: In your own opinion, Polus. 

POLUS: Yes, and I rather suspect that I was in the right. 

SOCRATES: You further said that the wrongdoer is happy if  he be  unpunished? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And I affirm that he is most miserable, and that  those who are  punished are less

miserableare you going to refute  this proposition also? 

POLUS: A proposition which is harder of refutation than the  other,  Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Say rather, Polus, impossible; for who can refute  the truth? 

POLUS: What do you mean?  If a man is detected in an unjust  attempt to  make himself a tyrant, and when

detected is racked,  mutilated, has his eyes  burned out, and after having had all sorts of  great injuries inflicted

on  him, and having seen his wife and children  suffer the like, is at last  impaled or tarred and burned alive,

will  he be happier than if he escape  and become a tyrant, and continue all  through life doing what he likes

and  holding the reins of government,  the envy and admiration both of citizens  and strangers?  Is that the

paradox which, as you say, cannot be refuted? 

SOCRATES: There again, noble Polus, you are raising  hobgoblins instead of  refuting me; just now you were

calling witnesses  against me.  But please to  refresh my memory a little; did you  say'in an unjust attempt to

make  himself a tyrant'? 

POLUS: Yes, I did. 

SOCRATES: Then I say that neither of them will be happier  than the other,  neither he who unjustly

acquires a tyranny, nor he  who suffers in the  attempt, for of two miserables one cannot be the  happier, but

that he who  escapes and becomes a tyrant is the more  miserable of the two.  Do you  laugh, Polus?  Well, this is

a new kind  of refutation,when any one says  anything, instead of refuting him to  laugh at him. 

POLUS: But do you not think, Socrates, that you have been  sufficiently  refuted, when you say that which no

human being will  allow?  Ask the  company. 

SOCRATES: O Polus, I am not a public man, and only last  year, when my  tribe were serving as Prytanes,

and it became my duty as  their president to  take the votes, there was a laugh at me, because I  was unable to

take them.  And as I failed then, you must not ask me to  count the suffrages of the  company now; but if, as I

was saying, you  have no better argument than  numbers, let me have a turn, and do you  make trial of the sort

of proof  which, as I think, is required; for I  shall produce one witness only of the  truth of my words, and he is

the  person with whom I am arguing; his  suffrage I know how to take; but  with the many I have nothing to do,

and do  not even address myself to  them.  May I ask then whether you will answer in  turn and have your  words

put to the proof?  For I certainly think that I  and you and  every man do really believe, that to do is a greater

evil than  to  suffer injustice:  and not to be punished than to be punished. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 53



Top




Page No 56


POLUS: And I should say neither I, nor any man:  would you  yourself, for  example, suffer rather than do

injustice? 

SOCRATES: Yes, and you, too; I or any man would. 

POLUS: Quite the reverse; neither you, nor I, nor any man. 

SOCRATES: But will you answer? 

POLUS: To be sure, I will; for I am curious to hear what you  can have to  say. 

SOCRATES: Tell me, then, and you will know, and let us  suppose that I am  beginning at the beginning:

which of the two,  Polus, in your opinion, is  the worst?to do injustice or to suffer? 

POLUS: I should say that suffering was worst. 

SOCRATES: And which is the greater disgrace?Answer. 

POLUS: To do. 

SOCRATES: And the greater disgrace is the greater evil? 

POLUS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: I understand you to say, if I am not mistaken,  that the  honourable is not the same as the good,

or the disgraceful as  the evil? 

POLUS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Let me ask a question of you:  When you speak of  beautiful  things, such as bodies, colours,

figures, sounds,  institutions, do you not  call them beautiful in reference to some  standard:  bodies, for

example,  are beautiful in proportion as they  are useful, or as the sight of them  gives pleasure to the spectators;

can you give any other account of  personal beauty? 

POLUS: I cannot. 

SOCRATES: And you would say of figures or colours generally  that they were  beautiful, either by reason of

the pleasure which they  give, or of their  use, or of both? 

POLUS: Yes, I should. 

SOCRATES: And you would call sounds and music beautiful for  the same  reason? 

POLUS: I should. 

SOCRATES: Laws and institutions also have no beauty in them  except in so  far as they are useful or

pleasant or both? 

POLUS: I think not. 

SOCRATES: And may not the same be said of the beauty of  knowledge? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 54



Top




Page No 57


POLUS: To be sure, Socrates; and I very much approve of your  measuring  beauty by the standard of

pleasure and utility. 

SOCRATES: And deformity or disgrace may be equally measured  by the  opposite standard of pain and evil? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then when of two beautiful things one exceeds in  beauty, the  measure of the excess is to be

taken in one or both of  these; that is to  say, in pleasure or utility or both? 

POLUS: Very true. 

SOCRATES: And of two deformed things, that which exceeds in  deformity or  disgrace, exceeds either in

pain or evilmust it not be  so? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But then again, what was the observation which you  just now  made, about doing and suffering

wrong?  Did you not say, that  suffering  wrong was more evil, and doing wrong more disgraceful? 

POLUS: I did. 

SOCRATES: Then, if doing wrong is more disgraceful than  suffering, the  more disgraceful must be more

painful and must exceed  in pain or in evil or  both:  does not that also follow? 

POLUS: Of course. 

SOCRATES: First, then, let us consider whether the doing of  injustice  exceeds the suffering in the

consequent pain:  Do the  injurers suffer more  than the injured? 

POLUS: No, Socrates; certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Then they do not exceed in pain? 

POLUS: No. 

SOCRATES: But if not in pain, then not in both? 

POLUS: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: Then they can only exceed in the other? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: That is to say, in evil? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: Then doing injustice will have an excess of evil,  and will  therefore be a greater evil than

suffering injustice? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 55



Top




Page No 58


POLUS: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: But have not you and the world already agreed that  to do  injustice is more disgraceful than to

suffer? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And that is now discovered to be more evil? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And would you prefer a greater evil or a greater  dishonour to a  less one?  Answer, Polus, and

fear not; for you will  come to no harm if you  nobly resign yourself into the healing hand of  the argument as

to a  physician without shrinking, and either say 'Yes'  or 'No' to me. 

POLUS: I should say 'No.' 

SOCRATES: Would any other man prefer a greater to a less  evil? 

POLUS: No, not according to this way of putting the case,  Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Then I said truly, Polus, that neither you, nor I,  nor any man,  would rather do than suffer

injustice; for to do  injustice is the greater  evil of the two. 

POLUS: That is the conclusion. 

SOCRATES: You see, Polus, when you compare the two kinds of  refutations,  how unlike they are.  All men,

with the exception of  myself, are of your  way of thinking; but your single assent and  witness are enough for

me,I  have no need of any other, I take your  suffrage, and am regardless of the  rest.  Enough of this, and

now let  us proceed to the next question; which  is, Whether the greatest of  evils to a guilty man is to suffer

punishment,  as you supposed, or  whether to escape punishment is not a greater evil, as  I supposed.

Consider:You would say that to suffer punishment is another  name  for being justly corrected when you do

wrong? 

POLUS: I should. 

SOCRATES: And would you not allow that all just things are  honourable in  so far as they are just?  Please to

reflect, and tell me  your opinion. 

POLUS: Yes, Socrates, I think that they are. 

SOCRATES: Consider again:Where there is an agent, must  there not also be  a patient? 

POLUS: I should say so. 

SOCRATES: And will not the patient suffer that which the  agent does, and  will not the suffering have the

quality of the action?  I mean, for  example, that if a man strikes, there must be something  which is stricken? 

POLUS: Yes. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 56



Top




Page No 59


SOCRATES: And if the striker strikes violently or quickly,  that which is  struck will he struck violently or

quickly? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And the suffering to him who is stricken is of the  same nature  as the act of him who strikes? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if a man burns, there is something which is  burned? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And if he burns in excess or so as to cause pain,  the thing  burned will be burned in the same

way? 

POLUS: Truly. 

SOCRATES: And if he cuts, the same argument holdsthere  will be something  cut? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if the cutting be great or deep or such as  will cause pain,  the cut will be of the same

nature? 

POLUS: That is evident. 

SOCRATES: Then you would agree generally to the universal  proposition  which I was just now asserting:

that the affection of the  patient answers  to the affection of the agent? 

POLUS: I agree. 

SOCRATES: Then, as this is admitted, let me ask whether  being punished is  suffering or acting? 

POLUS: Suffering, Socrates; there can be no doubt of that. 

SOCRATES: And suffering implies an agent? 

POLUS: Certainly, Socrates; and he is the punisher. 

SOCRATES: And he who punishes rightly, punishes justly? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And therefore he acts justly? 

POLUS: Justly. 

SOCRATES: Then he who is punished and suffers retribution,  suffers justly? 

POLUS: That is evident. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 57



Top




Page No 60


SOCRATES: And that which is just has been admitted to be  honourable? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then the punisher does what is honourable, and the  punished  suffers what is honourable? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And if what is honourable, then what is good, for  the honourable  is either pleasant or useful? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then he who is punished suffers what is good? 

POLUS: That is true. 

SOCRATES: Then he is benefited? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Do I understand you to mean what I mean by the  term 'benefited'?  I mean, that if he be justly

punished his soul is  improved. 

POLUS: Surely. 

SOCRATES: Then he who is punished is delivered from the evil  of his soul? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And is he not then delivered from the greatest  evil?  Look at  the matter in this way:In

respect of a man's estate,  do you see any  greater evil than poverty? 

POLUS: There is no greater evil. 

SOCRATES: Again, in a man's bodily frame, you would say that  the evil is  weakness and disease and

deformity? 

POLUS: I should. 

SOCRATES: And do you not imagine that the soul likewise has  some evil of  her own? 

POLUS: Of course. 

SOCRATES: And this you would call injustice and ignorance  and cowardice,  and the like? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: So then, in mind, body, and estate, which are  three, you have  pointed out three corresponding

evilsinjustice,  disease, poverty? 

POLUS: True. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 58



Top




Page No 61


SOCRATES: And which of the evils is the most  disgraceful?Is not the most  disgraceful of them injustice,

and in  general the evil of the soul? 

POLUS: By far the most. 

SOCRATES: And if the most disgraceful, then also the worst? 

POLUS: What do you mean, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I mean to say, that is most disgraceful has been  already  admitted to be most painful or hurtful,

or both. 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And now injustice and all evil in the soul has  been admitted by  us to be most disgraceful? 

POLUS: It has been admitted. 

SOCRATES: And most disgraceful either because most painful  and causing  excessive pain, or most hurtful,

or both? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And therefore to be unjust and intemperate, and  cowardly and  ignorant, is more painful than to

be poor and sick? 

POLUS: Nay, Socrates; the painfulness does not appear to me  to follow from  your premises. 

SOCRATES: Then, if, as you would argue, not more painful,  the evil of the  soul is of all evils the most

disgraceful; and the  excess of disgrace must  be caused by some preternatural greatness, or  extraordinary

hurtfulness of  the evil. 

POLUS: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: And that which exceeds most in hurtfulness will be  the greatest  of evils? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then injustice and intemperance, and in general  the depravity of  the soul, are the greatest of

evils? 

POLUS: That is evident. 

SOCRATES: Now, what art is there which delivers us from  poverty?  Does not  the art of making money? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And what art frees us from disease?  Does not the  art of  medicine? 

POLUS: Very true. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 59



Top




Page No 62


SOCRATES: And what from vice and injustice?  If you are not  able to answer  at once, ask yourself whither

we go with the sick, and  to whom we take  them. 

POLUS: To the physicians, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: And to whom do we go with the unjust and  intemperate? 

POLUS: To the judges, you mean. 

SOCRATES: Who are to punish them? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And do not those who rightly punish others, punish  them in  accordance with a certain rule of

justice? 

POLUS: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: Then the art of moneymaking frees a man from  poverty; medicine  from disease; and justice

from intemperance and  injustice? 

POLUS: That is evident. 

SOCRATES: Which, then, is the best of these three? 

POLUS: Will you enumerate them? 

SOCRATES: Moneymaking, medicine, and justice. 

POLUS: Justice, Socrates, far excels the two others. 

SOCRATES: And justice, if the best, gives the greatest  pleasure or  advantage or both? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But is the being healed a pleasant thing, and are  those who are  being healed pleased? 

POLUS: I think not. 

SOCRATES: A useful thing, then? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Yes, because the patient is delivered from a great  evil; and  this is the advantage of enduring

the painthat you get  well? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And would he be the happier man in his bodily  condition, who is  healed, or who never was out

of health? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 60



Top




Page No 63


POLUS: Clearly he who was never out of health. 

SOCRATES: Yes; for happiness surely does not consist in  being delivered  from evils, but in never having

had them. 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And suppose the case of two persons who have some  evil in their  bodies, and that one of them

is healed and delivered  from evil, and another  is not healed, but retains the evilwhich of  them is the most

miserable? 

POLUS: Clearly he who is not healed. 

SOCRATES: And was not punishment said by us to be a  deliverance from the  greatest of evils, which is

vice? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And justice punishes us, and makes us more just,  and is the  medicine of our vice? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: He, then, has the first place in the scale of  happiness who has  never had vice in his soul; for

this has been shown  to be the greatest of  evils. 

POLUS: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: And he has the second place, who is delivered from  vice? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: That is to say, he who receives admonition and  rebuke and  punishment? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then he lives worst, who, having been unjust, has  no deliverance  from injustice? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: That is, he lives worst who commits the greatest  crimes, and  who, being the most unjust of

men, succeeds in escaping  rebuke or  correction or punishment; and this, as you say, has been  accomplished

by  Archelaus and other tyrants and rhetoricians and  potentates?  (Compare  Republic.) 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: May not their way of proceeding, my friend, be  compared to the  conduct of a person who is

afflicted with the worst of  diseases and yet  contrives not to pay the penalty to the physician for  his sins

against his  constitution, and will not be cured, because,  like a child, he is afraid of  the pain of being burned or

cut:Is not  that a parallel case? 

POLUS: Yes, truly. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 61



Top




Page No 64


SOCRATES: He would seem as if he did not know the nature of  health and  bodily vigour; and if we are

right, Polus, in our previous  conclusions,  they are in a like case who strive to evade justice,  which they see to

be  painful, but are blind to the advantage which  ensues from it, not knowing  how far more miserable a

companion a  diseased soul is than a diseased body;  a soul, I say, which is corrupt  and unrighteous and

unholy.  And hence they  do all that they can to  avoid punishment and to avoid being released from  the

greatest of  evils; they provide themselves with money and friends, and  cultivate  to the utmost their powers of

persuasion.  But if we, Polus, are  right, do you see what follows, or shall we draw out the consequences  in

form? 

