Title: On War
Subject:
Author: Carl von Clausewitz
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
On War
Carl von Clausewitz
Page No 2
Table of Contents
On War................................................................................................................................................................1
On War
i
Page No 3
On War
Carl von Clausewitz
BOOK I ON THE NATURE OF WAR
I WHAT IS WAR?
II END AND MEANS IN WAR
III THE GENIUS FOR WAR
IV OF DANGER IN WAR
V OF BODILY EXERTION IN WAR
VI INFORMATION IN WAR
VII FRICTION IN WAR
VIII CONCLUDING REMARKS
BOOK II ON THE THEORY OF WAR
I BRANCHES OF THE ART OF WAR
II ON THE THEORY OF WAR
III ART OR SCIENCE OF WAR
IV METHODICISM
V CRITICISM
VI ON EXAMPLES
BOOK III OF STRATEGY IN GENERAL
I STRATEGY
II ELEMENTS OF STRATEGY
III MORAL FORCES
IV THE CHIEF MORAL POWERS
V MILITARY VIRTUE OF AN ARMY
VI BOLDNESS
VII PERSEVERANCE
VIII SUPERIORITY OF NUMBERS
IX THE SURPRISE
X STRATAGEM
XI ASSEMBLY OF FORCES IN SPACE
XII ASSEMBLY OF FORCES IN TIME
XIII STRATEGIC RESERVE
XIV ECONOMY OF FORCES
XV GEOMETRICAL ELEMENT
XVI ON THE SUSPENSION OF THE ACT IN WAR
XVII ON THE CHARACTER OF MODERN WAR
XVIII TENSION AND REST
BOOK IV THE COMBAT
I INTRODUCTORY
II CHARACTER OF THE MODERN BATTLE
III THE COMBAT IN GENERAL
IV THE COMBAT IN GENERAL (continuation)
V ON THE SIGNIFICATION OF THE COMBAT
VI DURATION OF THE COMBAT
VII DECISION OF THE COMBAT
VIII MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING AS TO A BATTLE
On War 1
Page No 4
IX THE BATTLE
X EFFECTS OF VICTORY
XI THE USE OF THE BATTLE
XII STRATEGIC MEANS OF UTILISING VICTORY
XIII RETREAT AFTER A LOST BATTLE
XIV NIGHT FIGHTING
ON WAR
GENERAL CARL VON CLAUSEWITZ
TRANSLATED BY
COLONEL J.J. GRAHAM
NEW AND REVISED EDITION
WITH AN INTRODUCTION AND NOTES BY
COLONEL F.N. MAUDE C.B. (LATE R.E.)
EIGHTH IMPRESSION
IN THREE VOLUMES
VOLUME I
INTRODUCTION
THE Germans interpret their new national coloursblack, red, and whiteby the saying, "Durch Nacht und
Blut zur licht." ("Through night and blood to light"), and no work yet written conveys to the thinker a clearer
conception of all that the red streak in their flag stands for than this deep and philosophical analysis of "War"
by Clausewitz.
It reveals "War," stripped of all accessories, as the exercise of force for the attainment of a political object,
unrestrained by any law save that of expediency, and thus gives the key to the interpretation of German
political aims, past, present, and future, which is unconditionally necessary for every student of the modern
conditions of Europe. Step by step, every event since Waterloo follows with logical consistency from the
teachings of Napoleon, formulated for the first time, some twenty years afterwards, by this remarkable
thinker.
What Darwin accomplished for Biology generally Clausewitz did for the LifeHistory of Nations nearly half
a century before him, for both have proved the existence of the same law in each case, viz., "The survival of
the fittest"the "fittest," as Huxley long since pointed out, not being necessarily synonymous with the
ethically "best." Neither of these thinkers was concerned with the ethics of the struggle which each studied so
exhaustively, but to both men the phase or condition presented itself neither as moral nor immoral, any more
than are famine, disease, or other natural phenomena, but as emanating from a force inherent in all living
organisms which can only be mastered by understanding its nature. It is in that spirit that, one after the other,
all the Nations of the Continent, taught by such drastic lessons as Koniggratz and Sedan, have accepted the
On War
On War 2
Page No 5
lesson, with the result that today Europe is an armed camp, and peace is maintained by the equilibrium of
forces, and will continue just as long as this equilibrium exists, and no longer.
Whether this state of equilibrium is in itself a good or desirable thing may be open to argument. I have
discussed it at length in my "War and the World's Life"; but I venture to suggest that to no one would a
renewal of the era of warfare be a change for the better, as far as existing humanity is concerned. Meanwhile,
however, with every year that elapses the forces at present in equilibrium are changing in magnitudethe
pressure of populations which have to be fed is rising, and an explosion along the line of least resistance is,
sooner or later, inevitable.
As I read the teaching of the recent Hague Conference, no responsible Government on the Continent is
anxious to form in themselves that line of least resistance; they know only too well what War would mean;
and we alone, absolutely unconscious of the trend of the dominant thought of Europe, are pulling down the
dam which may at any moment let in on us the flood of invasion.
Now no responsible man in Europe, perhaps least of all in Germany, thanks us for this voluntary destruction
of our defences, for all who are of any importance would very much rather end their days in peace than incur
the burden of responsibility which War would entail. But they realise that the gradual dissemination of the
principles taught by Clausewitz has created a condition of molecular tension in the minds of the Nations they
govern analogous to the "critical temperature of water heated above boilingpoint under pressure," which
may at any moment bring about an explosion which they will be powerless to control.
The case is identical with that of an ordinary steam boiler, delivering so and so many pounds of steam to its
engines as long as the envelope can contain the pressure; but let a breach in its continuity ariserelieving the
boiling water of all restraintand in a moment the whole mass flashes into vapour, developing a power no
work of man can oppose.
The ultimate consequences of defeat no man can foretell. The only way to avert them is to ensure victory;
and, again following out the principles of Clausewitz, victory can only be ensured by the creation in peace of
an organisation which will bring every available man, horse, and gun (or ship and gun, if the war be on the
sea) in the shortest possible time, and with the utmost possible momentum, upon the decisive field of
action which in turn leads to the final doctrine formulated by Von der Goltz in excuse for the action of the
late President Kruger in 1899:
"The Statesman who, knowing his instrument to be ready, and seeing War inevitable, hesitates to strike first
is guilty of a crime against his country."
It is because this sequence of cause and effect is absolutely unknown to our Members of Parliament, elected
by popular representation, that all our efforts to ensure a lasting peace by securing efficiency with economy
in our National Defences have been rendered nugatory.
This estimate of the influence of Clausewitz's sentiments on contemporary thought in Continental Europe
may appear exaggerated to those who have not familiarised themselves with M. Gustav de Bon's exposition
of the laws governing the formation and conduct of crowds I do not wish for one minute to be understood as
asserting that Clausewitz has been conscientiously studied and understood in any Army, not even in the
Prussian, but his work has been the ultimate foundation on which every drill regulation in Europe, except our
own, has been reared. It is this ceaseless repetition of his fundamental ideas to which onehalf of the male
population of every Continental Nation has been subjected for two to three years of their lives, which has
tuned their minds to vibrate in harmony with his precepts, and those who know and appreciate this fact at its
true value have only to strike the necessary chords in order to evoke a response sufficient to overpower any
other ethical conception which those who have not organised their forces beforehand can appeal to.
On War
On War 3
Page No 6
The recent setback experienced by the Socialists in Germany is an illustration of my position. The Socialist
leaders of that country are far behind the responsible Governors in their knowledge of the management of
crowds. The latter had long before (in 1893, in fact) made their arrangements to prevent the spread of
Socialistic propaganda beyond certain useful limits. As long as the Socialists only threatened capital they
were not seriously interfered with, for the Government knew quite well that the undisputed sway of the
employer was not for the ultimate good of the State. The standard of comfort must not be pitched too low if
men are to he ready to die for their country. But the moment the Socialists began to interfere seriously with
the discipline of the Army the word went round, and the Socialists lost heavily at the polls.
If this power of predetermined reaction to acquired ideas can be evoked successfully in a matter of internal
interest only, in which the "obvious interest" of the vast majority of the population is so clearly on the side of
the Socialist, it must be evident how enormously greater it will prove when set in motion against an external
enemy, where the "obvious interest" of the people is, from the very nature of things, as manifestly on the side
of the Government; and the Statesman who failed to take into account the force of the "resultant thought
wave" of a crowd of some seven million men, all trained to respond to their ruler's call, would be guilty of
treachery as grave as one who failed to strike when he knew the Army to be ready for immediate action.
As already pointed out, it is to the spread of Clausewitz's ideas that the present state of more or less
immediate readiness for war of all European Armies is due, and since the organisation of these forces is
uniform this "more or less" of readiness exists in precise proportion to the sense of duty which animates the
several Armies. Where the spirit of duty and selfsacrifice is low the troops are unready and inefficient;
where, as in Prussia, these qualities, by the training of a whole century, have become instinctive, troops really
are ready to the last button, and might be poured down upon any one of her neighbours with such rapidity that
the very first collision must suffice to ensure ultimate successa success by no means certain if the enemy,
whoever he may be, is allowed breathingtime in which to set his house in order.
An example will make this clearer. In 1887 Germany was on the very verge of War with France and Russia.
At that moment her superior efficiency, the consequence of this inborn sense of dutysurely one of the
highest qualities of humanitywas so great that it is more than probable that less than six weeks would have
sufficed to bring the French to their knees. Indeed, after the first fortnight it would have been possible to
begin transferring troops from the Rhine to the Niemen; and the same case may arise again. But if France and
Russia had been allowed even ten days' warning the German plan would have been completely defeated.
France alone might then have claimed all the efforts that Germany could have put forth to defeat her.
Yet there are politicians in England so grossly ignorant of the German reading of the Napoleonic lessons that
they expect that Nation to sacrifice the enormous advantage sacrifice and practical patriotism by an appeal to
a Court of Arbitration, and the further delays which must arise by going through the medieaeval formalities
of recalling Ambassadors and exchanging ultimatums.
Most of our presentday politicians have made their money in businessa "form of human competition
greatly resembling War," to paraphrase Clausewitz. Did they, when in the throes of such competition, send
formal notice to their rivals of their plans to get the better of them in commerce? Did Mr. Carnegie, the arch
priest of Peace at any price, when he built up the Steel Trust, notify his competitors when and how he
proposed to strike the blows which successively made him master of millions? Surely the Directors of a Great
Nation may consider the interests of their shareholdersi.e., the people they governas sufficiently serious
not to be endangered by the deliberate sacrifice of the preponderant position of readiness which generations
of selfdevotion, patriotism and wise forethought have won for them?
As regards the strictly military side of this work, though the recent researches of the French General Staff into
the records and documents of the Napoleonic period have shown conclusively that Clausewitz had never
grasped the essential point of the Great Emperor's strategic method, yet it is admitted that he has completely
On War
On War 4
Page No 7
fathomed the spirit which gave life to the form; and notwithstandingthe variations in application which have
resulted from the progress of invention in every field of national activity (not in the technical improvements
in armament alone), this spirit still remains the essential factor in the whole matter. Indeed, if anything,
modern appliances have intensified its importance, for though, with equal armaments on both sides, the form
of battles must always remain the same, the facility and certainty of combination which better methods of
communicating orders and intelligence have conferred upon the Commanders has rendered the control of
great masses immeasurably more certain than it was in the past.
Men kill each other at greater distances, it is true but killing is a constant factor in all battles. The
difference between "now and then" lies in this, that, thanks to the enormous increase in range (the essential
feature in modern armaments), it is possible to concentrate by surprise, on any chosen spot, a mankilling
power fully twentyfold greater than was conceivable in the days of Waterloo; and whereas in Napoleon's time
this concentration of mankilling power (which in his hands took the form of the great caseshot attack)
depended almost entirely on the shape and condition of the ground, which might or might not be favourable,
nowadays such concentration of firepower is almost independent of the country altogether.
Thus, at Waterloo, Napoleon was compelled to wait till the ground became firm enough for his guns to gallop
over; nowadays every gun at his disposal, and five times that number had he possessed them, might have
opened on any point in the British position he had selected, as soon as it became light enough to see.
Or, to take a more modern instance, viz., the battle of St. PrivatGravelotte, August 18, 1870, where the
Germans were able to concentrate on both wings batteries of two hundred guns and upwards, it would have
been practically impossible, owing to the section of the slopes of the French position, to carry out the
oldfashioned caseshot attack at all. Nowadays there would be no difficulty in turning on the fire of two
thousand guns on any point of the position, and switching this fire up and down the line like water from a
fireengine hose, if the occasion demanded such concentration.
But these alterations in method make no difference in the truth of the picture of War which Clausewitz
presents, with which every soldier, and above all every Leader, should be saturated.
Death, wounds, suffering, and privation remain the same, whatever the weapons employed, and their reaction
on the ultimate nature of man is the same now as in the struggle a century ago. It is this reaction that the
Great Commander has to understand and prepare himself to control; and the task becomes ever greater as,
fortunately for humanity, the opportunities for gathering experience become more rare.
In the end, and with every improvement in science, the result depends more and more on the character of the
Leader and his power of resisting "the sensuous impressions of the battlefield." Finally, for those who would
fit themselves in advance for such responsibility, I know of no more inspiring advice than that given by
Krishna to Arjuna ages ago, when the latter trembled before the awful responsibility of launching his Army
against the hosts of the Pandav's:
This Life within all living things, my Prince,
Hides beyond harm. Scorn thou to suffer, then,
For that which cannot suffer. Do thy part!
Be mindful of thy name, and tremble not.
Nought better can betide a martial soul
Than lawful war. Happy the warrior
To whom comes joy of battle....
. . . But if thou shunn'st
This honourable fielda Kshittriya
If, knowing thy duty and thy task, thou bidd'st
Duty and task go bythat shall be sin!
On War
On War 5
Page No 8
And those to come shall speak thee infamy
From age to age. But infamy is worse
For men of noble blood to bear than death!
. . . . . .
Therefore arise, thou Son of Kunti! Brace
Thine arm for conflict; nerve thy heart to meet,
As things alike to thee, pleasure or pain,
Profit or ruin, victory or defeat.
So minded, gird thee to the fight, for so
Thou shalt not sin!
COL. F. N. MAUDE, C.B., late R.E.
PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION
IT will naturally excite surprise that a preface by a female hand should accompany a work on such a subject
as the present. For my friends no explanation of the circumstance is required; but I hope by a simple relation
of the cause to clear myself of the appearance of presumption in the eyes also of those to whom I am not
known.
The work to which these lines serve as a preface occupied almost entirely the last twelve years of the life of
my inexpressibly beloved husband, who has unfortunately been torn too soon from myself and his country.
To complete it was his most earnest desire; but it was not his intention that it should be published during his
life; and if I tried to persuade him to alter that intention, he often answered, half in jest, but also, perhaps, half
in a foreboding of early death: "Thou shalt publish it." These words (which in those happy days often drew
tears from me, little as I was inclined to attach a serious meaning to them) make it now, in the opinion of my
friends, a duty incumbent on me to introduce the posthumous works of my beloved husband, with a few
prefatory lines from myself; and although here may be a difference of opinion on this point, still I am sure
there will be no mistake as to the feeling which has prompted me to overcome the timidity which makes any
such appearance, even in a subordinate part, so difficult for a woman.
It will be understood, as a matter of course, that I cannot have the most remote intention of considering
myself as the real editress of a work which is far above the scope of my capacity: I only stand at its side as an
affectionate companion on its entrance into the world. This position I may well claim, as a similar one was
allowed me during its formation and progress. Those who are acquainted with our happy married life, and
know how we shared everything with each othernot only joy and sorrow, but also every occupation, every
interest of daily lifewill understand that my beloved husband could not be occupied on a work of this kind
without its being known to me. Therefore, no one can like me bear testimony to the zeal, to the love with
which he laboured on it, to the hopes which he bound up with it, as well as the manner and time of its
elaboration. His richly gifted mind had from his early youth longed for light and truth, and, varied as were his
talents, still he had chiefly directed his reflections to the science of war, to which the duties of his profession
called him, and which are of such importance for the benefit of States. Scharnhorst was the first to lead him
into the right road, and his subsequent appointment in 1810 as Instructor at the General War School, as well
as the honour conferred on him at the same time of giving military instruction to H.R.H. the Crown Prince,
tended further to give his investigations and studies that direction, and to lead him to put down in writing
whatever conclusions he arrived at. A paper with which he finished the instruction of H.R.H. the Crown
Prince contains the germ of his subsequent works. But it was in the year 1816, at Coblentz, that he first
devoted himself again to scientific labours, and to collecting the fruits which his rich experience in those four
eventful years had brought to maturity. He wrote down his views, in the first place, in short essays, only
loosely connected with each other. The following, without date, which has been found amongst his papers,
seems to belong to those early days.
