Title: On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
Subject:
Author: FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
Page No 2
Table of Contents
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life........................................................................................................1
FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE ......................................................................................................................1
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
i
Page No 3
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
Forward
I
II
III
IV
V
VI
VII
VIII
IX
X
translated by
Ian C. Johnston
Liberal Studies Department
Malaspina UniversityCollege
Nanaimo, British Columbia
V9R 5S5
September 1998
For comments, improvements, corrections, or questions please contact johnstoi@mala.bc.ca
[Note that phrases in square brackets have been added to the text by the translator. Nietzsche's longer
paragraphs have been broken into shorter paragraphs. This text is in the public domain, released September
1998]
Forward
"Incidentally, I despise everything which merely instructs me without increasing or immediately enlivening
my activity." These are Goethe's words. With them, as with a heartfelt expression of Ceterum censeo [I judge
otherwise], our consideration of the worth and the worthlessness of history may begin. For this work is to set
down why, in the spirit of Goethe's saying, we must seriously despise instruction without vitality, knowledge
which enervates activity, and history as an expensive surplus of knowledge and a luxury, because we lack
what is still most essential to us and because what is superfluous is hostile to what is essential. To be sure, we
need history. But we need it in a manner different from the way in which the spoilt idler in the garden of
knowledge uses it, no matter how elegantly he may look down on our coarse and graceless needs and
distresses. That is, we need it for life and action, not for a comfortable turning away from life and action or
merely for glossing over the egotistical life and the cowardly bad act. We wish to use history only insofar as
it serves living. But there is a degree of doing history and a valuing of it through which life atrophies and
degenerates. To bring this phenomenon to light as a remarkable symptom of our time is every bit as necessary
as it may be painful.
I have tried to describe a feeling which has often enough tormented me. I take my revenge on this feeling
when I expose it to the general public. Perhaps with such a description someone or other will have reason to
point out to me that he also knows this particular sensation but that I have not felt it with sufficient purity and
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 1
Page No 4
naturalness and definitely have not expressed myself with the appropriate certainty and mature experience.
Perhaps one or two will respond in this way. However, most people will tell me that this feeling is totally
wrong, unnatural, abominable, and absolutely forbidden, that with it, in fact, I have shown myself unworthy
of the powerful historical tendency of the times, as it has been, by common knowledge, observed for the past
two generations, particularly among the Germans. Whatever the reaction, now that I dare to expose myself
with this natural description of my feeling, common decency will be fostered rather than shamed, because I
am providing many opportunities for a contemporary tendency like the reaction just mentioned to make polite
pronouncements. Moreover, I obtain for myself something of even more value to me than respectability: I
become publicly instructed and set straight about our times.
This essay is also out of touch with the times because here I am trying for once to see as a contemporary
disgrace, infirmity, and defect something of which our age is justifiably proud, its historical culture. For I
believe, in fact, that we are all suffering from a consumptive historical fever and at the very least should
recognize that we are afflicted with it. If Goethe with good reason said that with our virtues we
simultaneously cultivate our faults and if, as everyone knows, a hypertrophic virtue (as the historical sense of
our age appears to me to be) can serve to destroy a people just as well as a hypertrophic vice, then people
may make allowance for me this once. Also in my defence I should not conceal the fact that the experiences
which aroused these feelings of torment in me I have derived for the most part from myself and only from
others for the purpose of comparison and that, insofar as I am a student more of ancient times, particularly the
Greeks, I come as a child in these present times to such anachronistic experiences concerning myself. But I
must be allowed to ascribe this much to myself on account of my profession as a classical philologue, for I
would not know what sense classical philology would have in our age unless it is to be effective by its
inappropriateness for the times, that is, in opposition to the age, thus working on the age, and, we hope, for
the benefit of a coming time.
I
Observe the herd which is grazing beside you. It does not know what yesterday or today is. It springs around,
eats, rests, digests, jumps up again, and so from morning to night and from day to day, with its likes and
dislikes closely tied to the peg of the moment, and thus neither melancholy nor weary. To witness this is hard
for man, because he boasts to himself that his human race is better than the beast and yet looks with jealousy
at its happiness. For he wishes only to live like the beast, neither weary nor amid pains, and he wants it in
vain, because he does not will it as the animal does. One day the man demands of the beast: "Why do you not
talk to me about your happiness and only gaze at me?" The beast wants to answer, too, and say: "That comes
about because I always immediately forget what I wanted to say." But by then the beast has already forgotten
this reply and remains silent, so that the man wonders on once more.
But he also wonders about himself, that he is not able to learn to forget and that he always hangs onto past
things. No matter how far or how fast he runs, this chain runs with him. It is something amazing: the moment,
in one sudden motion there, in one sudden motion gone, before nothing, afterwards nothing, nevertheless
comes back again as a ghost and disturbs the tranquillity of each later moment. A leaf is continuously
released from the roll of time, falls out, flutters awayand suddenly flutters back again into the man's lap.
For the man says, "I remember," and envies the beast, which immediately forgets and sees each moment
really perish, sink back in cloud and night, and vanish forever.
Thus the beast lives unhistorically, for it gets up in the present like a number without any odd fraction left
over; it does not know how to play a part, hides nothing, and appears in each moment exactly and entirely
what it is. Thus a beast can be nothing other than honest. By contrast, the human being resists the large and
ever increasing burden of the past, which pushes him down or bows him over. It makes his way difficult, like
an invisible and dark burden which he can for appearances' sake even deny, and which he is only too happy
to deny in his interactions with his peers, in order to awaken their envy. Thus, it moves him, as if he
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 2
Page No 5
remembered a lost paradise, to see the grazing herd or, something more closely familiar, the child, which
does not yet have a past to deny and plays in blissful blindness between the fences of the past and the future.
Nonetheless this game must be upset for the child. He will be summoned all too soon out of his forgetfulness.
For he learns to understand the expression "It was," that password with which struggle, suffering, and
weariness come over human beings, so as to remind him what his existence basically isa never completed
past tense. If death finally brings the longed for forgetting, it nevertheless thereby destroys present existence
and thus impresses its seal on the knowledge that existence is only an uninterrupted living in the past
[Gewesensein], something which exists for the purpose of selfdenial, selfdestruction, and
selfcontradiction.
If happiness or if, in some sense or other, a reaching out for new happiness is what holds the living onto life
and pushes them forward into life, then perhaps no philosopher has more justification than the cynic. For the
happiness of the beast, like that of the complete cynic, is the living proof of the rightness of cynicism. The
smallest happiness, if only it is uninterrupted and creates happiness, is incomparably more happiness than the
greatest which comes only as an episode, as it were, like a mood, as a fantastic interruption between nothing
but boredom, cupidity, and deprivation. However, with the smallest and with the greatest good fortune,
happiness becomes happiness in the same way: through forgetting or, to express the matter in a more
scholarly fashion, through the capacity, for as long as the happiness lasts, to sense things unhistorically.
The person who cannot set himself down on the crest of the moment, forgetting everything from the past,
who is not capable of standing on a single point, like a goddess of victory, without dizziness or fear, will
never know what happiness is. Even worse, he will never do anything to make other people happy. Imagine
the most extreme example, a person who did not possess the power of forgetting at all, who would be
condemned to see everywhere a coming into being. Such a person no longer believes in his own being, no
longer believes in himself, sees everything in moving points flowing out of each other, and loses himself in
this stream of becoming. He will, like the true pupil of Heraclitus, finally hardly dare any more to lift his
finger. Forgetting belongs to all action, just as both light and darkness belong in the life of all organic things.
A person who wanted to feel utterly and only historically would be like someone who was forced to abstain
from sleep, or like the beast that is to continue its life only from rumination to constantly repeated
rumination. For this reason, it is possible to live almost without remembering, indeed, to live happily, as the
beast demonstrates; however, it is generally completely impossible to live without forgetting. Or, to explain
myself more clearly concerning my thesis: There is a degree of insomnia, of rumination, of the historical
sense, through which living comes to harm and finally is destroyed, whether it is a person or a people or a
culture.
In order to determine this degree of history and, through that, the borderline at which the past must be
forgotten if it is not to become the gravedigger of the present, we have to know precisely how great the
plastic force of a person, a people, or a culture is. I mean that force of growing in a different way out of
oneself, of reshaping and incorporating the past and the foreign, of healing wounds, compensating for what
has been lost, rebuilding shattered forms out of one's self. There are people who possess so little of this force
that they bleed to death incurably from a single experience, a single pain, often even from a single tender
injustice, as from a really small bloody scratch. On the other hand, there are people whom the wildest and
most horrific accidents in life and even actions of their own wickedness injure so little that right in the middle
of these experiences or shortly after they bring the issue to a reasonable state of well being with a sort of quiet
conscience.
The stronger the roots which the inner nature of a person has, the more he will appropriate or forcibly take
from the past. And if we imagine the most powerful and immense nature, then we would recognize there that
for it there would be no frontier at all beyond which the historical sense would be able to work as an injurious
overseer. Everything in the past, in its own and in the most alien, this nature would draw upon, take it into
itself, and, as it were, transform into blood. What such a nature does not subjugate it knows how to forget. It
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 3
Page No 6
is there no more. The horizon is closed completely, and nothing can recall that there still are men, passions,
instruction, and purposes beyond it. This is a general principle: each living being can become healthy, strong,
and fertile only within a horizon. If he is incapable of drawing a horizon around himself and too egotistical to
enclose his own view within an alien one, then he wastes away there, pale or weary, to an early death.
Cheerfulness, good conscience, joyful action, trust in what is to comeall that depends, with the individual
as with a people, on the following facts: that there is a line which divides the observable brightness from the
unilluminated darkness, that we know how to forget at the right time just as well as we remember at the right
time, that we feel with powerful instinct the time when we must perceive historically and when
unhistorically. This is the specific principle which the reader is invited to consider: that for the health of a
single individual, a people, and a culture the unhistorical and the historical are equally essential.
At this point everyone brings up the comment that a person's historical knowledge and feeling can be very
limited, his horizon hemmed in like that of an inhabitant of an Alpine valley; in every judgement he might set
down an injustice and in every experience a mistake, which he was the first to make, and nevertheless in spite
of all injustice and every mistake he stands there in invincible health and vigour and fills every eye with joy,
while close beside him the far more just and scholarly person grows ill and collapses, because the lines of his
horizon are always being shifted about restlessly, because he cannot wriggle himself out of the much softer
nets of his justices and truths to strong willing and desiring. By contrast, we saw the beast, which is
completely unhistorical and which lives almost in the middle of a sort of horizon of points, and yet exists
with a certain happiness, at least without weariness and pretence. Thus, we will have to assess the capacity of
being able to feel to a certain degree unhistorically as more important and more basic, to the extent that in it
lies the foundation above which something right, healthy, and great, something truly human, can generally
first grow. The unhistorical is like an enveloping atmosphere in which life generates itself alone, only to
disappear again with the destruction of this atmosphere.
The truth is that, in the process by which the human being, in thinking, reflecting, comparing, separating, and
combining, first limits that unhistorical sense, the process in which inside that surrounding misty cloud a
bright gleaming beam of light arises, only then, through the power of using the past for living and making
history out of what has happened, does a person first become a person. But in an excess of history the human
being stops once again; without that cover of the unhistorical he would never have started or dared to start.
Where do the actions come from which men are capable of doing without previously having gone into that
misty patch of the unhistorical? Or to set pictures to one side and to grasp an example for illustration: we
picture a man whom a violent passion, for a woman or for a great idea, shakes up and draws forward. How
his world is changed for him! Looking backwards, he feels blind; listening to the side he hears the
strangeness like a dull sound empty of meaning. What he is generally aware of he has never yet perceived as
so true, so perceptibly close, coloured, resounding, illuminated, as if he is comprehending with all the senses
simultaneously. All his estimates of worth are altered and devalued. He is unable any longer to value so
much, because he can hardly feel it any more. He asks himself whether he has been the fool of strange words
and strange opinions for long. He is surprised that his memory turns tirelessly in a circle but is nevertheless
too weak and tired to make a single leap out of this circle. It is the most unjust condition of the world,
narrow, thankless with respect to the past, blind to what has passed, deaf to warnings, a small living vortex in
a dead sea of night and forgetting: nevertheless this conditionunhistorical, thoroughly antihistoricalis
the birthing womb not only of an unjust deed but much more of every just deed. And no artist would achieve
his picture, no field marshal his victory, and no people its freedom, without previously having desired and
striven for them in that sort of unhistorical condition. As the active person, according to what Goethe said, is
always without conscience, so he is also always without knowledge. He forgets most things in order to do one
thing; he is unjust towards what lies behind him and knows only one right, the right of what is to come into
being now. So every active person loves his deed infinitely more than it deserves to be loved, and the best
deeds happen in such a excess of love that they would certainly have to be unworthy of this love, even if their
worth were otherwise incalculably great.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 4
Page No 7
Should a person be in a position to catch in many examples the scent of this unhistorical atmosphere, in
which every great historical event arose, and to breathe it in, then such a person might perhaps be able, as a
knowledgeable being, to elevate himself up to a superhistorical standpoint, in the way Niebuhr once
described a possible result of historical research: "In one thing at least," he says, "is history, clearly and
thoroughly grasped, useful, the fact that one knows, as even the greatest and highest spirits of our human race
do not know, how their eyes have acquired by chance the way in which they see and the way in which they
forcefully demand that everyone see, forcefully because the intensity of their awareness is particularly great.
Someone who has not, through many examples, precisely determined, known, and grasped this point is
overthrown by the appearance of a mighty spirit who in a given shape presents the highest form of passionate
dedication."
We could call such a standpoint superhistorical, because a person who assumes such a stance could feel no
more temptation to continue living and to participate in history. For he would have recognized the single
condition of every event, that blindness and injustice in the soul of the man of action. He himself would have
been cured from now on of taking history excessively seriously. But in the process he would have learned, for
every person and for every experience, among the Greeks or Turks, from a moment of the first or the
nineteenth century, to answer for himself the question how and why they conducted their lives. Anyone who
asks his acquaintances whether they would like to live through the last ten or twenty years again will easily
perceive which of them has been previously educated for that superhistorical point of view. For they will
probably all answer "No!", but they will substantiate that "No!" differently, some of them perhaps with the
confident hope "But the next twenty years will be better." Those are the ones of whom David Hume
mockingly says:
And from the dregs of life hope to receive, What the first sprightly running could not give.
We will call these the historical people. The glance into the past pushes them into the future, fires their spirit
to take up life for a longer time yet, kindles the hope that justice may still come and that happiness may sit
behind the mountain towards which they are walking. These historical people believe that the meaning of
existence will come increasingly to light in the course of its process. Therefore they look backwards only to
understand the present by considering previous process and to learn to desire the future more keenly. In spite
of all their history, they do not understand at all how unhistorically they think and act and also how their
concern with history stands, not in service to pure knowledge, but to living.
But that question whose first answer we have heard can be answered again in a different way, that is, once
more with a "No!" but with a "No!" that has a different grounding. The denial comes from the superhistorical
person, who does not see healing in the process and for whom the world is much more complete and at its
end in every moment. What could ten new years teach that the past ten years has not been able to teach!
Now, whether the meaning of the theory is happiness, resignation, virtue, or repentance, on that issue the
superhistorical people have not been united. But contrary to all the historical ways of considering the past,
they do come to full unanimity on the following principle: the past and the present are one and the same, that
is, in all their multiplicity typically identical and, as unchanging types everywhere present, they are a
motionless picture of immutable values and eternally similar meaning. As the hundreds of different languages
correspond to the same typically permanent needs of people, so that someone who understood these needs
could learn nothing new from all the languages, so the superhistorical thinker illuminates for himself all the
histories of people and of individuals from within, guessing like a clairvoyant the original sense of the
different hieroglyphics and gradually even growing tired of avoiding the constantly new streams of written
signals streaming forth. For, in the endless excess of what is happening, how is he not finally to reach
saturation, supersaturation, and, yes, even revulsion, so that the most daring ones are perhaps finally ready,
with Giacomo Leopardi, to say to their heart
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 5
Page No 8
Nothing lives which would be worthy of your striving, and the earth deserves not a sigh. Pain and boredom is
our being and the world is excrement, nothing else. Calm yourself.
However, let us leave the superhistorical people to their revulsion and their wisdom. Today for once we
would much rather become joyful in our hearts with our lack of wisdom and make the day happy for
ourselves as active and progressive people, as men who revere the process. Let our evaluation of the
historical be only a western bias, if only from within this bias we at least move forward and not do remain
still, if only we always just learn better to carry on history for the purposes of living! For we will happily
concede that the superhistorical people possess more wisdom than we do, so long, that is, as we may be
confident that we possess more life than they do. For thus at any rate our lack of wisdom will have more of a
future than their wisdom. Moreover, so as to remove the slightest doubt about the meaning of this contrast
between living and wisdom, I will reinforce my argument with a method well established from time
immemorial: I will immediately establish a few theses.