POLUS: If you please. 

SOCRATES: Is it not a fact that injustice, and the doing of  injustice, is  the greatest of evils? 

POLUS: That is quite clear. 

SOCRATES: And further, that to suffer punishment is the way  to be released  from this evil? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And not to suffer, is to perpetuate the evil? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: To do wrong, then, is second only in the scale of  evils; but to  do wrong and not to be punished,

is first and greatest  of all? 

POLUS: That is true. 

SOCRATES: Well, and was not this the point in dispute, my  friend?  You  deemed Archelaus happy, because

he was a very great  criminal and  unpunished:  I, on the other hand, maintained that he or  any other who like

him has done wrong and has not been punished, is,  and ought to be, the most  miserable of all men; and that

the doer of  injustice is more miserable than  the sufferer; and he who escapes  punishment, more miserable

than he who  suffers.Was not that what I  said? 

POLUS: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And it has been proved to be true? 

POLUS: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Well, Polus, but if this is true, where is the  great use of  rhetoric?  If we admit what has been

just now said, every  man ought in  every way to guard himself against doing wrong, for he  will thereby suffer

great evil? 

POLUS: True. 

SOCRATES: And if he, or any one about whom he cares, does  wrong, he ought  of his own accord to go

where he will be immediately  punished; he will run  to the judge, as he would to the physician, in  order that

the disease of  injustice may not be rendered chronic and  become the incurable cancer of  the soul; must we not

allow this  consequence, Polus, if our former  admissions are to stand:is any  other inference consistent with

them? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 62



Top




Page No 65


POLUS: To that, Socrates, there can be but one answer. 

SOCRATES: Then rhetoric is of no use to us, Polus, in  helping a man to  excuse his own injustice, that of his

parents or  friends, or children or  country; but may be of use to any one who  holds that instead of excusing he

ought to accusehimself above all,  and in the next degree his family or  any of his friends who may be  doing

wrong; he should bring to light the  iniquity and not conceal it,  that so the wrongdoer may suffer and be

made  whole; and he should  even force himself and others not to shrink, but with  closed eyes like  brave men

to let the physician operate with knife or  searing iron, not  regarding the pain, in the hope of attaining the good

and  the  honourable; let him who has done things worthy of stripes, allow  himself to be scourged, if of bonds,

to be bound, if of a fine, to be  fined, if of exile, to be exiled, if of death, to die, himself being  the  first to

accuse himself and his own relations, and using rhetoric  to this  end, that his and their unjust actions may be

made manifest,  and that they  themselves may be delivered from injustice, which is the  greatest evil.  Then,

Polus, rhetoric would indeed be useful.  Do you  say 'Yes' or 'No' to  that? 

POLUS: To me, Socrates, what you are saying appears very  strange, though  probably in agreement with your

premises. 

SOCRATES: Is not this the conclusion, if the premises are  not disproven? 

POLUS: Yes; it certainly is. 

SOCRATES: And from the opposite point of view, if indeed it  be our duty to  harm another, whether an

enemy or notI except the  case of selfdefence  then I have to be upon my guardbut if my  enemy

injures a third person,  then in every sort of way, by word as  well as deed, I should try to prevent  his being

punished, or appearing  before the judge; and if he appears, I  should contrive that he should  escape, and not

suffer punishment:  if he  has stolen a sum of money,  let him keep what he has stolen and spend it on  him and

his,  regardless of religion and justice; and if he have done things  worthy  of death, let him not die, but rather

be immortal in his wickedness;  or, if this is not possible, let him at any rate be allowed to live as  long  as he

can.  For such purposes, Polus, rhetoric may be useful, but  is of  small if of any use to him who is not

intending to commit  injustice; at  least, there was no such use discovered by us in the  previous discussion. 

CALLICLES: Tell me, Chaerephon, is Socrates in earnest, or  is he joking? 

CHAEREPHON: I should say, Callicles, that he is in most  profound earnest;  but you may well ask him. 

CALLICLES: By the gods, and I will.  Tell me, Socrates, are  you in  earnest, or only in jest?  For if you are in

earnest, and what  you say is  true, is not the whole of human life turned upside down;  and are we not  doing, as

would appear, in everything the opposite of  what we ought to be  doing? 

SOCRATES: O Callicles, if there were not some community of  feelings among  mankind, however varying

in different personsI mean  to say, if every  man's feelings were peculiar to himself and were not  shared by

the rest of  his speciesI do not see how we could ever  communicate our impressions to  one another.  I make

this remark  because I perceive that you and I have a  common feeling.  For we are  lovers both, and both of us

have two loves  apiece:I am the lover of  Alcibiades, the son of Cleinias, and of  philosophy; and you of the

Athenian Demus, and of Demus the son of  Pyrilampes.  Now, I observe  that you, with all your cleverness, do

not  venture to contradict your  favourite in any word or opinion of his; but as  he changes you change,

backwards and forwards.  When the Athenian Demus  denies anything that  you are saying in the assembly, you

go over to his  opinion; and you do  the same with Demus, the fair young son of Pyrilampes.  For you have  not

the power to resist the words and ideas of your loves; and  if a  person were to express surprise at the

strangeness of what you say  from time to time when under their influence, you would probably reply  to  him,

if you were honest, that you cannot help saying what your  loves say  unless they are prevented; and that you


Gorgias

GORGIAS 63



Top




Page No 66


can only be silent  when they are.  Now you must understand that my words are an echo too,  and therefore you

need not wonder at me; but if you want to silence  me, silence philosophy,  who is my love, for she is always

telling me  what I am now telling you, my  friend; neither is she capricious like  my other love, for the son of

Cleinias says one thing today and  another thing tomorrow, but philosophy  is always true.  She is the

teacher at whose words you are now wondering,  and you have heard her  yourself.  Her you must refute, and

either show, as  I was saying, that  to do injustice and to escape punishment is not the  worst of all  evils; or, if

you leave her word unrefuted, by the dog the god  of  Egypt, I declare, O Callicles, that Callicles will never be

at one with  himself, but that his whole life will be a discord.  And yet, my  friend, I  would rather that my lyre

should be inharmonious, and that  there should be  no music in the chorus which I provided; aye, or that  the

whole world  should be at odds with me, and oppose me, rather than  that I myself should  be at odds with

myself, and contradict myself. 

CALLICLES: O Socrates, you are a regular declaimer, and seem  to be running  riot in the argument.  And

now you are declaiming in  this way because Polus  has fallen into the same error himself of which  he accused

Gorgias:for he  said that when Gorgias was asked by you,  whether, if some one came to him  who wanted to

learn rhetoric, and did  not know justice, he would teach him  justice, Gorgias in his modesty  replied that he

would, because he thought  that mankind in general  would be displeased if he answered 'No'; and then  in

consequence of  this admission, Gorgias was compelled to contradict  himself, that  being just the sort of thing

in which you delight.  Whereupon  Polus  laughed at you deservedly, as I think; but now he has himself fallen

into the same trap.  I cannot say very much for his wit when he  conceded to  you that to do is more

dishonourable than to suffer  injustice, for this was  the admission which led to his being entangled  by you;

and because he was  too modest to say what he thought, he had  his mouth stopped.  For the truth  is, Socrates,

that you, who pretend  to be engaged in the pursuit of truth,  are appealing now to the  popular and vulgar

notions of right, which are not  natural, but only  conventional.  Convention and nature are generally at  variance

with  one another:  and hence, if a person is too modest to say  what he  thinks, he is compelled to contradict

himself; and you, in your  ingenuity perceiving the advantage to be thereby gained, slyly ask of  him  who is

arguing conventionally a question which is to be determined  by the  rule of nature; and if he is talking of the

rule of nature, you  slip away  to custom:  as, for instance, you did in this very  discussion about doing  and

suffering injustice.  When Polus was  speaking of the conventionally  dishonourable, you assailed him from  the

point of view of nature; for by  the rule of nature, to suffer  injustice is the greater disgrace because the  greater

evil; but  conventionally, to do evil is the more disgraceful.  For  the suffering  of injustice is not the part of a

man, but of a slave, who  indeed had  better die than live; since when he is wronged and trampled  upon, he  is

unable to help himself, or any other about whom he cares.  The  reason, as I conceive, is that the makers of

laws are the majority who  are  weak; and they make laws and distribute praises and censures with  a view to

themselves and to their own interests; and they terrify the  stronger sort  of men, and those who are able to get

the better of  them, in order that  they may not get the better of them; and they say,  that dishonesty is  shameful

and unjust; meaning, by the word  injustice, the desire of a man to  have more than his neighbours; for

knowing their own inferiority, I suspect  that they are too glad of  equality.  And therefore the endeavour to

have  more than the many, is  conventionally said to be shameful and unjust, and  is called injustice  (compare

Republic), whereas nature herself intimates  that it is just  for the better to have more than the worse, the more

powerful than the  weaker; and in many ways she shows, among men as well as  among  animals, and indeed

among whole cities and races, that justice  consists in the superior ruling over and having more than the

inferior.  For on what principle of justice did Xerxes invade Hellas,  or his father  the Scythians? (not to speak

of numberless other  examples).  Nay, but these  are the men who act according to nature;  yes, by Heaven, and

according to  the law of nature:  not, perhaps,  according to that artificial law, which  we invent and impose

upon our  fellows, of whom we take the best and  strongest from their youth  upwards, and tame them like

young lions,  charming them with the  sound of the voice, and saying to them, that with  equality they must

be content, and that the equal is the honourable and the  just.  But if  there were a man who had sufficient force,

he would shake off  and  break through, and escape from all this; he would trample under foot  all our formulas

and spells and charms, and all our laws which are  against  nature:  the slave would rise in rebellion and be lord

over  us, and the  light of natural justice would shine forth.  And this I  take to be the  sentiment of Pindar, when


Gorgias

GORGIAS 64



Top




Page No 67


he says in his poem, that 

'Law is the king of all, of mortals as well as of immortals;' 

this, as he says, 

'Makes might to be right, doing violence with highest hand; as I  infer from  the deeds of Heracles, for without

buying them' (Fragm.  Incert. 151  (Bockh).) 

I do not remember the exact words, but the meaning is, that  without  buying them, and without their being

given to him, he carried  off the oxen  of Geryon, according to the law of natural right, and  that the oxen and

other possessions of the weaker and inferior  properly belong to the  stronger and superior.  And this is true, as

you may ascertain, if you will  leave philosophy and go on to higher  things:  for philosophy, Socrates, if

pursued in moderation and at the  proper age, is an elegant accomplishment,  but too much philosophy is  the

ruin of human life.  Even if a man has good  parts, still, if he  carries philosophy into later life, he is necessarily

ignorant of all  those things which a gentleman and a person of honour ought  to know;  he is inexperienced in

the laws of the State, and in the language  which ought to be used in the dealings of man with man, whether

private or  public, and utterly ignorant of the pleasures and desires  of mankind and of  human character in

general.  And people of this  sort, when they betake  themselves to politics or business, are as  ridiculous as I

imagine the  politicians to be, when they make their  appearance in the arena of  philosophy.  For, as Euripides

says, 

'Every man shines in that and pursues that, and devotes the  greatest  portion of the day to that in which he

most excels,'  (Antiope, fragm. 20  (Dindorf).) 

but anything in which he is inferior, he avoids and depreciates,  and  praises the opposite from partiality to

himself, and because he  thinks that  he will thus praise himself.  The true principle is to  unite them.

Philosophy, as a part of education, is an excellent thing,  and there is no  disgrace to a man while he is young

in pursuing such a  study; but when he  is more advanced in years, the thing becomes  ridiculous, and I feel

towards  philosophers as I do towards those who  lisp and imitate children.  For I  love to see a little child, who

is  not of an age to speak plainly, lisping  at his play; there is an  appearance of grace and freedom in his

utterance,  which is natural to  his childish years.  But when I hear some small  creature carefully  articulating its

words, I am offended; the sound is  disagreeable, and  has to my ears the twang of slavery.  So when I hear a

man lisping, or  see him playing like a child, his behaviour appears to me  ridiculous  and unmanly and worthy

of stripes.  And I have the same feeling  about  students of philosophy; when I see a youth thus engaged,the

study  appears to me to be in character, and becoming a man of liberal  education,  and him who neglects

philosophy I regard as an inferior  man, who will never  aspire to anything great or noble.  But if I see  him

continuing the study  in later life, and not leaving off, I should  like to beat him, Socrates;  for, as I was saying,

such a one, even  though he have good natural parts,  becomes effeminate.  He flies from  the busy centre and

the marketplace, in  which, as the poet says, men  become distinguished; he creeps into a corner  for the rest

of his  life, and talks in a whisper with three or four  admiring youths, but  never speaks out like a freeman in a

satisfactory  manner.  Now I,  Socrates, am very well inclined towards you, and my feeling  may be  compared

with that of Zethus towards Amphion, in the play of  Euripides, whom I was mentioning just now:  for I am

disposed to say  to you  much what Zethus said to his brother, that you, Socrates, are  careless  about the things

of which you ought to be careful; and that  you 

'Who have a soul so noble, are remarkable for a puerile exterior;  Neither in a court of justice could you state a

case, or give any  reason or  proof,  Or offer valiant counsel on another's behalf.' 

And you must not be offended, my dear Socrates, for I am speaking  out of  goodwill towards you, if I ask

whether you are not ashamed of  being thus  defenceless; which I affirm to be the condition not of you  only but


Gorgias

GORGIAS 65



Top




Page No 68


of all  those who will carry the study of philosophy too far.  For suppose that  some one were to take you, or

any one of your sort,  off to prison,  declaring that you had done wrong when you had done no  wrong, you

must  allow that you would not know what to do:there you  would stand giddy and  gaping, and not having a

word to say; and when  you went up before the  Court, even if the accuser were a poor creature  and not good

for much, you  would die if he were disposed to claim the  penalty of death.  And yet,  Socrates, what is the

value of 

'An art which converts a man of sense into a fool,' 

who is helpless, and has no power to save either himself or others,  when he  is in the greatest danger and is

going to be despoiled by his  enemies of  all his goods, and has to live, simply deprived of his  rights of

citizenship?he being a man who, if I may use the  expression, may be boxed  on the ears with impunity.

Then, my good  friend, take my advice, and  refute no more: 

'Learn the philosophy of business, and acquire the reputation of  wisdom.  But leave to others these niceties,' 

whether they are to be described as follies or absurdities: 

'For they will only  Give you poverty for the inmate of your  dwelling.' 

Cease, then, emulating these paltry splitters of words, and emulate  only  the man of substance and honour,

who is well to do. 