On War
On War 6
Page No 9
"In the principles here committed to paper, in my opinion, the chief things which compose Strategy, as it is
called, are touched upon. I looked upon them only as materials, and had just got to such a length towards the
moulding them into a whole.
"These materials have been amassed without any regularly preconceived plan. My view was at first, without
regard to system and strict connection, to put down the results of my reflections upon the most important
points in quite brief, precise, compact propositions. The manner in which Montesquieu has treated his subject
floated before me in idea. I thought that concise, sententious chapters, which I proposed at first to call grains,
would attract the attention of the intelligent just as much by that which was to be developed from them, as by
that which they contained in themselves. I had, therefore, before me in idea, intelligent readers already
acquainted with the subject. But my nature, which always impels me to development and systematising, at
last worked its way out also in this instance. For some time I was able to confine myself to extracting only the
most important results from the essays, which, to attain clearness and conviction in my own mind, I wrote
upon different subjects, to concentrating in that manner their spirit in a small compass; but afterwards my
peculiarity gained ascendency completelyI have developed what I could, and thus naturally have supposed
a reader not yet acquainted with the subject.
"The more I advanced with the work, and the more I yielded to the spirit of investigation, so much the more I
was also led to system; and thus, then, chapter after chapter has been inserted.
"My ultimate view has now been to go through the whole once more, to establish by further explanation
much of the earlier treatises, and perhaps to condense into results many analyses on the later ones, and thus to
make a moderate whole out of it, forming a small octavo volume. But it was my wish also in this to avoid
everything common, everything that is plain of itself, that has been said a hundred times, and is generally
accepted; for my ambition was to write a book that would not be forgotten in two or three years, and which
any one interested in the subject would at all events take up more than once."
In Coblentz, where he was much occupied with duty, he could only give occasional hours to his private
studies. It was not until 1818, after his appointment as Director of the General Academy of War at Berlin,
that he had the leisure to expand his work, and enrich it from the history of modern wars. This leisure also
reconciled him to his new avocation, which, in other respects, was not satisfactory to him, as, according to the
existing organisation of the Academy, the scientific part of the course is not under the Director, but conducted
by a Board of Studies. Free as he was from all petty vanity, from every feeling of restless, egotistical
ambition, still he felt a desire to be really useful, and not to leave inactive the abilities with which God had
endowed him. In active life he was not in a position in which this longing could be satisfied, and he had little
hope of attaining to any such position: his whole energies were therefore directed upon the domain of
science, and the benefit which he hoped to lay the foundation of by his work was the object of his life. That,
notwithstanding this, the resolution not to let the work appear until after his death became more confirmed is
the best proof that no vain, paltry longing for praise and distinction, no particle of egotistical views, was
mixed up with this noble aspiration for great and lasting usefulness.
Thus he worked diligently on, until, in the spring of 1830, he was appointed to the artillery, and his energies
were called into activity in such a different sphere, and to such a high degree, that he was obliged, for the
moment at least, to give up all literary work. He then put his papers in order, sealed up the separate packets,
labelled them, and took sorrowful leave of this employment which he loved so much. He was sent to Breslau
in August of the same year, as Chief of the Second Artillery District, but in December recalled to Berlin, and
appointed Chief of the Staff to FieldMarshal Count Gneisenau (for the term of his command). In March
1831, he accompanied his revered Commander to Posen. When he returned from there to Breslau in
November after the melancholy event which had taken place, he hoped to resume his work and perhaps
complete it in the course of the winter. The Almighty has willed it should be otherwise. On the 7th November
he returned to Breslau; on the 16th he was no more; and the packets sealed by himself were not opened until
On War
On War 7
Page No 10
after his death.
The papers thus left are those now made public in the following volumes, exactly in the condition in which
they were found, without a word being added or erased. Still, however, there was much to do before
publication, in the way of putting them in order and consulting about them; and I am deeply indebted to
several sincere friends for the assistance they have afforded me, particularly Major O'Etzel, who kindly
undertook the correction of the Press, as well as the preparation of the maps to accompany the historical parts
of the work. I must also mention my muchloved brother, who was my support in the hour of my misfortune,
and who has also done much for me in respect of these papers; amongst other things, by carefully examining
and putting them in order, he found the commencement of the revision which my dear husband wrote in the
year 1827, and mentions in the Notice hereafter annexed as a work he had in view. This revision has been
inserted in the place intended for it in the first book (for it does not go any further).
There are still many other friends to whom I might offer my thanks for their advice, for the sympathy and
friendship which they have shown me; but if I do not name them all, they will, I am sure, not have any doubts
of my sincere gratitude. It is all the greater, from my firm conviction that all they have done was not only on
my own account, but for the friend whom God has thus called away from them so soon.
If I have been highly blessed as the wife of such a man during one and twenty years, so am I still,
notwithstanding my irreparable loss, by the treasure of my recollections and of my hopes, by the rich legacy
of sympathy and friendship which I owe the beloved departed, by the elevating feeling which I experience at
seeing his rare worth so generally and honourably acknowledged.
The trust confided to me by a Royal Couple is a fresh benefit for which I have to thank the Almighty, as it
opens to me an honourable occupation, to which Idevote myself. May this occupation be blessed, and may
the dear little Prince who is now entrusted to my care, some day read this book, and be animated by it to
deeds like those of his glorious ancestors.
Written at the Marble Palace, Potsdam, 30th June, 1832.
MARIE VON CLAUSEWITZ, Born Countess Bruhl, Oberhofmeisterinn to H.R.H. the Princess William.
NOTICE
I LOOK upon the first six books, of which a fair copy has now been made, as only a mass which is still in a
manner without form, and which has yet to be again revised. In this revision the two kinds of War will be
everywhere kept more distinctly in view, by which all ideas will acquire a clearer meaning, a more precise
direction, and a closer application. The two kinds of War are, first, those in which the object is the
OVERTHROW OF THE ENEMY, whether it be that we aim at his destruction, politically, or merely at
disarming him and forcing him to conclude peace on our terms; and next, those in which our object is
MERELY TO MAKE SOME CONQUESTS ON THE FRONTIERS OF HIS COUNTRY, either for the
purpose of retaining them permanently, or of turning them to account as matter of exchange in the settlement
of a peace. Transition from one kind to the other must certainly continue to exist, but the completely different
nature of the tendencies of the two must everywhere appear, and must separate from each other things which
are incompatible.
Besides establishing this real difference in Wars, another practically necessary point of view must at the same
time be established, which is, that WAR IS ONLY A CONTINUATION OF STATE POLICY BY OTHER
MEANS. This point of view being adhered to everywhere, will introduce much more unity into the
consideration of the subject, and things will be more easily disentangled from each other. Although the chief
On War
On War 8
Page No 11
application of this point of view does not commence until we get to the eighth book, still it must be
completely developed in the first book, and also lend assistance throughout the revision of the first six books.
Through such a revision the first six books will get rid of a good deal of dross, many rents and chasms will be
closed up, and much that is of a general nature will be transformed into distinct conceptions and forms.
The seventh bookon attackfor the different chapters of which sketches are already made, is to be
considered as a reflection of the sixth, and must be completed at once, according to the abovementioned
more distinct points of view, so that it will require no fresh revision, but rather may serve as a model in the
revision of the first six books.
For the eighth bookon the Plan of a War, that is, of the organisation of a whole War in generalseveral
chapters are designed, but they are not at all to be regarded as real materials, they are merely a track, roughly
cleared, as it were, through the mass, in order by that means to ascertain the points of most importance. They
have answered this object, and I propose, on finishing the seventh book, to proceed at once to the working out
of the eighth, where the two points of view above mentioned will be chiefly affirmed, by which everything
will be simplified, and at the same time have a spirit breathed into it. I hope in this book to iron out many
creases in the heads of strategists and statesmen, and at least to show the object of action, and the real point to
be considered in War.
Now, when I have brought my ideas clearly out by finishing this eighth book, and have properly established
the leading features of War, it will be easier for me to carry the spirit of these ideas in to the first six books,
and to make these same features show themselves everywhere. Therefore I shall defer till then the revision of
the first six books.
Should the work be interrupted by my death, then what is found can only be called a mass of conceptions not
brought into form; but as these are open to endless misconceptions, they will doubtless give rise to a number
of crude criticisms: for in these things, every one thinks, when he takes up his pen, that whatever comes into
his head is worth saying and printing, and quite as incontrovertible as that twice two make four. If such a one
would take the pains, as I have done, to think over the subject, for years, and to compare his ideas with
military history, he would certainly be a little more guarded in his criticism.
Still, notwithstanding this imperfect form, I believe that an impartial reader thirsting for truth and conviction
will rightly appreciate in the first six books the fruits of several years' reflection and a diligent study of War,
and that, perhaps, he will find in them some leading ideas which may bring about a revolution in the theory of
War.
Berlin, 10th July, 1827.
Besides this notice, amongst the papers left the following unfinished memorandum was found, which appears
of very recent date:
The manuscript on the conduct of the Grande Guerre, which will be found after my death, in its present state
can only be regarded as a collection of materials from which it is intended to construct a theory of War. With
the greater part I am not yet satisfied; and the sixth book is to be looked at as a mere essay: I should have
completely remodelled it, and have tried a different line.
But the ruling principles which pervade these materials I hold to be the right ones: they are the result of a
very varied reflection, keeping always in view the reality, and always bearing in mind what I have learnt by
experience and by my intercourse with distinguished soldiers.
The seventh book is to contain the attack, the subjects of which are thrown together in a hasty manner: the
On War
On War 9
Page No 12
eighth, the plan for a War, in which I would have examined War more especially in its political and human
aspects.
The first chapter of the first book is the only one which I consider as completed; it will at least serve to show
the manner in which I proposed to treat the subject throughout.
The theory of the Grande Guerre, or Strategy, as it is called, is beset with extraordinary difficulties, and we
may affirm that very few men have clear conceptions of the separate subjects, that is, conceptions carried up
to their full logical conclusions. In real action most men are guided merely by the tact of judgment which hits
the object more or less accurately, according as they possess more or less genius.
This is the way in which all great Generals have acted, and therein partly lay their greatness and their genius,
that they always hit upon what was right by this tact. Thus also it will always be in action, and so far this tact
is amply sufficient. But when it is a question, not of acting oneself, but of convincing others in a consultation,
then all depends on clear conceptions and demonstration of the inherent relations, and so little progress has
been made in this respect that most deliberations are merely a contention of words, resting on no firm basis,
and ending either in every one retaining his own opinion, or in a compromise from mutual considerations of
respect, a middle course really without any value.[*]
[*] Herr Clausewitz evidently had before his mind the endless consultations at the Headquarters of the
Bohemian Army in the Leipsic Campaign 1813.
Clear ideas on these matters are therefore not wholly useless; besides, the human mind has a general tendency
to clearness, and always wants to be consistent with the necessary order of things.
Owing to the great difficulties attending a philosophical construction of the Art of War, and the many
attempts at it that have failed, most people have come to the conclusion that such a theory is impossible,
because it concerns things which no standing law can embrace. We should also join in this opinion and give
up any attempt at a theory, were it not that a great number of propositions make themselves evident without
any difficulty, as, for instance, that the defensive form, with a negative object, is the stronger form, the attack,
with the positive object, the weakerthat great results carry the little ones with themthat, therefore,
strategic effects may be referred to certain centres of gravitythat a demonstration is a weaker application of
force than a real attack, that, therefore, there must be some special reason for resorting to the formerthat
victory consists not merely in the conquest on the field of battle, but in the destruction of armed forces,
physically and morally, which can in general only be effected by a pursuit after the battle is gainedthat
successes are always greatest at the point where the victory has been gained, that, therefore, the change from
one line and object to another can only be regarded as a necessary evilthat a turning movement is only
justified by a superiority of numbers generally or by the advantage of our lines of communication and retreat
over those of the enemythat flank positions are only justifiable on similar groundsthat every attack
becomes weaker as it progresses.
THE INTRODUCTION OF THE AUTHOR
THAT the conception of the scientific does not consist alone, or chiefly, in system, and its finished
theoretical constructions, requires nowadays no exposition. System in this treatise is not to be found on the
surface, and instead of a finished building of theory, there are only materials.
The scientific form lies here in the endeavour to explore the nature of military phenomena to show their
affinity with the nature of the things of which they are composed. Nowhere has the philosophical argument
been evaded, but where it runs out into too thin a thread the Author has preferred to cut it short, and fall back
upon the corresponding results of experience; for in the same way as many plants only bear fruit when they
On War
On War 10
Page No 13
do not shoot too high, so in the practical arts the theoretical leaves and flowers must not be made to sprout
too far, but kept near to experience, which is their proper soil.
Unquestionably it would be a mistake to try to discover from the chemical ingredients of a grain of corn the
form of the ear of corn which it bears, as we have only to go to the field to see the ears ripe. Investigation and
observation, philosophy and experience, must neither despise nor exclude one another; they mutually afford
each other the rights of citizenship. Consequently, the propositions of this book, with their arch of inherent
necessity, are supported either by experience or by the conception of War itself as external points, so that
they are not without abutments.[*]
[*] That this is not the case in the works of many military writers especially of those who have aimed at
treating of War itself in a scientific manner, is shown in many instances, in which by their reasoning, the pro
and contra swallow each other up so effectually that there is no vestige of the tails even which were left in the
case of the two lions.
It is, perhaps, not impossible to write a systematic theory of War full of spirit and substance, but ours.
hitherto, have been very much the reverse. To say nothing of their unscientific spirit, in their striving after
coherence and completeness of system, they overflow with commonplaces, truisms, and twaddle of every
kind. If we want a striking picture of them we have only to read Lichtenberg's extract from a code of
regulations in case of fire.
If a house takes fire, we must seek, above all things, to protect the right side of the house standing on the left,
and, on the other hand, the left side of the house on the right; for if we, for example, should protect the left
side of the house on the left, then the right side of the house lies to the right of the left, and consequently as
the fire lies to the right of this side, and of the right side (for we have assumed that the house is situated to the
left of the fire), therefore the right side is situated nearer to the fire than the left, and the right side of the
house might catch fire if it was not protected before it came to the left, which is protected. Consequently,
something might be burnt that is not protected, and that sooner than something else would be burnt, even if it
was not protected; consequently we must let alone the latter and protect the former. In order to impress the
thing on one's mind, we have only to note if the house is situated to the right of the fire, then it is the left side,
and if the house is to the left it is the right side.
In order not to frighten the intelligent reader by such commonplaces, and to make the little good that there is
distasteful by pouring water upon it, the Author has preferred to give in small ingots of fine metal his
impressions and convictions, the result of many years' reflection on War, of his intercourse with men of
ability, and of much personal experience. Thus the seemingly weakly boundtogether chapters of this book
have arisen, but it is hoped they will not be found wanting in logical connection. Perhaps soon a greater head
may appear, and instead of these single grains, give the whole in a casting of pure metal without dross.