A historical phenomenon, purely and completely known and resolved into an object of knowledge, is, for the
person who has recognized it, dead. In it the person perceives the delusion, the injustice, the blind suffering,
and generally the entire temporal dark horizon of that phenomenon and, at the same time, in the process he
perceives his own historical power. This power has now become for him, as a knower, powerless, but perhaps
not yet for him as a living person.
History, conceived as pure knowledge, once it becomes sovereign, would be a kind of conclusion to living
and a final reckoning for humanity. Only when historical culture is ruled and led by a higher force and does
not itself govern and lead does it bring with it a powerful new stream of life, a developing culture for
example, something healthy with future promise.
Insofar as history stands in the service of life, it stands in the service of an unhistorical power and will
therefore, in this subordinate position, never be able to (and should never be able to) become pure science,
something like mathematics. However, the problem to what degree living requires the services of history
generally is one of the most important questions and concerns with respect to the health of a human being, a
people, or a culture. For with a certain excess of history, living crumbles away and degenerates. Moreover,
history itself also degenerates through this decay.
II
However, the fact that living requires the services of history must be just as clearly understood as the
principle, which will be demonstrated later, that an excess of history harms the living person. In three
respects history belongs to the living person: it belongs to him as an active and striving person; it belongs to
him as a person who preserves and admires; it belongs to him as a suffering person in need of emancipation.
This trinity of relationships corresponds to a trinity of methods for history, to the extent that one may make
the distinctions, a monumental method, an antiquarian method, and a critical method
History belongs, above all, to the active and powerful man, the man who fights one great battle, who needs
the exemplary men, teachers, and comforters and cannot find them among his contemporary companions.
Thus, history belongs to Schiller: for our age is so bad, said Goethe, that the poet no longer encounters any
useful nature in the human life surrounding him. Looking back to the active men, Polybius calls political
history an example of the right preparation for ruling a state and the most outstanding teacher, something
which, through the memory of other people's accidents, advises us to bear with resolution the changes in our
happiness. Anyone who has learned to recognize the sense of history in this way must get annoyed to see
inquisitive travellers or painstaking micrologists climbing all over the pyramids of the great things of the
past. There, in the place where he finds the stimulation to breath deeply and to make things better, he does not
wish to come across an idler who strolls around, greedy for distraction or stimulation, as among the
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 6
Page No 9
accumulated art treasures of a gallery.
In order not to despair and feel disgust in the midst of weak and hopeless idlers, surrounded by apparently
active, but really only agitated and fidgeting companions, the active man looks behind him and interrupts the
path to his goal to take a momentary deep breath. His purpose is some happiness or other, perhaps not his
own, often that of a people or of humanity collectively. He runs back away from resignation and uses history
as a way of fighting resignation. For the most part, no reward beckons him on, other than fame, that is,
becoming a candidate for an honoured place in the temple of history, where he himself can be, in his turn, a
teacher, consoler, and advisor for those who come later.
For his orders state: whatever once was able to expand the idea of "Human being" and to define it more
beautifully must constantly be present in order that it always keeps its potential. The greatest moments in the
struggle of single individuals make up a chain, in which a range of mountains of humanity are joined over
thousands of years. For me the loftiest thing of such a moment from the distant past is bright and greatthat
is the basic idea of the faith in humanity which expresses itself in the demand for a monumental history.
However, with this demand that greatness should be eternal there is immediately ignited the most dreadful
struggle. For everything else still living cries out no. The monumental should not be createdthat is
opposition's cry.
The dull habit, the small and the base, filling all corners of the world, like a heavy atmosphere clouding
around everything great, casts itself as a barrier, deceiving, dampening and suffocating along the road which
greatness has to go toward immortality. This way, however, leads through human minds! Through the minds
of anxious and shortlived animals, who always come back to the same needs and who with difficulty
postpone their destruction for a little while. As a first priority they want only one thing: to live at any price.
Who might suppose among them the difficult torch race of monumental history, through which alone
greatness lives once more! Nevertheless, a few of them always wake up again, those who, by a look back at
past greatness and strengthened by their observation, feel so blessed, as if the life of human beings is a
beautiful thing, as if it is indeed the most beautiful fruit of this bitter plant to know that in earlier times once
one man went through this existence proud and strong, another with profundity, a third with pity and a desire
to helpall however leaving behind one teaching: that the person lives most beautifully who does not reflect
upon existence.
If the common man considers this time span with such melancholy seriousness and longing, those men on
their way to immorality and to monumental history knew how to bring to life an Olympian laughter or at least
a lofty scorn. Often they climbed with irony into their graves, for what was there of them to bury! Surely only
what had always impressed them as cinders, garbage, vanity, animality and what now sinks into oblivion,
long after it was exposed to their contempt. But one thing will live, the monogram of their very own essence,
a work, a deed, an uncommon inspiration, a creation. That will live, because no later world can do without it.
In this most blessed form fame is indeed something more that the expensive piece of our amour propre, as
Schopenhauer has called it. It is the belief in the unity and continuity of the greatness of all times. It is a
protest against the changes of the generations and transience!
Now, what purpose is served for contemporary man by the monumental consideration of the past, busying
ourselves with the classics and rarities of earlier times? He derives from that the fact that the greatness which
was once there at all events once was possible and therefore will really be possible once again. He goes along
his path more bravely, for now the doubt which falls over him in weaker hours, that he might perhaps be
wishing for the impossible, is beaten back from the field. Let us assume that somebody believes it would take
no more than a hundred productive men, effective people brought up in a new spirit, to get rid of what has
become trendy in German culture right now , how must it strengthen him to perceive that the culture of the
Renaissance raised itself on the shoulders of such a crowd of a hundred men.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 7
Page No 10
Nevertheless, to learn right away something new from the same example, how fleeting and weak, how
imprecise that comparison would be! If the comparison is to carry out this powerful effect, how much of the
difference will be missed in the process. How forcefully must the individuality of the past be wrenched into a
general shape, with all its sharp corners and angles broken off for the sake of the correspondence! In fact,
basically something that once was possible could appear possible a second time only if the Pythagoreans
were correct in thinking that with the same constellations of the celestial bodies the same phenomena on the
Earth had to repeat themselves, even in the small single particulars, so that when the stars have a certain
position relative to each other, a Stoic and an Epicurean will, in an eternal recurrence, unite and assassinate
Caesar, and with another stellar position Columbus will eternally rediscover America.
Only if the Earth were always to begin its theatrical performance once again after the fifth act, if it were
certain that the same knot of motives, the same deux ex machina, the same catastrophe returned in the same
determined interval, could the powerful man desire monumental history in complete iconic truth, that is, each
fact in its precisely described characteristics and unity, and probably not before the time when astronomers
have once again become astrologers. Until that time monumental history will not be able to produce that full
truthfulness. It will always bring closer what is unlike, generalize, and finally make things equal. It will
always tone down the difference in motives and events, in order to set down the monumental effect, that is,
the exemplary effect worthy of imitation, at the cost of the cause. Thus, because monumental history turns
away as much as possible from the cause, we can call it a collection of "effects in themselves" with less
exaggeration than calling it events which will have an effect on all ages. What is celebrated in folk festivals
and in religious or military remembrance days is basically such an "effect in itself." It is the thing which does
not let the ambitious sleep, which for the enterprising lies like an amulet on the heart, but it is not the true
historical interconnection between cause and effect, which fully recognized, would only prove that never
again could anything completely the same fall out in the dice throw of future contingency.
As long as the soul of historical writing lies in the great driving impulses which a powerful man derives from
it, as long as the past must be written about as worthy of imitation, as capable of being imitated, with the
possibility of a second occurrence, history is definitely in danger of becoming something altered,
reinterpreted into something more beautiful, and thus coming close to free poeticizing. Indeed, there are times
which one cannot distinguish at all between a monumental history and a mythic fiction, because from a single
world one of these impulses can be derived as easily as the other. Thus, if the monumental consideration of
the past rules over the other forms of analyzing it, I mean, over the antiquarian and the critical methods, then
the past itself suffers harm. Really large parts of it are forgotten, despised, and flow forth like an
uninterrupted grey flood, and only a few embellished facts raise themselves up above, like islands. Something
unnatural and miraculous strikes our vision of the remarkable person who becomes especially visible, just
like the golden hips which the pupils of Pythagoras wished to attribute to their master.
Monumental history deceives through its analogies. It attracts the spirited man to daring acts with its
seductive similarities and the enthusiastic man to fanaticism. If we imagine this history really in the hands
and heads of the talented egoists and the wild crowds of evil rascals, then empires are destroyed, leaders
assassinated, wars and revolutions instigated, and the number of the historical "effects in themselves," that is,
the effects without adequate causes, increased once more. No matter how much monumental history can
serve to remind us of the injuries among great and active people, whether for better or worse, that is what it
first brings about when the impotent and inactive empower themselves with it and serve it.
Let us take the simplest and most frequent example. If we imagine to ourselves uncultured and weakly
cultured natures energized and armed by monumental cultural history, against whom will they now direct
their weapons? Against their hereditary enemies, the strong cultural spirits and also against the only ones who
are able to learn truly from that history, that is, for life, and to convert what they have learned into an noble
practice. For them the path will be blocked and the air darkened, if we dance around a halfunderstood
monument of some great past or other like truly zealous idolaters, as if we wanted to state: "See, that is the
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 8
Page No 11
true and real culture. What concern of yours is becoming and willing!" Apparently this dancing swarm
possess even the privilege of good taste. The creative man always stands at a disadvantage with respect to the
man who only looks on and does not play his own hand, as for example in all times the political knowitall
was wiser, more just, and more considerate than the ruling statesman.
If we want to transfer into the area of culture the customs of popular agreement and the popular majority and,
as it were, to require the artist to stand in his own defence before the forum of the artistically inert types, then
we can take an oath in advance that he will be condemned, not in spite of but just because his judges have
solemnly proclaimed the canon of monumental culture (that is, in accordance with the given explanation,
culture which in all ages "has had effects"). Whereas, for the judges everything which is not yet monumental,
because it is contemporary, lacks, first, the need for history, second, the clear inclination toward history, and
third, the very authority of history. On the other hand, their instinct tells them that culture can be struck dead
by culture. The monumental is definitely not to rise up once more. And for that their instinct uses precisely
what has the authority of the monumental from the past.
So they are knowledgeable about culture because they generally like to get rid of culture. They behave as if
they were doctors, while basically they are only concerned with mixing poisons. Thus, they develop their
languages and their taste, in order to explain in their discriminating way why they so persistently disapprove
of all offerings of more nourishing cultural food. For they do not want greatness to arise. Their method is to
say: "See greatness is already there!" In truth, this greatness that is already there is of as little concern to them
as what arises out of it. Of that their life bears witness. Monumental history is the theatrical costume in which
they pretend that their hate for the powerful and the great of their time is a fulfilling admiration for the strong
and the great of past times. In this, through disguise they invert the real sense of that method of historical
observation into its opposite. Whether they know it or not, they certainly act as if their motto were: let the
dead bury the living.
Each of the three existing types of history is only exactly right for a single area and a single climate; on every
other one it grows up into a destructive weed. If a man who wants to create greatness uses the past, then he
will empower himself through monumental history. On the other hand, the man who wishes to emphasise the
customary and traditionally valued cultivates the past as an antiquarian historian. Only the man whose breast
is oppressed by a present need and who wants to cast off his load at any price has a need for critical history,
that is, history which sits in judgement and passes judgement. From the thoughtless transplanting of plants
stem many ills: the critical man without need, the antiquarian without reverence, and the student of greatness
without the ability for greatness are the sort who are receptive to weeds estranged from their natural mother
earth and therefore degenerate growths.
III
History belongs secondly to the man who preserves and honours, to the person who with faith and love looks
back in the direction from which he has come, where he has been. Through this reverence he, as it were,
gives thanks for his existence. While he nurtures with a gentle hand what has stood from time immemorial,
he want to preserve the conditions under which he came into existence for those who are to come after him.
And so he serves life. His possession of his ancestors' goods changes the ideas in such a soul, for those goods
are far more likely to take possession of his soul. The small, limited, crumbling, and archaic keep their own
worth and integrity, because the conserving and honouring soul of the antiquarian man settles on these things
and there prepares for itself a secret nest. The history of his city becomes for him the history of his own self.
He understands the walls, the turreted gate, the dictate of the city council, and the folk festival, like an
illustrated diary of his youth, and he rediscovers for himself in all this his force, his purpose, his passion, his
opinion, his foolishness, and his bad habits. He says to himself, here one could live, for here one may live,
and here one can go on living, because we endure and do not collapse overnight. Thus, with this "We" he
looks back over the past amazing lives of individuals and feels himself like the spirit of the house, the
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 9
Page No 12
generation, and the city. From time to time he personally greets from the far away, obscure, and confused
centuries the soul of a people as his own soul, with a feeling of completion and premonition, a scent of almost
lost tracks, an instinctively correct reading even of a past which has been written over, a swift understanding
of the erased and reused parchments (which have, in fact, been erased and written over many times). These
are his gifts and his virtues. With them stands Goethe in front of the memorial to Erwin von Steinbach. In the
storm of his feeling the veil of the historical cloud spread out between them was torn apart. He saw the
German work for the first time once more, "working from the strong rough German soul."
Such a sense and attraction led the Italians of the Renaissance and reawoke in their poets the old Italian
genius, to a "wonderfully renewed sound of the ancient lyre," as Jakob Burckhardt says. But that antiquarian
historical sense of reverence has the highest value when it infuses into the modest, raw, even meagre
conditions in which an individual or a people live a simple moving feeling of pleasure and satisfaction, in the
way, for example, Niebuhr admitted with honest sincerity he could live happily on moor and heath among
free farmers who had a history, without missing art. How could history better serve living than by the fact
that it thus links the less favoured races and people to their home region and home traditions, keeps them
settled there, and prevents them from roaming around and from competition and warfare, looking for
something better in foreign places?
Sometimes it seems as if it is an obstinate lack of understanding which keeps individuals, as it were, screwed
tight to these companions and surroundings, to this arduous daily routine, to these bare mountain ridges, but it
is the most healthy lack of understanding, the most beneficial to the community, as anyone knows who has
clearly experienced the frightening effects of an adventurous desire to wander away, sometimes even among
entire hordes of people, or who sees nearby the condition of a people which has lost faith in its ancient history
and has fallen into a restless cosmopolitan choice and a constant search for novelty after novelty. The
opposite feeling, the sense of well being of a tree for its roots, the happiness to know oneself in a manner not
entirely arbitrary and accidental, but as someone who has grown out of a past, as an heir, flower, and fruit,
and thus to have one's existence excused, indeed justified, this is what people nowadays lovingly describe as
the real historical sense.
Now, that is naturally not the condition in which a person would be most capable of dissolving the past into
pure knowledge. Thus, also we perceive here what we discerned in connection with monumental history, that
the past itself suffers, so long as history serves life and is ruled by the drive to live. To speak with some
freedom in the illustration, the tree feels its roots more than it can see them. The extent of this feeling,
however, is measured by the size and force of its visible branches. If the tree makes a mistake here, then how
mistaken it will be about the entire forest around it! From that forest the tree only knows and feels something
insofar as this hinders or helps it, but not otherwise. The antiquarian sense of a person, a civic community, an
entire people always has a very highly restricted field of vision. It does not perceive most things at all, and
the few things which it does perceive it looks at far too closely and in isolation. It cannot measure it and
therefore takes everything as equally important. Thus, for the antiquarian sense each single thing is too
important. For it assigns to the things of the past no difference in value and proportion which would
distinguish things from each other fairly, but measures things by the proportions of the antiquarian individual
or people looking back into the past.
Here there is always the imminent danger that at some point everything old and past, especially what still
enters a particular field of vision, is taken as equally worthy of reverence but that everything which does not
fit this respect for ancient things, like the new and the coming into being, is rejected and treated as hostile. So
even the Greeks tolerated the hieratic style of their plastic arts alongside the free and the great styles, indeed,
they not only tolerated later the pointed noses and the frosty smiles, but made them into an elegant fashion.
When the sense of a people is hardened like this, when history serves the life of the past in such a way that it
buries further living, especially higher living, when the historical sense no longer conserves life, but
mummifies it, then the tree dies unnaturally, from the top gradually down to the roots, and at last the roots
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 10
Page No 13
themselves are generally destroyed. Antiquarian history itself degenerates in that moment when it no longer
inspires and fills with enthusiasm the fresh life of the present. Then reverence withers away. The scholarly
habit lives on without it and orbits in an egotistical and selfsatisfied manner around its own centre. Then we
get a glimpse of the wretched drama of a blind mania for collecting, a restless compiling together of
everything that ever existed. The man envelops himself in a mouldy smell. With the antiquarian style, he
manages to corrupt a significant talent, a noble need, into an insatiable new lust, a desire for everything really
old. Often he sinks so deep that he is finally satisfied with that nourishment and takes pleasure in gobbling up
for himself the dust of biographical quisquilien [rubbish].