SOCRATES: If my soul, Callicles, were made of gold, should I  not rejoice  to discover one of those stones

with which they test gold,  and the very  best possible one to which I might bring my soul; and if  the stone and

I  agreed in approving of her training, then I should  know that I was in a  satisfactory state, and that no other

test was  needed by me. 

CALLICLES: What is your meaning, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: I will tell you; I think that I have found in you  the desired  touchstone. 

CALLICLES: Why? 

SOCRATES: Because I am sure that if you agree with me in any  of the  opinions which my soul forms, I

have at last found the truth  indeed.  For I  consider that if a man is to make a complete trial of  the good or evil

of  the soul, he ought to have three  qualitiesknowledge, goodwill,  outspokenness, which are all  possessed

by you.  Many whom I meet are unable  to make trial of me,  because they are not wise as you are; others are

wise,  but they will  not tell me the truth, because they have not the same  interest in me  which you have; and

these two strangers, Gorgias and Polus,  are  undoubtedly wise men and my very good friends, but they are not

outspoken enough, and they are too modest.  Why, their modesty is so  great  that they are driven to contradict

themselves, first one and  then the other  of them, in the face of a large company, on matters of  the highest

moment.  But you have all the qualities in which these  others are deficient, having  received an excellent

education; to this  many Athenians can testify.  And  you are my friend.  Shall I tell you  why I think so?  I know

that you,  Callicles, and Tisander of Aphidnae,  and Andron the son of Androtion, and  Nausicydes of the deme

of  Cholarges, studied together:  there were four of  you, and I once heard  you advising with one another as to

the extent to  which the pursuit of  philosophy should be carried, and, as I know, you came  to the  conclusion

that the study should not be pushed too much into detail.  You were cautioning one another not to be

overwise; you were afraid  that  too much wisdom might unconsciously to yourselves be the ruin of  you.  And

now when I hear you giving the same advice to me which you  then gave to  your most intimate friends, I have

a sufficient evidence  of your real good  will to me.  And of the frankness of your nature  and freedom from


Gorgias

GORGIAS 66



Top




Page No 69


modesty I  am assured by yourself, and the assurance  is confirmed by your last speech.  Well then, the

inference in the  present case clearly is, that if you agree  with me in an argument  about any point, that point

will have been  sufficiently tested by us,  and will not require to be submitted to any  further test.  For you  could

not have agreed with me, either from lack of  knowledge or from  superfluity of modesty, nor yet from a desire

to deceive  me, for you  are my friend, as you tell me yourself.  And therefore when you  and I  are agreed, the

result will be the attainment of perfect truth.  Now  there is no nobler enquiry, Callicles, than that which you

censure me  for  making,What ought the character of a man to be, and what his  pursuits,  and how far is he to

go, both in maturer years and in youth?  For be  assured that if I err in my own conduct I do not err

intentionally, but  from ignorance.  Do not then desist from advising  me, now that you have  begun, until I have

learned clearly what this is  which I am to practise,  and how I may acquire it.  And if you find me  assenting to

your words, and  hereafter not doing that to which I  assented, call me 'dolt,' and deem me  unworthy of

receiving further  instruction.  Once more, then, tell me what  you and Pindar mean by  natural justice:  Do you

not mean that the superior  should take the  property of the inferior by force; that the better should  rule the

worse, the noble have more than the mean?  Am I not right in my  recollection? 

CALLICLES: Yes; that is what I was saying, and so I still  aver. 

SOCRATES: And do you mean by the better the same as the  superior? for I  could not make out what you

were saying at the  timewhether you meant by  the superior the stronger, and that the  weaker must obey the

stronger, as  you seemed to imply when you said  that great cities attack small ones in  accordance with natural

right,  because they are superior and stronger, as  though the superior and  stronger and better were the same; or

whether the  better may be also  the inferior and weaker, and the superior the worse, or  whether better  is to be

defined in the same way as superior:this is the  point which  I want to have cleared up.  Are the superior and

better and  stronger  the same or different? 

CALLICLES: I say unequivocally that they are the same. 

SOCRATES: Then the many are by nature superior to the one,  against whom,  as you were saying, they make

the laws? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then the laws of the many are the laws of the  superior? 

CALLICLES: Very true. 

SOCRATES: Then they are the laws of the better; for the  superior class are  far better, as you were saying? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And since they are superior, the laws which are  made by them are  by nature good? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And are not the many of opinion, as you were  lately saying, that  justice is equality, and that to

do is more  disgraceful than to suffer  injustice?is that so or not?  Answer,  Callicles, and let no modesty be

found to come in the way; do the many  think, or do they not think thus?I  must beg of you to answer, in

order that if you agree with me I may fortify  myself by the assent of  so competent an authority. 

CALLICLES: Yes; the opinion of the many is what you say. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 67



Top




Page No 70


SOCRATES: Then not only custom but nature also affirms that  to do is more  disgraceful than to suffer

injustice, and that justice  is equality; so that  you seem to have been wrong in your former  assertion, when

accusing me you  said that nature and custom are  opposed, and that I, knowing this, was  dishonestly playing

between  them, appealing to custom when the argument is  about nature, and to  nature when the argument is

about custom? 

CALLICLES: This man will never cease talking nonsense.  At  your age,  Socrates, are you not ashamed to be

catching at words and  chuckling over  some verbal slip? do you not seehave I not told you  already, that by

superior I mean better:  do you imagine me to say,  that if a rabble of  slaves and nondescripts, who are of no

use except  perhaps for their  physical strength, get together, their ipsissima  verba are laws? 

SOCRATES: Ho! my philosopher, is that your line? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: I was thinking, Callicles, that something of the  kind must have  been in your mind, and that is

why I repeated the  question,What is the  superior?  I wanted to know clearly what you  meant; for you surely

do not  think that two men are better than one,  or that your slaves are better than  you because they are

stronger?  Then please to begin again, and tell me who  the better are, if they  are not the stronger; and I will

ask you, great  Sir, to be a little  milder in your instructions, or I shall have to run  away from you. 

CALLICLES: You are ironical. 

SOCRATES: No, by the hero Zethus, Callicles, by whose aid  you were just  now saying many ironical things

against me, I am  not:tell me, then, whom  you mean, by the better? 

CALLICLES: I mean the more excellent. 

SOCRATES: Do you not see that you are yourself using words  which have no  meaning and that you are

explaining nothing?will you  tell me whether you  mean by the better and superior the wiser, or if  not,

whom? 

CALLICLES: Most assuredly, I do mean the wiser. 

SOCRATES: Then according to you, one wise man may often be  superior to ten  thousand fools, and he

ought to rule them, and they  ought to be his  subjects, and he ought to have more than they should.  This is

what I  believe that you mean (and you must not suppose that I  am wordcatching),  if you allow that the one

is superior to the ten  thousand? 

CALLICLES: Yes; that is what I mean, and that is what I  conceive to be  natural justicethat the better and

wiser should rule  and have more than  the inferior. 

SOCRATES: Stop there, and let me ask you what you would say  in this case:  Let us suppose that we are all

together as we are now;  there are several of  us, and we have a large common store of meats and  drinks, and

there are all  sorts of persons in our company having  various degrees of strength and  weakness, and one of us,

being a  physician, is wiser in the matter of food  than all the rest, and he is  probably stronger than some and

not so strong  as others of uswill he  not, being wiser, be also better than we are, and  our superior in this

matter of food? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 68



Top




Page No 71


SOCRATES: Either, then, he will have a larger share of the  meats and  drinks, because he is better, or he will

have the  distribution of all of  them by reason of his authority, but he will  not expend or make use of a  larger

share of them on his own person, or  if he does, he will be punished;  his share will exceed that of some,  and

be less than that of others, and  if he be the weakest of all, he  being the best of all will have the  smallest share

of all,  Callicles:am I not right, my friend? 

CALLICLES: You talk about meats and drinks and physicians  and other  nonsense; I am not speaking of

them. 

SOCRATES: Well, but do you admit that the wiser is the  better?  Answer  'Yes' or 'No.' 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And ought not the better to have a larger share? 

CALLICLES: Not of meats and drinks. 

SOCRATES: I understand:  then, perhaps, of coatsthe  skilfullest weaver  ought to have the largest coat,

and the greatest  number of them, and go  about clothed in the best and finest of them? 

CALLICLES: Fudge about coats! 

SOCRATES: Then the skilfullest and best in making shoes  ought to have the  advantage in shoes; the

shoemaker, clearly, should  walk about in the  largest shoes, and have the greatest number of them? 

CALLICLES: Fudge about shoes!  What nonsense are you  talking? 

SOCRATES: Or, if this is not your meaning, perhaps you would  say that the  wise and good and true

husbandman should actually have a  larger share of  seeds, and have as much seed as possible for his own

land? 

CALLICLES: How you go on, always talking in the same way,  Socrates! 

SOCRATES: Yes, Callicles, and also about the same things. 

CALLICLES: Yes, by the Gods, you are literally always  talking of cobblers  and fullers and cooks and

doctors, as if this had  to do with our argument. 

SOCRATES: But why will you not tell me in what a man must be  superior and  wiser in order to claim a

larger share; will you neither  accept a  suggestion, nor offer one? 

CALLICLES: I have already told you.  In the first place, I  mean by  superiors not cobblers or cooks, but wise

politicians who  understand the  administration of a state, and who are not only wise,  but also valiant and  able

to carry out their designs, and not the men  to faint from want of  soul. 

SOCRATES: See now, most excellent Callicles, how different  my charge  against you is from that which you

bring against me, for you  reproach me  with always saying the same; but I reproach you with never  saying the

same  about the same things, for at one time you were  defining the better and the  superior to be the stronger,

then again as  the wiser, and now you bring  forward a new notion; the superior and  the better are now declared

by you  to be the more courageous:  I wish,  my good friend, that you would tell me,  once for all, whom you

affirm  to be the better and superior, and in what  they are better? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 69



Top




Page No 72


CALLICLES: I have already told you that I mean those who are  wise and  courageous in the administration

of a statethey ought to be  the rulers of  their states, and justice consists in their having more  than their

subjects. 

SOCRATES: But whether rulers or subjects will they or will  they not have  more than themselves, my

friend? 

CALLICLES: What do you mean? 

SOCRATES: I mean that every man is his own ruler; but  perhaps you think  that there is no necessity for him

to rule himself;  he is only required to  rule others? 

CALLICLES: What do you mean by his 'ruling over himself'? 

SOCRATES: A simple thing enough; just what is commonly said,  that a man  should be temperate and

master of himself, and ruler of his  own pleasures  and passions. 

CALLICLES: What innocence! you mean those fools,the  temperate? 

SOCRATES: Certainly:any one may know that to be my  meaning. 

CALLICLES: Quite so, Socrates; and they are really fools,  for how can a  man be happy who is the servant

of anything?  On the  contrary, I plainly  assert, that he who would truly live ought to  allow his desires to wax

to  the uttermost, and not to chastise them;  but when they have grown to their  greatest he should have courage

and  intelligence to minister to them and to  satisfy all his longings.  And  this I affirm to be natural justice and

nobility.  To this however the  many cannot attain; and they blame the  strong man because they are  ashamed of

their own weakness, which they  desire to conceal, and hence  they say that intemperance is base.  As I have

remarked already, they  enslave the nobler natures, and being unable to  satisfy their  pleasures, they praise

temperance and justice out of their  own  cowardice.  For if a man had been originally the son of a king, or had

a nature capable of acquiring an empire or a tyranny or sovereignty,  what  could be more truly base or evil

than temperanceto a man like  him, I say,  who might freely be enjoying every good, and has no one to

stand in his  way, and yet has admitted custom and reason and the  opinion of other men to  be lords over

him?must not he be in a  miserable plight whom the  reputation of justice and temperance hinders  from

giving more to his  friends than to his enemies, even though he be  a ruler in his city?  Nay,  Socrates, for you

profess to be a votary of  the truth, and the truth is  this:that luxury and intemperance and  licence, if they be

provided with  means, are virtue and happinessall  the rest is a mere bauble, agreements  contrary to nature,

foolish talk  of men, nothing worth.  (Compare  Republic.) 

SOCRATES: There is a noble freedom, Callicles, in your way  of approaching  the argument; for what you

say is what the rest of the  world think, but do  not like to say.  And I must beg of you to  persevere, that the true

rule of  human life may become manifest.  Tell  me, then:you say, do you not, that  in the rightlydeveloped

man the  passions ought not to be controlled, but  that we should let them grow  to the utmost and somehow or

other satisfy  them, and that this is  virtue? 

CALLICLES: Yes; I do. 

SOCRATES: Then those who want nothing are not truly said to  be happy? 

CALLICLES: No indeed, for then stones and dead men would be  the happiest  of all. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 70



Top




Page No 73


SOCRATES: But surely life according to your view is an awful  thing; and  indeed I think that Euripides may

have been right in  saying, 

'Who knows if life be not death and death life;' 

and that we are very likely dead; I have heard a philosopher say  that at  this moment we are actually dead, and

that the body (soma) is  our tomb  (sema (compare Phaedr.)), and that the part of the soul which  is the seat  of

the desires is liable to be tossed about by words and  blown up and down;  and some ingenious person,

probably a Sicilian or  an Italian, playing with  the word, invented a tale in which he called  the soulbecause

of its  believing and makebelieve naturea vessel  (An untranslatable pun,dia to  pithanon te kai pistikon

onomase  pithon.), and the ignorant he called the  uninitiated or leaky, and the  place in the souls of the

uninitiated in  which the desires are seated,  being the intemperate and incontinent part,  he compared to a

vessel  full of holes, because it can never be satisfied.  He is not of your  way of thinking, Callicles, for he

declares, that of all  the souls in  Hades, meaning the invisible world (aeides), these uninitiated  or  leaky

persons are the most miserable, and that they pour water into a  vessel which is full of holes out of a colander

which is similarly  perforated.  The colander, as my informer assures me, is the soul, and  the  soul which he

compares to a colander is the soul of the ignorant,  which is  likewise full of holes, and therefore incontinent,

owing to a  bad memory  and want of faith.  These notions are strange enough, but  they show the  principle

which, if I can, I would fain prove to you;  that you should  change your mind, and, instead of the intemperate

and  insatiate life,  choose that which is orderly and sufficient and has a  due provision for  daily needs.  Do I

make any impression on you, and  are you coming over to  the opinion that the orderly are happier than  the

intemperate?  Or do I  fail to persuade you, and, however many  tales I rehearse to you, do you  continue of the

same opinion still? 