BRIEF MEMOIR OF GENERAL CLAUSEWITZ
(BY TRANSLATOR)
THE Author of the work here translated, General Carl Von Clausewitz, was born at Burg, near Magdeburg, in
1780, and entered the Prussian Army as Fahnenjunker (i.e., ensign) in 1792. He served in the campaigns of
179394 on the Rhine, after which he seems to have devoted some time to the study of the scientific branches
of his profession. In 1801 he entered the Military School at Berlin, and remained there till 1803. During his
residence there he attracted the notice of General Scharnhorst, then at the head of the establishment; and the
patronage of this distinguished officer had immense influence on his future career, and we may gather from
his writings that he ever afterwards continued to entertain a high esteem for Scharnhorst. In the campaign of
On War
On War 11
Page No 14
1806 he served as Aidedecamp to Prince Augustus of Prussia; and being wounded and taken prisoner, he
was sent into France until the close of that war. On his return, he was placed on General Scharnhorst's Staff,
and employed in the work then going on for the reorganisation of the Army. He was also at this time selected
as military instructor to the late King of Prussia, then Crown Prince. In 1812 Clausewitz, with several other
Prussian officers, having entered the Russian service, his first appointment was as Aidedecamp to General
Phul. Afterwards, while serving with Wittgenstein's army, he assisted in negotiating the famous convention
of Tauroggen with York. Of the part he took in that affair he has left an interesting account in his work on the
"Russian Campaign." It is there stated that, in order to bring the correspondence which had been carried on
with York to a termination in one way or another, the Author was despatched to York's headquarters with two
letters, one was from General d'Auvray, the Chief of the Staff of Wittgenstein's army, to General Diebitsch,
showing the arrangements made to cut off York's corps from Macdonald (this was necessary in order to give
York a plausible excuse for seceding from the French); the other was an intercepted letter from Macdonald to
the Duke of Bassano. With regard to the former of these, the Author says, "it would not have had weight with
a man like York, but for a military justification, if the Prussian Court should require one as against the
French, it was important."
The second letter was calculated at the least to call up in General York's mind all the feelings of bitterness
which perhaps for some days past bad been diminished by the consciousness of his own behaviour towards
the writer.
As the Author entered General York's chamber, the latter called out to him, "Keep off from me; I will have
nothing more to do with you; your dd Cossacks have let a letter of Macdonald's pass through them,
which brings me an order to march on Piktrepohnen, in order there to effect our junction. All doubt is now at
an end; your troops do not come up; you are too weak; march I must, and I must excuse myself from further
negotiation, which may cost me my head." The Author said that be would make no opposition to all this, but
begged for a candle, as he had letters to show the General, and, as the latter seemed still to hesitate, the
Author added, "Your Excellency will not surely place me in the embarrassment of departing without having
executed my commission." The General ordered candles, and called in Colonel von Roeder, the chief of his
staff, from the antechamber. The letters were read. After a pause of an instant, the General said,
"Clausewitz, you are a Prussian, do you believe that the letter of General d'Auvray is sincere, and that
Wittgenstein's troops will really be at the points he mentioned on the 31st?" The Author replied, "I pledge
myself for the sincerity of this letter upon the knowledge I have of General d'Auvray and the other men of
Wittgenstein's headquarters; whether the dispositions he announces can be accomplished as he lays down I
certainly cannot pledge myself; for your Excellency knows that in war we must often fall short of the line we
have drawn for ourselves." The General was silent for a few minutes of earnest reflection; then he held out
his hand to the Author, and said, "You have me. Tell General Diebitsch that we must confer early tomorrow
at the mill of Poschenen, and that I am now firmly determined to separate myself from the French and their
cause." The hour was fixed for 8 A.M. After this was settled, the General added, "But I will not do the thing
by halves, I will get you Massenbach also." He called in an officer who was of Massenbach's cavalry, and
who had just left them. Much like Schiller's Wallenstein, he asked, walking up and down the room the while,
"What say your regiments?" The officer broke out with enthusiasm at the idea of a riddance from the French
alliance, and said that every man of the troops in question felt the same.
"You young ones may talk; but my older head is shaking on my shoulders," replied the General.[*]
[*] "Campaign in Russia in 1812"; translated from the German of General Von Clausewitz (by Lord
Ellesmere).
After the close of the Russian campaign Clausewitz remained in the service of that country, but was attached
as a Russian staff officer to Blucher's headquarters till the Armistice in 1813.
On War
On War 12
Page No 15
In 1814, he became Chief of the Staff of General Walmoden's RussoGerman Corps, which formed part of
the Army of the North under Bernadotte. His name is frequently mentioned with distinction in that campaign,
particularly in connection with the affair of Goehrde.
Clausewitz reentered the Prussian service in 1815, and served as Chief of the Staff to Thielman's corps,
which was engaged with Grouchy at Wavre, on the 18th of June.
After the Peace, he was employed in a command on the Rhine. In 1818, he became MajorGeneral, and
Director of the Military School at which he had been previously educated.
In 1830, he was appointed Inspector of Artillery at Breslau, but soon after nominated Chief of the Staff to the
Army of Observation, under Marshal Gneisenau on the Polish frontier.
The latest notices of his life and services are probably to be found in the memoirs of General Brandt, who,
from being on the staff of Gneisenau's army, was brought into daily intercourse with Clausewitz in matters of
duty, and also frequently met him at the table of Marshal Gneisenau, at Posen.
Amongst other anecdotes, General Brandt relates that, upon one occasion, the conversation at the Marshal's
table turned upon a sermon preached by a priest, in which some great absurdities were introduced, and a
discussion arose as to whether the Bishop should not be made responsible for what the priest had said. This
led to the topic of theology in general, when General Brandt, speaking of himself, says, "I expressed an
opinion that theology is only to be regarded as an historical process, as a MOMENT in the gradual
development of the human race. This brought upon me an attack from all quarters, but more especially from
Clausewitz, who ought to have been on my side, he having been an adherent and pupil of Kiesewetter's, who
had indoctrinated him in the philosophy of Kant, certainly dilutedI might even say in homoeopathic
doses." This anecdote is only interesting as the mention of Kiesewetter points to a circumstance in the life of
Clausewitz that may have had an influence in forming those habits of thought which distinguish his writings.
"The way," says General Brandt, "in which General Clausewitz judged of things, drew conclusions from
movements and marches, calculated the times of the marches, and the points where decisions would take
place, was extremely interesting. Fate has unfortunately denied him an opportunity of showing his talents in
high command, but I have a firm persuasion that as a strategist he would have greatly distinguished himself.
As a leader on the field of battle, on the other hand, he would not have been so much in his right place, from a
manque d'habitude du commandement, he wanted the art d'enlever les troupes."
After the Prussian Army of Observation was dissolved, Clausewitz returned to Breslau, and a few days after
his arrival was seized with cholera, the seeds of which he must have brought with him from the army on the
Polish frontier. His death took place in November 1831.
His writings are contained in nine volumes, published after his death, but his fame rests most upon the three
volumes forming his treatise on "War." In the present attempt to render into English this portion of the works
of Clausewitz, the translator is sensible of many deficiencies, but he hopes at all events to succeed in making
this celebrated treatise better known in England, believing, as he does, that so far as the work concerns the
interests of this country, it has lost none of the importance it possessed at the time of its first publication.
J. J. GRAHAM (Col.)
On War
On War 13
Page No 16
BOOK I. ON THE NATURE OF WAR
CHAPTER I. WHAT IS WAR?
1. INTRODUCTION.
WE propose to consider first the single elements of our subject, then each branch or part, and, last of all, the
whole, in all its relationstherefore to advance from the simple to the complex. But it is necessary for us to
commence with a glance at the nature of the whole, because it is particularly necessary that in the
consideration of any of the parts their relation to the whole should be kept constantly in view.
2. DEFINITION.
We shall not enter into any of the abstruse definitions of War used by publicists. We shall keep to the element
of the thing itself, to a duel. War is nothing but a duel on an extensive scale. If we would conceive as a unit
the countless number of duels which make up a War, we shall do so best by supposing to ourselves two
wrestlers. Each strives by physical force to compel the other to submit to his will: each endeavours to throw
his adversary, and thus render him incapable of further resistance.
WAR THEREFORE IS AN ACT OF VIOLENCE INTENDED TO COMPEL OUR OPPONENT TO
FULFIL OUR WILL.
Violence arms itself with the inventions of Art and Science in order to contend against violence. Self
imposed restrictions, almost imperceptible and hardly worth mentioning, termed usages of International Law,
accompany it without essentially impairing its power. Violence, that is to say, physical force (for there is no
moral force without the conception of States and Law), is therefore the MEANS; the compulsory submission
of the enemy to our will is the ultimate object. In order to attain this object fully, the enemy must be
disarmed, and disarmament becomes therefore the immediate OBJECT of hostilities in theory. It takes the
place of the final object, and puts it aside as something we can eliminate from our calculations.
3. UTMOST USE OF FORCE.
Now, philanthropists may easily imagine there is a skilful method of disarming and overcoming an enemy
withoutgreat bloodshed, and that this is the proper tendency of the Art of War. However plausible this may
appear, still it is an error which must be extirpated; for in such dangerous things as War, the errors which
proceed from a spirit of benevolence are the worst. As the use of physical power to the utmost extent by no
means excludes the cooperation of the intelligence, it follows that he who uses force unsparingly, without
reference to the bloodshed involved, must obtain a superiority if his adversary uses less vigour in its
application. The former then dictates the law to the latter, and both proceed to extremities to which the only
limitations are those imposed by the amount of counter acting force on each side.
This is the way in which the matter must be viewed and it is to no purpose, it is even against one's own
interest, to turn away from the consideration of the real nature of the affair because the horror of its elements
excites repugnance.
If the Wars of civilised people are less cruel and destructive than those of savages, the difference arises from
the social condition both of States in themselves and in their relations to each other. Out of this social
condition and its relations War arises, and by it War is subjected to conditions, is controlled and modified.
But these things do not belong to War itself; they are only given conditions; and to introduce into the
On War
On War 14
Page No 17
philosophy of War itself a principle of moderation would be an absurdity.
Two motives lead men to War: instinctive hostility and hostile intention. In our definition of War, we have
chosen as its characteristic the latter of these elements, because it is the most general. It is impossible to
conceive the passion of hatred of the wildest description, bordering on mere instinct, without combining with
it the idea of a hostile intention. On the other hand, hostile intentions may often exist without being
accompanied by any, or at all events by any extreme, hostility of feeling. Amongst savages views emanating
from the feelings, amongst civilised nations those emanating from the understanding, have the predominance;
but this difference arises from attendant circumstances, existing institutions, and, therefore, is not to be found
necessarily in all cases, although it prevails in the majority. In short, even the most civilised nations may burn
with passionate hatred of each other.
We may see from this what a fallacy it would be to refer the War of a civilised nation entirely to an intelligent
act on the part of the Government, and to imagine it as continually freeing itself more and more from all
feeling of passion in such a way that at last the physical masses of combatants would no longer be required;
in reality, their mere relations would sufficea kind of algebraic action.
Theory was beginning to drift in this direction until the facts of the last War[*] taught it better. If War is an
ACT of force, it belongs necessarily also to the feelings. If it does not originate in the feelings, it REACTS,
more or less, upon them, and the extent of this reaction depends not on the degree of civilisation, but upon the
importance and duration of the interests involved.
[*] Clausewitz alludes here to the "Wars of Liberation," 1813,14,15.
Therefore, if we find civilised nations do not put their prisoners to death, do not devastate towns and
countries, this is because their intelligence exercises greater influence on their mode of carrying on War, and
has taught them more effectual means of applying force than these rude acts of mere instinct. The invention
of gunpowder, the constant progress of improvements in the construction of firearms, are sufficient proofs
that the tendency to destroy the adversary which lies at the bottom of the conception of War is in no way
changed or modified through the progress of civilisation.
We therefore repeat our proposition, that War is an act of violence pushed to its utmost bounds; as one side
dictates the law to the other, there arises a sort of reciprocal action, which logically must lead to an extreme.
This is the first reciprocal action, and the first extreme with which we meet (FIRST RECIPROCAL
ACTION).
4. THE AIM IS TO DISARM THE ENEMY.
We have already said that the aim of all action in War is to disarm the enemy, and we shall now show that
this, theoretically at least, is indispensable.
If our opponent is to be made to comply with our will, we must place him in a situation which is more
oppressive to him than the sacrifice which we demand; but the disadvantages of this position must naturally
not be of a transitory nature, at least in appearance, otherwise the enemy, instead of yielding, will hold out, in
the prospect of a change for the better. Every change in this position which is produced by a continuation of
the War should therefore be a change for the worse. The worst condition in which a belligerent can be placed
is that of being completely disarmed. If, therefore, the enemy is to be reduced to submission by an act of War,
he must either be positively disarmed or placed in such a position that he is threatened with it. From this it
follows that the disarming or overthrow of the enemy, whichever we call it, must always be the aim of
Warfare. Now War is always the shock of two hostile bodies in collision, not the action of a living power
upon an inanimate mass, because an absolute state of endurance would not be making War; therefore, what
On War
On War 15
Page No 18
we have just said as to the aim of action in War applies to both parties. Here, then, is another case of
reciprocal action. As long as the enemy is not defeated, he may defeat me; then I shall be no longer my own
master; he will dictate the law to me as I did to him. This is the second reciprocal action, and leads to a
second extreme (SECOND RECIPROCAL ACTION).
5. UTMOST EXERTION OF POWERS.
If we desire to defeat the enemy, we must proportion our efforts to his powers of resistance. This is expressed
by the product of two factors which cannot be separated, namely, the sum of available means and the strength
of the Will. The sum of the available means may be estimated in a measure, as it depends (although not
entirely) upon numbers; but the strength of volition is more difficult to determine, and can only be estimated
to a certain extent by the strength of the motives. Granted we have obtained in this way an approximation to
the strength of the power to be contended with, we can then take of our own means, and either increase them
so as to obtain a preponderance, or, in case we have not the resources to effect this, then do our best by
increasing our means as far as possible. But the adversary does the same; therefore, there is a new mutual
enhancement, which, in pure conception, must create a fresh effort towards an extreme. This is the third case
of reciprocal action, and a third extreme with which we meet (THIRD RECIPROCAL ACTION).
6. MODIFICATION IN THE REALITY.
Thus reasoning in the abstract, the mind cannot stop short of an extreme, because it has to deal with an
extreme, with a conflict of forces left to themselves, and obeying no other but their own inner laws. If we
should seek to deduce from the pure conception of War an absolute point for the aim which we shall propose
and for the means which we shall apply, this constant reciprocal action would involve us in extremes, which
would be nothing but a play of ideas produced by an almost invisible train of logical subtleties. If, adhering
closely to the absolute, we try to avoid all difficulties by a stroke of the pen, and insist with logical strictness
that in every case the extreme must be the object, and the utmost effort must be exerted in that direction, such
a stroke of the pen would be a mere paper law, not by any means adapted to the real world.
Even supposing this extreme tension of forces was an absolute which could easily be ascertained, still we
must admit that the human mind would hardly submit itself to this kind of logical chimera. There would be in
many cases an unnecessary waste of power, which would be in opposition to other principles of statecraft; an
effort of Will would be required disproportioned to the proposed object, which therefore it would be
impossible to realise, for the human will does not derive its impulse from logical subtleties.
But everything takes a different shape when we pass from abstractions to reality. In the former, everything
must be subject to optimism, and we must imagine the one side as well as the other striving after perfection
and even attaining it. Will this ever take place in reality? It will if,
(1) War becomes a completely isolated act, which arises suddenly, and is in no way connected with the
previous history of the combatant States.
(2) If it is limited to a single solution, or to several simultaneous solutions.
(3) If it contains within itself the solution perfect and complete, free from any reaction upon it, through a
calculation beforehand of the political situation which will follow from it.
7. WAR IS NEVER AN ISOLATED ACT.
With regard to the first point, neither of the two opponents is an abstract person to the other, not even as
regards that factor in the sum of resistance which does not depend on objective things, viz., the Will. This
On War
On War 16
Page No 19
Will is not an entirely unknown quantity; it indicates what it will be tomorrow by what it is today. War
does not spring up quite suddenly, it does not spread to the full in a moment; each of the two opponents can,
therefore, form an opinion of the other, in a great measure, from what he is and what he does, instead of
judging of him according to what he, strictly speaking, should be or should do. But, now, man with his
incomplete organisation is always below the line of absolute perfection, and thus these deficiencies, having
an influence on both sides, become a modifying principle.