But even when this degeneration does not enter into it, when antiquarian history does not lose the basis upon
which it alone can take root as a cure for living, enough dangers still remain, especially if it becomes too
powerful and grows over the other ways of dealing with the past. Antiquarian history knows only how to
preserve life, not how to generate it. Therefore, it always undervalues what is coming into being, because it
has no instinctive feel for it, as, for example, monumental history has. Thus, antiquarian history hinders the
powerful willing of new things; it cripples the active man, who always, as an active person, will and must set
aside reverence to some extent. The fact that something has become old now gives birth to the demand that it
must be immortal, for when a man reckons what every such ancient fact, an old custom of his fathers, a
religious belief, an inherited political right, has undergone throughout its existence, what sum of reverence
and admiration from individuals and generations ever since, then it seems presumptuous or even criminal to
replace such an antiquity with something new and to set up in opposition to such a numerous cluster of
revered and admired things the single fact of what is coming into being and what is present.
Here it becomes clear how a third method of analyzing the past is quite often necessary for human beings,
alongside the monumental and the antiquarian: the critical method. Once again this is in the service of living.
A person must have the power and from time to time use it to break a past and to dissolve it, in order to be
able to live. He manages to do this by dragging the past before the court of justice, investigating it
meticulously, and finally condemning it. That past is worthy of condemnation; for that is how it stands with
human things: in them human force and weakness have always been strong. Here it is not righteousness
which sits in the judgement seat or, even less, mercy which announces judgement, but life alone, that dark,
driving, insatiable selfdesiring force. Its judgement is always unmerciful, always unjust, because it never
emerges from a pure spring of knowledge, but in most cases the judgement would be like that anyway, even
if righteousness itself were to utter it. "For everything that arises is worth destroying. Therefore, it would be
better that nothing arose." It requires a great deal of power to be able to live and to forget just how much life
and being unjust are one and the same. Luther himself once voiced the opinion that the world only came into
being through the forgetfulness of God; if God had thought about "heavy artillery," he would never have
made the world. From time to time, however, this same life, which uses forgetting, demands the temporary
destruction of this forgetfulness. For it should be made quite clear how unjust the existence of something or
other is, a right, a caste, a dynasty, for example, and how this thing merits destruction.
For when its past is analyzed critically, then we grasp with a knife at its roots and go cruelly beyond all
reverence. It is always a dangerous process, that is, a dangerous process for life itself. And people or ages
serving life in this way, by judging and destroying a past, are always dangerous and in danger. For since we
are now the products of earlier generations, we are also the products of their aberrations, passions, mistakes,
and even crimes. It is impossible to loose oneself from this chain entirely. When we condemn that confusion
and consider ourselves released from it, then we have not overcome the fact that we are derived from it. In
the best case, we bring the matter to a conflict between our inherited customary nature and our knowledge, in
fact, even to a war between a new strict discipline and how we have been brought up and what we have
inherited from time immemorial. We cultivate a new habit, a new instinct, a second nature, so that the first
nature atrophies. It is an attempt to give oneself, as it were, a past a posteriori [after the fact], out of which we
may be descended in opposition to the one from which we are descended. It is always a dangerous attempt,
because it is so difficult to find a borderline to the denial of the past and because the second nature usually is
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 11
Page No 14
weaker than the first. Too often what remains is a case of someone who understands the good without doing
it, because we also understand what is better without being able to do it. But here and there victory is
nevertheless achieved, and for the combatants, for those who make use of critical history for their own living,
there is even a remarkable consolation, namely, they know that that first nature was at one time or another
once a second nature and that every victorious second nature becomes a first nature.
IV
These are the services which history can carry out for living. Every person and every people, according to its
goals, forces, and needs, uses a certain knowledge of the past, sometimes as monumental history, sometimes
as antiquarian history, and sometimes as critical history, but not as a crowd of pure thinkers only watching
life closely, not as people eager for knowledge, individuals only satisfied by knowledge, for whom an
increase of understanding is the only goal, but always only for the purpose of living and, in addition, under
the command and the highest guidance of this life. This is the natural relationship to history of an age, a
culture, and a people: summoned up by hunger, regulated by the degree of the need, held to limits by the
plastic power within, the understanding of the past is desired at all times to serve the future and the present,
not to weaken the present, not to uproot a forceful living future. That all is simple, as the truth is simple, and
is also immediately convincing for anyone who does not begin by letting himself be guided by historical
proof.
And now for a quick look at our time! We are frightened and run back. Where is all the clarity, all the
naturalness and purity of that connection between life and history? How confusedly, excessively, and
anxiously this problem now streams before our eyes! Does the fault lie with us, the observers? Or has the
constellation of life and history altered, because a powerful and hostile star has interposed itself between
them? Other people might point out that we have seen things incorrectly, but we want to state what we think
we see. In any case, such a star has come in between, an illuminating and beautiful star. The constellation has
truly changed through science, through the demand that history is to be a science. Now not only does life no
longer rule and control knowledge about the past, but also all the border markings have been ripped up, and
everything that used to exist has come crashing down onto people. As far back as there has been a coming
into being, far back into the endless depths, all perspectives have also shifted. No generation ever saw such an
immense spectacle as is shown now by the science of universal becoming, by history. Of course, history even
shows this with the dangerous boldness of its motto: Fiat veritas, pereat vita [let the truth be done and let life
perish].
Let us picture to ourselves the spiritual result produced by this process in the soul of the modern man.
Historical knowledge streams out of invincible sources always renewing itself with more. Strange and
disconnected things push forward. Memory opens all its gates and is nevertheless not open wide enough.
Nature strives its utmost to receive these strange guests, to arrange and honour them. But these are at war
with each other, and it appears necessary to overcome them forcibly, in order not to destroy oneself in their
conflict. Habituation to such a disorderly, stormy, and warring household gradually becomes a second nature,
although it is immediately beyond question that this second nature is much weaker, much more restless, and
completely less healthy than the first. Modern man finally drags a huge crowd of indigestible rocks of
knowledge around inside him, which then occasionally audibly bang around in his body, as it says in fairy
tales. Through this noise the most characteristic property of this modern man reveals itself: the remarkable
conflict on the inside, to which nothing on the outside corresponds, and an outside to which nothing inside
corresponds, a conflict of which ancient peoples were ignorant.
Knowledge, taken up to excess without hunger, even in opposition to any need, now works no longer as
something which reorganizes, a motivation driving outwards. It stays hidden in a certain chaotic inner world,
which that modern man describes with a strange pride as an "Inwardness" peculiar to him. Thus, people say
that we have the content and that only the form is lacking. But with respect to everything alive this is a totally
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 12
Page No 15
improper contradiction. For our modern culture is not alive, simply because it does let itself be understood
without that contradiction; that is, it is really no true culture, but only a way of knowing about culture. There
remain in it thoughts of culture, feelings of culture, but no cultural imperatives come from it. In contrast to
this, what really motivates and moves outward into action then often amounts to not much more than a trivial
convention, a pathetic imitation, or even a raw grimace. At that point the inner feeling is probably asleep, like
the snake which has swallowed an entire rabbit and then lies down contentedly still in the sunlight and avoids
all movements other than the most essential.
The inner process, that is now the entire business, that essentially is "Culture." And everyone who wanders
by has only one wish, that such a culture does not collapse from indigestion. Think, for example, of a Greek
going past such a culture. He would perceive that for more recent people "educated" and "historically
educated" appear to be mentioned very closely together, as if they are one and the same and are distinguished
only by the number of words. If he talked of his own principle that it is possible for an individual to be very
educated and nevertheless not to be historically educated at all, then people would think they had not heard
him correctly and shake their heads. That famous people of a not too distant past, I mean those very Greeks,
had in the period of their greatest power an unhistorical sense tried and tested in rough times. A contemporary
man magically taken back into that world would presumably find the Greeks very uneducated. In that
reaction, of course, the secret of modern education, so painstakingly disguised, would be exposed to public
laughter. For we modern people have nothing at all which comes from us. Only because we fill and overfill
ourselves with foreign ages, customs, arts, philosophies, religions, and discoveries do we become something
worthy of consideration, that is, like wandering encyclopaedias, as some ancient Greek lost our time would
put it.
However, people come across all the value of encyclopaedias only in what is inside, in the contents, not in
what is on the outside or in the binding and on the cover. Thus, all modern education is essentially inner. The
bookbinder has printed on the outside something to this effect: Handbook of inner education for external
barbarians. In fact, this contrast between inner and outer makes the outer even more barbaric than it would
have to be, if a rough people were evolving out of it only according to their basic needs. For what means does
nature still have at its disposal to deal with the superabundance forcing itself outward? Only one means, to
take it as lightly as possible in order to shove it aside again quickly and dispose of it. From that arises a habit
of not taking real things seriously any more. From that arises the "weak personality," as a result of which
reality and existence make only an insignificant impression. Finally people become constantly more venial
and more comfortable and widen the disturbing gulf between content and form until they are insensitive to
the barbarism, so long as the memory is always newly stimulated, so long as constantly new things worthy of
knowledge flow by, which can be neatly packaged in the compartments of memory.
The culture of a people, in contrast to that barbarism, was once described (and correctly so, in my view) as a
unity of the artistic style in all expressions of the life of the people. This description must not be
misunderstood, as if the issue were an opposition between barbarism and a beautiful style. The people to
whom we ascribe a culture should be only in a really vital unity and not so miserably split apart into inner
and outer, into content and form. Anyone who wants to strive after and foster the culture of a people strives
after and fosters this higher unity and, for the sake of a true education, works to destroy the modern notion of
being educated. He dares to consider how the health of a people which has been disturbed by history could be
restored, how the people could find their instinct once again and with that their integrity.
Now I want to speak directly about us Germans of the present day. It is our lot to suffer more than any other
people from this weakness of the personality and from the contradiction between content and form. Form is
commonly accepted by us Germans as a convention, as a disguise and a pretence, and is thus, when not hated,
then at any rate not particularly loved. It would be even more just to say that we have an extraordinary
anxiety with the word convention and also with the fact of convention. In this anxiety, the German abandoned
the French school, for he wanted to become more natural and thereby more German. Now, however, he
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 13
Page No 16
appears to have included in this "thereby" a running away from the school of convention. Now he lets himself
go how and where he has the mere desire to go, and basically imitates nervously whatever he wants in
semiforgetfulness of what in earlier times he imitated painstakingly and often happily.
Thus, measured against earlier times, people still live according to a slipshod, incorrect French convention, as
all our moving, standing, conversing, clothing, and dwelling demonstrate. While people believe they are
escaping back to the natural, they only think about letting themselves go, about comfort, and about the
smallest possible amount of selfcontrol. Wander through a German city: everything is conventional,
compared to the particular national characteristics of foreign cities. This shows itself in negatives: all is
colourless, worn out, badly copied, apathetic. Each man goes about as he wishes, but not with a forceful
desire rich in ideas, but following the laws which the general haste, along with the general desire for comfort,
establishes for the time being. A piece of clothing, whose invention required no brain power, whose
manufacture took no time, one derived from foreigners and imitated as casually as possible, instantly counts
among the Germans as a contribution to German national dress. The sense of form is disavowed with
complete irony, for people have indeed the sense of the content. After all, they are the renowned people of the
inward life.
However, there is a well known danger with this inwardness: the content itself, which people assume they
cannot see at all from the outside, may one day happen to disappear. From the outside people would not
notice either its absence or its earlier presence. But even if people think that, in any case, the German people
are as far as possible from this danger; the foreigner will always have a certain justification when he levels
the accusation at us that our inner life is too weak and unorganized to be effective on the outside and to give
itself a shape. This inward life can to a rare degree prove delicately sensitive, serious, strong, and sincere, and
perhaps even richer than the inward lives of other peoples. But as a totality it remains weak, because all the
beautiful threads are not tied together into a powerful knot. Thus, the visible act is not the total action and
selfrevelation of this inner life, but only a weak or crude attempt of a few strands or other to will something
whose appearance might pass muster as the totality. Thus, one cannot judge the German according to a single
action. As an individual he is still completely hidden after the action. As is well known, he must be measured
by his thoughts and feelings, and they speak out nowadays in his books. If only these books did not awaken,
in recent times more than ever, a doubt about whether the famous inner life is really still sitting in its
inaccessible little temple. It would be a horrible idea that one day it may have disappeared and now the only
thing left behind is the externality, that arrogant, clumsy, and respectfully unkempt German externality.
Almost as terrible as if that inner life, without people being able to see it, sat inside, counterfeit, coloured,
painted over, and had become an actress, if not something worse, as, for example, Grillparzer, who stood on
the sidelines as a quiet observer, appears to assume about his experience as a dramatist in the theatre: "We
feel with abstractions," he says, "we hardly know any more how feeling expresses itself among our
contemporaries. We let our feelings jump about in ways they do not affect us any more. Shakespeare has
destroyed everything new for us."
This is a single example, perhaps too quickly generalized. But how fearful would his justified generalization
be if the individual cases should force themselves upon the observer far too frequently, how despairingly the
statement would echo: We Germans feel abstractedly; we have all been corrupted by history. This statement
would destroy at the root every hope for a future national culture. For that kind of hope grows out of the faith
in the authenticity and the immediacy of German feeling, from the belief in the undamaged inner life. What is
there still to be hoped for or to be believed, if the inner life has learned to leap about, to dance, to put on make
up, and to express itself outwardly with abstraction and calculation and gradually to lose itself! And how is
the great productive spirit to maintain himself among a people no longer sure of its unified inner life, which
falls apart into sections, with a miseducated and seduced inner life among the cultured, and an inadequate
inner life among the uneducated? How is he to keep going if the unity of the people's feeling gets lost, if, in
addition, he knows that the very part which calls itself the educated portion of the people and which arrogates
to itself the national artistic spirit is false and biased. Here and there the judgement and taste of individuals
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 14
Page No 17
may themselves have become finer and more sublimated, but that is no compensation for him. It pains the
productive spirit to have to speak, as it were, to one class and no longer to be necessary within his own
people. Perhaps he would sooner bury his treasure, since it disgusts him to be exquisitely patronized by one
class, while his heart is full of pity for all. The instinct of the people no longer comes to meet him. It is
useless to stretch out one's arms toward it in yearning. What still remains for him, other than to turn his
enthusiastic hate against that restricting prohibition, against the barriers erected in the socalled education of
his people, in order at least, as a judge, to condemn what for him, the living and the producer of life, is
destruction and degradation? Thus, he exchanges the deep understanding of his own fate for the divine
pleasure of the creator and helper and finishes up a lonely philosopher, a supersaturated wise man.
It is the most painful spectacle. Generally whoever sees it will recognize a holy need here. He tells himself:
here it is necessary to give assistance; that higher unity in the nature and soul of a people must be established
once more; that gulf between the inner and the outer must disappear again under the hammer blows of need.
What means should he now reach for? What remains for him now other than his deep understanding? By
speaking out on this and spreading awareness of it, by sowing from his full hands, he hopes to plant a need.
And out of the strong need will one day arise the strong deed. And so that I leave no doubt where I derive the
example of that need, that necessity, that knowledge, here my testimony should stand, that it is German unity
in that highest sense which we are striving for and more passionately for that than for political reunification,
the unity of the German spirit and life after the destruction of the opposition of form and content, of the inner
life and convention.
V
In five ways the supersaturation of an age in history seems to me hostile and dangerous. Through such an
excess, first, that hitherto mentioned contrast between inner and outer is produced; second, the personality is
weakened; an age is caught up in the fantasy that it possesses the rarest virtue, righteousness, in a higher
degree than any other time; third, the instincts of a people are disrupted, and the individual no less than the
totality is hindered from developing maturely; fourth, through this excess the always dangerous belief in the
old age of humanity takes root, the belief that we are late arrivals and epigones; fifth, an age attains the
dangerous mood of irony about itself and, beyond that, an even more dangerous cynicism. In this, however, it
increasingly ripens towards a cleverly egotistical practice, through which the forces of life are crippled and
finally destroyed.