CALLICLES: The latter, Socrates, is more like the truth. 

SOCRATES: Well, I will tell you another image, which comes  out of the same  school:Let me request you

to consider how far you  would accept this as an  account of the two lives of the temperate and  intemperate in a

figure:  There are two men, both of whom have a  number of casks; the one man has his  casks sound and

full, one of  wine, another of honey, and a third of milk,  besides others filled  with other liquids, and the

streams which fill them  are few and  scanty, and he can only obtain them with a great deal of toil  and

difficulty; but when his casks are once filled he has no need to feed  them any more, and has no further trouble

with them or care about  them.  The other, in like manner, can procure streams, though not  without  difficulty;

but his vessels are leaky and unsound, and night  and day he is  compelled to be filling them, and if he pauses

for a  moment, he is in an  agony of pain.  Such are their respective  lives:And now would you say  that the

life of the intemperate is  happier than that of the temperate?  Do  I not convince you that the  opposite is the

truth? 

CALLICLES: You do not convince me, Socrates, for the one who  has filled  himself has no longer any

pleasure left; and this, as I was  just now  saying, is the life of a stone:  he has neither joy nor  sorrow after he is

once filled; but the pleasure depends on the  superabundance of the influx. 

SOCRATES: But the more you pour in, the greater the waste;  and the holes  must be large for the liquid to

escape. 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: The life which you are now depicting is not that  of a dead man,  or of a stone, but of a

cormorant; you mean that he is  to be hungering and  eating? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 71



Top




Page No 74


SOCRATES: And he is to be thirsting and drinking? 

CALLICLES: Yes, that is what I mean; he is to have all his  desires about  him, and to be able to live happily

in the gratification  of them. 

SOCRATES: Capital, excellent; go on as you have begun, and  have no shame;  I, too, must disencumber

myself of shame:  and first,  will you tell me  whether you include itching and scratching, provided  you have

enough of  them and pass your life in scratching, in your  notion of happiness? 

CALLICLES: What a strange being you are, Socrates! a regular  moborator. 

SOCRATES: That was the reason, Callicles, why I scared Polus  and Gorgias,  until they were too modest to

say what they thought; but  you will not be  too modest and will not be scared, for you are a brave  man.  And

now,  answer my question. 

CALLICLES: I answer, that even the scratcher would live  pleasantly. 

SOCRATES: And if pleasantly, then also happily? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: But what if the itching is not confined to the  head?  Shall I  pursue the question?  And here,

Callicles, I would have  you consider how  you would reply if consequences are pressed upon you,  especially

if in the  last resort you are asked, whether the life of a  catamite is not terrible,  foul, miserable?  Or would you

venture to  say, that they too are happy, if  they only get enough of what they  want? 

CALLICLES: Are you not ashamed, Socrates, of introducing  such topics into  the argument? 

SOCRATES: Well, my fine friend, but am I the introducer of  these topics,  or he who says without any

qualification that all who  feel pleasure in  whatever manner are happy, and who admits of no  distinction

between good  and bad pleasures?  And I would still ask,  whether you say that pleasure  and good are the same,

or whether there  is some pleasure which is not a  good? 

CALLICLES: Well, then, for the sake of consistency, I will  say that they  are the same. 

SOCRATES: You are breaking the original agreement,  Callicles, and will no  longer be a satisfactory

companion in the  search after truth, if you say  what is contrary to your real opinion. 

CALLICLES: Why, that is what you are doing too, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Then we are both doing wrong.  Still, my dear  friend, I would  ask you to consider whether

pleasure, from whatever  source derived, is the  good; for, if this be true, then the  disagreeable consequences

which have  been darkly intimated must  follow, and many others. 

CALLICLES: That, Socrates, is only your opinion. 

SOCRATES: And do you, Callicles, seriously maintain what you  are saying? 

CALLICLES: Indeed I do. 

SOCRATES: Then, as you are in earnest, shall we proceed with  the argument? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 72



Top




Page No 75


CALLICLES: By all means.  (Or, 'I am in profound earnest.') 

SOCRATES: Well, if you are willing to proceed, determine  this question for  me:There is something, I

presume, which you would  call knowledge? 

CALLICLES: There is. 

SOCRATES: And were you not saying just now, that some  courage implied  knowledge? 

CALLICLES: I was. 

SOCRATES: And you were speaking of courage and knowledge as  two things  different from one another? 

CALLICLES: Certainly I was. 

SOCRATES: And would you say that pleasure and knowledge are  the same, or  not the same? 

CALLICLES: Not the same, O man of wisdom. 

SOCRATES: And would you say that courage differed from  pleasure? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Well, then, let us remember that Callicles, the  Acharnian, says  that pleasure and good are the

same; but that  knowledge and courage are not  the same, either with one another, or  with the good. 

CALLICLES: And what does our friend Socrates, of Foxton,  saydoes he  assent to this, or not? 

SOCRATES: He does not assent; neither will Callicles, when  he sees himself  truly.  You will admit, I

suppose, that good and evil  fortune are opposed  to each other? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if they are opposed to each other, then, like  health and  disease, they exclude one another;

a man cannot have them  both, or be  without them both, at the same time? 

CALLICLES: What do you mean? 

SOCRATES: Take the case of any bodily affection:a man may  have the  complaint in his eyes which is

called ophthalmia? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: But he surely cannot have the same eyes well and  sound at the  same time? 

CALLICLES: Certainly not. 

SOCRATES: And when he has got rid of his ophthalmia, has he  got rid of the  health of his eyes too?  Is the

final result, that he  gets rid of them both  together? 

CALLICLES: Certainly not. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 73



Top




Page No 76


SOCRATES: That would surely be marvellous and absurd? 

CALLICLES: Very. 

SOCRATES: I suppose that he is affected by them, and gets  rid of them in  turns? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And he may have strength and weakness in the same  way, by fits? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Or swiftness and slowness? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And does he have and not have good and happiness,  and their  opposites, evil and misery, in a

similar alternation?  (Compare Republic.) 

CALLICLES: Certainly he has. 

SOCRATES: If then there be anything which a man has and has  not at the  same time, clearly that cannot be

good and evildo we  agree?  Please not  to answer without consideration. 

CALLICLES: I entirely agree. 

SOCRATES: Go back now to our former admissions.Did you say  that to  hunger, I mean the mere state of

hunger, was pleasant or  painful? 

CALLICLES: I said painful, but that to eat when you are  hungry is  pleasant. 

SOCRATES: I know; but still the actual hunger is painful:  am I not right? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And thirst, too, is painful? 

CALLICLES: Yes, very. 

SOCRATES: Need I adduce any more instances, or would you  agree that all  wants or desires are painful? 

CALLICLES: I agree, and therefore you need not adduce any  more instances. 

SOCRATES: Very good.  And you would admit that to drink,  when you are  thirsty, is pleasant? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And in the sentence which you have just uttered,  the word  'thirsty' implies pain? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 74



Top




Page No 77


SOCRATES: And the word 'drinking' is expressive of pleasure,  and of the  satisfaction of the want? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: There is pleasure in drinking? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: When you are thirsty? 

SOCRATES: And in pain? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Do you see the inference:that pleasure and pain  are  simultaneous, when you say that being

thirsty, you drink?  For are  they not  simultaneous, and do they not affect at the same time the  same part,

whether of the soul or the body?which of them is affected  cannot be  supposed to be of any consequence:  Is

not this true? 

CALLICLES: It is. 

SOCRATES: You said also, that no man could have good and  evil fortune at  the same time? 

CALLICLES: Yes, I did. 

SOCRATES: But you admitted, that when in pain a man might  also have  pleasure? 

CALLICLES: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: Then pleasure is not the same as good fortune, or  pain the same  as evil fortune, and therefore

the good is not the same  as the pleasant? 

CALLICLES: I wish I knew, Socrates, what your quibbling  means. 

SOCRATES: You know, Callicles, but you affect not to know. 

CALLICLES: Well, get on, and don't keep fooling:  then you  will know what  a wiseacre you are in your

admonition of me. 

SOCRATES: Does not a man cease from his thirst and from his  pleasure in  drinking at the same time? 

CALLICLES: I do not understand what you are saying. 

GORGIAS: Nay, Callicles, answer, if only for our sakes;we  should like to  hear the argument out. 

CALLICLES: Yes, Gorgias, but I must complain of the habitual  trifling of  Socrates; he is always arguing

about little and unworthy  questions. 

GORGIAS: What matter?  Your reputation, Callicles, is not at  stake.  Let  Socrates argue in his own fashion. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 75



Top




Page No 78


CALLICLES: Well, then, Socrates, you shall ask these little  peddling  questions, since Gorgias wishes to

have them. 

SOCRATES: I envy you, Callicles, for having been initiated  into the great  mysteries before you were

initiated into the lesser.  I  thought that this  was not allowable.  But to return to our  argument:Does not a

man cease  from thirsting and from the pleasure  of drinking at the same moment? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: And if he is hungry, or has any other desire, does  he not cease  from the desire and the pleasure

at the same moment? 

CALLICLES: Very true. 

SOCRATES: Then he ceases from pain and pleasure at the same  moment? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But he does not cease from good and evil at the  same moment, as  you have admitted:  do you

still adhere to what you  said? 

CALLICLES: Yes, I do; but what is the inference? 

SOCRATES: Why, my friend, the inference is that the good is  not the same  as the pleasant, or the evil the

same as the painful;  there is a cessation  of pleasure and pain at the same moment; but not  of good and evil,

for they  are different.  How then can pleasure be  the same as good, or pain as evil?  And I would have you

look at the  matter in another light, which could  hardly, I think, have been  considered by you when you

identified them:  Are  not the good good  because they have good present with them, as the  beautiful are those

who have beauty present with them? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And do you call the fools and cowards good men?  For you were  saying just now that the

courageous and the wise are the  goodwould you  not say so? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And did you never see a foolish child rejoicing? 

CALLICLES: Yes, I have. 

SOCRATES: And a foolish man too? 

CALLICLES: Yes, certainly; but what is your drift? 

SOCRATES: Nothing particular, if you will only answer. 

CALLICLES: Yes, I have. 

SOCRATES: And did you ever see a sensible man rejoicing or  sorrowing? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 76



Top




Page No 79


CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Which rejoice and sorrow mostthe wise or the  foolish? 

CALLICLES: They are much upon a par, I think, in that  respect. 

SOCRATES: Enough:  And did you ever see a coward in battle? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And which rejoiced most at the departure of the  enemy, the  coward or the brave? 

CALLICLES: I should say 'most' of both; or at any rate, they  rejoiced  about equally. 

SOCRATES: No matter; then the cowards, and not only the  brave, rejoice? 

CALLICLES: Greatly. 

SOCRATES: And the foolish; so it would seem? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And are only the cowards pained at the approach of  their  enemies, or are the brave also

pained? 

CALLICLES: Both are pained. 

SOCRATES: And are they equally pained? 

CALLICLES: I should imagine that the cowards are more  pained. 

SOCRATES: And are they not better pleased at the enemy's  departure? 

CALLICLES: I dare say. 

SOCRATES: Then are the foolish and the wise and the cowards  and the brave  all pleased and pained, as you

were saying, in nearly  equal degree; but are  the cowards more pleased and pained than the  brave? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: But surely the wise and brave are the good, and  the foolish and  the cowardly are the bad? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then the good and the bad are pleased and pained  in a nearly  equal degree? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then are the good and bad good and bad in a nearly  equal degree,  or have the bad the

advantage both in good and evil?  (i.e. in having more  pleasure and more pain.) 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 77



Top




Page No 80


CALLICLES: I really do not know what you mean. 

SOCRATES: Why, do you not remember saying that the good were  good because  good was present with

them, and the evil because evil;  and that pleasures  were goods and pains evils? 

CALLICLES: Yes, I remember. 

SOCRATES: And are not these pleasures or goods present to  those who  rejoiceif they do rejoice? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: Then those who rejoice are good when goods are  present with  them? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And those who are in pain have evil or sorrow  present with them? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And would you still say that the evil are evil by  reason of the  presence of evil? 

CALLICLES: I should. 

SOCRATES: Then those who rejoice are good, and those who are  in pain evil? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: The degrees of good and evil vary with the degrees  of pleasure  and of pain? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Have the wise man and the fool, the brave and the  coward, joy  and pain in nearly equal

degrees? or would you say that  the coward has  more? 

CALLICLES: I should say that he has. 

SOCRATES: Help me then to draw out the conclusion which  follows from our  admissions; for it is good to

repeat and review what  is good twice and  thrice over, as they say.  Both the wise man and the  brave man we

allow to  be good? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the foolish man and the coward to be evil? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And he who has joy is good? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And he who is in pain is evil? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 78



Top




Page No 81


CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: The good and evil both have joy and pain, but,  perhaps, the evil  has more of them? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then must we not infer, that the bad man is as  good and bad as  the good, or, perhaps, even

better?is not this a  further inference which  follows equally with the preceding from the  assertion that the

good and the  pleasant are the same:can this be  denied, Callicles? 

CALLICLES: I have been listening and making admissions to  you, Socrates;  and I remark that if a person

grants you anything in  play, you, like a  child, want to keep hold and will not give it back.  But do you really

suppose that I or any other human being denies that  some pleasures are good  and others bad? 

SOCRATES: Alas, Callicles, how unfair you are! you certainly  treat me as  if I were a child, sometimes

saying one thing, and then  another, as if you  were meaning to deceive me.  And yet I thought at  first that you

were my  friend, and would not have deceived me if you  could have helped.  But I see  that I was mistaken; and

now I suppose  that I must make the best of a bad  business, as they said of old, and  take what I can get out of

you.Well,  then, as I understand you to  say, I may assume that some pleasures are good  and others evil? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: The beneficial are good, and the hurtful are evil? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And the beneficial are those which do some good,  and the hurtful  are those which do some

evil? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Take, for example, the bodily pleasures of eating  and drinking,  which we were just now

mentioningyou mean to say that  those which promote  health, or any other bodily excellence, are good,  and

their opposites evil? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And in the same way there are good pains and there  are evil  pains? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And ought we not to choose and use the good  pleasures and pains? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: But not the evil? 

CALLICLES: Clearly. 

SOCRATES: Because, if you remember, Polus and I have agreed  that all our  actions are to be done for the

sake of the good;and  will you agree with  us in saying, that the good is the end of all our  actions, and that


Gorgias

GORGIAS 79



Top




Page No 82


all our  actions are to be done for the sake of the  good, and not the good for the  sake of them?will you add a

third  vote to our two? 

CALLICLES: I will. 