8. WAR DOES NOT CONSIST OF A SINGLE INSTANTANEOUS BLOW.
The second point gives rise to the following considerations:
If War ended in a single solution, or a number of simultaneous ones, then naturally all the preparations for the
same would have a tendency to the extreme, for an omission could not in any way be repaired; the utmost,
then, that the world of reality could furnish as a guide for us would be the preparations of the enemy, as far as
they are known to us; all the rest would fall into the domain of the abstract. But if the result is made up from
several successive acts, then naturally that which precedes with all its phases may be taken as a measure for
that which will follow, and in this manner the world of reality again takes the place of the abstract, and thus
modifies the effort towards the extreme.
Yet every War would necessarily resolve itself into a single solution, or a sum of simultaneous results, if all
the means required for the struggle were raised at once, or could be at once raised; for as one adverse result
necessarily diminishes the means, then if all the means have been applied in the first, a second cannot
properly be supposed. All hostile acts which might follow would belong essentially to the first, and form, in
reality only its duration.
But we have already seen that even in the preparation for War the real world steps into the place of mere
abstract conceptiona material standard into the place of the hypotheses of an extreme: that therefore in that
way both parties, by the influence of the mutual reaction, remain below the line of extreme effort, and
therefore all forces are not at once brought forward.
It lies also in the nature of these forces and their application that they cannot all be brought into activity at the
same time. These forces are THE ARMIES ACTUALLY ON FOOT, THE COUNTRY, with its superficial
extent and its population, AND THE ALLIES.
In point of fact, the country, with its superficial area and the population, besides being the source of all
military force, constitutes in itself an integral part of the efficient quantities in War, providing either the
theatre of war or exercising a considerable influence on the same.
Now, it is possible to bring all the movable military forces of a country into operation at once, but not all
fortresses, rivers, mountains, people, short, not the whole country, unless it is so small that it may be
completely embraced by the first act of the War. Further, the cooperation of allies does not depend on the
Will of the belligerents; and from the nature of the political relations of states to each other, this cooperation
is frequently not afforded until after the War has commenced, or it may be increased to restore the balance of
power.
That this part of the means of resistance, which cannot at once be brought into activity, in many cases, is a
much greater part of the whole than might at first be supposed, and that it often restores the balance of power,
seriously affected by the great force of the first decision, will be more fully shown hereafter. Here it is
sufficient to show that a complete concentration of all available means in a moment of time is contradictory
to the nature of War.
On War
On War 17
Page No 20
Now this, in itself, furnishes no ground for relaxing our efforts to accumulate strength to gain the first result,
because an unfavourable issue is always a disadvantage to which no one would purposely expose himself,
and also because the first decision, although not the only one, still will have the more influence on subsequent
events, the greater it is in itself.
But the possibility of gaining a later result causes men to take refuge in that expectation, owing to the
repugnance in the human mind to making excessive efforts; and therefore forces are not concentrated and
measures are not taken for the first decision with that energy which would otherwise be used. Whatever one
belligerent omits from weakness, becomes to the other a real objective ground for limiting his own efforts,
and thus again, through this reciprocal action, extreme tendencies are brought down to efforts on a limited
scale.
9. THE RESULT IN WAR IS NEVER ABSOLUTE.
Lastly, even the final decision of a whole War is not always to be regarded as absolute. The conquered State
often sees in it only a passing evil, which may be repaired in after times by means of political combinations.
How much this must modify the degree of tension, and the vigour of the efforts made, is evident in itself.
10. THE PROBABILITIES OF REAL LIFE TAKE THE PLACE OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF THE
EXTREME AND THE ABSOLUTE.
In this manner, the whole act of War is removed from the rigorous law of forces exerted to the utmost. If the
extreme is no longer to be apprehended, and no longer to be sought for, it is left to the judgment to determine
the limits for the efforts to be made in place of it, and this can only be done on the data furnished by the facts
of the real world by the LAWS OF PROBABILITY. Once the belligerents are no longer mere conceptions,
but individual States and Governments, once the War is no longer an ideal, but a definite substantial
procedure, then the reality will furnish the data to compute the unknown quantities which are required to be
found.
From the character, the measures, the situation of the adversary, and the relations with which he is
surrounded, each side will draw conclusions by the law of probability as to the designs of the other, and act
accordingly.
11. THE POLITICAL OBJECT NOW REAPPEARS.
Here the question which we had laid aside forces itself again into consideration (see No. 2), viz., the political
object of the War. The law of the extreme, the view to disarm the adversary, to overthrow him, has hitherto to
a certain extent usurped the place of this end or object. Just as this law loses its force, the political must again
come forward. If the whole consideration is a calculation of probability based on definite persons and
relations, then the political object, being the original motive, must be an essential factor in the product. The
smaller the sacrifice we demand from our, the smaller, it may be expected, will be the means of resistance
which he will employ; but the smaller his preparation, the smaller will ours require to be. Further, the smaller
our political object, the less value shall we set upon it, and the more easily shall we be induced to give it up
altogether.
Thus, therefore, the political object, as the original motive of the War, will be the standard for determining
both the aim of the military force and also the amount of effort to be made. This it cannot be in itself, but it is
so in relation to both the belligerent States, because we are concerned with realities, not with mere
abstractions. One and the same political object may produce totally different effects upon different people, or
even upon the same people at different times; we can, therefore, only admit the political object as the
measure, by considering it in its effects upon those masses which it is to move, and consequently the nature
On War
On War 18
Page No 21
of those masses also comes into consideration. It is easy to see that thus the result may be very different
according as these masses are animated with a spirit which will infuse vigour into the action or otherwise. It
is quite possible for such a state of feeling to exist between two States that a very trifling political motive for
War may produce an effect quite disproportionatein fact, a perfect explosion.
This applies to the efforts which the political object will call forth in the two States, and to the aim which the
military action shall prescribe for itself. At times it may itself be that aim, as, for example, the conquest of a
province. At other times the political object itself is not suitable for the aim of military action; then such a
one must be chosen as will be an equivalent for it, and stand in its place as regards the conclusion of peace.
But also, in this, due attention to the peculiar character of the States concerned is always supposed. There are
circumstances in which the equivalent must be much greater than the political object, in order to secure the
latter. The political object will be so much the more the standard of aim and effort, and have more influence
in itself, the more the masses are indifferent, the less that any mutual feeling of hostility prevails in the two
States from other causes, and therefore there are cases where the political object almost alone will be
decisive.
If the aim of the military action is an equivalent for the political object, that action will in general diminish as
the political object diminishes, and in a greater degree the more the political object dominates. Thus it is
explained how, without any contradiction in itself, there may be Wars of all degrees of importance and
energy, from a War of extermination down to the mere use of an army of observation. This, however, leads to
a question of another kind which we have hereafter to develop and answer.
12. A SUSPENSION IN THE ACTION OF WAR UNEXPLAINED BY ANYTHING SAID AS YET.
However insignificant the political claims mutually advanced, however weak the means put forth, however
small the aim to which military action is directed, can this action be suspended even for a moment? This is a
question which penetrates deeply into the nature of the subject.
Every transaction requires for its accomplishment a certain time which we call its duration. This may be
longer or shorter, according as the person acting throws more or less despatch into his movements.
About this more or less we shall not trouble ourselves here. Each person acts in his own fashion; but the slow
person does not protract the thing because he wishes to spend more time about it, but because by his nature he
requires more time, and if he made more haste would not do the thing so well. This time, therefore, depends
on subjective causes, and belongs to the length, so called, of the action.
If we allow now to every action in War this, its length, then we must assume, at first sight at least, that any
expenditure of time beyond this length, that is, every suspension of hostile action, appears an absurdity; with
respect to this it must not be forgotten that we now speak not of the progress of one or other of the two
opponents, but of the general progress of the whole action of the War.
13. THERE IS ONLY ONE CAUSE WHICH CAN SUSPEND THE ACTION, AND THIS SEEMS TO BE
ONLY POSSIBLE ON ONE SIDE IN ANY CASE.
If two parties have armed themselves for strife, then a feeling of animosity must have moved them to it; as
long now as they continue armed, that is, do not come to terms of peace, this feeling must exist; and it can
only be brought to a standstill by either side by one single motive alone, which is, THAT HE WAITS FOR A
MORE FAVOURABLE MOMENT FOR ACTION. Now, at first sight, it appears that this motive can never
exist except on one side, because it, eo ipso, must be prejudicial to the other. If the one has an interest in
acting, then the other must have an interest in waiting.
On War
On War 19
Page No 22
A complete equilibrium of forces can never produce a suspension of action, for during this suspension he
who has the positive object (that is, the assailant) must continue progressing; for if we should imagine an
equilibrium in this way, that he who has the positive object, therefore the strongest motive, can at the same
time only command the lesser means, so that the equation is made up by the product of the motive and the
power, then we must say, if no alteration in this condition of equilibrium is to be expected, the two parties
must make peace; but if an alteration is to be expected, then it can only be favourable to one side, and
therefore the other has a manifest interest to act without delay. We see that the conception of an equilibrium
cannot explain a suspension of arms, but that it ends in the question of the EXPECTATION OF A MORE
FAVOURABLE MOMENT.
Let us suppose, therefore, that one of two States has a positive object, as, for instance, the conquest of one of
the enemy's provinceswhich is to be utilised in the settlement of peace. After this conquest, his political
object is accomplished, the necessity for action ceases, and for him a pause ensues. If the adversary is also
contented with this solution, he will make peace; if not, he must act. Now, if we suppose that in four weeks
he will be in a better condition to act, then he has sufficient grounds for putting off the time of action.
But from that moment the logical course for the enemy appears to be to act that he may not give the
conquered party THE DESIRED time. Of course, in this mode of reasoning a complete insight into the state
of circumstances on both sides is supposed.
14. THUS A CONTINUANCE OF ACTION WILL ENSUE WHICH WILL ADVANCE TOWARDS A
CLIMAX.
If this unbroken continuity of hostile operations really existed, the effect would be that everything would
again be driven towards the extreme; for, irrespective of the effect of such incessant activity in inflaming the
feelings, and infusing into the whole a greater degree of passion, a greater elementary force, there would also
follow from this continuance of action a stricter continuity, a closer connection between cause and effect, and
thus every single action would become of more importance, and consequently more replete with danger.
But we know that the course of action in War has seldom or never this unbroken continuity, and that there
have been many Wars in which action occupied by far the smallest portion of time employed, the whole of
the rest being consumed in inaction. It is impossible that this should be always an anomaly; suspension of
action in War must therefore be possible, that is no contradiction in itself. We now proceed to show how this
is.
15. HERE, THEREFORE, THE PRINCIPLE OF POLARITY IS BROUGHT INTO REQUISITION.
As we have supposed the interests of one Commander to be always antagonistic to those of the other, we
have assumed a true POLARITY. We reserve a fuller explanation of this for another chapter, merely making
the following observation on it at present.
The principle of polarity is only valid when it can be conceived in one and the same thing, where the positive
and its opposite the negative completely destroy each other. In a battle both sides strive to conquer; that is
true polarity, for the victory of the one side destroys that of the other. But when we speak of two different
things which have a common relation external to themselves, then it is not the things but their relations which
have the polarity.
16. ATTACK AND DEFENCE ARE THINGS DIFFERING IN KIND AND OF UNEQUAL FORCE.
POLARITY IS, THEREFORE, NOT APPLICABLE TO THEM.
If there was only one form of War, to wit, the attack of the enemy, therefore no defence; or, in other words, if
On War
On War 20
Page No 23
the attack was distinguished from the defence merely by the positive motive, which the one has and the other
has not, but the methods of each were precisely one and the same: then in this sort of fight every advantage
gained on the one side would be a corresponding disadvantage on the other, and true polarity would exist.
But action in War is divided into two forms, attack and defence, which, as we shall hereafter explain more
particularly, are very different and of unequal strength. Polarity therefore lies in that to which both bear a
relation, in the decision, but not in the attack or defence itself.
If the one Commander wishes the solution put off, the other must wish to hasten it, but only by the same form
of action. If it is A's interest not to attack his enemy at present, but four weeks hence, then it is B's interest to
be attacked, not four weeks hence, but at the present moment. This is the direct antagonism of interests, but it
by no means follows that it would be for B's interest to attack A at once. That is plainly something totally
different.
17. THE EFFECT OF POLARITY IS OFTEN DESTROYED BY THE SUPERIORITY OF THE DEFENCE
OVER THE ATTACK, AND THUS THE SUSPENSION OF ACTION IN WAR IS EXPLAINED.
If the form of defence is stronger than that of offence, as we shall hereafter show, the question arises, Is the
advantage of a deferred decision as great on the one side as the advantage of the defensive form on the other?
If it is not, then it cannot by its counterweight over balance the latter, and thus influence the progress of the
action of the War. We see, therefore, that the impulsive force existing in the polarity of interests may be lost
in the difference between the strength of the offensive and the defensive, and thereby become ineffectual.
If, therefore, that side for which the present is favourable, is too weak to be able to dispense with the
advantage of the defensive, he must put up with the unfavourable prospects which the future holds out; for it
may still be better to fight a defensive battle in the unpromising future than to assume the offensive or make
peace at present. Now, being convinced that the superiority of the defensive[*] (rightly understood) is very
great, and much greater than may appear at first sight, we conceive that the greater number of those periods
of inaction which occur in war are thus explained without involving any contradiction. The weaker the
motives to action are, the more will those motives be absorbed and neutralised by this difference between
attack and defence, the more frequently, therefore, will action in warfare be stopped, as indeed experience
teaches.
[*] It must be remembered that all this antedates by some years the introduction of longrange weapons.
18 A SECOND GROUND CONSISTS IN THE IMPERFECT KNOWLEDGE OF CIRCUMSTANCES.
But there is still another cause which may stop action in War, viz., an incomplete view of the situation. Each
Commander can only fully know his own position; that of his opponent can only be known to him by reports,
which are uncertain; he may, therefore, form a wrong judgment with respect to it upon data of this
description, and, in consequence of that error, he may suppose that the power of taking the initiative rests
with his adversary when it lies really with himself. This want of perfect insight might certainly just as often
occasion an untimely action as untimely inaction, and hence it would in itself no more contribute to delay
than to accelerate action in War. Still, it must always be regarded as one of the natural causes which may
bring action in War to a standstill without involving a contradiction. But if we reflect how much more we are
inclined and induced to estimate the power of our opponents too high than too low, because it lies in human
nature to do so, we shall admit that our imperfect insight into facts in general must contribute very much to
delay action in War, and to modify the application of the principles pending our conduct.
The possibility of a standstill brings into the action of War a new modification, inasmuch as it dilutes that
action with the element of time, checks the influence or sense of danger in its course, and increases the means
On War
On War 21
Page No 24
of reinstating a lost balance of force. The greater the tension of feelings from which the War springs, the
greater therefore the energy with which it is carried on, so much the shorter will be the periods of inaction; on
the other hand, the weaker the principle of warlike activity, the longer will be these periods: for powerful
motives increase the force of the will, and this, as we know, is always a factor in the product of force.
19. FREQUENT PERIODS OF INACTION IN WAR REMOVE IT FURTHER FROM THE ABSOLUTE,
AND MAKE IT STILL MORE A CALCULATION OF PROBABILITIES.
But the slower the action proceeds in War, the more frequent and longer the periods of inaction, so much the
more easily can an error be repaired; therefore, so much the bolder a General will be in his calculations, so
much the more readily will he keep them below the line of the absolute, and build everything upon
probabilities and conjecture. Thus, according as the course of the War is more or less slow, more or less time
will be allowed for that which the nature of a concrete case particularly requires, calculation of probability
based on given circumstances.
20. THEREFORE, THE ELEMENT OF CHANCE ONLY IS WANTING TO MAKE OF WAR A GAME,
AND IN THAT ELEMENT IT IS LEAST OF ALL DEFICIENT.
We see from the foregoing how much the objective nature of War makes it a calculation of probabilities; now
there is only one single element still wanting to make it a game, and that element it certainly is not without: it
is chance. There is no human affair which stands so constantly and so generally in close connection with
chance as War. But together with chance, the accidental, and along with it good luck, occupy a great place in
War.