And now back to our first statement: modern man suffers from a weakened personality. Just as the Roman in
the time of the Caesars became unRoman with regard to the area of the earth standing at his disposal, as he
lost himself among the foreigners streaming in and degenerated with the cosmopolitan carnival of gods,
customs, and arts, so matters must go with the modern person who continually allows his historical artists to
prepare the celebration of a world market fair. He has become a spectator, enjoying and wandering around,
converted into a condition in which even great wars and huge revolutions are hardly able to change anything
momentarily. The war has not yet ended, and already it is transformed on printed paper a hundred thousand
times over; soon it will be promoted as the newest stimulant for the palate of those greedy for history. It
appears almost impossible that a strong and full tone will be produced by the most powerful plucking of the
strings. As soon as the sound appears again, already in the next moment it dies away, softly evaporating
without force into history. To state the matter in moral terms: you do not manage to hold onto what is noble
any more; your deeds are sudden bangs, not rolling thunder. If the very greatest and most wonderful thing is
accomplished, it must nevertheless move to Hades without any fuss. For art runs away, when you instantly
throw over your actions the roof of the historical marquee. The person there who wants to understand
immediately, to calculate and grasp, where he should in an enduring oscillation hang onto the unknowable as
something sublime, may be called intelligent, but only in the sense in which Schiller speaks of the
understanding of the intelligent person: he does not see some things which even the child sees; he does not
hear some things which the child hears; these "some things" are precisely the most important thing. Because
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 15
Page No 18
he does not understand this, his understanding is more childish than the child's and more simplistic than
simple mindedness, in spite of the many shrewd wrinkles on his parchmentlike features and the virtuoso
practice of his fingers unravelling all complexities. This amounts to the fact that he has destroyed and lost his
instinct. Now he can no longer let the reins hang loose, trusting the "divine animal," when his understanding
wavers and his road leads through deserts. Thus, individuality becomes timid and unsure and can no longer
believe in itself. It sinks into itself, into the inner life. That means here only into the piled up mass of
scholarly data which does not work towards the outside, instruction which does not become living. If we look
for a moment out to the exterior, then we notice how the expulsion of instinct by history has converted people
almost into nothing but abstraction and shadows. A man no longer gambles his identity on that instinct.
Instead he masks himself as educated man, as scholar, as poet, as politician.
If we seize such masks because we believe the matter is something serious and not merely a marionette play
(for they all paper themselves over with seriousness), then we suddenly have only rags and bright patches in
our hands. Therefore, we should no longer allow ourselves to be deceived and should shout out, "Strip off
your jackets or be what you seem." No longer should each serious person turn into a Don Quixote, for he has
something better to do than to keep getting into fights with such illusory realities. In any case, however, he
must keenly inspect each mask, cry "Halt! Who goes there?" and pull the mask down onto their necks.
Strange! We should have thought that history encouraged human beings above all to be honest, even if only
an honest fool. This has always been its effect. But nowadays it is no longer that! Historical education and the
common uniform of the middle class together both rule. While never before has there been such sonorous talk
of the "free personality," we never once see personalities, to say nothing of free people, but only anxiously
disguised universal people. Individuality has drawn itself back into the inner life: on the outside we no longer
observe any of it. This being the case, we could doubt whether, in general, there could be causes without
effects. Or should a race of eunuchs be necessary as a guard over the great historical harem of the world? For
them, of course, pure objectivity is well and truly established on their faces. However, it does seem almost as
if it was their assignment to stand guardian over history, so that nothing comes out of it other than just
histories without events, to ensure that through it no personalities become "free," that is, true to themselves
and true with respect to others in word and deed. First through this truthfulness will the need, the inner
misery of the modern man, see the light of day, and art and religion will be able to enter as true helpers in
place of that anxiously concealed convention and masquerade, in order to cultivate a common culture
corresponding to real needs, culture which does not, like the present universal education, just teach one to lie
to oneself about these needs and thus to become a wandering lie.
In what an unnatural, artificial, and definitely unworthy position must the truly naked goddess Philosophy,
the most sincere of all sciences, be in a time which suffers from universal education. She remains in such a
world of compulsory external uniformity the learned monologue of a solitary stroller, an individual's
accidental hunting trophy, a hidden parlour secret, or a harmless prattle between academic old men and
children. No one is allowed to venture on fulfilling the law of philosophy on his own. No one lives
philosophically, with that simple manly truth, which acted forcefully on a man in ancient times, wherever he
was, and which thus drove him to behave as Stoic if he had once promised to be true to the Stoa.
All modern philosophy is political and policelike, restricted to the appearance of learning through the ruling
powers, churches, academies, customs, and human cowardice. It sticks around with sighs of "If only" or with
the knowledge "There was once." Philosophy is wrong to be at the heart of historical education, if it wants to
be more than an inner repressed knowledge without effect. If the modern human being were, in general, only
courageous and decisive, if he were in even his hostility not just an inner being, he would banish philosophy.
Thus, he contents himself by modestly covering up her nudity. Yes, people think, write, print, speak, and
learn philosophically; to this extent almost everything is allowed. Only in action, in socalled living, are
things otherwise. There only one thing is always allowed, and everything else is simply impossible. So
historical education wills it. Are they still human beings, we ask ourselves then, or perhaps only thinking,
writing, and speaking machines?
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 16
Page No 19
Of Shakespeare Goethe once said, "No one hated the material costume more than he. He understood really
well the inner costume of human beings, and here all people are alike. People say he presented the Romans
excellently. I do not find that. They are nothing but inveterate Englishmen, but naturally they are human
beings, people from the ground up, and the Roman toga suits them well enough." Now, I ask if it might be
possible to lead out our contemporary men of letters, men of the people, officials, and politicians as Romans.
It will not work, because they are not human beings, but only physical compendia and, as it were, concrete
abstractions. If they should have character and their own style, this is buried so deep that it has no power at
all to struggle out into the daylight. If they should be human beings, then they are that only for the man "who
tests the kidneys." For everyone else they are something other, not human beings, not gods, not animals, but
historically educated pictures, completely and utterly education, picture, form, without demonstrable content,
unfortunately only bad form and, in addition, uniform. And in this sense may my claim may be understood
and considered: History is borne only by strong personalities; the weak personalities it obliterates completely.
It comes down to this: history bewilders feeling and sensing where these are not strong enough to measure
the past against themselves.
Anyone who does not dare any longer to trust himself but who involuntarily turns to history for his feeling
and seeks advice by asking "What should I feel here?" in his timidity gradually becomes an actor and plays a
role, usually in fact many roles. Therefore, he plays each badly and superficially. Gradually the congruence
between the man and his historical sphere fails. We see no forward young men associating with the Romans,
as if they were their equals. They rummage around and dig away in the remnants of the Greek poets, as if
these bodies were also ready for their postmortem examination and were worthless things, whatever their
own literary bodies might be. If we assume there is a concern with Democritus, then the question always on
my lips is this: Why then just Democritus? Why not Heraclitus? Or Philo? Or Bacon? Or Descartes? and so
on to one's heart's content. And in that case, why then just a philosopher? Why not a poet, an orator? And
why particularly a Greek? Why not an Englishman, a Turk? Is the past then not large enough to find
something, so that you do not make yourself so ridiculous on your own. But, as I have mentioned, it is a race
of eunuchs; for a eunuch one woman is like another, in effect, one woman, the womaninitself, the eternally
unapproachable, and so what drives them is something indifferent, so long as history itself remains splendidly
objective and protected by precisely the sort of people who could never create history themselves. And since
the eternally feminine is never attracted to you, then you pull it down to yourselves and assume, since you are
neuters, that history is also a neuter.
However, so that people do not think that I am serious in comparing history with the eternally feminine, I will
express myself much more clearly: I consider that history is the opposite of the eternally masculine and that it
must be quite unimportant for those who are through and through "historically educated." But whatever the
case, such people are themselves neither male nor female, not something common to both, but always only
neutral or, to express myself in a more educated way, they are just the eternally objective.
If the personalities are, first of all, as has been described, inflated to an eternal loss of subjectivity or, as
people say, to objectivity, then nothing more can work on them. Let something good and right come about, in
action, poetry, or music. Immediately the person emptied out by his education looks out over the world and
asks about the history of the author. If this author has already created a number of things, immediately the
critic must allow himself to point out the earlier and the presumed future progress of the author's
development; right away he will bring in others for comparative purposes, he will dissect and rip apart the
choice of the author's material and his treatment, and will, in his wisdom, fit the work together again anew,
giving him advice and setting him right about everything. Let the most astonishing thing occur; the crowd of
historical neutrals is always in place ready to assess the author from a great distance. Momentarily the echo
resounds, but always as "Criticism." A short time before, however, the critic did not permit himself to dream
that such an event was possible.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 17
Page No 20
The work never achieves an influence, but only more "Criticism," and the criticism itself, in its turn, has no
influence, but leads only to further criticism. In this business people have agreed to consider a lot of critics as
an influence and a few critics or none as a failure. Basically, however, everything remains as in the past, even
with this "influence." True, people chat for a while about something new, and then about something else new,
and in between do what they always do. The historical education of our critics no longer permits an influence
on our real understanding, namely, an influence on life and action. On the blackest writing they impress
immediately their blotting paper, to the most delightful drawing they apply their thick brush strokes, which
are to be considered corrections. And then everything is over once again. However, their critical pens never
cease flying, for they have lost power over them and are led by them rather than leading them. In this excess
of their critical ejaculations, in the lack of control over themselves, in what the Romans call impotence, the
weakness of the modern personality reveals itself.
VI
But let us leave this weakness. Let us rather turn to a much praised strength of the modern person, with the
truly awkward question whether, on account of his well known "Objectivity," he has a right to call himself
strong, that is, just, and just to a higher degree than the people of other times. Is it true that this objectivity
originates from a heightened need and demand for justice? Or does it, as an effect with quite different causes,
merely create the appearance that justice might be its real cause? Does this objectivity perhaps tempt one to a
detrimental and too flattering bias concerning the virtues of modern man? Socrates considered it an illness
close to insanity to imagine oneself in possession of a virtue and not to possess it. Certainly such conceit is
more dangerous than the opposite delusion, suffering from a mistake or vice. For through the latter delusion it
is perhaps still possible to become better. The former conceit, however, makes a person or a time daily worse,
and, in this case, less just.
True, no one has a higher claim on our admiration than the man who possesses the drive and the power for
justice. For in such people are united and hidden the highest and rarest virtues, as in a bottomless sea that
receives streams from all sides and absorbs them into itself. The hand of the just man authorized to sit in
judgement no longer trembles when it holds the scales. Unsparingly he puts on weight after weight against
himself. His eye does not become dim if he sees the pan in the scales rise and fall, and his voice rings out
neither hard nor broken when he delivers the verdict. If he were a cold demon of knowledge, then he would
spread out around him the ice cold atmosphere of a terrifyingly superhuman majesty, which we would have
to fear and not to revere. But since he is a human being and yet has tried to rise above venial doubt to a strong
certainty, above a patient leniency to an imperative "You must," above the rare virtue of magnanimity to the
rarest virtue of all justice, since he now is like this demon, but from the very beginning without being
anything other than a poor human being, and above all, since in each moment he has to atone for his
humanity and be tragically consumed by an impossible virtue, all this places him on a lonely height, as the
example of the human race most worthy of reverence. For he wills truth, not as cold knowledge without
consequences, but as the ordering and punishing judge, truth not as a selfish possession of the individual but
as the sacred entitlement to shift all the boundary stones of egotistical possessions, in a word, truth as the Last
Judgement and not at all something like the captured trophy desired by the individual hunter.
Only insofar as the truthful man has the unconditional will to be just is the striving after truth, which is so
thoughtlessly glorified, something great. In the vision of the duller person a large number of different sorts of
drives (like curiosity, the flight from boredom, resentment, vanity, playfulness), which have nothing at all to
do with the truth, blend in with that striving for truth which has its roots in justice. In fact, the world seems to
be full of people who "serve the truth." But the virtue of justice is very seldom present, even more rarely
recognized, and almost always hated to the death; whereas, the crowd of the apparently virtuous are honoured
as they march in with a great public display. Few people serve truthfulness, because only a few have the
purity of will to be just. Moreover, even of these, the fewest have the strength to be able to be just. It is
certainly not enough only to have the will for justice. And the most horrible sufferings have come directly
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 18
Page No 21
from the drive for justice without the power of judgement among human beings. For this reason the general
welfare would require nothing more than to scatter the seeds of the power of judgement as widely as possible,
so that the fanatic remained distinguishable from the judge and blind desire to be a judge distinguishable
from the conscious power to be able to judge. But where would one find a means of cultivating the power of
judgement! Thus, when there is talk of truth and justice, people remain in an eternal wavering hesitation
whether a fanatic or a judge is talking. Hence, we should forgive those who welcome benevolently the
"servers of the truth" who possess neither the will nor the power to judge and who set themselves the task of
searching for pure knowledge with no attention to consequences or, more clearly, of searching for a barren
truth. There are many trivial truths; there are problems that never require effort, let alone any selfsacrifice,
in order for one to judge them correctly. In this field of the trivial and the safe, a person indeed succeeds in
becoming a cold demon of knowledge nonetheless. When, especially in favourable times, whole cohorts of
learned people and researchers are turned into such demons, it always remains unfortunately possible that the
time in question suffers from a lack of strong and great righteousness, in short, of the most noble kernel of the
socalled drive to the truth.
Let us now place before our eyes the historical virtuoso of the present times. Is he the most just man of his
time? It is true that he has cultivated in himself such a tenderness and sensitivity of feeling that for him
nothing human is far distant. The most different times and people ring out at once from his lyre in
harmonious tones. He has become a tuneful passive thing, which through its resounding tone works on other
passive things of the same type, until finally the entire air of an age is full of such delicate reverberations,
twanging away in concord. But, in my view, we hear that original historical major chord only as an overtone,
so to speak: the sturdiness and power of the original can no longer be sensed in the thin shrill sound of the
strings. Whereas the original tone usually aroused actions, needs, and terrors, this lulls us to sleep and makes
us weak hedonists. It is as if we have arranged the Eroica Symphony for two flutes and use it for dreamy
opium smoking. By that we may now measure, among the virtuosi, how things stand with the highest
demands of modern man for a loftier and purer justice, a virtue which never has anything pleasant, knows no
attractive feelings, but is hard and terrifying.
Measured by that, how low magnanimity stands now on the ladder of virtues, magnanimity characteristic of a
few rare historians! But for many more it is a matter only of tolerance, of leaving aside all consideration of
what cannot be once and for all denied, of editing and glossing over in a moderate and benevolent way, of an
intelligent acceptance of the fact that the inexperienced man interprets it as a virtue of justice if the past is
generally explained without hard accents and without the expression of hate. But only the superior power can
judge. Weakness must tolerate, unless it wishes to feign strength and turn justice on the judgement seat into a
performing actress.
There is just one fearful species of historian still remaining: efficient, strong, and honest characters, but with
narrow heads. Here good will to be just is present, together with the strong feeling in the judgements. But all
the pronouncements of the judges are false, roughly for the same reasons that the judgements of the ordinary
sworn jury are false.
How unlikely the frequency of historical talent is! To say nothing at all here about the disguised egoists and
fellow travellers, who adopt a thoroughly objective demeanour for the insidious games they play; and by the
same token to say nothing of the unthinking people who write as historians in the naive belief that their own
age is right in all its popular views and that to write by the standards of the time generally amounts to being
right, a faith in which each and every religion lives and about which, in the case of religion, there is nothing
more to say. Those naive historians call "Objectivity" the process of measuring past opinions and deeds by
the universal public opinion of the moment. Here they find the canon of all truths. Their work is to adapt the
past to contemporary triviality. By contrast, they call "subjective" that way of writing history which does not
take popular opinion as canonical.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 19
Page No 22
And might not an illusion have occurred in the highest interpretation of the word objectivity? With this word,
people understand a condition in the historian in which he looks at an event with such purity in all his
motives and consequences that they have no effect at all on his subject. People mean that aesthetic
phenomenon, that state of being detached from one's personal interests, with which the painter in a stormy
landscape, under lightning and thunder, or on the moving sea looks at his inner picture and, in the process,
forgets his own person. Thus, people also demand from the historian the artistic tranquillity and the full
immersion in the thing. However, it is a myth that the picture which shows things in a person constituted in
this way reflects the empirical essence of things. Or is it the case that, by some inner capacity at these times
things depict themselves and, as it were, draw a good likeness of themselves or photograph themselves on a
purely passive medium?
This would be a mythology and on top of that a bad one. In addition, people might forget that that very
moment is the most artistic and most spontaneous creative moment in the inner life of the artist, a moment of
composition of the very highest order, whose result will be an artistically really true picture, not a historically
true one. To think of history as objective in this way is the secret work of the dramatist, that is, to think of
everything one after the other, to weave the isolated details into a totality, always on the condition that a unity
of the plan in the material has to be established, if it is not inherent in it. Thus, man spins a web over the past
and tames it; in this way the artistic impulse itself expresses its drive for justice, but not its drive for truth.
Objectivity and Justice have nothing to do with each other.