SOCRATES: Then pleasure, like everything else, is to be  sought for the  sake of that which is good, and not

that which is good  for the sake of  pleasure? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: But can every man choose what pleasures are good  and what are  evil, or must he have art or

knowledge of them in detail? 

CALLICLES: He must have art. 

SOCRATES: Let me now remind you of what I was saying to  Gorgias and Polus;  I was saying, as you will

not have forgotten, that  there were some  processes which aim only at pleasure, and know nothing  of a better

and  worse, and there are other processes which know good  and evil.  And I  considered that cookery, which I

do not call an art,  but only an  experience, was of the former class, which is concerned  with pleasure, and  that

the art of medicine was of the class which is  concerned with the good.  And now, by the god of friendship, I

must beg  you, Callicles, not to jest,  or to imagine that I am jesting with you;  do not answer at random and

contrary to your real opinionfor you  will observe that we are arguing  about the way of human life; and to a

man who has any sense at all, what  question can be more serious than  this?whether he should follow after

that way of life to which you  exhort me, and act what you call the manly  part of speaking in the  assembly,

and cultivating rhetoric, and engaging in  public affairs,  according to the principles now in vogue; or whether

he  should pursue  the life of philosophy;and in what the latter way differs  from the  former.  But perhaps we

had better first try to distinguish them,  as I  did before, and when we have come to an agreement that they are

distinct, we may proceed to consider in what they differ from one  another,  and which of them we should

choose.  Perhaps, however, you do  not even now  understand what I mean? 

CALLICLES: No, I do not. 

SOCRATES: Then I will explain myself more clearly:  seeing  that you and I  have agreed that there is such a

thing as good, and  that there is such a  thing as pleasure, and that pleasure is not the  same as good, and that the

pursuit and process of acquisition of the  one, that is pleasure, is  different from the pursuit and process of

acquisition of the other, which  is goodI wish that you would tell me  whether you agree with me thus far  or

notdo you agree? 

CALLICLES: I do. 

SOCRATES: Then I will proceed, and ask whether you also  agree with me, and  whether you think that I

spoke the truth when I  further said to Gorgias and  Polus that cookery in my opinion is only  an experience,

and not an art at  all; and that whereas medicine is an  art, and attends to the nature and  constitution of the

patient, and  has principles of action and reason in  each case, cookery in attending  upon pleasure never

regards either the  nature or reason of that  pleasure to which she devotes herself, but goes  straight to her end,

nor ever considers or calculates anything, but works  by experience and  routine, and just preserves the

recollection of what she  has usually  done when producing pleasure.  And first, I would have you  consider

whether I have proved what I was saying, and then whether there  are  not other similar processes which have

to do with the soulsome of  them processes of art, making a provision for the soul's highest  interest

others despising the interest, and, as in the previous  case, considering  only the pleasure of the soul, and how

this may be  acquired, but not  considering what pleasures are good or bad, and  having no other aim but to


Gorgias

GORGIAS 80



Top




Page No 83


afford gratification, whether good or bad.  In my opinion, Callicles, there  are such processes, and this is the

sort of thing which I term flattery,  whether concerned with the body  or the soul, or whenever employed with

a  view to pleasure and without  any consideration of good and evil.  And now I  wish that you would  tell me

whether you agree with us in this notion, or  whether you  differ. 

CALLICLES: I do not differ; on the contrary, I agree; for in  that way I  shall soonest bring the argument to

an end, and shall  oblige my friend  Gorgias. 

SOCRATES: And is this notion true of one soul, or of two or  more? 

CALLICLES: Equally true of two or more. 

SOCRATES: Then a man may delight a whole assembly, and yet  have no regard  for their true interests? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Can you tell me the pursuits which delight  mankindor rather,  if you would prefer, let me

ask, and do you  answer, which of them belong to  the pleasurable class, and which of  them not?  In the first

place, what say  you of fluteplaying?  Does  not that appear to be an art which seeks only  pleasure, Callicles,

and  thinks of nothing else? 

CALLICLES: I assent. 

SOCRATES: And is not the same true of all similar arts, as,  for example,  the art of playing the lyre at

festivals? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And what do you say of the choral art and of  dithyrambic  poetry?are not they of the same

nature?  Do you imagine  that Cinesias the  son of Meles cares about what will tend to the moral  improvement

of his  hearers, or about what will give pleasure to the  multitude? 

CALLICLES: There can be no mistake about Cinesias, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: And what do you say of his father, Meles the  harpplayer?  Did  he perform with any view to

the good of his hearers?  Could he be said to  regard even their pleasure?  For his singing was  an infliction to

his  audience.  And of harpplaying and dithyrambic  poetry in general, what  would you say?  Have they not

been invented  wholly for the sake of  pleasure? 

CALLICLES: That is my notion of them. 

SOCRATES: And as for the Muse of Tragedy, that solemn and  august  personagewhat are her aspirations?

Is all her aim and desire  only to  give pleasure to the spectators, or does she fight against  them and refuse  to

speak of their pleasant vices, and willingly  proclaim in word and song  truths welcome and

unwelcome?which in your  judgment is her character? 

CALLICLES: There can be no doubt, Socrates, that Tragedy has  her face  turned towards pleasure and the

gratification of the  audience. 

SOCRATES: And is not that the sort of thing, Callicles,  which we were just  now describing as flattery? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 81



Top




Page No 84


CALLICLES: Quite true. 

SOCRATES: Well now, suppose that we strip all poetry of song  and rhythm  and metre, there will remain

speech?  (Compare Republic.) 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And this speech is addressed to a crowd of people? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then poetry is a sort of rhetoric? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: And do not the poets in the theatres seem to you  to be  rhetoricians? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then now we have discovered a sort of rhetoric  which is  addressed to a crowd of men,

women, and children, freemen and  slaves.  And  this is not much to our taste, for we have described it  as

having the  nature of flattery. 

CALLICLES: Quite true. 

SOCRATES: Very good.  And what do you say of that other  rhetoric which  addresses the Athenian assembly

and the assemblies of  freemen in other  states?  Do the rhetoricians appear to you always to  aim at what is best,

and do they seek to improve the citizens by their  speeches, or are they  too, like the rest of mankind, bent upon

giving  them pleasure, forgetting  the public good in the thought of their own  interest, playing with the  people

as with children, and trying to  amuse them, but never considering  whether they are better or worse for  this? 

CALLICLES: I must distinguish.  There are some who have a  real care of the  public in what they say, while

others are such as you  describe. 

SOCRATES: I am contented with the admission that rhetoric is  of two sorts;  one, which is mere flattery and

disgraceful declamation;  the other, which  is noble and aims at the training and improvement of  the souls of

the  citizens, and strives to say what is best, whether  welcome or unwelcome, to  the audience; but have you

ever known such a  rhetoric; or if you have, and  can point out any rhetorician who is of  this stamp, who is he? 

CALLICLES: But, indeed, I am afraid that I cannot tell you  of any such  among the orators who are at

present living. 

SOCRATES: Well, then, can you mention any one of a former  generation, who  may be said to have

improved the Athenians, who found  them worse and made  them better, from the day that he began to make

speeches? for, indeed, I do  not know of such a man. 

CALLICLES: What! did you never hear that Themistocles was a  good man, and  Cimon and Miltiades and

Pericles, who is just lately  dead, and whom you  heard yourself? 

SOCRATES: Yes, Callicles, they were good men, if, as you  said at first,  true virtue consists only in the

satisfaction of our  own desires and those  of others; but if not, and if, as we were  afterwards compelled to


Gorgias

GORGIAS 82



Top




Page No 85


acknowledge, the satisfaction of some desires  makes us better, and of  others, worse, and we ought to gratify

the one  and not the other, and there  is an art in distinguishing them,can  you tell me of any of these

statesmen who did distinguish them? 

CALLICLES: No, indeed, I cannot. 

SOCRATES: Yet, surely, Callicles, if you look you will find  such a one.  Suppose that we just calmly

consider whether any of these  was such as I  have described.  Will not the good man, who says  whatever he

says with a  view to the best, speak with a reference to  some standard and not at  random; just as all other

artists, whether  the painter, the builder, the  shipwright, or any other look all of  them to their own work, and

do not  select and apply at random what  they apply, but strive to give a definite  form to it?  The artist  disposes

all things in order, and compels the one  part to harmonize  and accord with the other part, until he has

constructed  a regular and  systematic whole; and this is true of all artists, and in the  same way  the trainers and

physicians, of whom we spoke before, give order  and  regularity to the body:  do you deny this? 

CALLICLES: No; I am ready to admit it. 

SOCRATES: Then the house in which order and regularity  prevail is good;  that in which there is disorder,

evil? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the same is true of a ship? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And the same may be said of the human body? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And what would you say of the soul?  Will the good  soul be that  in which disorder is prevalent,

or that in which there is  harmony and  order? 

CALLICLES: The latter follows from our previous admissions. 

SOCRATES: What is the name which is given to the effect of  harmony and  order in the body? 

CALLICLES: I suppose that you mean health and strength? 

SOCRATES: Yes, I do; and what is the name which you would  give to the  effect of harmony and order in

the soul?  Try and discover  a name for this  as well as for the other. 

CALLICLES: Why not give the name yourself, Socrates? 

SOCRATES: Well, if you had rather that I should, I will; and  you shall say  whether you agree with me, and

if not, you shall refute  and answer me.  'Healthy,' as I conceive, is the name which is given to  the regular order

of the body, whence comes health and every other  bodily excellence:  is  that true or not? 

CALLICLES: True. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 83



Top




Page No 86


SOCRATES: And 'lawful' and 'law' are the names which are  given to the  regular order and action of the

soul, and these make men  lawful and  orderly:and so we have temperance and justice:  have we  not? 

CALLICLES: Granted. 

SOCRATES: And will not the true rhetorician who is honest  and understands  his art have his eye fixed upon

these, in all the  words which he addresses  to the souls of men, and in all his actions,  both in what he gives

and in  what he takes away?  Will not his aim be  to implant justice in the souls of  his citizens and take away

injustice, to implant temperance and take away  intemperance, to  implant every virtue and take away every

vice?  Do you not  agree? 

CALLICLES: I agree. 

SOCRATES: For what use is there, Callicles, in giving to the  body of a  sick man who is in a bad state of

health a quantity of the  most delightful  food or drink or any other pleasant thing, which may  be really as bad

for  him as if you gave him nothing, or even worse if  rightly estimated.  Is not  that true? 

CALLICLES: I will not say No to it. 

SOCRATES: For in my opinion there is no profit in a man's  life if his body  is in an evil plightin that case

his life also is  evil:  am I not right? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: When a man is in health the physicians will  generally allow him  to eat when he is hungry and

drink when he is  thirsty, and to satisfy his  desires as he likes, but when he is sick  they hardly suffer him to

satisfy  his desires at all:  even you will  admit that? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And does not the same argument hold of the soul,  my good sir?  While she is in a bad state and

is senseless and  intemperate and unjust and  unholy, her desires ought to be controlled,  and she ought to be

prevented  from doing anything which does not tend  to her own improvement. 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Such treatment will be better for the soul  herself? 

CALLICLES: To be sure. 

SOCRATES: And to restrain her from her appetites is to  chastise her? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then restraint or chastisement is better for the  soul than  intemperance or the absence of

control, which you were just  now preferring? 

CALLICLES: I do not understand you, Socrates, and I wish  that you would  ask some one who does. 

SOCRATES: Here is a gentleman who cannot endure to be  improved or to  subject himself to that very

chastisement of which the  argument speaks! 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 84



Top




Page No 87


CALLICLES: I do not heed a word of what you are saying, and  have only  answered hitherto out of civility

to Gorgias. 

SOCRATES: What are we to do, then?  Shall we break off in  the middle? 

CALLICLES: You shall judge for yourself. 

SOCRATES: Well, but people say that 'a tale should have a  head and not  break off in the middle,' and I

should not like to have  the argument going  about without a head (compare Laws); please then to  go on a little

longer,  and put the head on. 

CALLICLES: How tyrannical you are, Socrates!  I wish that  you and your  argument would rest, or that you

would get some one else  to argue with you. 

SOCRATES: But who else is willing?I want to finish the  argument. 

CALLICLES: Cannot you finish without my help, either talking  straight on,  or questioning and answering

yourself? 

SOCRATES: Must I then say with Epicharmus, 'Two men spoke  before, but now  one shall be enough'?  I

suppose that there is  absolutely no help.  And if  I am to carry on the enquiry by myself, I  will first of all

remark that not  only I but all of us should have an  ambition to know what is true and what  is false in this

matter, for  the discovery of the truth is a common good.  And now I will proceed to  argue according to my

own notion.  But if any of  you think that I  arrive at conclusions which are untrue you must interpose  and

refute  me, for I do not speak from any knowledge of what I am saying; I  am an  enquirer like yourselves, and

therefore, if my opponent says anything  which is of force, I shall be the first to agree with him.  I am  speaking

on the supposition that the argument ought to be completed;  but if you  think otherwise let us leave off and go

our ways. 

GORGIAS: I think, Socrates, that we should not go our ways  until you have  completed the argument; and

this appears to me to be  the wish of the rest  of the company; I myself should very much like to  hear what

more you have  to say. 

SOCRATES: I too, Gorgias, should have liked to continue the  argument with  Callicles, and then I might

have given him an 'Amphion'  in return for his  'Zethus'; but since you, Callicles, are unwilling to  continue, I

hope that  you will listen, and interrupt me if I seem to  you to be in error.  And if  you refute me, I shall not be

angry with  you as you are with me, but I  shall inscribe you as the greatest of  benefactors on the tablets of my

soul. 

CALLICLES: My good fellow, never mind me, but get on. 

SOCRATES: Listen to me, then, while I recapitulate the  argument:Is the  pleasant the same as the good?

Not the same.  Callicles and I are agreed  about that.  And is the pleasant to be  pursued for the sake of the

good? or  the good for the sake of the  pleasant?  The pleasant is to be pursued for  the sake of the good.  And

that is pleasant at the presence of which we are  pleased, and  that is good at the presence of which we are

good?  To be  sure.  And  we are good, and all good things whatever are good when some  virtue is  present in us

or them?  That, Callicles, is my conviction.  But  the  virtue of each thing, whether body or soul, instrument or

creature,  when given to them in the best way comes to them not by chance but as  the  result of the order and

truth and art which are imparted to them:  Am I not  right?  I maintain that I am.  And is not the virtue of each

thing  dependent on order or arrangement?  Yes, I say.  And that which  makes a  thing good is the proper order

inhering in each thing?  Such  is my view.  And is not the soul which has an order of her own better  than that


Gorgias

GORGIAS 85



Top




Page No 88


which  has no order?  Certainly.  And the soul which has  order is orderly?  Of  course.  And that which is orderly

is temperate?  Assuredly.  And the  temperate soul is good?  No other answer can I  give, Callicles dear; have

you any? 