21. WAR IS A GAME BOTH OBJECTIVELY AND SUBJECTIVELY.
If we now take a look at the subjective nature of War, that is to say, at those conditions under which it is
carried on, it will appear to us still more like a game. Primarily the element in which the operations of War
are carried on is danger; but which of all the moral qualities is the first in danger? COURAGE. Now certainly
courage is quite compatible with prudent calculation, but still they are things of quite a different kind,
essentially different qualities of the mind; on the other hand, daring reliance on good fortune, boldness,
rashness, are only expressions of courage, and all these propensities of the mind look for the fortuitous (or
accidental), because it is their element.
We see, therefore, how, from the commencement, the absolute, the mathematical as it is called, nowhere
finds any sure basis in the calculations in the Art of War; and that from the outset there is a play of
possibilities, probabilities, good and bad luck, which spreads about with all the coarse and fine threads of its
web, and makes War of all branches of human activity the most like a gambling game.
22. HOW THIS ACCORDS BEST WITH THE HUMAN MIND IN GENERAL.
Although our intellect always feels itself urged towards clearness and certainty, still our mind often feels
itself attracted by uncertainty. Instead of threading its way with the understanding along the narrow path of
philosophical investigations and logical conclusions, in order, almost unconscious of itself, to arrive in spaces
where it feels itself a stranger, and where it seems to part from all wellknown objects, it prefers to remain
with the imagination in the realms of chance and luck. Instead of living yonder on poor necessity, it revels
here in the wealth of possibilities; animated thereby, courage then takes wings to itself, and daring and danger
make the element into which it launches itself as a fearless swimmer plunges into the stream.
Shall theory leave it here, and move on, selfsatisfied with absolute conclusions and rules? Then it is of no
practical use. Theory must also take into account the human element; it must accord a place to courage, to
On War
On War 22
Page No 25
boldness, even to rashness. The Art of War has to deal with living and with moral forces, the consequence of
which is that it can never attain the absolute and positive. There is therefore everywhere a margin for the
accidental, and just as much in the greatest things as in the smallest. As there is room for this accidental on
the one hand, so on the other there must be courage and selfreliance in proportion to the room available. If
these qualities are forthcoming in a high degree, the margin left may likewise be great. Courage and
selfreliance are, therefore, principles quite essential to War; consequently, theory must only set up such
rules as allow ample scope for all degrees and varieties of these necessary and noblest of military virtues. In
daring there may still be wisdom, and prudence as well, only they are estimated by a different standard of
value.
23. WAR IS ALWAYS A SERIOUS MEANS FOR A SERIOUS OBJECT. ITS MORE PARTICULAR
DEFINITION.
Such is War; such the Commander who conducts it; such the theory which rules it. But War is no pastime; no
mere passion for venturing and winning; no work of a free enthusiasm: it is a serious means for a serious
object. All that appearance which it wears from the varying hues of fortune, all that it assimilates into itself of
the oscillations of passion, of courage, of imagination, of enthusiasm, are only particular properties of this
means.
The War of a communityof whole Nations, and particularly of civilised Nationsalways starts from a
political condition, and is called forth by a political motive. It is, therefore, a political act. Now if it was a
perfect, unrestrained, and absolute expression of force, as we had to deduct it from its mere conception, then
the moment it is called forth by policy it would step into the place of policy, and as something quite
independent of it would set it aside, and only follow its own laws, just as a mine at the moment of explosion
cannot be guided into any other direction than that which has been given to it by preparatory arrangements.
This is how the thing has really been viewed hitherto, whenever a want of harmony between policy and the
conduct of a War has led to theoretical distinctions of the kind. But it is not so, and the idea is radically false.
War in the real world, as we have already seen, is not an extreme thing which expends itself at one single
discharge; it is the operation of powers which do not develop themselves completely in the same manner and
in the same measure, but which at one time expand sufficiently to overcome the resistance opposed by inertia
or friction, while at another they are too weak to produce an effect; it is therefore, in a certain measure, a
pulsation of violent force more or less vehement, consequently making its discharges and exhausting its
powers more or less quicklyin other words, conducting more or less quickly to the aim, but always lasting
long enough to admit of influence being exerted on it in its course, so as to give it this or that direction, in
short, to be subject to the will of a guiding intelligence., if we reflect that War has its root in a political object,
then naturally this original motive which called it into existence should also continue the first and highest
consideration in its conduct. Still, the political object is no despotic lawgiver on that account; it must
accommodate itself to the nature of the means, and though changes in these means may involve modification
in the political objective, the latter always retains a prior right to consideration. Policy, therefore, is
interwoven with the whole action of War, and must exercise a continuous influence upon it, as far as the
nature of the forces liberated by it will permit.
24. WAR IS A MERE CONTINUATION OF POLICY BY OTHER MEANS.
We see, therefore, that War is not merely a political act, but also a real political instrument, a continuation of
political commerce, a carrying out of the same by other means. All beyond this which is strictly peculiar to
War relates merely to the peculiar nature of the means which it uses. That the tendencies and views of policy
shall not be incompatible with these means, the Art of War in general and the Commander in each particular
case may demand, and this claim is truly not a trifling one. But however powerfully this may react on
political views in particular cases, still it must always be regarded as only a modification of them; for the
political view is the object, War is the means, and the means must always include the object in our
On War
On War 23
Page No 26
conception.
25. DIVERSITY IN THE NATURE OF WARS.
The greater and the more powerful the motives of a War, the more it affects the whole existence of a people.
The more violent the excitement which precedes the War, by so much the nearer will the War approach to its
abstract form, so much the more will it be directed to the destruction of the enemy, so much the nearer will
the military and political ends coincide, so much the more purely military and less political the War appears
to be; but the weaker the motives and the tensions, so much the less will the natural direction of the military
element that is, forcebe coincident with the direction which the political element indicates; so much the
more must, therefore, the War become diverted from its natural direction, the political object diverge from the
aim of an ideal War, and the War appear to become political.
But, that the reader may not form any false conceptions, we must here observe that by this natural tendency
of War we only mean the philosophical, the strictly logical, and by no means the tendency of forces actually
engaged in conflict, by which would be supposed to be included all the emotions and passions of the
combatants. No doubt in some cases these also might be excited to such a degree as to be with difficulty
restrained and confined to the political road; but in most cases such a contradiction will not arise, because by
the existence of such strenuous exertions a great plan in harmony therewith would be implied. If the plan is
directed only upon a small object, then the impulses of feeling amongst the masses will be also so weak that
these masses will require to be stimulated rather than repressed.
26. THEY MAY ALL BE REGARDED AS POLITICAL ACTS.
Returning now to the main subject, although it is true that in one kind of War the political element seems
almost to disappear, whilst in another kind it occupies a very prominent place, we may still affirm that the
one is as political as the other; for if we regard the State policy as the intelligence of the personified State,
then amongst all the constellations in the political sky whose movements it has to compute, those must be
included which arise when the nature of its relations imposes the necessity of a great War. It is only if we
understand by policy not a true appreciation of affairs in general, but the conventional conception of a
cautious, subtle, also dishonest craftiness, averse from violence, that the latter kind of War may belong more
to policy than the first.
27. INFLUENCE OF THIS VIEW ON THE RIGHT UNDERSTANDING OF MILITARY HISTORY, AND
ON THE FOUNDATIONS OF THEORY.
We see, therefore, in the first place, that under all circumstances War is to be regarded not as an independent
thing, but as a political instrument; and it is only by taking this point of view that we can avoid finding
ourselves in opposition to all military history. This is the only means of unlocking the great book and making
it intelligible. Secondly, this view shows us how Wars must differ in character according to the nature of the
motives and circumstances from which they proceed.
Now, the first, the grandest, and most decisive act of judgment which the Statesman and General exercises is
rightly to understand in this respect the War in which he engages, not to take it for something, or to wish to
make of it something, which by the nature of its relations it is impossible for it to be. This is, therefore, the
first, the most comprehensive, of all strategical questions. We shall enter into this more fully in treating of the
plan of a War.
For the present we content ourselves with having brought the subject up to this point, and having thereby
fixed the chief point of view from which War and its theory are to be studied.
On War
On War 24
Page No 27
28. RESULT FOR THEORY.
War is, therefore, not only chameleonlike in character, because it changes its colour in some degree in each
particular case, but it is also, as a whole, in relation to the predominant tendencies which are in it, a
wonderful trinity, composed of the original violence of its elements, hatred and animosity, which may be
looked upon as blind instinct; of the play of probabilities and chance, which make it a free activity of the
soul; and of the subordinate nature of a political instrument, by which it belongs purely to the reason.
The first of these three phases concerns more the people the second, more the General and his Army; the
third, more the Government. The passions which break forth in War must already have a latent existence in
the peoples. The range which the display of courage and talents shall get in the realm of probabilities and of
chance depends on the particular characteristics of the General and his Army, but the political objects belong
to the Government alone.
These three tendencies, which appear like so many different lawgivers, are deeply rooted in the nature of the
subject, and at the same time variable in degree. A theory which would leave any one of them out of account,
or set up any arbitrary relation between them, would immediately become involved in such a contradiction
with the reality, that it might be regarded as destroyed at once by that alone.
The problem is, therefore, that theory shall keep itself poised in a manner between these three tendencies, as
between three points of attraction.
The way in which alone this difficult problem can be solved we shall examine in the book on the "Theory of
War." In every case the conception of War, as here defined, will be the first ray of light which shows us the
true foundation of theory, and which first separates the great masses and allows us to distinguish them from
one another.
CHAPTER II. END AND MEANS IN WAR
HAVING in the foregoing chapter ascertained the complicated and variable nature of War, we shall now
occupy ourselves in examining into the influence which this nature has upon the end and means in War.
If we ask, first of all, for the object upon which the whole effort of War is to be directed, in order that it may
suffice for the attainment of the political object, we shall find that it is just as variable as are the political
object and the particular circumstances of the War.
If, in the next place, we keep once more to the pure conception of War, then we must say that the political
object properly lies out of its province, for if War is an act of violence to compel the enemy to fulfil our will,
then in every case all depends on our overthrowing the enemy, that is, disarming him, and on that alone. This
object, developed from abstract conceptions, but which is also the one aimed at in a great many cases in
reality, we shall, in the first place, examine in this reality.
In connection with the plan of a campaign we shall hereafter examine more closely into the meaning of
disarming a nation, but here we must at once draw a distinction between three things, which, as three general
objects, comprise everything else within them. They are the MILITARY POWER, THE COUNTRY, and
THE WILL OF THE ENEMY.
The military power must be destroyed, that is, reduced to such a state as not to be able to prosecute the War.
On War
On War 25
Page No 28
This is the sense in which we wish to be understood hereafter, whenever we use the expression "destruction
of the enemy's military power."
The country must be conquered, for out of the country a new military force may be formed.
But even when both these things are done, still the War, that is, the hostile feeling and action of hostile
agencies, cannot be considered as at an end as long as the will of the enemy is not subdued also; that is, its
Government and its Allies must be forced into signing a peace, or the people into submission; for whilst we
are in full occupation of the country, the War may break out afresh, either in the interior or through assistance
given by Allies. No doubt, this may also take place after a peace, but that shows nothing more than that every
War does not carry in itself the elements for a complete decision and final settlement.
But even if this is the case, still with the conclusion of peace a number of sparks are always extinguished
which would have smouldered on quietly, and the excitement of the passions abates, because all those whose
minds are disposed to peace, of which in all nations and under all circumstances there is always a great
number, turn themselves away completely from the road to resistance. Whatever may take place
subsequently, we must always look upon the object as attained, and the business of War as ended, by a peace.
As protection of the country is the primary object for which the military force exists, therefore the natural
order is, that first of all this force should be destroyed, then the country subdued; and through the effect of
these two results, as well as the position we then hold, the enemy should be forced to make peace. Generally
the destruction of the enemy's force is done by degrees, and in just the same measure the conquest of the
country follows immediately. The two likewise usually react upon each other, because the loss of provinces
occasions a diminution of military force. But this order is by no means necessary, and on that account it also
does not always take place. The enemy's Army, before it is sensibly weakened, may retreat to the opposite
side of the country, or even quite outside of it. In this case, therefore, the greater part or the whole of the
country is conquered.
But this object of War in the abstract, this final means of attaining the political object in which all others are
combined, the DISARMING THE ENEMY, is rarely attained in practice and is not a condition necessary to
peace. Therefore it can in no wise be set up in theory as a law. There are innumerable instances of treaties in
which peace has been settled before either party could be looked upon as disarmed; indeed, even before the
balance of power had undergone any sensible alteration. Nay, further, if we look at the case in the concrete,
then we must say that in a whole class of cases, the idea of a complete defeat of the enemy would be a mere
imaginative flight, especially when the enemy is considerably superior.
The reason why the object deduced from the conception of War is not adapted in general to real War lies in
the difference between the two, which is discussed in the preceding chapter. If it was as pure theory gives it,
then a War between two States of very unequal military strength would appear an absurdity; therefore
impossible. At most, the inequality between the physical forces might be such that it could be balanced by the
moral forces, and that would not go far with our present social condition in Europe. Therefore, if we have
seen Wars take place between States of very unequal power, that has been the case because there is a wide
difference between War in reality and its original conception.
There are two considerations which as motives may practically take the place of inability to continue the
contest. The first is the improbability, the second is the excessive price, of success.
According to what we have seen in the foregoing chapter, War must always set itself free from the strict law
of logical necessity, and seek aid from the calculation of probabilities; and as this is so much the more the
case, the more the War has a bias that way, from the circumstances out of which it has arisenthe smaller its
motives are, and the excitement it has raisedso it is also conceivable how out of this calculation of
On War
On War 26
Page No 29
probabilities even motives to peace may arise. War does not, therefore, always require to be fought out until
one party is overthrown; and we may suppose that, when the motives and passions are slight, a weak
probability will suffice to move that side to which it is unfavourable to give way. Now, were the other side
convinced of this beforehand, it is natural that he would strive for this probability only, instead of first
wasting time and effort in the attempt to achieve the total destruction of the enemy's Army.
Still more general in its influence on the resolution to peace is the consideration of the expenditure of force
already made, and further required. As War is no act of blind passion, but is dominated by the political object,
therefore the value of that object determines the measure of the sacrifices by which it is to be purchased. This
will be the case, not only as regards extent, but also as regards duration. As soon, therefore, as the required
outlay becomes so great that the political object is no longer equal in value, the object must be given up, and
peace will be the result.
We see, therefore, that in Wars where one side cannot completely disarm the other, the motives to peace on
both sides will rise or fall on each side according to the probability of future success and the required outlay.
If these motives were equally strong on both sides, they would meet in the centre of their political difference.
Where they are strong on one side, they might be weak on the other. If their amount is only sufficient, peace
will follow, but naturally to the advantage of that side which has the weakest motive for its conclusion. We
purposely pass over here the difference which the POSITIVE and NEGATIVE character of the political end
must necessarily produce practically; for although that is, as we shall hereafter show, of the highest
importance, still we are obliged to keep here to a more general point of view, because the original political
views in the course of the War change very much, and at last may become totally different, JUST BECAUSE
THEY ARE DETERMINED BY RESULTS AND PROBABLE EVENTS.
Now comes the question how to influence the probability of success. In the first place, naturally by the same
means which we use when the object is the subjugation of the enemy, by the destruction of his military force
and the conquest of his provinces; but these two means are not exactly of the same import here as they would
be in reference to that object. If we attack the enemy's Army, it is a very different thing whether we intend to
follow up the first blow with a succession of others, until the whole force is destroyed, or whether we mean to
content ourselves with a victory to shake the enemy's feeling of security, to convince him of our superiority,
and to instil into him a feeling of apprehension about the future. If this is our object, we only go so far in the
destruction of his forces as is sufficient. In like manner, the conquest, of the enemy's provinces is quite a
different measure if the object is not the destruction of the enemy's Army. In the latter case the destruction of
the Army is the real effectual action, and the taking of the provinces only a consequence of it; to take them
before the Army had been defeated would always be looked upon only as a necessary evil. On the other hand,
if our views are not directed upon the complete destruction of the enemy's force, and if we are sure that the
enemy does not seek but fears to bring matters to a bloody decision, the taking possession of a weak or
defenceless province is an advantage in itself, and if this advantage is of sufficient importance to make the
enemy apprehensive about the general result, then it may also be regarded as a shorter road to peace.