One might imagine a way of writing history which has no drop of the common empirical truth in it and yet
which might be able to claim the highest rating on an objective scale. Indeed, Grillparzer ventures to clarify
this point. "What is history then other than the way in which the spirit of man takes in the events which are
impenetrable to him, something in which only God knows whether there is a relationship holding it together,
in which that spirit replaces an incomprehensible thing with something comprehensible, underwrites with its
ideas of external purposes a totality which really can only be known from within, and assumes chance events,
where a thousand small causes were at work. At any one time everyone has his own individual necessity so
that millions of trends run next to each other in parallel, crooked, and straight lines, intersect each other, help,
hinder, flow forward and backwards, thus taking on in relation to each other the character of chance and, to
say nothing of the effects of natural events, render it impossible to prove a compelling, allencompassing
necessity for events."
However, this necessary conclusion about that "objective" look at the matter in hand should be exposed right
away. This is an assumption which, when it is voiced as a statement of belief by historians, can only assume
an odd form. Schiller, in fact, is completely clear concerning the essential subjectivity of this assumption,
when he says of historians: "One phenomenon after another begins to liberate itself from accidental and
lawless freedom and, as a coordinated link, to become part of a harmonious totality, which naturally is
present only in its depiction." But how should we consider the claim (made in good faith) of a famous
historical virtuoso, a claim hovering artificially between tautology and absurdity: "The fact is that that all
human action and striving are subordinate to the light and often unremarked but powerful and irresistible
progress of things"? In such a statement we do not feel any mysterious wisdom expressing itself as clear
illogic, like the saying of Goethe's gardener, "Nature lets itself be forced but not compelled", or in the
inscription of a booth in a fair ground, as Swift tells it, "Here you can see the largest elephant in the world
except itself." For what is, in fact, the opposition between the actions and the drives of men and the progress
of things? In particular, it strikes me that such historians, like that one from whom we quoted a sentence,
cease to instruct as soon as they become general and then, in their darkness, show a sense of weakness. In
other sciences generalizations are the most important thing, insofar as they contain laws. However, if
statements like the one we quoted were to serve as valid laws, one would have to reply that then the work of
the writer of history is changed, for what remains particularly true in such statements, once we remove the
abovementioned irreconcilably dark remainder, is well known and totally trivial. For it is apparent to
everyone's eye in the smallest area of experience.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 20
Page No 23
However, for that reason to inconvenience entire peoples and to spend wearisome years of work on the
subject amounts to nothing more than, as in the natural sciences, to pile experiment on experiment a long
time after the law can be inferred from the present store of experiments. Incidentally, according to Zoellner,
natural science nowadays may suffer from an excess of experimentation. If the value of a drama is to lie only
in the main ideas of the conclusion, then drama itself would be the furthest possible route to the goal, crooked
and laborious. And thus I hope that history can realize that its significance is not in universal ideas, like some
sort of blossom or fruit, but that its worth is directly one which indicates a known, perhaps a habitual theme,
a daily melody, in an elegant way, elevates it, intensifies it to an inclusive symbol, and thus allows one to
make out in the original theme an entire world of profundity, power, and beauty. What is appropriate,
however, in this process, before everything else, is a great artistic potential, a creative hovering above and a
loving immersion in the empirical data, a further poetical composing on the given typesto this process
objectivity certainly belongs, but as a positive quality.
However, too often objectivity is only a phrase. Instead of that innerly flashing, externally unmoving and
mysterious composure in the artist's eyes, the affectation of composure emerges, just as the lack of pathos and
moral power cultivates the disguise of a biting coldness of expression. In certain cases, the banality of the
conviction ventures to appear, that wisdom of every man, which creates the impression of composure for
unexcited people only through its tediousness, in order to pass muster as that artistic condition in which the
subject is silent and becomes completely imperceptible. So everything which generally does not rouse
emotion is sought out, and the driest expression is immediately the right one. Indeed, people go as far as to
assume that the person whom a moment in the past does not affect in the slightest is competent to present it.
Philologues and Greeks frequently behave towards each other in this way. They do not concern themselves
with each other in the slightest. People call this real "objectivity," as well. Now, in those places where the
highest and rarest matter is to be directly presented, it is absolutely outrageous to find the deliberate state of
indifference, something put on for show, the acquired flat and sober art of seeking out motives, especially
when the vanity of the historian drives toward this objectively indifferent behaviour. Incidentally, with such
authors people should base their judgement more closely on the principle that each man's vanity is inversely
proportional to his understanding. No, at least be honest! Do not seek the appearance of that artistic power
truly called objectivity, and do not seek the appearance of justice, if you have not been ordained in the fearful
vocation of the just. As if it also were the work of every age to have to be just in relation to everything that
once was! As a matter of fact, times and generations never have the right to be the judges of all earlier times
and generations. Such an uncomfortable task always falls to only a few, indeed, to the rarest people. Who
compels you then to judge? And so, just test yourselves, whether you could be just, if you wanted to! As
judges you must stand higher than what is being assessed, whereas, you have only come later. The guests
who come last to the table should in all fairness receive the last places. And you wish to have the first places?
Then at least do something of the highest and best order. Perhaps people will then really make a place for
you, even if you come at the end.
You can interpret the past only on the basis of the highest power of the present. Only in the strongest tension
of your noblest characteristics will you surmise what from the past is great and worth knowing and
preserving. Like by like! Otherwise you reduce the past down to your level. Do not believe a piece of
historical writing if it does not spring out of the head of the rarest of spirits. You will always perceive the
quality of its spirit if it is forced to express something universal or to repeat once more something universally
known. The true historian must have the power of reshaping the universally known into what has never been
heard and to announce what is universal so simply and deeply that people overlook the simplicity in the
profundity and the profundity in the simplicity. No person can be simultaneously a great historian, an artistic
person, and a numskull. On the other hand, people should not rate as insignificant the workers who go around
with a cart, piling things up and sifting through them, because they will certainly not be able to become great
historians. Even less should we exchange them for numskulls. We should see them as the necessary
colleagues and manual labourers in the service of the master, just as the French, with greater naïveté than is
possible among the Germans, were accustomed to speak of the historiens de M. Thiers [historians of
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 21
Page No 24
Monsieur Thiers]. These workers should gradually become very learned men, but for that reason cannot ever
become masters. An eminently learned man and a great numskullthose go together very easily under a
single hat.
Thus, the person of experience and reflection writes history. Anyone who has not experienced life on a
greater and higher level than everyone else will not know how to interpret the greatness and loftiness of the
past. The utterance of the past is always an oracular pronouncement. You will understand it only as builders
of the future and as people who know about the present. People now explain the extraordinarily deep and
farreaching effect of Delphi by the particular fact that the Delphic priests had precise knowledge about the
past. It is appropriate now to understand that only the man who builds the future has a right to judge the past.
In order to look ahead, set yourselves an important goal, and at the same time control that voluptuous
analytical drive with which you now lay waste the present and render almost impossible all tranquillity, all
peaceful growth and maturing. Draw around yourself the fence of a large and extensive hope, an optimistic
striving. Create in yourselves a picture to which the future is to correspond, and forget the myth that you are
epigones. You have enough to plan and to invent when you imagine that future life for yourselves. But in
considering history do not ask that she show you the "How?" and the "With what?" If, however, you live your
life in the history of great men, then you will learn from history the highest command: to become mature and
to flee away from that paralyzing and prohibiting upbringing of the age, which sees advantages for itself in
not allowing you to become mature, in order to rule and exploit you, the immature. And when you ask after
biographies, then do not ask for those with the refrain "Mr. Soandso and His Age" but for those whose title
page must read "A Fighter Against His Age." Fill your souls with Plutarch, and dare to believe in yourselves
when you have faith in his heroes. With a hundred people raised in such an unmodern way, that is, people
who have become mature and familiar with the heroic, one could permanently silence the entire noisy
pseudoeducation of this age.
VII
When the historical sense reigns unchecked and drags with it all its consequences, it uproots the future,
because it destroys illusions and takes from existing things the atmosphere in which they alone can live.
Historical justice, even if it is practised truly and with a purity of conviction, is therefore a fearful virtue,
because it always undermines living and brings about its downfall. Its judgement is always an annihilation. If
behind the historical drive no constructive urge is at work, if things are not destroyed and cleared away so
that a future, something already alive in hope, builds its dwelling on the liberated ground, if justice alone
rules, then the creative instinct is enfeebled and disheartened.
For example, a religion which is to be turned into historical knowledge under the power of pure justice, a
religion which is to be scientifically understood through and through, is by the end of this process
immediately destroyed. The reason for this is that in the historical method of reckoning so many false, crude,
inhuman, absurd, and violent things always emerge that the fully pious atmosphere of illusion in which alone
everything that wants to live can live necessarily disappears. But only in love, only in a love overshadowed
by illusion, does a person create, that is, only in unconditional belief in perfection and righteousness.
Anything which compels a person no longer to love unconditionally cuts away the roots of his power. He
must wither up, that is, become dishonest.
In effects like this, history is opposed by art. And only when history takes it upon itself to turn itself into an
art work and thus to become a purely artistic picture can it perhaps maintain the instincts or even arouse
them. Such historical writing, however, would thoroughly go against the analytical and inartistic trends of our
time; indeed, they would consider it counterfeit. But history which only destroys, without an inner drive to
build guiding it, makes its implements permanently blasé and unnatural. For such people destroy illusions,
and "whoever destroys illusions in himself and others is punished by the strongest tyrant, nature." True, for a
fairly long time one can keep oneself really busy with history completely harmlessly and thoughtlessly, as if
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 22
Page No 25
it were an occupation as good as any other. The newer Theology, in particular, seems to have become
involved with history purely harmlessly, and now it will hardly notice that, in doing so, it stands, probably
very much against its will, in the service of Voltaire's écrasez [i.e., Voltaire's extreme hostility to the church].
Let no one assume from this a new powerfully constructive instinct. For that we would have to let the
socalled Protestant Union be considered the maternal womb of a new religion and someone like Judge
Holtzendorf (the editor of and chief spokesman for the even more questionable Protestant Bible) as John at
the River Jordan. For some time perhaps the Hegelian philosophy still clouding the brains of older people
will help to promote that harmlessness, somewhat in the way that people differentiate the "Idea of
Christianity" from its manifold incomplete "apparent forms" and convince themselves it is really just a matter
of the "tendency of the idea" to reveal itself in ever purer forms, and finally as certainly the purest, most
transparent, that is, the hardly visible form in the brain of the present theologus liberalis vulgis [liberal
theologian for the rabble].
However, if we listen to this purest of all Christianities expressing itself concerning the earlier impure forms
of Christianity, then the uninvolved listener often has the impression that the talk is not at all about
Christianity, but ofnow, what are we to think if we find Christianity described by the "greatest Theologian
of the century" as the religion which makes the claim that "it can be found in all true and even in a few other
barely possible religions" and when the "true church" is to be the one which "becomes a flowing mass, where
there is no outline, where each part finds itself sometimes here, sometimes there, and everything mingles
freely with everything else." Once again, what are we to think?
What we can learn from Christianity, how under the effect of a historicising treatment it has become blasé
and unnatural, until finally a fully historical, that is, an impartial treatment, dissolves it in pure knowledge
about Christianity and thereby destroys it, that fact we can study in everything which has life. It ceases to live
when it is completely dissected and exists in pain and sickness, if we start to practice historical dissection on
it. There are people who believe in a revolutionary and reforming art of healing in German music among
German people. They get angry and consider it an injustice committed against the most living aspect of our
culture when even such men as Mozart and Beethoven are inundated nowadays with the entire scholarly
welter of biographical detail and are compelled through the systematic torture of the historical critic to
answer to a thousand importunate questions. Through this method, is it not the case that something which has
definitely not yet exhausted its living effects is dismissed as irrelevant or at least paralyzed, because we direct
our curiosity at countless microscopic details of the life and work and seek intellectual problems in places
where we should learn to live and to forget all problems? Set a pair of such modern biographers to thinking
about the birth place of Christianity or Luther's Reformation. Their dispassionate pragmatic curiosity would
immediately manage to make every spiritual action at a distance impossible, just as the most wretched animal
can prevent the origin of the most powerful oak by gobbling down the acorn. All living things need an
atmosphere around them, a secret circle of darkness. If this veil is taken from them, if people condemn a
religion, an art, a genius to orbit like a star without an atmosphere, then we should no longer wonder about
their rapid decay and the way they become hard and barren. That is the way it is now with all great things
which never succeed without some delusion as Hans Sachs says in the Meistersinger.
But every people, indeed every person, who wishes to become mature needs such an enveloping delusion,
such a protecting and veiling cloud. But today people generally despise becoming mature, because they
honour history more than living. Indeed, people exult over the fact that now "science is beginning to rule over
living." It is possible that people will attain that goal but it is certain that a life so governed is not worth
much, because it is much less living and it establishes a life for the future far less than does the previous life
governed not by knowledge but by instinct and powerful illusory images. But, as stated, it is clearly not to be
the era of fully developed and mature people, of harmonious personalities, but the era of common work
which is as useful as possible. That, however, amounts only to the fact that people are to be trained for the
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 23
Page No 26
purposes of the time, in order to get to work with their hands as promptly as possible. They are to labour in
the factories of the universal utilities before they are mature, that is, so that they really no longer become
mature, because this would be a luxury, which would deprive the "labour market" of a lot of power. We blind
some birds, so that they sing more beautifully. I do not think that today's people sing more beautifully than
their grandfathers, but I do know this: we blind them early. But the method, the disreputable method, which
people use to blind them is excessively bright, excessively sudden, and excessively changing light. The
young person is lashed through all the centuries. Youngsters who understand nothing about a war, a
diplomatic action, or a trade policy are found fit to be introduced to political history. But then, just as the
young person races through history, so we moderns race through the store rooms of art and listen to concerts.
We really feel that something sounds different from something else, that something has a different effect than
something else. Constantly losing more of this feeling of surprise and dislike, becoming excessively
astonished no longer, or finally allowing oneself to enjoy everythingpeople really call that historical sense
historical education.
Without saying anything to gloss over the expression: the mass of stuff streaming in is so great that what is
surprising, shocking, barbarous, and powerful, "concentrated in a dreadful cluster," presses so
overpoweringly on the young soul that it knows how to rescue itself only with a deliberate apathy. Where a
keener and stronger consciousness is firmly established, then a very different feeling appears: disgust. The
young man has become homeless and has doubts about all customs and ideas. Now he knows this fact: that at
all times things were different, and they do not depend upon the way you are. In melancholy absence of
feeling he lets opinion on opinion flow past him and understands Holderlein's pointed words in response to
his reading of Laertius Diogenes concerning the life and teaching of the Greek philosophers: "Here I have
also experienced more of what I have already come across sometimes, that what passes temporarily by and
what comes and goes in human thoughts and systems strike me as almost more tragic than the fates which we
usually call the only realities."
No, such an overwhelming, anaesthetizing, and powerful historicising is certainly not required for the young,
as ancient times demonstrate, and is, indeed, dangerous in the highest degree, as newer ages demonstrate. But
let us really look at the historical student, the inheritor of a blasé attitude, already apparent all too early,
almost in childhood. Now the "method" in his own work, the right grip and the elegant tone of the master's
manner, have become his own. An entirely isolated small chapter of the past has fallen victim to his keen
mind and the method he has learned. He has already produced, indeed, in prouder language, he has "created."
He has now become a servant of truth in action and master in the world empire of history. If, as a child, he
was already "ready," now he is already overready. One only needs to shake him for wisdom to fall into one's
lap with a rattle. But the wisdom is rotten, and each apple has its own worm. Believe me on this point: when
people work in the scientific factory and are to become useful before they are mature, then science itself is
ruined in the process, just like the slaves used these days in this factory. I regret that people even find it
necessary to use the verbal jargon of the slave holder and employer to describe such relationships which
should be thought of as free from utility, free from life's needs, but the words "Factory, labour market,
bargain, exploitation," uttered like all the words assisting egoism, spontaneously press themselves on the lips
when we want to describe the youngest generation of scholars. The stolid mediocrity becomes ever more
mediocre, science becomes ever more practical economically. Essentially all the most recent scholars are
wise in only a single point, and in that naturally wiser than all people of the past. In all other points they are,
to speak with care, only infinitely different from all the scholars of the old school. Nevertheless they demand
respect and perquisites for themselves, as if the state and official opinion were under an obligation to consider
the new coins just as valuable as the old. The labourers have made a working compact among themselves and
decreed that genius is superfluous because each labourer is stamped as a genius. Presumably a later time will
consider the structure they have cobbled together, not built together.
To those who tirelessly proclaim the modern cry of combat and sacrifice "Division of labour! In rows and
tiers!" we can once and for all say clearly and firmly: "Do you want to destroy science as quickly as possible,
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 24
Page No 27
just as you destroy hens, which you artificially compel to lay eggs too quickly." Well, in the last century
science has been promoted at an astonishing rate. But take a look now at the scholars, the exhausted hens.