CALLICLES: Go on, my good fellow. 

SOCRATES: Then I shall proceed to add, that if the temperate  soul is the  good soul, the soul which is in the

opposite condition,  that is, the  foolish and intemperate, is the bad soul.  Very true. 

And will not the temperate man do what is proper, both in relation  to the  gods and to men;for he would not

be temperate if he did not?  Certainly  he will do what is proper.  In his relation to other men he  will do what is

just; and in his relation to the gods he will do what  is holy; and he who  does what is just and holy must be

just and holy?  Very true.  And must he  not be courageous? for the duty of a  temperate man is not to follow or

to  avoid what he ought not, but what  he ought, whether things or men or  pleasures or pains, and patiently  to

endure when he ought; and therefore,  Callicles, the temperate man,  being, as we have described, also just and

courageous and holy, cannot  be other than a perfectly good man, nor can the  good man do otherwise  than

well and perfectly whatever he does; and he who  does well must of  necessity be happy and blessed, and the

evil man who does  evil,  miserable:  now this latter is he whom you were applaudingthe  intemperate who is

the opposite of the temperate.  Such is my  position, and  these things I affirm to be true.  And if they are true,

then I further  affirm that he who desires to be happy must pursue and  practise temperance  and run away from

intemperance as fast as his legs  will carry him:  he had  better order his life so as not to need  punishment; but if

either he or any  of his friends, whether private  individual or city, are in need of  punishment, then justice must

be  done and he must suffer punishment, if he  would be happy.  This  appears to me to be the aim which a man

ought to  have, and towards  which he ought to direct all the energies both of himself  and of the  state, acting so

that he may have temperance and justice present  with  him and be happy, not suffering his lusts to be

unrestrained, and in  the neverending desire satisfy them leading a robber's life.  Such a  one  is the friend

neither of God nor man, for he is incapable of  communion, and  he who is incapable of communion is also

incapable of  friendship.  And  philosophers tell us, Callicles, that communion and  friendship and  orderliness

and temperance and justice bind together  heaven and earth and  gods and men, and that this universe is

therefore  called Cosmos or order,  not disorder or misrule, my friend.  But  although you are a philosopher you

seem to me never to have observed  that geometrical equality is mighty, both  among gods and men; you  think

that you ought to cultivate inequality or  excess, and do not  care about geometry.Well, then, either the

principle  that the happy  are made happy by the possession of justice and temperance,  and the  miserable

miserable by the possession of vice, must be refuted, or,  if  it is granted, what will be the consequences?  All

the consequences  which I drew before, Callicles, and about which you asked me whether I  was  in earnest

when I said that a man ought to accuse himself and his  son and  his friend if he did anything wrong, and that

to this end he  should use his  rhetoricall those consequences are true.  And that  which you thought that

Polus was led to admit out of modesty is true,  viz., that, to do injustice,  if more disgraceful than to suffer, is

in  that degree worse; and the other  position, which, according to Polus,  Gorgias admitted out of modesty, that

he who would truly be a  rhetorician ought to be just and have a knowledge  of justice, has also  turned out to

be true. 

And now, these things being as we have said, let us proceed in the  next  place to consider whether you are

right in throwing in my teeth  that I am  unable to help myself or any of my friends or kinsmen, or to  save them

in  the extremity of danger, and that I am in the power of  another like an  outlaw to whom any one may do

what he likes,he may  box my ears, which was  a brave saying of yours; or take away my goods  or banish

me, or even do his  worst and kill me; a condition which, as  you say, is the height of  disgrace.  My answer to

you is one which has  been already often repeated,  but may as well be repeated once more.  I  tell you,

Callicles, that to be  boxed on the ears wrongfully is not  the worst evil which can befall a man,  nor to have my

purse or my body  cut open, but that to smite and slay me and  mine wrongfully is far  more disgraceful and

more evil; aye, and to despoil  and enslave and  pillage, or in any way at all to wrong me and mine, is far  more


Gorgias

GORGIAS 86



Top




Page No 89


disgraceful and evil to the doer of the wrong than to me who am the  sufferer.  These truths, which have been

already set forth as I state  them  in the previous discussion, would seem now to have been fixed and  riveted  by

us, if I may use an expression which is certainly bold, in  words which  are like bonds of iron and adamant; and

unless you or some  other still more  enterprising hero shall break them, there is no  possibility of denying what

I say.  For my position has always been,  that I myself am ignorant how  these things are, but that I have never

met any one who could say  otherwise, any more than you can, and not  appear ridiculous.  This is my  position

still, and if what I am saying  is true, and injustice is the  greatest of evils to the doer of  injustice, and yet there

is if possible a  greater than this greatest  of evils (compare Republic), in an unjust man  not suffering

retribution, what is that defence of which the want will make  a man  truly ridiculous?  Must not the defence be

one which will avert the  greatest of human evils?  And will not the worst of all defences be  that  with which a

man is unable to defend himself or his family or his  friends?  and next will come that which is unable to

avert the next  greatest evil;  thirdly that which is unable to avert the third  greatest evil; and so of  other evils.

As is the greatness of evil so  is the honour of being able to  avert them in their several degrees,  and the

disgrace of not being able to  avert them.  Am I not right  Callicles? 

CALLICLES: Yes, quite right. 

SOCRATES: Seeing then that there are these two evils, the  doing injustice  and the suffering injusticeand

we affirm that to do  injustice is a  greater, and to suffer injustice a lesser evilby what  devices can a man

succeed in obtaining the two advantages, the one of  not doing and the other  of not suffering injustice? must

he have the  power, or only the will to  obtain them?  I mean to ask whether a man  will escape injustice if he

has  only the will to escape, or must he  have provided himself with the power? 

CALLICLES: He must have provided himself with the power;  that is clear. 

SOCRATES: And what do you say of doing injustice?  Is the  will only  sufficient, and will that prevent him

from doing injustice,  or must he have  provided himself with power and art; and if he have  not studied and

practised, will he be unjust still?  Surely you might  say, Callicles,  whether you think that Polus and I were

right in  admitting the conclusion  that no one does wrong voluntarily, but that  all do wrong against their  will? 

CALLICLES: Granted, Socrates, if you will only have done. 

SOCRATES: Then, as would appear, power and art have to be  provided in  order that we may do no

injustice? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And what art will protect us from suffering  injustice, if not  wholly, yet as far as possible?  I

want to know  whether you agree with me;  for I think that such an art is the art of  one who is either a ruler or

even tyrant himself, or the equal and  companion of the ruling power. 

CALLICLES: Well said, Socrates; and please to observe how  ready I am to  praise you when you talk sense. 

SOCRATES: Think and tell me whether you would approve of  another view of  mine:  To me every man

appears to be most the friend  of him who is most  like to himlike to like, as ancient sages say:  Would you

not agree to  this? 

CALLICLES: I should. 

SOCRATES: But when the tyrant is rude and uneducated, he may  be expected  to fear any one who is his

superior in virtue, and will  never be able to be  perfectly friendly with him. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 87



Top




Page No 90


CALLICLES: That is true. 

SOCRATES: Neither will he be the friend of any one who is  greatly his  inferior, for the tyrant will despise

him, and will never  seriously regard  him as a friend. 

CALLICLES: That again is true. 

SOCRATES: Then the only friend worth mentioning, whom the  tyrant can have,  will be one who is of the

same character, and has the  same likes and  dislikes, and is at the same time willing to be subject  and

subservient to  him; he is the man who will have power in the  state, and no one will injure  him with

impunity:is not that so? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if a young man begins to ask how he may become  great and  formidable, this would seem

to be the wayhe will accustom  himself, from  his youth upward, to feel sorrow and joy on the same

occasions as his  master, and will contrive to be as like him as  possible? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And in this way he will have accomplished, as you  and your  friends would say, the end of

becoming a great man and not  suffering  injury? 

CALLICLES: Very true. 

SOCRATES: But will he also escape from doing injury?  Must  not the very  opposite be true,if he is to be

like the tyrant in his  injustice, and to  have influence with him?  Will he not rather  contrive to do as much

wrong  as possible, and not be punished? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: And by the imitation of his master and by the  power which he  thus acquires will not his soul

become bad and  corrupted, and will not this  be the greatest evil to him? 

CALLICLES: You always contrive somehow or other, Socrates,  to invert  everything:  do you not know that

he who imitates the tyrant  will, if he  has a mind, kill him who does not imitate him and take  away his goods? 

SOCRATES: Excellent Callicles, I am not deaf, and I have  heard that a  great many times from you and from

Polus and from nearly  every man in the  city, but I wish that you would hear me too.  I dare  say that he will kill

him if he has a mindthe bad man will kill the  good and true. 

CALLICLES: And is not that just the provoking thing? 

SOCRATES: Nay, not to a man of sense, as the argument shows:  do you think  that all our cares should be

directed to prolonging life  to the uttermost,  and to the study of those arts which secure us from  danger

always; like  that art of rhetoric which saves men in courts of  law, and which you advise  me to cultivate? 

CALLICLES: Yes, truly, and very good advice too. 

SOCRATES: Well, my friend, but what do you think of  swimming; is that an  art of any great pretensions? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 88



Top




Page No 91


CALLICLES: No, indeed. 

SOCRATES: And yet surely swimming saves a man from death,  and there are  occasions on which he must

know how to swim.  And if you  despise the  swimmers, I will tell you of another and greater art, the  art of the

pilot,  who not only saves the souls of men, but also their  bodies and properties  from the extremity of danger,

just like  rhetoric.  Yet his art is modest  and unpresuming:  it has no airs or  pretences of doing anything

extraordinary, and, in return for the same  salvation which is given by the  pleader, demands only two obols, if

he  brings us from Aegina to Athens, or  for the longer voyage from Pontus  or Egypt, at the utmost two

drachmae,  when he has saved, as I was just  now saying, the passenger and his wife and  children and goods,

and  safely disembarked them at the Piraeus,this is  the payment which he  asks in return for so great a boon;

and he who is the  master of the  art, and has done all this, gets out and walks about on the  seashore  by his

ship in an unassuming way.  For he is able to reflect and  is  aware that he cannot tell which of his

fellowpassengers he has  benefited, and which of them he has injured in not allowing them to be  drowned.

He knows that they are just the same when he has disembarked  them  as when they embarked, and not a whit

better either in their  bodies or in  their souls; and he considers that if a man who is  afflicted by great and

incurable bodily diseases is only to be pitied  for having escaped, and is  in no way benefited by him in having

been  saved from drowning, much less he  who has great and incurable  diseases, not of the body, but of the

soul,  which is the more valuable  part of him; neither is life worth having nor of  any profit to the bad  man,

whether he be delivered from the sea, or the  lawcourts, or any  other devourer;and so he reflects that such

a one had  better not  live, for he cannot live well.  (Compare Republic.) 

And this is the reason why the pilot, although he is our saviour,  is not  usually conceited, any more than the

engineer, who is not at  all behind  either the general, or the pilot, or any one else, in his  saving power, for  he

sometimes saves whole cities.  Is there any  comparison between him and  the pleader?  And if he were to talk,

Callicles, in your grandiose style,  he would bury you under a mountain  of words, declaring and insisting that

we ought all of us to be  enginemakers, and that no other profession is  worth thinking about;  he would have

plenty to say.  Nevertheless you  despise him and his  art, and sneeringly call him an enginemaker, and you

will not allow  your daughters to marry his son, or marry your son to his  daughters.  And yet, on your

principle, what justice or reason is there in  your  refusal?  What right have you to despise the enginemaker,

and the  others whom I was just now mentioning?  I know that you will say, 'I  am  better, and better born.'  But

if the better is not what I say, and  virtue  consists only in a man saving himself and his, whatever may be  his

character, then your censure of the enginemaker, and of the  physician, and  of the other arts of salvation, is

ridiculous.  O my  friend! I want you to  see that the noble and the good may possibly be  something different

from  saving and being saved:May not he who is  truly a man cease to care about  living a certain time?he

knows, as  women say, that no man can escape  fate, and therefore he is not fond  of life; he leaves all that with

God,  and considers in what way he can  best spend his appointed term;whether by  assimilating himself to

the  constitution under which he lives, as you at  this moment have to  consider how you may become as like as

possible to the  Athenian  people, if you mean to be in their good graces, and to have power  in  the state;

whereas I want you to think and see whether this is for the  interest of either of us;I would not have us risk

that which is  dearest  on the acquisition of this power, like the Thessalian  enchantresses, who,  as they say,

bring down the moon from heaven at  the risk of their own  perdition.  But if you suppose that any man will

show you the art of  becoming great in the city, and yet not conforming  yourself to the ways of  the city,

whether for better or worse, then I  can only say that you are  mistaken, Callides; for he who would deserve  to

be the true natural friend  of the Athenian Demus, aye, or of  Pyrilampes' darling who is called after  them,

must be by nature like  them, and not an imitator only.  He, then, who  will make you most like  them, will make

you as you desire, a statesman and  orator:  for every  man is pleased when he is spoken to in his own language

and spirit,  and dislikes any other.  But perhaps you, sweet Callicles, may  be of  another mind.  What do you

say? 

CALLICLES: Somehow or other your words, Socrates, always  appear to me to  be good words; and yet, like

the rest of the world, I  am not quite  convinced by them.  (Compare Symp.:  1 Alcib.) 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 89



Top




Page No 92


SOCRATES: The reason is, Callicles, that the love of Demus  which abides in  your soul is an adversary to

me; but I dare say that  if we recur to these  same matters, and consider them more thoroughly,  you may be

convinced for  all that.  Please, then, to remember that  there are two processes of  training all things, including

body and  soul; in the one, as we said, we  treat them with a view to pleasure,  and in the other with a view to

the  highest good, and then we do not  indulge but resist them:  was not that the  distinction which we drew? 

CALLICLES: Very true. 

SOCRATES: And the one which had pleasure in view was just a  vulgar  flattery:was not that another of

our conclusions? 

CALLICLES: Be it so, if you will have it. 

SOCRATES: And the other had in view the greatest improvement  of that which  was ministered to, whether

body or soul? 

CALLICLES: Quite true. 

SOCRATES: And must we not have the same end in view in the  treatment of  our city and citizens?  Must we

not try and make them as  good as possible?  For we have already discovered that there is no use  in imparting

to them  any other good, unless the mind of those who are  to have the good, whether  money, or office, or any

other sort of  power, be gentle and good.  Shall we  say that? 