But now we come upon a peculiar means of influencing the probability of the result without destroying the
enemy's Army, namely, upon the expeditions which have a direct connection with political views. If there are
any enterprises which are particularly likely to break up the enemy's alliances or make them inoperative, to
gain new alliances for ourselves, to raise political powers in our own favour, then it is easy to conceive how
much these may increase the probability of success, and become a shorter way towards our object than the
routing of the enemy's forces.
The second question is how to act upon the enemy's expenditure in strength, that is, to raise the price of
success.
The enemy's outlay in strength lies in the WEAR AND TEAR of his forces, consequently in the
On War
On War 27
Page No 30
DESTRUCTION of them on our part, and in the LOSS of PROVINCES, consequently the CONQUEST of
them by us.
Here, again, on account of the various significations of these means, so likewise it will be found that neither
of them will be identical in its signification in all cases if the objects are different. The smallness in general of
this difference must not cause us perplexity, for in reality the weakest motives, the finest shades of difference,
often decide in favour of this or that method of applying force. Our only business here is to show that, certain
conditions being supposed, the possibility of attaining our purpose in different ways is no contradiction,
absurdity, nor even error.
Besides these two means, there are three other peculiar ways of directly increasing the waste of the enemy's
force. The first is INVASION, that is THE OCCUPATION OF THE ENEMY'S TERRITORY, NOT WITH
A VIEW TO KEEPING IT, but in order to levy contributions upon it, or to devastate it.
The immediate object here is neither the conquest of the enemy's territory nor the defeat of his armed force,
but merely to DO HIM DAMAGE IN A GENERAL WAY. The second way is to select for the object of our
enterprises those points at which we can do the enemy most harm. Nothing is easier to conceive than two
different directions in which our force may be employed, the first of which is to be preferred if our object is
to defeat the enemy's Army, while the other is more advantageous if the defeat of the enemy is out of the
question. According to the usual mode of speaking, we should say that the first is primarily military, the other
more political. But if we take our view from the highest point, both are equally military, and neither the one
nor the other can be eligible unless it suits the circumstances of the case. The third, by far the most important,
from the great number of cases which it embraces, is the WEARING OUT of the enemy. We choose this
expression not only to explain our meaning in few words, but because it represents the thing exactly, and is
not so figurative as may at first appear. The idea of wearing out in a struggle amounts in practice to A
GRADUAL EXHAUSTION OF THE PHYSICAL POWERS AND OF THE WILL BY THE LONG
CONTINUANCE OF EXERTION.
Now, if we want to overcome the enemy by the duration of the contest, we must content ourselves with as
small objects as possible, for it is in the nature of the thing that a great end requires a greater expenditure of
force than a small one; but the smallest object that we can propose to ourselves is simple passive resistance,
that is a combat without any positive view. In this way, therefore, our means attain their greatest relative
value, and therefore the result is best secured. How far now can this negative mode of proceeding be carried?
Plainly not to absolute passivity, for mere endurance would not be fighting; and the defensive is an activity
by which so much of the enemy's power must be destroyed that he must give up his object. That alone is what
we aim at in each single act, and therein consists the negative nature of our object.
No doubt this negative object in its single act is not so effective as the positive object in the same direction
would be, supposing it successful; but there is this difference in its favour, that it succeeds more easily than
the positive, and therefore it holds out greater certainty of success; what is wanting in the efficacy of its
single act must be gained through time, that is, through the duration of the contest, and therefore this negative
intention, which constitutes the principle of the pure defensive, is also the natural means of overcoming the
enemy by the duration of the combat, that is of wearing him out.
Here lies the origin of that difference of OFFENSIVE and DEFENSIVE, the influence of which prevails
throughout the whole province of War. We cannot at present pursue this subject further than to observe that
from this negative intention are to be deduced all the advantages and all the stronger forms of combat which
are on the side of the Defensive, and in which that philosophicaldynamic law which exists between the
greatness and the certainty of success is realised. We shall resume the consideration of all this hereafter.
If then the negative purpose, that is the concentration of all the means into a state of pure resistance, affords a
On War
On War 28
Page No 31
superiority in the contest, and if this advantage is sufficient to BALANCE whatever superiority in numbers
the adversary may have, then the mere DURATION of the contest will suffice gradually to bring the loss of
force on the part of the adversary to a point at which the political object can no longer be an equivalent, a
point at which, therefore, he must give up the contest. We see then that this class of means, the wearing out of
the enemy, includes the great number of cases in which the weaker resists the stronger.
Frederick the Great, during the Seven Years' War, was never strong enough to overthrow the Austrian
monarchy; and if he had tried to do so after the fashion of Charles the Twelfth, he would inevitably have had
to succumb himself. But after his skilful application of the system of husbanding his resources had shown the
powers allied against him, through a seven years' struggle, that the actual expenditure of strength far
exceeded what they had at first anticipated, they made peace.
We see then that there are many ways to one's object in War; that the complete subjugation of the enemy is
not essential in every case; that the destruction of the enemy's military force, the conquest of the enemy's
provinces, the mere occupation of them, the mere invasion of thementerprises which are aimed directly at
political objectslastly, a passive expectation of the enemy's blow, are all means which, each in itself, may
be used to force the enemy's will according as the peculiar circumstances of the case lead us to expect more
from the one or the other. We could still add to these a whole category of shorter methods of gaining the end,
which might be called arguments ad hominem. What branch of human affairs is there in which these sparks
of individual spirit have not made their appearance, surmounting all formal considerations? And least of all
can they fail to appear in War, where the personal character of the combatants plays such an important part,
both in the cabinet and in the field. We limit ourselves to pointing this out, as it would be pedantry to attempt
to reduce such influences into classes. Including these, we may say that the number of possible ways of
reaching the object rises to infinity.
To avoid underestimating these different short roads to one's purpose, either estimating them only as rare
exceptions, or holding the difference which they cause in the conduct of War as insignificant, we must bear in
mind the diversity of political objects which may cause a War measure at a glance the distance which there
is between a death struggle for political existence and a War which a forced or tottering alliance makes a
matter of disagreeable duty. Between the two innumerable gradations occur in practice. If we reject one of
these gradations in theory, we might with equal right reject the whole, which would be tantamount to shutting
the real world completely out of sight.
These are the circumstances in general connected with the aim which we have to pursue in War; let us now
turn to the means.
There is only one single means, it is the FIGHT. However diversified this may be in form, however widely it
may differ from a rough vent of hatred and animosity in a handtohand encounter, whatever number of
things may introduce themselves which are not actual fighting, still it is always implied in the conception of
War that all the effects manifested have their roots in the combat.
That this must always be so in the greatest diversity and complication of the reality is proved in a very simple
manner. All that takes place in War takes place through armed forces, but where the forces of War, i.e.,
armed men, are applied, there the idea of fighting must of necessity be at the foundation.
All, therefore, that relates to forces of Warall that is connected with their creation, maintenance, and
application belongs to military activity.
Creation and maintenance are obviously only the means, whilst application is the object.
The contest in War is not a contest of individual against individual, but an organised whole, consisting of
On War
On War 29
Page No 32
manifold parts; in this great whole we may distinguish units of two kinds, the one determined by the subject,
the other by the object. In an Army the mass of combatants ranges itself always into an order of new units,
which again form members of a higher order. The combat of each of these members forms, therefore, also a
more or less distinct unit. Further, the motive of the fight; therefore its object forms its unit.
Now, to each of these units which we distinguish in the contest we attach the name of combat.
If the idea of combat lies at the foundation of every application of armed power, then also the application of
armed force in general is nothing more than the determining and arranging a certain number of combats.
Every activity in War, therefore, necessarily relates to the combat either directly or indirectly. The soldier is
levied, clothed, armed, exercised, he sleeps, eats, drinks, and marches, all MERELY TO FIGHT AT THE
RIGHT TIME AND PLACE.
If, therefore, all the threads of military activity terminate in the combat, we shall grasp them all when we
settle the order of the combats. Only from this order and its execution proceed the effects, never directly from
the conditions preceding them. Now, in the combat all the action is directed to the DESTRUCTION of the
enemy, or rather of HIS FIGHTING POWERS, for this lies in the conception of combat. The destruction of
the enemy's fighting power is, therefore, always the means to attain the object of the combat.
This object may likewise be the mere destruction of the enemy's armed force; but that is not by any means
necessary, and it may be something quite different. Whenever, for instance, as we have shown, the defeat of
the enemy is not the only means to attain the political object, whenever there are other objects which may be
pursued as the aim in a War, then it follows of itself that such other objects may become the object of
particular acts of Warfare, and therefore also the object of combats.
But even those combats which, as subordinate acts, are in the strict sense devoted to the destruction of the
enemy's fighting force need not have that destruction itself as their first object.
If we think of the manifold parts of a great armed force, of the number of circumstances which come into
activity when it is employed, then it is clear that the combat of such a force must also require a manifold
organisation, a subordinating of parts and formation. There may and must naturally arise for particular parts a
number of objects which are not themselves the destruction of the enemy's armed force, and which, while
they certainly contribute to increase that destruction, do so only in an indirect manner. If a battalion is
ordered to drive the enemy from a rising ground, or a bridge, then properly the occupation of any such
locality is the real object, the destruction of the enemy's armed force which takes place only the means or
secondary matter. If the enemy can be driven away merely by a demonstration, the object is attained all the
same; but this hill or bridge is, in point of fact, only required as a means of increasing the gross amount of
loss inflicted on the enemy's armed force. It is the case on the field of battle, much more must it be so on the
whole theatre of war, where not only one Army is opposed to another, but one State, one Nation, one whole
country to another. Here the number of possible relations, and consequently possible combinations, is much
greater, the diversity of measures increased, and by the gradation of objects, each subordinate to another the
first means employed is further apart from the ultimate object.
It is therefore for many reasons possible that the object of a combat is not the destruction of the enemy's
force, that is, of the force immediately opposed to us, but that this only appears as a means. But in all such
cases it is no longer a question of complete destruction, for the combat is here nothing else but a measure of
strengthhas in itself no value except only that of the present result, that is, of its decision.
But a measuring of strength may be effected in cases where the opposing sides are very unequal by a mere
comparative estimate. In such cases no fighting will take place, and the weaker will immediately give way.
On War
On War 30
Page No 33
If the object of a combat is not always the destruction of the enemy's forces therein engagedand if its
object can often be attained as well without the combat taking place at all, by merely making a resolve to
fight, and by the circumstances to which this resolution gives rise then that explains how a whole
campaign may be carried on with great activity without the actual combat playing any notable part in it.
That this may be so military history proves by a hundred examples. How many of those cases can be justified,
that is, without involving a contradiction and whether some of the celebrities who rose out of them would
stand criticism, we shall leave undecided, for all we have to do with the matter is to show the possibility of
such a course of events in War.
We have only one means in Warthe battle; but this means, by the infinite variety of paths in which it may
be applied, leads us into all the different ways which the multiplicity of objects allows of, so that we seem to
have gained nothing; but that is not the case, for from this unity of means proceeds a thread which assists the
study of the subject, as it runs through the whole web of military activity and holds it together.
But we have considered the destruction of the enemy's force as one of the objects which maybe pursued in
War, and left undecided what relative importance should be given to it amongst other objects. In certain cases
it will depend on circumstances, and as a general question we have left its value undetermined. We are once
more brought back upon it, and we shall be able to get an insight into the value which must necessarily be
accorded to it.
The combat is the single activity in War; in the combat the destruction of the enemy opposed to us is the
means to the end; it is so even when the combat does not actually take place, because in that case there lies at
the root of the decision the supposition at all events that this destruction is to be regarded as beyond doubt. It
follows, therefore, that the destruction of the enemy's military force is the foundationstone of all action in
War, the great support of all combinations, which rest upon it like the arch on its abutments. All action,
therefore, takes place on the supposition that if the solution by force of arms which lies at its foundation
should be realised, it will be a favourable one. The decision by arms is, for all operations in War, great and
small, what cash payment is in bill transactions. However remote from each other these relations, however
seldom the realisation may take place, still it can never entirely fail to occur.
If the decision by arms lies at the foundation of all combinations, then it follows that the enemy can defeat
each of them by gaining a victory on the field, not merely in the one on which our combination directly
depends, but also in any other encounter, if it is only important enough; for every important decision by arms
that is, destruction of the enemy's forcesreacts upon all preceding it, because, like a liquid element, they
tend to bring themselves to a level.
Thus, the destruction of the enemy's armed force appears, therefore, always as the superior and more
effectual means, to which all others must give way.
It is, however, only when there is a supposed equality in all other conditions that we can ascribe to the
destruction of the enemy's armed force the greater efficacy. It would, therefore, be a great mistake to draw the
conclusion that a blind dash must always gain the victory over skill and caution. An unskilful attack would
lead to the destruction of our own and not of the enemy's force, and therefore is not what is here meant. The
superior efficacy belongs not to the MEANS but to the END, and we are only comparing the effect of one
realised purpose with the other.
If we speak of the destruction of the enemy's armed force, we must expressly point out that nothing obliges us
to confine this idea to the mere physical force; on the contrary, the moral is necessarily implied as well,
because both in fact are interwoven with each other, even in the most minute details, and therefore cannot be
separated. But it is just in connection with the inevitable effect which has been referred to, of a great act of
On War
On War 31
Page No 34
destruction (a great victory) upon all other decisions by arms, that this moral element is most fluid, if we may
use that expression, and therefore distributes itself the most easily through all the parts.
Against the far superior worth which the destruction of the enemy's armed force has over all other means
stands the expense and risk of this means, and it is only to avoid these that any other means are taken. That
these must be costly stands to reason, for the waste of our own military forces must, ceteris paribus, always
be greater the more our aim is directed upon the destruction of the enemy's power.
The danger lies in this, that the greater efficacy which we seek recoils on ourselves, and therefore has worse
consequences in case we fail of success.
Other methods are, therefore, less costly when they succeed, less dangerous when they fail; but in this is
necessarily lodged the condition that they are only opposed to similar ones, that is, that the enemy acts on the
same principle; for if the enemy should choose the way of a great decision by arms, OUR MEANS MUST
ON THAT ACCOUNT BE CHANGED AGAINST OUR WILL, IN ORDER TO CORRESPOND WITH
HIS. Then all depends on the issue of the act of destruction; but of course it is evident that, ceteris paribus, in
this act we must be at a disadvantage in all respects because our views and our means had been directed in
part upon other objects, which is not the case with the enemy. Two different objects of which one is not
partthe other exclude each other, and therefore a force which may be applicable for the one may not serve for
the other. If, therefore, one of two belligerents is determined to seek the great decision by arms, then he has a
high probability of success, as soon as he is certain his opponent will not take that way, but follows a
different object; and every one who sets before himself any such other aim only does so in a reasonable
manner, provided he acts on the supposition that his adversary has as little intention as he has of resorting to
the great decision by arms.
But what we have here said of another direction of views and forces relates only to other POSITIVE
OBJECTS, which we may propose to ourselves in War, besides the destruction of the enemy's force, not by
any means to the pure defensive, which may be adopted with a view thereby to exhaust the enemy's forces. In
the pure defensive the positive object is wanting, and therefore, while on the defensive, our forces cannot at
the same time be directed on other objects; they can only be employed to defeat the intentions of the enemy.
We have now to consider the opposite of the destruction of the enemy's armed force, that is to say, the
preservation of our own. These two efforts always go together, as they mutually act and react on each other;
they are integral parts of one and the same view, and we have only to ascertain what effect is produced when
one or the other has the predominance. The endeavour to destroy the enemy's force has a positive object, and
leads to positive results, of which the final aim is the conquest of the enemy. The preservation of our own
forces has a negative object, leads therefore to the defeat of the enemy's intentions, that is to pure resistance,
of which the final aim can be nothing more than to prolong the duration of the contest, so that the enemy shall
exhaust himself in it.
The effort with a positive object calls into existence the act of destruction; the effort with the negative object
awaits it.