There are in truth no "harmonious" natures. They can only cackle more than before, because they lay eggs
more often. Naturally, however, the eggs have become constantly smaller (although the books have become
constantly thicker). As the final natural result, things resign themselves to the commonly loved
"Popularizing" of science (in addition to the "Feminization" and "Infantization"), that is, the notorious
tailoring of the scientific coat to the body of the "motley public" (I am attempting here to cultivate a
moderately tailored German to describe a moderately tailored activity). Goethe saw an abuse in this and
demanded that sciences should have an effect on the external world only through a higher praxis. Besides, to
the older generation of scholars such an abuse appeared (for good reasons) difficult and tiresome. For
similarly good reasons it comes easily to the younger scholars, because they themselves, with the exception
of a really small corner of knowledge, are the motley public and carry its needs in themselves. They only
need once to settle themselves down comfortably in order for them to succeed in opening up the small study
area to that popular need for the variously curious. People pretend that below this action of making
themselves comfortable stands the title "the modest condescension of the scholar for his people"; while at
bottom the scholar, to the extent that he is not a scholar but a member of the rabble, is only descending into
himself. If you create for yourself the idea of a "people" then you can never think sufficiently nobly and
highly of it. If you thought highly of a people, then you would be also compassionate towards them and
would be on your guard against offering them your historical aqua fortis [nitric acid] as a living and
refreshing drink. But deep down you think little of the people, because you are permitted to have no true and
confidently based respect for its future, and you operate as practical pessimists, I mean as people led by the
premonition of destruction, people who thus become indifferent and permissive towards what is strange, even
towards your very own welfare. If only the soil still supported us! And if it no longer carries us, then that is
also all right. Thus they feel and live an ironic existence.
VIII
In fact, it must seem odd, although it is not contradictory, when to the age which so audibly and insistently is
in the habit of bursting out in the most carefree exulting over its historical culture, I nevertheless ascribe an
ironical selfconsciousness, a presentiment which hovers all around it that this is not a matter for rejoicing, a
fear that soon all the celebrations over historical knowledge will be over. Goethe proposed to us a similar
enigma with respect to a single personality in his remarkable characterization of Newton. He found at bottom
(or more correctly, at the top) of Newton's being "a dark premonition of his own error," as it were, the
expression (noticeable in solitary moments) of a consciousness with a superior power of judgement,
something which a certain ironical perspective had gained over the essential nature dwelling inside him. Thus
we find particularly in the greater people with a higher historical development a consciousness, often toned
down to a universal scepticism, of how much folly and superstition are in the belief that the education of a
people must be so overwhelmingly historical as it is now. For the most powerful people, that is, powerful in
deeds and works, have lived very differently and have raised their young people differently. But that folly and
that superstition suit usso runs the sceptical objectionus, the late comers, the faded last shoots of more
powerful and more happily courageous generations, us, in whom one can see realized Herod's prophecy that
one day people would be born with instant grey beards and that Zeus would destroy this generation as soon as
that sign became visible to him. Historical culture is really a kind of congenital grey haired condition, and
those who bear its mark from childhood on would have to come to the instinctive belief in the old age of
humanity. An old person's occupation, however, is appropriate to old age, that is, looking back, tallying the
accounts, balancing the books, seeing consolation in what used to be through memories, in short, a historical
culture.
The human race, however, is a tough and persistent thing and will not have its steps forward and backwards
viewed according to millennia, indeed hardly according to hundreds of thousands of years. That is, it will not
be viewed at all as a totality from the infinitely small point of an atomic individual person. Then what will a
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 25
Page No 28
couple of thousand years signify (or, put another way, the time period of thirtyfour consecutive human lives,
reckoned at sixty years each) so that we can speak of the beginning of such a time as still the "Youth of
Mankind" and the end of it as already the "Old Age of Mankind." Is it not much more that case that in this
paralyzing belief in an already faded humanity there sticks the misunderstanding of an idea of Christian
theology inherited from the Middle Ages, the idea of the imminent end of the world, of the nervously awaited
judgement? Has this idea, in fact, changed through the intensified need of history to judge, as if our time, the
last of all possible, has been authorized to consider itself the universal judge of everything in the past,
something which Christian belief awaits, not in any way from human beings, but from the "Son of Man." In
earlier times this was, for humanity as well as for the individual, a loudly proclaimed "memento mori,"
[reminder of death] an always tormenting barb and, so to speak, the summit of medieval knowledge and
conscience. The phrase of more recent times, called out in a contrasting response, "memento vivere" [a
reminder of living] sounds, to speak openly, still quite timid, is not a full throated cry, and has something
almost dishonest about it. For human beings still sit firmly on the memento mori and betray the fact through
their universal need for history.
In spite of the most powerful beating of its wings, knowledge cannot tear itself loose in freedom. A deep
feeling of hopelessness is left over and has taken on that historical colouring, because of which all higher
training and education are now melancholy and dark. A religion which of all the hours of a person's life
considers the last the most important, which generally predicts the end of earthy life and condemns all living
people to live in the fifth act of the tragedy, certainly arouses the deepest and noblest forces, but it is hostile
to all new cultivation, daring undertakings, and free desiring. It resists that flight into the unknown, because
there it does not love and does not hope. It lets what is coming into being push forward only unwillingly so
that at the right time it can push it to the side or sacrifice it as a seducer of being or as a liar about the worth
of existence. What the Florentines did when, under the influence of Savonarola's sermons calling for
repentance, they organized those famous sacrificial fires of paintings, manuscripts, mirrors, and masks,
Christianity would like to do with every culture which rouses one to renewed striving and which leads to that
slogan memento vivere. If it is not possible to achieve this directly, without a digression (that is, through
superior force), then it attains its goal nonetheless if it unites itself with historical education, usually even
with its knowledge. Now, speaking out through historical knowledge, with a shrug of its shoulders,
Christianity rejects all becoming and thus disseminates the feeling of the person who has come much too late
and is unoriginal, in short, of the person born with grey hair.
The stringent and profoundly serious consideration of the worthlessness of everything which has happened,
of the way in which the world in its maturity is ready for judgement, has subsided to a sceptical
consciousness that it is in any case good to know everything that has happened, because it is too late to do
anything better. Thus the historical sense makes its servants passive and retrospective. Only in momentary
forgetfulness, when that sense is intermittent, does the patient suffering from the historical fever become
active, so that, as soon as the action is over and done with, he may seize his deed, through analytical
consideration prevent any further effects, and finally flay it for "History." In this sense, we are still living in
the Middle Ages, and history is always still a disguised theology, in exactly the same way that the reverence
with which the unscientific laity treat the scientific caste is a reverence inherited from the clergy. What
people in earlier times gave the church, people now give, although in scantier amounts, to science. However,
the fact that people give was something the church achieved in earlier times, not something first done by the
modern spirit, which, along with its other good characteristics, much rather has something stingy about it, as
is well known, and is, so far as the preeminent virtue of generosity is concerned, a piker.
Perhaps this observation is not pleasant, perhaps no more pleasant than that derivation of the excess of history
from the medieval memento mori and from the hopelessness which Christianity carried in its heart
concerning all future ages of earthly existence. But at any rate people should replace the explanation which I
have put down only hesitantly with better explanations. For the origin of historical education and its inherent
and totally radical opposition to the spirit of a "new age," of a "modern consciousness"this origin must
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 26
Page No 29
itself be once again recognized historically. History must itself resolve the problem of history. Knowledge
must turn its barbs against itself. This triple Must is the spiritual imperative of the "new age," if there is in it
truly something new, powerful, vital, and original. Or if, to leave the Romance peoples out of consideration,
it should be the case that we Germans, in all higher matters of culture, always have to be only the "followers"
just because that is the only thing we could be, as William Wackernagel once expressed it all too
convincingly: "We Germans are a people of followers. With all our higher knowledge and even with our
faith, we are always still followers of the old world. Even those who are hostile to that and certainly do not
wish it breathe in the spirit of Christianity together with the immortal spirit of the old classical culture, and if
anyone were to succeed in separating out these two elements from the living air which envelops the inner
man, then not much would be left over with which one might still eke out a spiritual life."
But even if we wanted to reassure ourselves happily about this calling to be the followers of antiquity, if we
would only make up our minds to take the calling as something right, urgent, serious, and great, and would
recognize in this urgency our designated and unique privilege, nonetheless we would find it necessary to ask
whether it must always be our purpose to be pupils of a declining antiquity. At some time or other we might
be permitted to aim our goal somewhat higher and further, at some time or other we might permit ourselves
to praise ourselves for having reworked so fruitfully and splendidly the AlexandrianRoman culture in
ourselves also through our universal history, so that now, as the most noble reward we might set ourselves the
still more monumental task of getting back behind and above this Alexandrian world and seeking out our
models of the courageous gaze in the ancient Greek original world of the great, the natural, and the human.
But there we find also the reality of an essentially unhistorical education, an education nevertheless (or rather
therefore) unspeakably rich and vital. If we Germans were nothing but followers, then by looking at such a
culture as a legacy appropriately ours, there could be nothing greater or prouder for us than to be its
followers.
As a result we should say only this and nothing but this: that the often unpleasantly strange thought that we
are epigones, nobly thought out, can guarantee important effects and a richly hopeful desire for the future,
both for the individual and for a people, to the extent that we understand ourselves as the heirs and followers
of an astonishing classical force and see in that our legacy and our spur, but not as pale and withered late
arrivals of powerful races, who scrape out a cold living as the antiquarians and gravediggers of those races.
Such late arrivals naturally live an ironic existence. Destruction follows closely on the heels of their limping
passage through life. They shudder in the face of that, when they derive enjoyment from the past, for they are
living memorials, and yet their thoughts are senseless without someone to inherit them. So the dark
premonition envelops them that their life may be an injustice, for no future life can set it right. However, if
we were to imagine such antiquarian late comers suddenly exchanging that painfully ironic moderation for
impudence, and if we imagine them to ourselves as if they were reporting with a ringing voice: "The race is at
its peak, because now for the first time it has the knowledge of itself and has become clear to itself," then we
would have a performance in which, as in an allegory, the enigmatic meaning of a certain very famous
philosophy is deciphered for German culture.
I believe that there has been no dangerous variation or change in German culture in this century which has
not become more dangerous through the monstrous influence of the philosophy of Hegel, an influence which
continues to flow right up to the present. The belief that one is a late comer of the age is truly crippling and
disorienting; but it must appear fearful and destructive when such a belief one day with a bold reversal
idolizes this late comer as the true meaning and purpose of all earlier events, when his knowledgeable misery
is equated to the completion of world history. Such a way of considering things has made the Germans
accustomed to talking of the "World Process" and to justify their own time as the necessary result of the
world process. Such a way of thinking about things has made history the single sovereign, in the place of the
other spiritual powers, culture and religion, insofar as history is "the selfrealizing idea" and "the dialectic of
the spirits of peoples" and the "last judgement."
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 27
Page No 30
People have scornfully called this Hegelian understanding of history the earthly changes of God; but this God
for His part was first created by history. However, this God became intelligible and comprehensible inside
Hegelian brain cases and has already ascended all the dialectically possible steps of His being right up to that
selfrevelation. Thus, for Hegel the summit and end point of the world process coincided with his own
individual existence in Berlin. In fact, strictly speaking he should have said that everything coming after him
should be valued really only as a musical coda of the world historical rondo, or even more truly, as
superfluous. He did not say that. Thus, he planted in the generations leavened by him that admiration for the
"Power of History", which transforms practically every moment into a naked admiration of success and leads
to idolatrous worship of the factual. For this service people nowadays commonly repeat the very
mythological and, in addition, the truly German expression "to carry the bill of facts" But the person who has
first learned to stoop down and to bow his head before the "Power of History", finally nods his agreement
mechanically, in the Chinese fashion, to that power, whether it is a government or public opinion or a
numerical majority, and moves his limbs precisely to the beat of strings plucked by some "power" or other.
If every success contains within itself a rational necessity, if every event is the victory of the logical or the
"Idea", then get down quickly now and kneel before the entire hierarchy of "success." What? Do you claim
there are no ruling mythologies any more and religions are dying out? Only look at the religion of the power
of history; pay attention to the priests of the mythology of the Idea and their knees all covered in cuts! Surely
all the virtues come only in the wake of this new faith. Is it not unselfishness when the historical person lets
himself be blown into an objective glass mirror? Is it not generosity to do without all the force of heaven and
earth so that in this power people worship pure force in itself? Is it not justice to have a scale balance always
in one's hands and to watch closely what sinks down as the stronger and heavier? And what a respectable
school such a consideration of history is! To take everything objectively, to get angry about nothing, to love
nothing, to understand everything, how gentle and flexible that makes things. And even if one man brought
up in this school becomes publicly angry at some point and gets annoyed, people can then enjoy that, for they
know it is really only intended as an artistic expression; it is ira [anger] and studium [study]. However, it is
entirely sine ira et studio [without anger and study].
What antiquated thoughts I have in my heart about such a complex of mythology and virtue! But they should
come out for once, even if people should just go on laughing. I would also say: history constantly impresses
on us "It was once" and the moral "You should not" or "You should not have." So history turns into a
compendium of the really immoral. How seriously mistaken would the person be who at the same time
considered history as the judge of this factual immorality! For example, it is offensive to morality that a
Raphael had to die at thirtysix years of age; such a being should not have died. Now, if you want history, as
the apologist for the factual, to provide assistance, then you will say that Raphael expressed everything that
was in him; with a longer life he would have been able to create something beautiful only as a similar beauty,
and not as something beautifully new, and so on. In so doing, you are the devil's advocate for the very reason
that you make success, the fact, your idol; whereas, the fact is always dumb and at all times has looked upon
something like a calf as a god. Moreover, as apologists for history, you prompt each other by whispering this
ignorance. Because you do not know what such a natura naturans [essential creative force] like Raphael is, it
does not make you make you hot to hear that such a person was and will never be again. In Goethe's case,
recently someone wanted to teach us that with his eightytwo years he had reached his limit, and yet I would
happily trade a couple of years of the "washed up" Goethe for an entire cart full of fresh ultramodern lives,
in order to share in conversations like the ones Goethe conducted with Eckermann and in this way to remain
protected from all the contemporary teachings of the legionaries of the moment.
In comparison with such dead people, how few living people generally have a right to live! That the many
live and that those few no longer live is nothing more than a brutal truth, that is, an incorrigible stupidity, a
blatant "That is the case" in contrast to the moral "It should not have been so." Yes, in contrast to the moral!
For let people speak about whatever virtue they want, about righteousness, generosity, courage, wisdom and
human sympathya person is always virtuous just because he rebels against that blind power of the factual,
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 28
Page No 31
against the tyranny of the real and submits himself to laws which are not the laws of that historical
fluctuation. He constantly swims against the historical waves, whether he fights his passions as the closest
mute facts of his existence or whether he commits himself to truthfulness, while the lies spin around him their
glittering webs. If history were in general nothing more than "the world system of passion and error," then
human beings would have to read it in the way Goethe summoned us to read Werther, exactly as if it cried
out "Be a man and do not follow me!" Fortunately history also preserves the secret of the great fighters
against history, that is, against the blind force of the real, and thus puts itself right in the pillory, because it
brings out directly as the essential historical natures those who worried so little about the "Thus it was," in
order rather to follow with a more cheerful pride a "So it should be." Not to drag their race to the grave but to
found a new racethat drove them ceaselessly forwards; and if they themselves were born as latecomers,
there is an art of living which makes one forget this. The generations to come will know them only as first
comers.
IX
Is our age perhaps such a first comer? In fact, the vehemence of its historical sense is so great and expresses
itself in such a universal and simply unlimited way that at least in this the coming ages will assess its quality
as a first comer, if in fact there are going to be coming ages at all, understood in the sense of culture. But
right here there remains a serious doubt. Close by the pride of the modern man stands his irony about his very
self, his consciousness that he must live in a historicising and, as it were, a twilight mood, and his fear that in
future he will be totally unable to rescue any more of his youthful hopes and powers. Here and there people
go even further, into cynicism, and justify the passage of history, indeed, of the whole development of the
world as essentially for the use of modern man, according to the cynical rule that things must turn out just as
they are going right now, that man must be nothing other than what people now are, and that against this
Must no one may rebel. In the sense of well being of such a cynicism a person who cannot maintain that view
with irony curses himself. In addition, the last decade offers him as a gift one of its most beautiful inventions,
a rounded and sonorous phrase for such cynicism: it calls his style of living mindlessly with the times, "the
full dedication of the personality to the world process." The personality and the world process! The world
process and the personality of the turnip flea! If only people did not have to hear the eternal hyperbole of all
hyperboles, the word World, World, World, when really each person should speak in all honesty only of
Men, Men, Men. Heirs of the Greeks and Romans? Of Christianity? That all appears as nothing to this cynic.