CALLICLES: Yes, certainly, if you like. 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if you and I, Callicles, were  intending to set about  some public business, and were

advising one  another to undertake buildings,  such as walls, docks or temples of the  largest size, ought we not

to  examine ourselves, first, as to whether  we know or do not know the art of  building, and who taught

us?would  not that be necessary, Callicles? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: In the second place, we should have to consider  whether we had  ever constructed any private

house, either of our own  or for our friends,  and whether this building of ours was a success or  not; and if

upon  consideration we found that we had had good and  eminent masters, and had  been successful in

constructing many fine  buildings, not only with their  assistance, but without them, by our  own unaided

skillin that case  prudence would not dissuade us from  proceeding to the construction of  public works.  But

if we had no  master to show, and only a number of  worthless buildings or none at  all, then, surely, it would

be ridiculous in  us to attempt public  works, or to advise one another to undertake them.  Is  not this true? 

CALLICLES: Certainly. 

SOCRATES: And does not the same hold in all other cases?  If  you and I  were physicians, and were advising

one another that we were  competent to  practise as statephysicians, should I not ask about you,  and would

you not  ask about me, Well, but how about Socrates himself,  has he good health? and  was any one else ever

known to be cured by  him, whether slave or freeman?  And I should make the same enquiries  about you.  And

if we arrived at the  conclusion that no one, whether  citizen or stranger, man or woman, had ever  been any the

better for  the medical skill of either of us, then, by Heaven,  Callicles, what an  absurdity to think that we or

any human being should be  so silly as to  set up as statephysicians and advise others like ourselves  to do the

same, without having first practised in private, whether  successfully  or not, and acquired experience of the

art!  Is not this, as  they say,  to begin with the big jar when you are learning the potter's art;  which is a foolish


Gorgias

GORGIAS 90



Top




Page No 93


thing? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: And now, my friend, as you are already beginning  to be a public  character, and are

admonishing and reproaching me for  not being one,  suppose that we ask a few questions of one another.  Tell

me, then,  Callicles, how about making any of the citizens  better?  Was there ever a  man who was once

vicious, or unjust, or  intemperate, or foolish, and became  by the help of Callicles good and  noble?  Was there

ever such a man,  whether citizen or stranger, slave  or freeman?  Tell me, Callicles, if a  person were to ask

these  questions of you, what would you answer?  Whom  would you say that you  had improved by your

conversation?  There may have  been good deeds of  this sort which were done by you as a private person,

before you came  forward in public.  Why will you not answer? 

CALLICLES: You are contentious, Socrates. 

SOCRATES: Nay, I ask you, not from a love of contention, but  because I  really want to know in what way

you think that affairs  should be  administered among uswhether, when you come to the  administration of

them, you have any other aim but the improvement of  the citizens?  Have we  not already admitted many times

over that such  is the duty of a public man?  Nay, we have surely said so; for if you  will not answer for

yourself I must  answer for you.  But if this is  what the good man ought to effect for the  benefit of his own

state,  allow me to recall to you the names of those whom  you were just now  mentioning, Pericles, and

Cimon, and Miltiades, and  Themistocles, and  ask whether you still think that they were good citizens. 

CALLICLES: I do. 

SOCRATES: But if they were good, then clearly each of them  must have made  the citizens better instead of

worse? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And, therefore, when Pericles first began to speak  in the  assembly, the Athenians were not so

good as when he spoke last? 

CALLICLES: Very likely. 

SOCRATES: Nay, my friend, 'likely' is not the word; for if  he was a good  citizen, the inference is certain. 

CALLICLES: And what difference does that make? 

SOCRATES: None; only I should like further to know whether  the Athenians  are supposed to have been

made better by Pericles, or,  on the contrary, to  have been corrupted by him; for I hear that he was  the first

who gave the  people pay, and made them idle and cowardly,  and encouraged them in the  love of talk and

money. 

CALLICLES: You heard that, Socrates, from the laconising set  who bruise  their ears. 

SOCRATES: But what I am going to tell you now is not mere  hearsay, but  well known both to you and me:

that at first, Pericles  was glorious and  his character unimpeached by any verdict of the  Atheniansthis was

during  the time when they were not so goodyet  afterwards, when they had been  made good and gentle by

him, at the  very end of his life they convicted him  of theft, and almost put him  to death, clearly under the

notion that he was  a malefactor. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 91



Top




Page No 94


CALLICLES: Well, but how does that prove Pericles' badness? 

SOCRATES: Why, surely you would say that he was a bad  manager of asses or  horses or oxen, who had

received them originally  neither kicking nor  butting nor biting him, and implanted in them all  these savage

tricks?  Would he not be a bad manager of any animals who  received them gentle, and  made them fiercer than

they were when he  received them?  What do you say? 

CALLICLES: I will do you the favour of saying 'yes.' 

SOCRATES: And will you also do me the favour of saying  whether man is an  animal? 

CALLICLES: Certainly he is. 

SOCRATES: And was not Pericles a shepherd of men? 

CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: And if he was a good political shepherd, ought not  the animals  who were his subjects, as we

were just now acknowledging,  to have become  more just, and not more unjust? 

CALLICLES: Quite true. 

SOCRATES: And are not just men gentle, as Homer says?or  are you of  another mind? 

CALLICLES: I agree. 

SOCRATES: And yet he really did make them more savage than  he received  them, and their savageness was

shown towards himself;  which he must have  been very far from desiring. 

CALLICLES: Do you want me to agree with you? 

SOCRATES: Yes, if I seem to you to speak the truth. 

CALLICLES: Granted then. 

SOCRATES: And if they were more savage, must they not have  been more  unjust and inferior? 

CALLICLES: Granted again. 

SOCRATES: Then upon this view, Pericles was not a good  statesman? 

CALLICLES: That is, upon your view. 

SOCRATES: Nay, the view is yours, after what you have  admitted.  Take the  case of Cimon again.  Did not

the very persons  whom he was serving  ostracize him, in order that they might not hear  his voice for ten

years?  and they did just the same to Themistocles,  adding the penalty of exile;  and they voted that Miltiades,

the hero  of Marathon, should be thrown into  the pit of death, and he was only  saved by the Prytanis.  And yet,

if they  had been really good men, as  you say, these things would never have  happened to them.  For the good

charioteers are not those who at first keep  their place, and then,  when they have brokenin their horses, and

themselves become better  charioteers, are thrown outthat is not the way  either in  charioteering or in any

profession.What do you think? 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 92



Top




Page No 95


CALLICLES: I should think not. 

SOCRATES: Well, but if so, the truth is as I have said  already, that in  the Athenian State no one has ever

shown himself to  be a good statesman  you admitted that this was true of our present  statesmen, but not true

of  former ones, and you preferred them to the  others; yet they have turned out  to be no better than our present

ones; and therefore, if they were  rhetoricians, they did not use the  true art of rhetoric or of flattery, or  they

would not have fallen out  of favour. 

CALLICLES: But surely, Socrates, no living man ever came  near any one of  them in his performances. 

SOCRATES: O, my dear friend, I say nothing against them  regarded as the  servingmen of the State; and I

do think that they  were certainly more  serviceable than those who are living now, and  better able to gratify

the  wishes of the State; but as to transforming  those desires and not allowing  them to have their way, and

using the  powers which they had, whether of  persuasion or of force, in the  improvement of their fellow

citizens, which  is the prime object of the  truly good citizen, I do not see that in these  respects they were a

whit superior to our present statesmen, although I do  admit that they  were more clever at providing ships and

walls and docks,  and all that.  You and I have a ridiculous way, for during the whole time  that we  are arguing,

we are always going round and round to the same point,  and constantly misunderstanding one another.  If I am

not mistaken,  you  have admitted and acknowledged more than once, that there are two  kinds of  operations

which have to do with the body, and two which have  to do with  the soul:  one of the two is ministerial, and if

our bodies  are hungry  provides food for them, and if they are thirsty gives them  drink, or if  they are cold

supplies them with garments, blankets,  shoes, and all that  they crave.  I use the same images as before

intentionally, in order that  you may understand me the better.  The  purveyor of the articles may provide  them

either wholesale or retail,  or he may be the maker of any of them,  the baker, or the cook, or  the weaver, or

the shoemaker, or the currier;  and in so doing, being  such as he is, he is naturally supposed by himself  and

every one to  minister to the body.  For none of them know that there is  another  artan art of gymnastic and

medicine which is the true minister of  the body, and ought to be the mistress of all the rest, and to use  their

results according to the knowledge which she has and they have  not, of the  real good or bad effects of meats

and drinks on the body.  All other arts  which have to do with the body are servile and menial  and illiberal; and

gymnastic and medicine are, as they ought to be,  their mistresses.  Now,  when I say that all this is equally true

of  the soul, you seem at first to  know and understand and assent to my  words, and then a little while

afterwards you come repeating, Has not  the State had good and noble  citizens? and when I ask you who they

are, you reply, seemingly quite in  earnest, as if I had asked, Who are  or have been good trainers?and you

had replied, Thearion, the baker,  Mithoecus, who wrote the Sicilian  cookerybook, Sarambus, the vintner:

these are ministers of the body,  firstrate in their art; for the  first makes admirable loaves, the second

excellent dishes, and the  third capital wine;to me these appear to be the  exact parallel of  the statesmen

whom you mention.  Now you would not be  altogether  pleased if I said to you, My friend, you know nothing

of  gymnastics;  those of whom you are speaking to me are only the ministers and  purveyors of luxury, who

have no good or noble notions of their art,  and  may very likely be filling and fattening men's bodies and

gaining  their  approval, although the result is that they lose their original  flesh in the  long run, and become

thinner than they were before; and  yet they, in their  simplicity, will not attribute their diseases and  loss of

flesh to their  entertainers; but when in after years the  unhealthy surfeit brings the  attendant penalty of disease,

he who  happens to be near them at the time,  and offers them advice, is  accused and blamed by them, and if

they could  they would do him some  harm; while they proceed to eulogize the men who  have been the real

authors of the mischief.  And that, Callicles, is just  what you are  now doing.  You praise the men who feasted

the citizens and  satisfied  their desires, and people say that they have made the city great,  not  seeing that the

swollen and ulcerated condition of the State is to be  attributed to these elder statesmen; for they have filled

the city  full of  harbours and docks and walls and revenues and all that, and  have left no  room for justice and

temperance.  And when the crisis of  the disorder  comes, the people will blame the advisers of the hour,  and

applaud  Themistocles and Cimon and Pericles, who are the real  authors of their  calamities; and if you are not

careful they may  assail you and my friend  Alcibiades, when they are losing not only  their new acquisitions,


Gorgias

GORGIAS 93



Top




Page No 96


but also  their original possessions; not that  you are the authors of these  misfortunes of theirs, although you

may  perhaps be accessories to them.  A  great piece of work is always being  made, as I see and am told, now

as of  old; about our statesmen.  When  the State treats any of them as  malefactors, I observe that there is a

great uproar and indignation at the  supposed wrong which is done to  them; 'after all their many services to the

State, that they should  unjustly perish,'so the tale runs.  But the cry  is all a lie; for no  statesman ever could

be unjustly put to death by the  city of which he  is the head.  The case of the professed statesman is, I  believe,

very  much like that of the professed sophist; for the sophists,  although  they are wise men, are nevertheless

guilty of a strange piece of  folly; professing to be teachers of virtue, they will often accuse  their  disciples of

wronging them, and defrauding them of their pay,  and showing  no gratitude for their services.  Yet what can

be more  absurd than that men  who have become just and good, and whose  injustice has been taken away

from  them, and who have had justice  implanted in them by their teachers, should  act unjustly by reason of  the

injustice which is not in them?  Can anything  be more irrational,  my friends, than this?  You, Callicles, compel

me to be  a moborator,  because you will not answer. 

CALLICLES: And you are the man who cannot speak unless there  is some one  to answer? 

SOCRATES: I suppose that I can; just now, at any rate, the  speeches which  I am making are long enough

because you refuse to  answer me.  But I adjure  you by the god of friendship, my good sir, do  tell me whether

there does  not appear to you to be a great  inconsistency in saying that you have made  a man good, and then

blaming him for being bad? 

CALLICLES: Yes, it appears so to me. 

SOCRATES: Do you never hear our professors of education  speaking in this  inconsistent manner? 

CALLICLES: Yes, but why talk of men who are good for  nothing? 

SOCRATES: I would rather say, why talk of men who profess to  be rulers,  and declare that they are devoted

to the improvement of the  city, and  nevertheless upon occasion declaim against the utter  vileness of the city:

do you think that there is any difference  between one and the other?  My  good friend, the sophist and the

rhetorician, as I was saying to Polus, are  the same, or nearly the  same; but you ignorantly fancy that rhetoric

is a  perfect thing, and  sophistry a thing to be despised; whereas the truth is,  that sophistry  is as much superior

to rhetoric as legislation is to the  practice of  law, or gymnastic to medicine.  The orators and sophists, as I  am

inclined to think, are the only class who cannot complain of the  mischief ensuing to themselves from that

which they teach others,  without  in the same breath accusing themselves of having done no good  to those

whom  they profess to benefit.  Is not this a fact? 

CALLICLES: Certainly it is. 

SOCRATES: If they were right in saying that they make men  better, then  they are the only class who can

afford to leave their  remuneration to those  who have been benefited by them.  Whereas if a  man has been

benefited in  any other way, if, for example, he has been  taught to run by a trainer, he  might possibly defraud

him of his pay,  if the trainer left the matter to  him, and made no agreement with him  that he should receive

money as soon as  he had given him the utmost  speed; for not because of any deficiency of  speed do men act

unjustly,  but by reason of injustice. 

CALLICLES: Very true. 

SOCRATES: And he who removes injustice can be in no danger  of being  treated unjustly:  he alone can

safely leave the honorarium  to his pupils,  if he be really able to make them goodam I not right?  (Compare

Protag.) 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 94



Top




Page No 97


CALLICLES: Yes. 

SOCRATES: Then we have found the reason why there is no  dishonour in a man  receiving pay who is called

in to advise about  building or any other art? 

CALLICLES: Yes, we have found the reason. 

SOCRATES: But when the point is, how a man may become best  himself, and  best govern his family and

state, then to say that you  will give no advice  gratis is held to be dishonourable? 

CALLICLES: True. 

SOCRATES: And why?  Because only such benefits call forth a  desire to  requite them, and there is evidence

that a benefit has been  conferred when  the benefactor receives a return; otherwise not.  Is  this true? 

CALLICLES: It is. 