How far this state of expectation should and may be carried we shall enter into more particularly in the theory
of attack and defence, at the origin of which we again find ourselves. Here we shall content ourselves with
saying that the awaiting must be no absolute endurance, and that in the action bound up with it the destruction
of the enemy's armed force engaged in this conflict may be the aim just as well as anything else. It would
therefore be a great error in the fundamental idea to suppose that the consequence of the negative course is
that we are precluded from choosing the destruction of the enemy's military force as our object, and must
prefer a bloodless solution. The advantage which the negative effort gives may certainly lead to that, but only
at the risk of its not being the most advisable method, as that question is dependent on totally different
On War
On War 32
Page No 35
conditions, resting not with ourselves but with our opponents. This other bloodless way cannot, therefore, be
looked upon at all as the natural means of satisfying our great anxiety to spare our forces; on the contrary,
when circumstances are not favourable, it would be the means of completely ruining them. Very many
Generals have fallen into this error, and been ruined by it. The only necessary effect resulting from the
superiority of the negative effort is the delay of the decision, so that the party acting takes refuge in that way,
as it were, in the expectation of the decisive moment. The consequence of that is generally THE
POSTPONEMENT OF THE ACTION as much as possible in time, and also in space, in so far as space is in
connection with it. If the moment has arrived in which this can no longer be done without ruinous
disadvantage, then the advantage of the negative must be considered as exhausted, and then comes forward
unchanged the effort for the destruction of the enemy's force, which was kept back by a counterpoise, but
never discarded.
We have seen, therefore, in the foregoing reflections, that there are many ways to the aim, that is, to the
attainment of the political object; but that the only means is the combat, and that consequently everything is
subject to a supreme law: which is the DECISION BY ARMS; that where this is really demanded by one, it
is a redress which cannot be refused by the other; that, therefore, a belligerent who takes any other way must
make sure that his opponent will not take this means of redress, or his cause may be lost in that supreme
court; hence therefore the destruction of the enemy's armed force, amongst all the objects which can be
pursued in War, appears always as the one which overrules all others.
What may be achieved by combinations of another kind in War we shall only learn in the sequel, and
naturally only by degrees. We content ourselves here with acknowledging in general their possibility, as
something pointing to the difference between the reality and the conception, and to the influence of particular
circumstances. But we could not avoid showing at once that the BLOODY SOLUTION OF THE CRISIS, the
effort for the destruction of the enemy's force, is the firstborn son of War. If when political objects are
unimportant, motives weak, the excitement of forces small, a cautious commander tries in all kinds of ways,
without great crises and bloody solutions, to twist himself skilfully into a peace through the characteristic
weaknesses of his enemy in the field and in the Cabinet, we have no right to find fault with him, if the
premises on which he acts are well founded and justified by success; still we must require him to remember
that he only travels on forbidden tracks, where the God of War may surprise him; that he ought always to
keep his eye on the enemy, in order that he may not have to defend himself with a dress rapier if the enemy
takes up a sharp sword.
The consequences of the nature of War, how ends and means act in it, how in the modifications of reality it
deviates sometimes more, sometimes less, from its strict original conception, fluctuating backwards and
forwards, yet always remaining under that strict conception as under a supreme law: all this we must retain
before us, and bear constantly in mind in the consideration of each of the succeeding subjects, if we would
rightly comprehend their true relations and proper importance, and not become involved incessantly in the
most glaring contradictions with the reality, and at last with our own selves.
CHAPTER III. THE GENIUS FOR WAR
EVERY special calling in life, if it is to be followed with success, requires peculiar qualifications of
understanding and soul. Where these are of a high order, and manifest themselves by extraordinary
achievements, the mind to which they belong is termed GENIUS.
We know very well that this word is used in many significations which are very different both in extent and
nature, and that with many of these significations it is a very difficult task to define the essence of Genius; but
On War
On War 33
Page No 36
as we neither profess to be philosopher nor grammarian, we must be allowed to keep to the meaning usual in
ordinary language, and to understand by "genius" a very high mental capacity for certain employments.
We wish to stop for a moment over this faculty and dignity of the mind, in order to vindicate its title, and to
explain more fully the meaning of the conception. But we shall not dwell on that (genius) which has obtained
its title through a very great talent, on genius properly so called, that is a conception which has no defined
limits. What we have to do is to bring under consideration every common tendency of the powers of the mind
and soul towards the business of War, the whole of which common tendencies we may look upon as the
ESSENCE OF MILITARY GENIUS. We say "common," for just therein consists military genius, that it is
not one single quality bearing upon War, as, for instance, courage, while other qualities of mind and soul are
wanting or have a direction which is unserviceable for War, but that it is AN HARMONIOUS
ASSOCIATION OF POWERS, in which one or other may predominate, but none must be in opposition.
If every combatant required to be more or less endowed with military genius, then our armies would be very
weak; for as it implies a peculiar bent of the intelligent powers, therefore it can only rarely be found where
the mental powers of a people are called into requisition and trained in many different ways. The fewer the
employments followed by a Nation, the more that of arms predominates, so much the more prevalent will
military genius also be found. But this merely applies to its prevalence, by no means to its degree, for that
depends on the general state of intellectual culture in the country. If we look at a wild, warlike race, then we
find a warlike spirit in individuals much more common than in a civilised people; for in the former almost
every warrior possesses it, whilst in the civilised whole, masses are only carried away by it from necessity,
never by inclination. But amongst uncivilised people we never find a really great General, and very seldom
what we can properly call a military genius, because that requires a development of the intelligent powers
which cannot be found in an uncivilised state. That a civilised people may also have a warlike tendency and
development is a matter of course; and the more this is general, the more frequently also will military spirit
be found in individuals in their armies. Now as this coincides in such case with the higher degree of
civilisation, therefore from such nations have issued forth the most brilliant military exploits, as the Romans
and the French have exemplified. The greatest names in these and in all other nations that have been
renowned in War belong strictly to epochs of higher culture.
From this we may infer how great a share the intelligent powers have in superior military genius. We shall
now look more closely into this point.
War is the province of danger, and therefore courage above all things is the first quality of a warrior.
Courage is of two kinds: first, physical courage, or courage in presence of danger to the person; and next,
moral courage, or courage before responsibility, whether it be before the judgmentseat of external authority,
or of the inner power, the conscience. We only speak here of the first.
Courage before danger to the person, again, is of two kinds. First, it may be indifference to danger, whether
proceeding from the organism of the individual, contempt of death, or habit: in any of these cases it is to be
regarded as a permanent condition.
Secondly, courage may proceed from positive motives, such as personal pride, patriotism, enthusiasm of any
kind. In this case courage is not so much a normal condition as an impulse.
We may conceive that the two kinds act differently. The first kind is more certain, because it has become a
second nature, never forsakes the man; the second often leads him farther. In the first there is more of
firmness, in the second, of boldness. The first leaves the judgment cooler, the second raises its power at
times, but often bewilders it. The two combined make up the most perfect kind of courage.
On War
On War 34
Page No 37
War is the province of physical exertion and suffering. In order not to be completely overcome by them, a
certain strength of body and mind is required, which, either natural or acquired, produces indifference to
them. With these qualifications, under the guidance of simply a sound understanding, a man is at once a
proper instrument for War; and these are the qualifications so generally to be met with amongst wild and
halfcivilised tribes. If we go further in the demands which War makes on it, then we find the powers of the
understanding predominating. War is the province of uncertainty: threefourths of those things upon which
action in War must be calculated, are hidden more or less in the clouds of great uncertainty. Here, then, above
all a fine and penetrating mind is called for, to search out the truth by the tact of its judgment.
An average intellect may, at one time, perhaps hit upon this truth by accident; an extraordinary courage, at
another, may compensate for the want of this tact; but in the majority of cases the average result will always
bring to light the deficient understanding.
War is the province of chance. In no sphere of human activity is such a margin to be left for this intruder,
because none is so much in constant contact with him on all sides. He increases the uncertainty of every
circumstance, and deranges the course of events.
From this uncertainty of all intelligence and suppositions, this continual interposition of chance, the actor in
War constantly finds things different from his expectations; and this cannot fail to have an influence on his
plans, or at least on the presumptions connected with these plans. If this influence is so great as to render the
predetermined plan completely nugatory, then, as a rule, a new one must be substituted in its place; but at
the moment the necessary data are often wanting for this, because in the course of action circumstances press
for immediate decision, and allow no time to look about for fresh data, often not enough for mature
consideration.
But it more often happens that the correction of one premise, and the knowledge of chance events which have
arisen, are not sufficient to overthrow our plans completely, but only suffice to produce hesitation. Our
knowledge of circumstances has increased, but our uncertainty, instead of having diminished, has only
increased. The reason of this is, that we do not gain all our experience at once, but by degrees; thus our
determinations continue to be assailed incessantly by fresh experi ence; and the mind, if we may use the
expression, must always be "under arms."
Now, if it is to get safely through this perpetual conflict with the unexpected, two qualities are indispensable:
in the first place an intellect which, even in the midst of this intense obscurity, is not without some traces of
inner light, which lead to the truth, and then the courage to follow this faint light. The first is figuratively
expressed by the French phrase coup d'oeil. The other is resolution. As the battle is the feature in War to
which attention was originally chiefly directed, and as time and space are important elements in it, more
particularly when cavalry with their rapid decisions were the chief arm, the idea of rapid and correct decision
related in the first instance to the estimation of these two elements, and to denote the idea an expression was
adopted which actually only points to a correct judgment by eye. Many teachers of the Art of War then gave
this limited signification as the definition of coup d'oeil. But it is undeniable that all able decisions formed in
the moment of action soon came to be understood by the expression, as, for instance, the hitting upon the
right point of attack, It is, therefore, not only the physical, but more frequently the mental eye which is meant
in coup d'oeil. Naturally, the expression, like the thing, is always more in its place in the field of tactics: still,
it must not be wanting in strategy, inasmuch as in it rapid decisions are often necessary. If we strip this
conception of that which the expression has given it of the overfigurative and restricted, then it amounts
simply to the rapid discovery of a truth which to the ordinary mind is either not visible at all or only becomes
so after long examination and reflection.
Resolution is an act of courage in single instances, and if it becomes a characteristic trait, it is a habit of the
mind. But here we do not mean courage in face of bodily danger, but in face of responsibility, therefore, to a
On War
On War 35
Page No 38
certain extent against moral danger. This has been often called courage d'esprit, on the ground that it springs
from the understanding; nevertheless, it is no act of the understanding on that account; it is an act of feeling.
Mere intelligence is still not courage, for we often see the cleverest people devoid of resolution. The mind
must, therefore, first awaken the feeling of courage, and then be guided and supported by it, because in
momentary emergencies the man is swayed more by his feelings than his thoughts.
We have assigned to resolution the office of removing the torments of doubt, and the dangers of delay, when
there are no sufficient motives for guidance. Through the unscrupulous use of language which is prevalent,
this term is often applied to the mere propensity to daring, to bravery, boldness, or temerity. But, when there
are SUFFICIENT MOTIVES in the man, let them be objective or subjective, true or false, we have no right
to speak of his resolution; for, when we do so, we put ourselves in his place, and we throw into the scale
doubts which did not exist with him.
Here there is no question of anything but of strength and weakness. We are not pedantic enough to dispute
with the use of language about this little misapplication, our observation is only intended to remove wrong
objections.
This resolution now, which overcomes the state of doubting, can only be called forth by the intellect, and, in
fact, by a peculiar tendency of the same. We maintain that the mere union of a superior understanding and the
necessary feelings are not sufficient to make up resolution. There are persons who possess the keenest
perception for the most difficult problems, who are also not fearful of responsibility, and yet in cases of
difficulty cannot come to a resolution. Their courage and their sagacity operate independently of each other,
do not give each other a hand, and on that account do not produce resolution as a result. The forerunner of
resolution is an act of the mind making evident the necessity of venturing, and thus influencing the will. This
quite peculiar direction of the mind, which conquers every other fear in man by the fear of wavering or
doubting, is what makes up resolution in strong minds; therefore, in our opinion, men who have little
intelligence can never be resolute. They may act without hesitation under perplexing circumstances, but then
they act without reflection. Now, of course, when a man acts without reflection he cannot be at variance with
himself by doubts, and such a mode of action may now and then lead to the right point; but we say now as
before, it is the average result which indicates the existence of military genius. Should our assertion appear
extraordinary to any one, because he knows many a resolute hussar officer who is no deep thinker, we must
remind him that the question here is about a peculiar direction of the mind, and not about great thinking
powers.
We believe, therefore, that resolution is indebted to a special direction of the mind for its existence, a
direction which belongs to a strong head rather than to a brilliant one. In corroboration of this genealogy of
resolution we may add that there have been many instances of men who have shown the greatest resolution in
an inferior rank, and have lost it in a higher position. While, on the one hand, they are obliged to resolve, on
the other they see the dangers of a wrong decision, and as they are surrounded with things new to them, their
understanding loses its original force, and they become only the more timid the more they become aware of
the danger of the irresolution into which they have fallen, and the more they have formerly been in the habit
of acting on the spur of the moment.
From the coup d'oeil and resolution we are naturally to speak of its kindred quality, PRESENCE OF MIND,
which in a region of the unexpected like War must act a great part, for it is indeed nothing but a great
conquest over the unexpected. As we admire presence of mind in a pithy answer to anything said
unexpectedly, so we admire it in a ready expedient on sudden danger. Neither the answer nor the expedient
need be in themselves extraordinary, if they only hit the point; for that which as the result of mature reflection
would be nothing unusual, therefore insignificant in its impression on us, may as an instantaneous act of the
mind produce a pleasing impression. The expression "presence of mind" certainly denotes very fitly the
readiness and rapidity of the help rendered by the mind.
On War
On War 36
Page No 39
Whether this noble quality of a man is to be ascribed more to the peculiarity of his mind or to the equanimity
of his feelings, depends on the nature of the case, although neither of the two can be entirely wanting. A
telling repartee bespeaks rather a ready wit, a ready expedient on sudden danger implies more particularly a
wellbalanced mind.
If we take a general view of the four elements composing the atmosphere in which War moves, of DANGER,
PHYSICAL EFFORT, UNCERTAINTY, and CHANCE, it is easy to conceive that a great force of mind and
understanding is requisite to be able to make way with safety and success amongst such opposing elements, a
force which, according to the different modifications arising out of circumstances, we find termed by military
writers and annalists as ENERGY, FIRMNESS, STAUNCHNESS, STRENGTH OF MIND AND
CHARACTER. All these manifestations of the heroic nature might be regarded as one and the same power of
volition, modified according to circumstances; but nearly related as these things are to each other, still they
are not one and the same, and it is desirable for us to distinguish here a little more closely at least the action
of the powers of the soul in relation to them.
In the first place, to make the conception clear, it is essential to observe that the weight, burden, resistance, or
whatever it may be called, by which that force of the soul in the General is brought to light, is only in a very
small measure the enemy's activity, the enemy's resistance, the enemy's action directly. The enemy's activity
only affects the General directly in the first place in relation to his person, without disturbing his action as
Commander. If the enemy, instead of two hours, resists for four, the Commander instead of two hours is four
hours in danger; this is a quantity which plainly diminishes the higher the rank of the Commander. What is it
for one in the post of CommanderinChief? It is nothing.
Secondly, although the opposition offered by the enemy has a direct effect on the Commander through the
loss of means arising from prolonged resistance, and the responsibility connected with that loss, and his force
of will is first tested and called forth by these anxious considerations, still we maintain that this is not the
heaviest burden by far which he has to bear, because he has only himself to settle with. All the other effects
of the enemy's resistance act directly upon the combatants under his command, and through them react upon
him.
As long as his men full of good courage fight with zeal and spirit, it is seldom necessary for the Chief to
show great energy of purpose in the pursuit of his object. But as soon as difficulties ariseand that must
always happen when great results are at stakethen things no longer move on of themselves like a
welloiled machine, the machine itself then begins to offer resistance, and to overcome this the Commander
must have a great force of will. By this resistance we must not exactly suppose disobedience and murmurs,
although these are frequent enough with particular individuals; it is the whole feeling of the dissolution of all
physical and moral power, it is the heartrending sight of the bloody sacrifice which the Commander has to
contend with in himself, and then in all others who directly or indirectly transfer to him their impressions,
feelings, anxieties, and desires. As the forces in one individual after another become prostrated, and can no
longer be excited and supported by an effort of his own will, the whole inertia of the mass gradually rests its
weight on the Will of the Commander: by the spark in his breast, by the light of his spirit, the spark of
purpose, the light of hope, must be kindled afresh in others: in so far only as he is equal to this, he stands
above the masses and continues to be their master; whenever that influence ceases, and his own spirit is no
longer strong enough to revive the spirit of all others, the masses drawing him down with them sink into the
lower region of animal nature, which shrinks from danger and knows not shame. These are the weights which
the courage and intelligent faculties of the military Commander have to overcome if he is to make his name
illustrious. They increase with the masses, and therefore, if the forces in question are to continue equal to the
burden, they must rise in proportion to the height of the station.