But heirs of the world process! The high points and targets of the world process! High points and targets of
the world process! Sense and solution of all riddles of becoming in general, expressed in the modern man, the
ripest fruit of the tree of knowledgeI call that a swollen feeling of elation. By this symbol are the first
comers of all ages known, even if they have come along right at the end.
Historical considerations have never flown so far afield, not even in dreams. For now the history of human
beings is only the continuation of the history of animals and plants. Indeed, even in the furthest depths of the
sea the historical universalist finds the traces of himself, as living mucus; he gazes in astonishment (as if at a
miracle) at the immense route which human beings have already passed through and trembles at the sight of
the even more astonishing miracle, modern man himself, who has the ability to survey this route. He stands
high and proud on the pyramid of the world process. As he sets down on the top of it the final stone of his
knowledge, he appears to call out to nature listening all around, "We are at the goal, we are the goal, we are
the perfection of nature."
Arrogant European of the nineteenth century, you are raving! Your knowledge does not complete nature, but
only kills your own. For once measure your height as a knower against your depth as a person who can do
something. Of course, you clamber on the solar rays of knowledge upward towards heaven, but you also
climb downward to chaos. Your way of going, that is, clambering about as a knower, is your fate. The ground
and floor move back away from you into the unknown; for your life there are no supports any more, but only
spider's threads, which every new idea of your knowledge rips apart.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 29
Page No 32
But no more serious talk about this, for it is possible to say something more cheerful.
The incredibly thoughtless fragmenting and fraying of all the fundamentals, their disintegration into a
constantly flowing and dissolving becoming, the inexhaustible spinning away and historicising of all that has
come into being because of modern men, the great garden spiders in the knots of the world net, that may keep
the moralists, the artists, the devout, as well as the statesman, busy and worried. Today it should for once
cheer us up, because we see all this in the gleaming magical mirror of a philosophical writer of parodies, in
whose head the age has come to an ironical consciousness of itself, a consciousness clear all the way to
lunacy (to speak in Goethe's style). Hegel once taught us, "when the spirit makes a sudden turn, then we
philosophers are still there." Our age has made a turn into selfirony, and, lo and behold, E. von Hartmann
was also at hand and had written his famous Philosophy of the Unconscious, or, to speak more clearly, his
philosophy of unconscious irony. Rarely have we read a more amusing invention and a more philosophically
roguish prank than Hartmann's. Anyone who is not enlightened by him concerning Becoming, who is not
really set right on the inside, is truly ripe for the state of existing in the past. The start and the goal of the
world process, from the first motions of consciousness right to the state of being hurled back into
nothingness, together with the precisely defined task of our generation for the world process, all presented
from such a wittily inventive font of inspiration of the unconscious and illuminated with an apocalyptic light,
with everything so deceptively imitative of a unsophisticated seriousness, as if it were really serious
philosophy and not playful philosophy, such a totality makes its creator one of the preeminent writers of
philosophical parodies of all times. Let us sacrifice on an altar, sacrifice to him, the inventor of a truly
universal medicine, a lock of hair, to steal an expression of admiration from Schleiermacher. For what
medicine would be healthier against the excess of historical culture than Hartmann's parody of all world
history?
If we want a correct matteroffact account of what Hartmann is telling us about the noxious trilegged stool
of unconscious irony, then we would say that he is telling us that our age would have to be just the way it is if
humanity is to ever get seriously fed up with this existence. That is what we believe in our hearts. That
frightening fossilizing of the age, that anxious rattling of the bones, which David Strauss has described for us
in his naive way as the most beautiful reality, is justified in Hartmann not only retrospectively ex causis
efficientibus [from efficient causes, i.e., as the result of certain mechanical causes], but even looking ahead,
ex causa finali [from a final cause, i.e., as having a higher purpose]. The joker lets his light stream over the
most recent periods of our time, and there finds that our age is very good, especially for the person who wants
to endure as strongly as possible the indigestible nature of life and who cannot wish that doomsday comes
quickly enough. Indeed, Hartmann calls the age which humanity is now approaching the "maturity of
humanity." But that maturity is, according to his own description, the fortunate condition where there is still
only " pure mediocrity" and culture is "some evening farce for the Berlin stockbroker," where "geniuses are
no longer a requirement of the age, because that means casting pearls before swine or also because the age
has progressed to a more important level, beyond the stage for which geniuses are appropriate," that is, to that
stage of social development in which each worker "with a period of work which allows him sufficient leisure
for his intellectual development leads a comfortable existence." You rogue of all rogues, you speak of the
yearning of contemporary humanity; but you also know what sort of ghost will stand at the end of this
maturity of humanity as the result of that intellectual developmentdisgust. Things stand in a state of visible
wretchedness, but they will get even more wretched, "before our eyes the Antichrist reaches out further and
further around him"but things must be so, thing must come about this way, because for all that we are on
the best route to disgust with all existing things. "Thus, go forward vigorously into the world process as a
worker in the vineyard of the Lord, for the process is the only thing which can lead to redemption."
The vineyard of the Lord! The process! For redemption! Who does not see and hear the historical culture
which knows the word "becoming" only as it intentionally disguises itself in a misshapen parody, as it
expresses through the grotesque grimacing mask held up in front of its face the most wilful things about
itself! For what does this last mischievous summons to the workers in the vineyard essentially want from
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 30
Page No 33
them? In what work are they to strive vigorously forwards? Or, to ask the question another way, what has the
historically educated man, the modern fanatic swimming and drowning in the flood of becoming, still left to
do, in order to reap that disgust, the expensive grapes of that vineyard? He has to do nothing other than
continue to live as he has been living, to continue loving what he has loved, to continue to hate what he has
hated, and to continue reading the newspapers which he has been reading. For him there is only one sin, to
live differently from the way he has been living. But we are told the way he has been living with the
excessive clarity of something written in stone by that famous page with the sentences in large print, in which
the entire contemporary cultural rabble kingdom is caught up in a blind rapture and a frenzy of delight,
because they believe they read their own justification, indeed, their own justification in the light of the
apocalypse. For the unconscious writer of parody has required of each one of them "the complete dedication
of his personality to the world process in pursuit of its goal, for the sake of the world's redemption," or still
more pellucid, "the approval of the will to live is proclaimed as right only provisionally, for only in the full
dedication to life and its pains, not in cowardly renunciation and drawing back, is there something to achieve
for the world process," "the striving for individual denial of the will is just as foolish and useless, even more
foolish, than suicide." "The thinking reader will also understand without further suggestions how a practical
philosophy built on these principles would look and that such a philosophy cannot contain any falling apart
but only the full reconciliation with life."
The thinking reader will understand it. And people could misunderstand Hartmann! How unspeakably
amusing it is that people misunderstand him! Should contemporary Germans be very sensitive? A trusty
Englishman noticed their lack of a Delicacy of Perception, and even dared to say "in the German mind there
does seem to be something splay, something bluntedged, unhandy and infelicitous" Would the great
German writer of parodies really contradict him? In fact, according to Hartmann's explanation, we are
approaching "that ideal condition, where the race of mankind consciously makes his own history." But
obviously we are quite far from that state, perhaps even more ideal, where humanity reads Hartmann's book
with awareness. If that state ever arrives, then no person will let the word "World process" pass his lips any
more, without these lips breaking into a smile. For with that phrase people will remember the time when
Hartmann's parodying gospel with its stolidly middleclass notion of that "German mind," and with "the
distorted seriousness of the owl," as Goethe puts it, was listened to, absorbed, disputed, honoured, publicized,
and canonized.
But the world must go forward. The ideal condition cannot be dreamed up; it must be fought for and won.
Only through joy does the way go to redemption, to redemption from that misunderstood owllike
seriousness. The time will come in which people wisely refrain from all constructions of the world process or
even of human history, a time in which people in general no longer consider the masses but once again think
about individuals who construct a sort of bridge over the chaotic storm of becoming. These people do not set
out some sort of process, but live timelessly and contemporaneously, thanks to history which permits such a
combination. They live like the republic of geniuses, about which Schopenhauer once explained that one
giant shouts out to another across the barren intervals of time, and undisturbed by the wanton and noisy
midgets who creep around them, the giants continue their lofty spiritual conversation. The task of history is to
be a mediator between them and thus to provide an opportunity and the energies for the development of
greatness. No, the goal of humanity cannot finally be anywhere but in its greatest examples.
By contrast, our comic person naturally states with that wonderful dialectic, just as worthy of admiration as
its admirers, "With the idea of this development it would be inconsistent to ascribe to the world process an
infinite length of time in the past, because then each and every imaginable development must have already
been gone through; that, however, is not the case (O you rascal). And we are no more able to assign to the
process an infinite future period. Both of these raise the idea of development to a final goal (o, once again,
you rascal) and makes the world process like the water drawing of the Danaids. The complete victory of the
logical over the illogical (O, you rascal of all rascals), however, must coincide with the temporal end of the
world process, the day of judgement." No, you lucidly mocking spirit, as long as the illogical still prevails to
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 31
Page No 34
the extent it does today, for example, as long as people can still talk of the "world process" with a common
understanding, in the way you talk, judgement day is still a long way off. For it is still too joyful on this earth;
many illusions are still blooming (for example, the illusion of your contemporaries about you). We are not
yet sufficiently ripe to be flung back into your nothingness. For we believe that things here will get even
more amusing when people first begin to understand you, you misunderstood unconscious man. However, if
in spite of this, disgust should come with power, just as you have predicted to your readers, if you should be
right in your description of your present and future (and no one has hated both with such disgust as you have)
then I am happily prepared to vote with the majority, in the way you have proposed, that next Saturday
evening at twelve o'clock precisely your world will go under, and our decree may conclude that from
tomorrow on there will be no more time and no newspaper will appear any more. However, perhaps the result
will fail to materialize, and we have made our decree in vain.
Bit then at any rate we will not lack the time for a beautiful experiment. We take a balance scale and put in
one scale pan Hartmann's unconsciousness and in the other Hartmann's world process. There are people who
think that they will both weigh the same, for in each scale pan would lie an equally poor quotation and an
equally good jest. When people first come to understand Hartmann's jest, then no one will use Hartmann's
talk of "world process" as anything but a joke. In fact, it is high time we moved forward to proclaim satirical
malice against the dissipation of the historical sense, against the excessive pleasure in the process at the
expense of being and living, against the senseless shifting of all perspectives. And in praise of the author of
the Philosophy of the Unconscious it should always be repeated that he was the first to succeed in registering
keenly the ridiculousness of the idea of the "world process" and to allow an even keener appreciation of that
ridiculousness through the particular seriousness of his treatment. Why the "world" is there, why "humanity"
is therethese should not concern us at all for the time being. For it may be that we want to make a joke.
The presumptuousness of the small human worm is simultaneously the funniest and the most joyful thing on
this earthly stage. But why you, as an individual, are there, that is something I am asking you. And if no one
else can say it for you, then at least try once to justify the sense of your existence, as it were, a posteriori by
establishing for yourself a purpose, a final goal, a "To this end," and a high and noble "To this end." If you
are destroyed by this, well, I know no better purpose for life than to die in service of the great and the
impossible, animae magnae prodigus [a generous man with a great spirit].
If by contrast the doctrine of the sovereign becoming, of the fluidity of all ideas, types, and styles, of the lack
of all cardinal differences between man and animal (doctrines which I consider true but deadly) are foisted on
people for another generation with the frenzied instruction which is now customary, then it should take no
one by surprise if people destroy themselves in egotistical trifles and misery, ossifying themselves in their
selfabsorption, initially falling apart and ceasing to be a people. Then, in place of this condition, perhaps
systems of individual egotism, alliances for the systematic larcenous exploitation of those nonmembers of
the alliance and similar creations of utilitarian nastiness will step forward onto the future scene. Let people
just proceed to prepare these creations, to write history from the standpoint of the masses and to seek for
those laws in it which are to be inferred from the needs of these masses, and for the laws of motion of the
lowest clay and loam layers of society. To me, the masses seem to be worth a glance in only in three respects:
first as blurred copies of great men, presented on bad paper with worn out printing plates, then as the
resistance against the great men, and finally as working implements of the great. For the rest, let the devil and
statistics carry them off! How might statistics demonstrate that there could be laws in history? Laws? Yes,
statistics prove how coarse and disgustingly uniform the masses are. Are we to call the effects of the powerful
forces of stupidity, mimicry, love, and hunger laws?
Now, we are willing to concede that point, but by the same token the principle then is established that as far
as there are laws in history, they are worth nothing and history is worth nothing. However, precisely this sort
of history nowadays is generally esteemed, the history which takes the large mass tendencies as the important
and principal thing in history and considers all great men only like the clearest examples of bubbles which
become visible in the watery flood. Thus, the mass is to produce greatness out of itself, and chaos is to
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 32
Page No 35
produce order from itself. At the end, of course, the hymn is sung to the productive masses. Everything which
has preoccupied such masses for a long time is then called "Great" and, as people say, "a historical power"
has come into being. But is that not a case of quite deliberately exchanging quantity and quality? When the
podgy masses have found some idea or other (for example, a religious idea) quite adequate, has tenaciously
defended it, and dragged it along for centuries, then, and only then, the discoverer and founder of that idea is
to be great. But why? The most noble and highest things have no effect at all on the masses. The historical
success of Christianity, its historical power, tenacity, and duration, all that fortunately proves nothing with
respect to the greatness of its founder. Basically, that would act as a proof against him. But between him and
that historical success lies a very earthly and dark layer of passion, error, greed for power and honour, the
persisting powers of the imperium romanum, a layer from which Christianity acquired that earthy taste and
scrap of ground which made possible its perseverance in this world and, as it were, gave it its durability.
Greatness should not depend upon success. Demosthenes had greatness, although at the same time he had no
success. The purest and most genuine followers of Christianity were always more likely to put their worldly
success, their socalled "historical power," into question and to restrict it rather than to promote it. For they
trained themselves to stand outside "the world" and did not worry themselves about the "progress of the
Christian idea." For this reason, for the most part they are also unknown to history and have remained
unnamed. To express this in a Christian manner: in this way the devil is the regent of the world and the
master of success and progress. He is in all historical powers the essential power, and so it will substantially
remain, although it may for some time sound quite painful to ears which have become accustomed to the
idolatry of success and historical power. For in this matter these people have practised giving things new
names and have rechristened even the devil. It is certainly a time of great danger: human beings seem to be
close to discovering that the egotism of the individual, the group, or the masses was the lever of historical
movements at all times. However, at the same time, people are not at all worried by this discovery. On the
contrary, people declaim: Egotism is to be our God. With this new faith people are on the point of erecting,
with the clearest of intentions, future history on egotism. But it is only to be a clever egotism subject to a few
limitations, in order that it may consolidate itself in an enduring way. It is the sort of egotism which studies
history just in order to acquaint itself with unclever egotism.
Through this study people have learned that the state has received a very special mission in the established
world system of egotism: the state is to become the patron of all clever egotism, so that, with its military and
police forces, it may protect against the frightening outbreak of the unintelligent egotism. For the same
purpose history, that is, the history of animals and human beings, is also stirred into the popular masses and
working classes, who are dangerous because they are unintelligent, for people know that a small grain of
historical education is capable of breaking the rough and stupefied instincts and desires or to divert them into
the path of improved egotism. In summa: people are paying attention now, to express oneself with E. von
Hartmann, " to a deliberate looking into the future for a practical homely structure in their earthly home
region." The same writer calls such a period the "full maturity of mankind" and makes fun about what is now
called "Man," as if with that term one is to understand only the sober selfish person; in the same way he also
prophecies that after such a period of full maturity there comes to this "Man" an appropriate old age, but
apparently only with this idea to vent his ridicule on our contemporary old men. For he speaks of the mature
peacefulness with which they "review all the chaotic stormy suffering of their past lives and understand the
vanity of the previously assumed goals of their striving." No, a maturity of this sly egotism of a historical
culture is appropriate for an old age of hostile craving and disgraceful clinging to life and then a final act,
with its
last scene of all That ends this strange eventful history, Is second childhood and mere oblivion, Sans teeth,
sans eyes, sans taste, sans everything.
Whether the dangers of our life and our culture now come from these desolate, toothless and tasteless old
men, whether they come from those socalled "Men" of Hartmann's, in opposition to both we wish to hold on
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 33
Page No 36
with our teeth to our right to our youth and not to grow tired of defending, in our youth, the future against
these forceful portrayers of the future. In this fight, however, we would have to acknowledge a particularly
unpleasant perception: that people intentionally promote the excesses of the historical sense from which the
present time suffers, they encourage them, and they use them.