SOCRATES: Then to which service of the State do you invite  me? determine  for me.  Am I to be the

physician of the State who will  strive and struggle  to make the Athenians as good as possible; or am I  to be

the servant and  flatterer of the State?  Speak out, my good  friend, freely and fairly as  you did at first and ought

to do again,  and tell me your entire mind. 

CALLICLES: I say then that you should be the servant of the  State. 

SOCRATES: The flatterer? well, sir, that is a noble  invitation. 

CALLICLES: The Mysian, Socrates, or what you please.  For if  you refuse,  the consequences will be 

SOCRATES: Do not repeat the old storythat he who likes  will kill me and  get my money; for then I shall

have to repeat the old  answer, that he will  be a bad man and will kill the good, and that the  money will be of

no use  to him, but that he will wrongly use that  which he wrongly took, and if  wrongly, basely, and if basely,

hurtfully. 

CALLICLES: How confident you are, Socrates, that you will  never come to  harm! you seem to think that

you are living in another  country, and can  never be brought into a court of justice, as you very  likely may be

brought  by some miserable and mean person. 

SOCRATES: Then I must indeed be a fool, Callicles, if I do  not know that  in the Athenian State any man

may suffer anything.  And  if I am brought to  trial and incur the dangers of which you speak, he  will be a

villain who  brings me to trialof that I am very sure, for  no good man would accuse  the innocent.  Nor shall

I be surprised if I  am put to death.  Shall I tell  you why I anticipate this? 

CALLICLES: By all means. 

SOCRATES: I think that I am the only or almost the only  Athenian living  who practises the true art of

politics; I am the only  politician of my  time.  Now, seeing that when I speak my words are not  uttered with

any view  of gaining favour, and that I look to what is  best and not to what is most  pleasant, having no mind

to use those  arts and graces which you recommend,  I shall have nothing to say in  the justice court.  And you

might argue with  me, as I was arguing with  Polus:I shall be tried just as a physician  would be tried in a

court  of little boys at the indictment of the cook.  What would he reply  under such circumstances, if some one

were to accuse  him, saying, 'O  my boys, many evil things has this man done to you:  he is  the death  of you,


Gorgias

GORGIAS 95



Top




Page No 98


especially of the younger ones among you, cutting and  burning  and starving and suffocating you, until you

know not what to do; he  gives you the bitterest potions, and compels you to hunger and thirst.  How  unlike the

variety of meats and sweets on which I feasted you!'  What do  you suppose that the physician would be able to

reply when he  found himself  in such a predicament?  If he told the truth he could  only say, 'All these  evil

things, my boys, I did for your health,' and  then would there not just  be a clamour among a jury like that?

How  they would cry out! 

CALLICLES: I dare say. 

SOCRATES: Would he not be utterly at a loss for a reply? 

CALLICLES: He certainly would. 

SOCRATES: And I too shall be treated in the same way, as I  well know, if I  am brought before the court.

For I shall not be able  to rehearse to the  people the pleasures which I have procured for  them, and which,

although I  am not disposed to envy either the  procurers or enjoyers of them, are  deemed by them to be

benefits and  advantages.  And if any one says that I  corrupt young men, and perplex  their minds, or that I

speak evil of old  men, and use bitter words  towards them, whether in private or public, it is  useless for me to

reply, as I truly might:'All this I do for the sake of  justice, and  with a view to your interest, my judges, and

to nothing else.'  And  therefore there is no saying what may happen to me. 

CALLICLES: And do you think, Socrates, that a man who is  thus defenceless  is in a good position? 

SOCRATES: Yes, Callicles, if he have that defence, which as  you have often  acknowledged he should

haveif he be his own defence,  and have never said  or done anything wrong, either in respect of gods  or

men; and this has been  repeatedly acknowledged by us to be the best  sort of defence.  And if any  one could

convict me of inability to  defend myself or others after this  sort, I should blush for shame,  whether I was

convicted before many, or  before a few, or by myself  alone; and if I died from want of ability to do  so, that

would indeed  grieve me.  But if I died because I have no powers of  flattery or  rhetoric, I am very sure that you

would not find me repining at  death.  For no man who is not an utter fool and coward is afraid of death  itself,

but he is afraid of doing wrong.  For to go to the world below  having one's soul full of injustice is the last and

worst of all  evils.  And in proof of what I say, if you have no objection, I should  like to tell  you a story. 

CALLICLES: Very well, proceed; and then we shall have done. 

SOCRATES: Listen, then, as storytellers say, to a very  pretty tale, which  I dare say that you may be

disposed to regard as a  fable only, but which,  as I believe, is a true tale, for I mean to  speak the truth.  Homer

tells  us (Il.), how Zeus and Poseidon and  Pluto divided the empire which they  inherited from their father.

Now  in the days of Cronos there existed a law  respecting the destiny of  man, which has always been, and still

continues  to be in Heaven,that  he who has lived all his life in justice and  holiness shall go, when  he is

dead, to the Islands of the Blessed, and  dwell there in perfect  happiness out of the reach of evil; but that he

who  has lived unjustly  and impiously shall go to the house of vengeance and  punishment, which  is called

Tartarus.  And in the time of Cronos, and even  quite lately  in the reign of Zeus, the judgment was given on the

very day  on which  the men were to die; the judges were alive, and the men were  alive;  and the consequence

was that the judgments were not well given.  Then  Pluto and the authorities from the Islands of the Blessed

came to  Zeus, and said that the souls found their way to the wrong places.  Zeus  said:  'I shall put a stop to this;

the judgments are not well  given,  because the persons who are judged have their clothes on, for  they are

alive; and there are many who, having evil souls, are  apparelled in fair  bodies, or encased in wealth or rank,

and, when the  day of judgment  arrives, numerous witnesses come forward and testify  on their behalf that  they

have lived righteously.  The judges are awed  by them, and they  themselves too have their clothes on when

judging;  their eyes and ears and  their whole bodies are interposed as a veil  before their own souls.  All  this is a


Gorgias

GORGIAS 96



Top




Page No 99


hindrance to them; there are  the clothes of the judges and the  clothes of the judged.What is to  be done?  I

will tell you:In the first  place, I will deprive men of  the foreknowledge of death, which they possess  at

present:  this power  which they have Prometheus has already received my  orders to take from  them:  in the

second place, they shall be entirely  stripped before  they are judged, for they shall be judged when they are

dead; and the  judge too shall be naked, that is to say, deadhe with his  naked soul  shall pierce into the other

naked souls; and they shall die  suddenly  and be deprived of all their kindred, and leave their brave attire

strewn upon the earthconducted in this manner, the judgment will be  just.  I knew all about the matter

before any of you, and therefore I  have made my  sons judges; two from Asia, Minos and Rhadamanthus, and

one from Europe,  Aeacus.  And these, when they are dead, shall give  judgment in the meadow  at the parting

of the ways, whence the two  roads lead, one to the Islands  of the Blessed, and the other to  Tartarus.

Rhadamanthus shall judge those  who come from Asia, and  Aeacus those who come from Europe.  And to

Minos I  shall give the  primacy, and he shall hold a court of appeal, in case either  of the  two others are in any

doubt:then the judgment respecting the last  journey of men will be as just as possible.' 

From this tale, Callicles, which I have heard and believe, I draw  the  following inferences:Death, if I am

right, is in the first place  the  separation from one another of two things, soul and body; nothing  else.  And

after they are separated they retain their several natures,  as in life;  the body keeps the same habit, and the

results of  treatment or accident are  distinctly visible in it:  for example, he  who by nature or training or  both,

was a tall man while he was alive,  will remain as he was, after he is  dead; and the fat man will remain  fat; and

so on; and the dead man, who in  life had a fancy to have  flowing hair, will have flowing hair.  And if he  was

marked with the  whip and had the prints of the scourge, or of wounds in  him when he  was alive, you might

see the same in the dead body; and if his  limbs  were broken or misshapen when he was alive, the same

appearance would  be visible in the dead.  And in a word, whatever was the habit of the  body  during life would

be distinguishable after death, either  perfectly, or in a  great measure and for a certain time.  And I should

imagine that this is  equally true of the soul, Callicles; when a man  is stripped of the body,  all the natural or

acquired affections of the  soul are laid open to view.  And when they come to the judge, as  those from Asia

come to Rhadamanthus,  he places them near him and  inspects them quite impartially, not knowing  whose the

soul is:  perhaps he may lay hands on the soul of the great king,  or of some  other king or potentate, who has

no soundness in him, but his  soul is  marked with the whip, and is full of the prints and scars of  perjuries  and

crimes with which each action has stained him, and he is all  crooked with falsehood and imposture, and has

no straightness, because  he  has lived without truth.  Him Rhadamanthus beholds, full of all  deformity  and

disproportion, which is caused by licence and luxury and  insolence and  incontinence, and despatches him

ignominiously to his  prison, and there he  undergoes the punishment which he deserves. 

Now the proper office of punishment is twofold:  he who is rightly  punished  ought either to become better and

profit by it, or he ought  to be made an  example to his fellows, that they may see what he  suffers, and fear and

become better.  Those who are improved when they  are punished by gods and  men, are those whose sins are

curable; and  they are improved, as in this  world so also in another, by pain and  suffering; for there is no other

way  in which they can be delivered  from their evil.  But they who have been  guilty of the worst crimes,  and

are incurable by reason of their crimes,  are made examples; for,  as they are incurable, the time has passed at

which  they can receive  any benefit.  They get no good themselves, but others get  good when  they behold them

enduring for ever the most terrible and painful  and  fearful sufferings as the penalty of their sinsthere they

are,  hanging up as examples, in the prisonhouse of the world below, a  spectacle  and a warning to all

unrighteous men who come thither.  And  among them, as  I confidently affirm, will be found Archelaus, if

Polus  truly reports of  him, and any other tyrant who is like him.  Of these  fearful examples,  most, as I believe,

are taken from the class of  tyrants and kings and  potentates and public men, for they are the  authors of the

greatest and  most impious crimes, because they have the  power.  And Homer witnesses to  the truth of this; for

they are always  kings and potentates whom he has  described as suffering everlasting  punishment in the world

below:  such  were Tantalus and Sisyphus and  Tityus.  But no one ever described  Thersites, or any private

person  who was a villain, as suffering  everlasting punishment, or as  incurable.  For to commit the worst

crimes,  as I am inclined to think,  was not in his power, and he was happier than  those who had the power.  No,


Gorgias

GORGIAS 97



Top




Page No 100


Callicles, the very bad men come from the  class of those who have  power (compare Republic).  And yet in

that very  class there may arise  good men, and worthy of all admiration they are, for  where there is  great

power to do wrong, to live and to die justly is a hard  thing,  and greatly to be praised, and few there are who

attain to this.  Such  good and true men, however, there have been, and will be again, at  Athens and in other

states, who have fulfilled their trust  righteously; and  there is one who is quite famous all over Hellas,

Aristeides, the son of  Lysimachus.  But, in general, great men are  also bad, my friend. 

As I was saying, Rhadamanthus, when he gets a soul of the bad kind,  knows  nothing about him, neither who

he is, nor who his parents are;  he knows  only that he has got hold of a villain; and seeing this, he  stamps him

as  curable or incurable, and sends him away to Tartarus,  whither he goes and  receives his proper recompense.

Or, again, he  looks with admiration on the  soul of some just one who has lived in  holiness and truth; he may

have been  a private man or not; and I  should say, Callicles, that he is most likely  to have been a  philosopher

who has done his own work, and not troubled  himself with  the doings of other men in his lifetime; him

Rhadamanthus  sends to the  Islands of the Blessed.  Aeacus does the same; and they both  have  sceptres, and

judge; but Minos alone has a golden sceptre and is  seated looking on, as Odysseus in Homer declares that he

saw him: 

'Holding a sceptre of gold, and giving laws to the dead.' 

Now I, Callicles, am persuaded of the truth of these things, and I  consider  how I shall present my soul whole

and undefiled before the  judge in that  day.  Renouncing the honours at which the world aims, I  desire only to

know  the truth, and to live as well as I can, and, when  I die, to die as well as  I can.  And, to the utmost of my

power, I  exhort all other men to do the  same.  And, in return for your  exhortation of me, I exhort you also to

take  part in the great combat,  which is the combat of life, and greater than  every other earthly  conflict.  And I

retort your reproach of me, and say,  that you will  not be able to help yourself when the day of trial and

judgment, of  which I was speaking, comes upon you; you will go before the  judge,  the son of Aegina, and,

when he has got you in his grip and is  carrying you off, you will gape and your head will swim round, just as

mine  would in the courts of this world, and very likely some one will  shamefully  box you on the ears, and put

upon you any sort of insult. 

Perhaps this may appear to you to be only an old wife's tale, which  you  will contemn.  And there might be

reason in your contemning such  tales, if  by searching we could find out anything better or truer:  but now you

see  that you and Polus and Gorgias, who are the three  wisest of the Greeks of  our day, are not able to show

that we ought to  live any life which does not  profit in another world as well as in  this.  And of all that has

been said,  nothing remains unshaken but the  saying, that to do injustice is more to be  avoided than to suffer

injustice, and that the reality and not the  appearance of virtue is to  be followed above all things, as well in

public  as in private life;  and that when any one has been wrong in anything, he is  to be  chastised, and that the

next best thing to a man being just is that  he  should become just, and be chastised and punished; also that he

should  avoid all flattery of himself as well as of others, of the few or of  the  many:  and rhetoric and any other

art should be used by him, and  all his  actions should be done always, with a view to justice. 

Follow me then, and I will lead you where you will be happy in life  and  after death, as the argument shows.

And never mind if some one  despises  you as a fool, and insults you, if he has a mind; let him  strike you, by

Zeus, and do you be of good cheer, and do not mind the  insulting blow, for  you will never come to any harm

in the practice of  virtue, if you are a  really good and true man.  When we have practised  virtue together, we

will  apply ourselves to politics, if that seems  desirable, or we will advise  about whatever else may seem good

to us,  for we shall be better able to  judge then.  In our present condition  we ought not to give ourselves airs,

for even on the most important  subjects we are always changing our minds;  so utterly stupid are we!  Let us,

then, take the argument as our guide,  which has revealed to  us that the best way of life is to practise justice

and every virtue  in life and death.  This way let us go; and in this exhort  all men to  follow, not in the way to

which you trust and in which you  exhort me  to follow you; for that way, Callicles, is nothing worth. 


Gorgias

GORGIAS 98



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. Gorgias, page = 4

   3. Plato, page = 4

   4. INTRODUCTION., page = 4

   5. GORGIAS, page = 32