However, people use history against the young, in order to train them for that maturity of egotism which is
striven for everywhere; people use it to break the natural aversion of youth through a transfiguring, that is to
say, a magically scientific illumination of that manlyeffeminate egotism. Yes, people know what a certain
predominance of history is capable of; people know it only too well: to uproot the strongest instincts of
youth, fire, defiance, forgetting of the self, to dampen down the heat of their sense of right and wrong, to hold
back or repress the desire to mature slowly with the contrary desire to be finished quickly, to be useful and
productive, to infect the honesty and boldness of the feelings with doubts. Indeed, history is itself capable of
deceiving the young about their most beautiful privilege, about their power to cultivate in themselves with
complete conviction a great idea and to allow an even greater idea to grow forth out of it. A certain excess of
history is capable of all this. We have seen it. And this is the reason: through its incessant shifting of the
horizons of significance, through the elimination of a surrounding atmosphere, it no longer allows a person to
perceive and to act unhistorically. He then draws himself from the infinity of his horizon back into himself,
into the smallest egotistical region and there must wither away and dry up. He probably achieves cleverness
in this, but never wisdom. He permits himself inner conversations, calculates, and gets along well with the
facts, does not boil over, winks, and understands how to seek out his own advantage or that of his party amid
the advantages and disadvantages of strangers; he forgets superfluous modesty and thus step by step becomes
a "Man" and an "Old Man" on the Hartmann model. But he should become thisthat is the precise sense of
the cynical demand nowadays for "the complete dedication of the personality to the world process," so far as
his goal is concerned, for the sake of the redemption of the world, as that rascal E. Hartmann assures us.
Now, the will and goal of these Hartmann "men" and "old men" is indeed hardly the redemption of the world.
Certainly the world would be more redeemed if it were redeemed from these men and old men. For then the
kingdom of youth would come.
X
Imagining this reign of youth, I cry out "Land, land! Enough and more than enough of the passionate seeking
and the wandering passage on the dark alien seas!" Now finally a coast reveals itself. Whatever it may be, we
must land on it. The worst emergency port is better than returning to staggering in hopeless infinite
scepticism. If now we only hold on to the land, we will later find the good havens and ease the approach for
those who come later. This journey was dangerous and exciting. How far we are now from the calm
contemplation with which we first saw our ship set out to sea. By investigating the dangers of history, we
have found ourselves exposed to all these dangers as strongly as possible. We ourselves bear the traces of that
illness which has come over humanity in recent times as a result of an excess of history. For example, this
very treatise shows its modern character, the character of the weak personality (which I will not conceal from
myself) in the intemperance of its criticism, the immaturity of its humanity, the frequent transitions from
irony to cynicism, from pride to scepticism. Nevertheless I trust in the inspiring power which, rather than my
genius, controls the vessel: I trust in youth, that it has led me correctly when it requires from me now a
protest against the historical education of young modern people and if the protester demands that human
beings above all learn to live and to use history only in the service of the life which he has learned. People
must be young to understand this protest. In fact, among the contemporary greyhaired types of our present
youth, one can hardly be young enough still to feel what is here essentially being protested against.
To help people understand this point I will use an example. In Germany it is not much longer than a hundred
years ago that a natural instinct for what people call poetry arose in a few young people. Do people think that
the previous generations up to that time would never have spoken of that art, inwardly strange and unnatural
to them? We know the opposite is true: they thought about "poetry" with loving passion, wrote and argued
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 34
Page No 37
about it with words, words, and more words. The appearance of that revival of words for living was not the
immediate death of those word makers. In a certain sense they are still alive, because if, as Gibbon says, for a
world to go under takes not just time but plenty of time, then in Germany, the "land of gradual change," for a
false idea to be destroyed takes more than time; it takes a great deal of time. Today there are perhaps a
hundred people more than a hundred years ago who know what poetry is; perhaps one hundred years from
now there will be another hundred people more who in the meantime have also learned what culture is and
that the Germans up to this point have had no culture, no matter how much they may talk and boast about it.
For them the very general contentment of the Germans with their "culture" would seem just as incredible and
stupid as the formerly acknowledged classicism of Gottsched or the appraisal of Ramler as a German Pindar
seem to us. They will perhaps judge that this culture has been only a sort of knowledge about culture and, in
addition, a completely false and superficial knowledge. I say false and superficial because people endured the
contradiction of life and knowledge, for they did not see anything characteristic of a truly cultured people:
that the culture can only grow up and blossom forth out of living. By contrast, with the Germans culture is
put up like a paper flower or poured out like a sugar drink. Therefore it must always remain untruthful and
infertile.
The German education of the young, however, begins directly from this false and barren idea of culture. Its
end goal, imagined in all purity and loftiness, is not at all the freely educated man, but the scholar, the
scientific person, indeed, the scientific person who is useful as early as possible, the person who sets himself
apart from life in order to recognize it clearly. The product of this education, considered in a correct
empirically general way, is the historically and aesthetically educated Philistine, the precocious and freshly
wise chatterer about state, church, and art, the sensorium for thousands of sensations, the inexhaustible
stomach which nevertheless does not know what an honest hunger and thirst are. The fact that an education
with this goal and result is an unnatural education is felt only by the person who has not yet completed it; it is
felt only by the instinct of the young, because they still have the instinct of nature, which is first artificially
and powerfully broken through that education. But the person who wants to break this education in its turn
must assist the young in expressing themselves. He must shine the bright light of ideas to illuminate their
unconscious resistance and turn that into a conscious and loudly uttered consciousness. How is he to reach
such a strange goal?
Above all through the fact that he destroys a superstition, the faith in the necessity of that method of
education. People think that there would be no other possibility than our contemporary highly tiresome
reality. Just let someone examine the essential literature of the higher schooling and education system in the
last decades exactly on this point. For all the varieties of proposals and for all the intensity of the opposition,
the examiner will to his astonishment realize how uniform the thinking is about the entire purpose of
education, how thoughtlessly people assume that the present result, the "educated person," as the term is now
understood, is a necessary and reasonable fundamental basis for that wider education. That monotonous
orthodoxy would sound something like this: the young person has to begin with a knowledge of culture, not
at first with a knowledge of life, and even less with life and experience themselves. Moreover, this
knowledge about culture as historical knowledge is poured over or stirred into the youth; that is, his head is
filled up with a monstrous number of ideas derived from extremely indirect knowledge of past times and
peoples, not from the immediate contemplation of living. His desire to experience something for himself and
to feel growing in him a coordinated and living system of his own experiencessuch a desire is narcotized
and, as it were, made drunk through the opulent deceptions about matters of fact, as if it were possible in a
few years to sum up in oneself the highest and most remarkable experiences of all times, especially of the
greatest ages. It is precisely this insane procedure which leads our young developing artists into the halls of
culture and galleries instead of into the workshop of a master and, above all, into the extraordinary workshops
of the extraordinary master craftswoman Nature. Yes, as if people were able to predict their ideas and arts,
their actual life's work, as cursory strollers in the history of past times. Yes, as if life itself were not a craft
which must be learned continuously from the basic material and practised without special treatment, if it is
not to allow bunglers and chatterers to be produced
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 35
Page No 38
Plato considered it necessary that the first generation of his new society (in the perfect state) would be
brought up with the help of a powerful necessary lie. The children were to learn to believe that they had all
already lived a long time dreaming under the earth, where they had been properly kneaded and formed by
nature's master worker. It was impossible to have any effect against this work of the gods. It is to stand as an
inviolable law of nature that the person who is born a philosopher has gold in his body, the person who is
born as a guard has only silver, and the person who is born as a worker has iron and bronze. Since it is not
possible to mix these metals, Plato explains, then it should not be possible to overthrow or mix up the order
of classes. The faith in the aeterna veritas [eternal truth] of this order is the basis of the new education and
thus of the new state. The modern German similarly believes now in the aeterna veritas of his education, of
his style of culture. Nevertheless, this faith would collapse, as the Platonic state would have collapsed, if in
opposition to the necessary lie there was set up a necessary truth: the German has no culture, because he can
have nothing whatsoever on the basis of his education. He wants the flowers without roots and stalk. So he
wants them in vain. That is the simple truth, unpleasant and gross, a correct necessary truth.
In this necessary truth, however, our first generation must be educated. Certainly they suffer from it with the
greatest difficulty, for they must educate themselves through it, in fact, divided against themselves, to new
habits and a new nature derived out of old and previous nature and habits, so that they might be able to say
with the ancient Spaniards: "Efienda me Dios de my," God, defend me from myself, that is, from the nature
already instilled into me. They must taste that truth drop by drop, as if sampling a bitter and powerful
medicine. Each individual of this generation must overcome himself, to judge for himself what he might
more easily endure as a general judgement concerning an entire age: we are without education, even more,
we are ruined for living, for correct and simple seeing and hearing, for the fortunate grasping of what is
closest at hand and natural, and we have up to this moment not yet even the basis of a culture, because we
ourselves are not convinced that we have a genuine life within us. Fractured and fallen apart, in everything
carved up mechanically into an inner and an outer half, saturated with ideas like dragons' teeth producing
dragon ideas, thus suffering from the sickness of words and without trust in any unique sensation which is not
yet franked with words, as such a nonliving and yet uncannily lively factory of ideas and words, I still
perhaps have the right to say about myself cogito, ergo sum [I am thinking; therefore, I am], but not vivo,
ergo cogito [I am living; therefore, I am thinking]. That empty "Being", not that full and green "Living" is
ensured for me. My original feeling only guarantees me that I am a thinking thing, not that I am a living
essence, that I am not animal, but at most a cogital. First give me life; then I will make a culture out of it for
you!so shouts each individual of this first generation, and all these individuals will recognize each other
from this call. Who will present this life to them?
No god and no human being: only their own youth unleashes this life, and with it you will liberate life for
yourself. For it only lay hidden in a prison. It has not yet withered away and diedinquire of yourself!
But this unbridled life is sick and must be healed. It is ailing from many ills. Not only does it suffer from the
memory of its fetters; it suffers from what is here our principal concern, from the historical sickness. The
excess of history has seized the plastic force of life. It understands no more to make use of the past as a
powerful nourishment. The evil is fearsome, and nevertheless if youth did not have the clairvoyant gift of
nature, then no one would know that that is an evil and that a paradise of health has been lost. This same
youth surmises, however, also with the powerful healing instinct of this same nature, how this paradise can be
won back. It knows the juices for wounds and the medicines to combat the historical sickness, to combat the
excess of the historical. What are they called?
Now, people should not be surprised: they are the names of poisons: the antidotes against the historical are
called the unhistorical and the superhistorical. With these names we turn back to the start of our
examination and to its close.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 36
Page No 39
With the phrase "the unhistorical" I designate the art and the power of being able to forget and to enclose
oneself in a horizon with borders; "superhistorical" I call the powers which divert the gaze from what is
developing back to what gives existence an eternal and unchanging character, to art and religion. Science (for
it is science which would talk about poisons) sees in that force, in these powers opposing forces, for it
maintains that only the observation of things is true and right, the scientific way of considering things, which
everywhere sees what has come into being as something historical and never as something eternally living.
Science lives in an inner contradiction against the eternalizing powers of art and religion just as much as it
hates forgetfulness, the death of knowledge, when it seeks to remove all limitations of horizons and to hurl
human beings into an infinite sea without frontiers, a sea of light waves of acknowledged becoming.
If he only could live there! As the cities collapse in an earthquake and become desolate and the human being,
trembling and in haste, erects his house on volcanic ground, so life breaks apart and becomes weak and
dispirited when the earthquake of ideas which science arouses takes from a person the basis of all his
certainty and rest, his faith in the eternally permanent. Is life to rule over knowledge now, over science, or is
knowledge to rule over life? Which of the two forces is the higher and the decisive one? No one will have any
doubt: life is the higher, the ruling power, for knowledge which destroyed life would in the process have
destroyed itself. Knowledge presupposes life and has the same interest in preserving life which every being
has in its own continuing existence. So science needs a higher supervision and control. A doctrine of a
healthy life is positioned close beside science, and a principle of this doctrine of health would sound like this:
the unhistorical and the superhistorical are the natural countermeasures against the excess cancerous
growth of history on life, against the historical sickness. It is probable that we, the historically ill, also have to
suffer from the counter measures. But the fact that we suffer from them is no proof against the correctness of
the course of treatment we have chosen.
And here I recognize the mission of that youth, that first generation of fighters and dragon slayers, which
brings forth a more fortunate and more beautiful culture and humanity, without having more of this future
happiness and future beauty than a promisefilled premonition. These youth will suffer from the evil and the
countermeasures simultaneously, and nevertheless they believe they may boast of a more powerful health
and in general a more natural nature than their previous generations, the educated "Men" and "Old Men" of
the present. However, their mission is to shake the ideas which this present holds about "health" and "culture"
and to develop contempt and hatred against such hybrid monstrous ideas. The most strongly guaranteed mark
of their own stronger health is to be precisely the fact that they, I mean these youth, themselves can use no
idea, no party slogan from the presently circulating currency of words and ideas, as a designation of their
being, but are convinced only by a power acting in it, a power which fights, eliminates, and cuts into pieces,
and by an always heightened sense of life in every good hour. People may dispute the fact that these youth
already have culture, but for what young person would this be a reproach? People may speak against their
crudeness and immoderation, but they are not yet old and wise enough to be content; above all they do not
need to feign any readymade culture to defend and enjoy all the comforts and rights of youth, especially the
privilege of a braver spontaneous honesty and the rousing consolation of hope.
Of these hopeful people I know that they understand all these generalities at close hand and in their own most
personal experience will translate them into a personally thoughtout teaching for themselves. The others
may for the time being perceive nothing but covered over bowls, which could also really be empty, until,
surprised one day, they see with their own eyes that the bowls are full and that attacks, demands, living
impulses, passions lay mixed in and impressed into these generalities, which could not lie hidden in this way
for a long time. I refer these doubters to time, which brings all things to light, and, in conclusion, I turn my
attention to that society of those who hope, in order to explain to them in an allegory the progress and
outcome of their healing, their salvation from the historical sickness, and thus their own history, up to the
point where they will be again healthy enough to undertake a new history and to make use of the past under
the mastery of life in a threefold sense, that is, monumental, or antiquarian, or critical. At that point of time
they will be less knowledgeable than the "educated" of the present, for they will have forgotten a good deal
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 37
Page No 40
and even have lost the pleasure of looking for what those educated ones above all wish to know, in general
still in order to look back. Their distinguishing marks, from the point of view of those educated ones, are
precisely their "lack of education," their indifference and reserve with respect to many famous men, even
with respect to many good things. But they have become, at this final point of their healing, once again men
and have ceased to be humanlike aggregatesthat is something! There are still hopes! Are you not
laughing at that in your hearts, you hopeful ones!
And, you will ask, How do we come to that end point? The Delphic god shouts out to you, at the very start of
your trek to that goal, his aphorism: "Know thyself." It is a difficult saying; for that god "hides nothing and
announces nothing, but only points the way," as Heraclitus has said. But what direction is he indicating to
you?
There were centuries when the Greeks found themselves in a danger similar to the one in which we find
ourselves, that is, the danger of destruction from being swamped by what is foreign and past, from "history."
The Greeks never lived in proud isolation; their "culture" was for a long time much more a chaos of foreign,
Semitic, Babylonian, Lydian, and Egyptian forms and ideas, and their religion a real divine struggle of the
entire Orient, something similar to the way "German culture" and religion are now a selfstruggling chaos of
all foreign lands and all prehistory. Nevertheless Hellenic culture did not become an aggregate, thanks to that
Apollonian saying. The Greeks learned gradually to organize the chaos because, in accordance with the
Delphic teaching, they directed their thoughts back to themselves, that is, to their real needs, and let the
apparent needs die off. So they seized possession of themselves again. They did not remain long the
overendowed heirs and epigones of the entire Orient. After an arduous battle with themselves, through the
practical interpretation of that saying, they became the most fortunate enrichers and increasers of the treasure
they had inherited and the firstlings and models for all future national cultures.
This is a parable for every individual among us. He must organize the chaos in himself by recalling in himself
his own real needs. His honesty, his better and more genuine character must now and then struggle against
what will be constantly repeated, relearned, and imitated. He begins then to grasp that culture can still be
something other than a decoration of life, that is, basically always only pretence and disguise; for all
ornamentation covers over what is decorated. So the Greek idea of culture reveals itself to him, in opposition
to the Roman, the idea of culture as a new and improved nature, without inner and outer, without pretence
and convention, culture as a unanimity of living, thinking, appearing, and willing. Thus, he learns out of his
own experience that it was the higher power of moral nature through which the Greeks attained their victory
over all other cultures and that each increase of truthfulness must also be a demand in preparation for true
culture. This truthfulness may also occasionally seriously harm the idea of culture esteemed at the time; it
even may be able to assist a totally decorative culture to collapse.
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life
On the Use and Abuse of History for Life 38
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. On the Use and Abuse of History for Life, page = 4
3. FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE, page = 4