Energy in action expresses the strength of the motive through which the action is excited, let the motive have
its origin in a conviction of the understanding, or in an impulse. But the latter can hardly ever be wanting
On War
On War 37
Page No 40
where great force is to show itself.
Of all the noble feelings which fill the human heart in the exciting tumult of battle, none, we must admit, are
so powerful and constant as the soul's thirst for honour and renown, which the German language treats so
unfairly and tends to depreciate by the unworthy associations in the words Ehrgeiz (greed of honour) and
Ruhmsucht (hankering after glory). No doubt it is just in War that the abuse of these proud aspirations of the
soul must bring upon the human race the most shocking outrages, but by their origin they are certainly to be
counted amongst the noblest feelings which belong to human nature, and in War they are the vivifying
principle which gives the enormous body a spirit. Although other feelings may be more general in their
influence, and many of themsuch as love of country, fanaticism, revenge, enthusiasm of every kindmay
seem to stand higher, the thirst for honour and renown still remains indispensable. Those other feelings may
rouse the great masses in general, and excite them more powerfully, but they do not give the Leader a desire
to will more than others, which is an essential requisite in his position if he is to make himself distinguished
in it. They do not, like a thirst for honour, make the military act specially the property of the Leader, which he
strives to turn to the best account; where he ploughs with toil, sows with care, that he may reap plentifully. It
is through these aspirations we have been speaking of in Commanders, from the highest to the lowest, this
sort of energy, this spirit of emulation, these incentives, that the action of armies is chiefly animated and
made successful. And now as to that which specially concerns the head of all, we ask, Has there ever been a
great Commander destitute of the love of honour, or is such a character even conceivable?
FIRMNESS denotes the resistance of the will in relation to the force of a single blow, STAUNCHNESS in
relation to a continuance of blows. Close as is the analogy between the two, and often as the one is used in
place of the other, still there is a notable difference between them which cannot be mistaken, inasmuch as
firmness against a single powerful impression may have its root in the mere strength of a feeling, but
staunchness must be supported rather by the understanding, for the greater the duration of an action the more
systematic deliberation is connected with it, and from this staunchness partly derives its power.
If we now turn to STRENGTH OF MIND OR SOUL, then the first question is, What are we to understand
thereby?
Plainly it is not vehement expressions of feeling, nor easily excited passions, for that would be contrary to all
the usage of language, but the power of listening to reason in the midst of the most intense excitement, in the
storm of the most violent passions. Should this power depend on strength of understanding alone? We doubt
it. The fact that there are men of the greatest intellect who cannot command themselves certainly proves
nothing to the contrary, for we might say that it perhaps requires an understanding of a powerful rather than
of a comprehensive nature; but we believe we shall be nearer the truth if we assume that the power of
submitting oneself to the control of the understanding, even in moments of the most violent excitement of the
feelings, that power which we call SELFCOMMAND, has its root in the heart itself. It is, in point of fact,
another feeling, which in strong minds balances the excited passions without destroying them; and it is only
through this equilibrium that the mastery of the understanding is secured. This counterpoise is nothing but a
sense of the dignity of man, that noblest pride, that deeply seated desire of the soul always to act as a being
endued with understanding and reason. We may therefore say that a strong mind is one which does not lose
its balance even under the most violent excitement.
If we cast a glance at the variety to be observed in the human character in respect to feeling, we find, first,
some people who have very little excitability, who are called phlegmatic or indolent.
Secondly, some very excitable, but whose feelings still never overstep certain limits, and who are therefore
known as men full of feeling, but soberminded.
Thirdly, those who are very easily roused, whose feelings blaze up quickly and violently like gunpowder, but
On War
On War 38
Page No 41
do not last.
Fourthly, and lastly, those who cannot be moved by slight causes, and who generally are not to be roused
suddenly, but only gradually; but whose feelings become very powerful and are much more lasting. These are
men with strong passions, lying deep and latent.
This difference of character lies probably close on the confines of the physical powers which move the
human organism, and belongs to that amphibious organisation which we call the nervous system, which
appears to be partly material, partly spiritual. With our weak philosophy, we shall not proceed further in this
mysterious field. But it is important for us to spend a moment over the effects which these different natures
have on, action in War, and to see how far a great strength of mind is to be expected from them.
Indolent men cannot easily be thrown out of their equanimity, but we cannot certainly say there is strength of
mind where there is a want of all manifestation of power.
At the same time, it is not to be denied that such men have a certain peculiar aptitude for War, on account of
their constant equanimity. They often want the positive motive to action, impulse, and consequently activity,
but they are not apt to throw things into disorder.
The peculiarity of the second class is that they are easily excited to act on trifling grounds, but in great
matters they are easily overwhelmed. Men of this kind show great activity in helping an unfortunate
individual, but by the distress of a whole Nation they are only inclined to despond, not roused to action.
Such people are not deficient in either activity or equanimity in War; but they will never accomplish anything
great unless a great intellectual force furnishes the motive, and it is very seldom that a strong, independent
mind is combined with such a character.
Excitable, inflammable feelings are in themselves little suited for practical life, and therefore they are not
very fit for War. They have certainly the advantage of strong impulses, but that cannot long sustain them. At
the same time, if the excitability in such men takes the direction of courage, or a sense of honour, they may
often be very useful in inferior positions in War, because the action in War over which commanders in
inferior positions have control is generally of shorter duration. Here one courageous resolution, one
effervescence of the forces of the soul, will often suffice. A brave attack, a soulstirring hurrah, is the work
of a few moments, whilst a brave contest on the battlefield is the work of a day, and a campaign the work of
a year.
Owing to the rapid movement of their feelings, it is doubly difficult for men of this description to preserve
equilibrium of the mind; therefore they frequently lose head, and that is the worst phase in their nature as
respects the conduct of War. But it would be contrary to experience to maintain that very excitable spirits can
never preserve a steady equilibriumthat is to say, that they cannot do so even under the strongest
excitement. Why should they not have the sentiment of selfrespect, for, as a rule, they are men of a noble
nature? This feeling is seldom wanting in them, but it has not time to produce an effect. After an outburst
they suffer most from a feeling of inward humiliation. If through education, selfobservance, and experience
of life, they have learned, sooner or later, the means of being on their guard, so that at the moment of
powerful excitement they are conscious betimes of the counteracting force within their own breasts, then
even such men may have great strength of mind.
Lastly, those who are difficult to move, but on that account susceptible of very deep feelings, men who stand
in the same relation to the preceding as red heat to a flame, are the best adapted by means of their Titanic
strength to roll away the enormous masses by which we may figuratively represent the difficulties which
beset command in War. The effect of their feelings is like the movement of a great body, slower, but more
On War
On War 39
Page No 42
irresistible.
Although such men are not so likely to be suddenly surprised by their feelings and carried away so as to be
afterwards ashamed of themselves, like the preceding, still it would be contrary to experience to believe that
they can never lose their equanimity, or be overcome by blind passion; on the contrary, this must always
happen whenever the noble pride of selfcontrol is wanting, or as often as it has not sufficient weight. We see
examples of this most frequently in men of noble minds belonging to savage nations, where the low degree of
mental cultivation favours always the dominance of the passions. But even amongst the most civilised classes
in civilised States, life is full of examples of this kindof men carried away by the violence of their
passions, like the poacher of old chained to the stag in the forest.
We therefore say once more a strong mind is not one that is merely susceptible of strong excitement, but one
which can maintain its serenity under the most powerful excitement, so that, in spite of the storm in the
breast, the perception and judgment can act with perfect freedom, like the needle of the compass in the
stormtossed ship.
By the term STRENGTH OF CHARACTER, or simply CHARACTER, is denoted tenacity of conviction, let
it be the result of our own or of others' views, and whether they are principles, opinions, momentary
inspirations, or any kind of emanations of the understanding; but this kind of firmness certainly cannot
manifest itself if the views themselves are subject to frequent change. This frequent change need not be the
consequence of external influences; it may proceed from the continuous activity of our own mind, in which
case it indicates a characteristic unsteadiness of mind. Evidently we should not say of a man who changes his
views every moment, however much the motives of change may originate with himself, that he has character.
Only those men, therefore, can be said to have this quality whose conviction is very constant, either because
it is deeply rooted and clear in itself, little liable to alteration, or because, as in the case of indolent men, there
is a want of mental activity, and therefore a want of motives to change; or lastly, because an explicit act of the
will, derived from an imperative maxim of the understanding, refuses any change of opinion up to a certain
point.
Now in War, owing to the many and powerful impressions to which the mind is exposed, and in the
uncertainty of all knowledge and of all science, more things occur to distract a man from the road he has
entered upon, to make him doubt himself and others, than in any other human activity.
The harrowing sight of danger and suffering easily leads to the feelings gaining ascendency over the
conviction of the understanding; and in the twilight which surrounds everything a deep clear view is so
difficult that a change of opinion is more conceivable and more pardonable. It is, at all times, only conjecture
or guesses at truth which we have to act upon. This is why differences of opinion are nowhere so great as in
War, and the stream of impressions acting counter to one's own convictions never ceases to flow. Even the
greatest impassibility of mind is hardly proof against them, because the impressions are powerful in their
nature, and always act at the same time upon the feelings.
When the discernment is clear and deep, none but general principles and views of action from a high
standpoint can be the result; and on these principles the opinion in each particular case immediately under
consideration lies, as it were, at anchor. But to keep to these results of bygone reflection, in opposition to the
stream of opinions and phenomena which the present brings with it, is just the difficulty. Between the
particular case and the principle there is often a wide space which cannot always be traversed on a visible
chain of conclusions, and where a certain faith in self is necessary and a certain amount of scepticism is
serviceable. Here often nothing else will help us but an imperative maxim which, independent of reflection, at
once controls it: that maxim is, in all doubtful cases to adhere to the first opinion, and not to give it up until a
clear conviction forces us to do so. We must firmly believe in the superior authority of welltried maxims,
and under the dazzling influence of momentary events not forget that their value is of an inferior stamp. By
On War
On War 40
Page No 43
this preference which in doubtful cases we give to first convictions, by adherence to the same our actions
acquire that stability and consistency which make up what is called character.
It is easy to see how essential a wellbalanced mind is to strength of character; therefore men of strong minds
generally have a great deal of character.
Force of character leads us to a spurious variety of it OBSTINACY.
It is often very difficult in concrete cases to say where the one ends and the other begins; on the other hand, it
does not seem difficult to determine the difference in idea.
Obstinacy is no fault of the understanding; we use the term as denoting a resistance against our better
judgment, and it would be inconsistent to charge that to the understanding, as the understanding is the power
of judgment. Obstinacy is A FAULT OF THE FEELINGS or heart. This inflexibility of will, this impatience
of contradiction, have their origin only in a particular kind of egotism, which sets above every other pleasure
that of governing both self and others by its own mind alone. We should call it a kind of vanity, were it not
decidedly something better. Vanity is satisfied with mere show, but obstinacy rests upon the enjoyment of the
thing.
We say, therefore, force of character degenerates into obstinacy whenever the resistance to opposing
judgments proceeds not from better convictions or a reliance upon a trustworthy maxim, but from a feeling of
opposition. If this definition, as we have already admitted, is of little assistance practically, still it will prevent
obstinacy from being considered merely force of character intensified, whilst it is something essentially
differentsomething which certainly lies close to it and is cognate to it, but is at the same time so little an
intensification of it that there are very obstinate men who from want of understanding have very little force of
character.
Having in these high attributes of a great military Commander made ourselves acquainted with those qualities
in which heart and head cooperate, we now come to a speciality of military activity which perhaps may be
looked upon as the most marked if it is not the most important, and which only makes a demand on the power
of the mind without regard to the forces of feelings. It is the connection which exists between War and
country or ground.
This connection is, in the first place, a permanent condition of War, for it is impossible to imagine our
organised Armies effecting any operation otherwise than in some given space; it is, secondly, of the most
decisive importance, because it modifies, at times completely alters, the action of all forces; thirdly, while on
the one hand it often concerns the most minute features of locality, on the other it may apply to immense
tracts of country.
In this manner a great peculiarity is given to the effect of this connection of War with country and ground. If
we think of other occupations of man which have a relation to these objects, on horticulture, agriculture, on
building houses and hydraulic works, on mining, on the chase, and forestry, they are all confined within very
limited spaces which may be soon explored with sufficient exactness. But the Commander in War must
commit the business he has in hand to a corresponding space which his eye cannot survey, which the keenest
zeal cannot always explore, and with which, owing to the constant changes taking place, he can also seldom
become properly acquainted. Certainly the enemy generally is in the same situation; still, in the first place,
the difficulty, although common to both, is not the less a difficulty, and he who by talent and practice
overcomes it will have a great advantage on his side; secondly, this equality of the difficulty on both sides is
merely an abstract supposition which is rarely realised in the particular case, as one of the two opponents (the
defensive) usually knows much more of the locality than his adversary.
On War
On War 41
Page No 44
This very peculiar difficulty must be overcome by a natural mental gift of a special kind which is known by
thetoo restrictedterm of Orisinn sense of locality. It is the power of quickly forming a correct
geometrical idea of any portion of country, and consequently of being able to find one's place in it exactly at
any time. This is plainly an act of the imagination. The perception no doubt is formed partly by means of the
physical eye, partly by the mind, which fills up what is wanting with ideas derived from knowledge and
experience, and out of the fragments visible to the physical eye forms a whole; but that this whole should
present itself vividly to the reason, should become a picture, a mentally drawn map, that this picture should
be fixed, that the details should never again separate themselvesall that can only be effected by the mental
faculty which we call imagination. If some great poet or painter should feel hurt that we require from his
goddess such an office; if he shrugs his shoulders at the notion that a sharp gamekeeper must necessarily
excel in imagination, we readily grant that we only speak here of imagination in a limited sense, of its service
in a really menial capacity. But, however slight this service, still it must be the work of that natural gift, for if
that gift is wanting, it would be difficult to imagine things plainly in all the completeness of the visible. That
a good memory is a great assistance we freely allow, but whether memory is to be considered as an
independent faculty of the mind in this case, or whether it is just that power of imagination which here fixes
these things better on the memory, we leave undecided, as in many respects it seems difficult upon the whole
to conceive these two mental powers apart from each other.
That practice and mental acuteness have much to do with it is not to be denied. Puysegur, the celebrated
QuartermasterGeneral of the famous Luxemburg, used to say that he had very little confidence in himself in
this respect at first, because if he had to fetch the parole from a distance he always lost his way.
It is natural that scope for the exercise of this talent should increase along with rank. If the hussar and
rifleman in command of a patrol must know well all the highways and byways, and if for that a few marks, a
few limited powers of observation, are sufficient, the Chief of an Army must make himself familiar with the
general geographical features of a province and of a country; must always have vividly before his eyes the
direction of the roads, rivers, and hills, without at the same time being able to dispense with the narrower
"sense of locality" Orisinn. No doubt, information of various kinds as to objects in general, maps, books,
memoirs, and for details the assistance of his Staff, are a great help to him; but it is nevertheless certain that if
he has himself a talent for forming an ideal picture of a country quickly and distinctly, it lends to his action an
easier and firmer step, saves him from a certain mental helplessness, and makes him less dependent on others.
If this talent then is to be ascribed to imagination, it is also almost the only service which military activity
requires from that erratic goddess, whose influence is more hurtful than useful in other respects.
We think we have now passed in review those manifestations of the powers of mind and soul which military
activity requires from human nature. Everywhere intellect appears as an essential cooperative force; and
thus we can understand how the work of War, although so plain and simple in its effects, can never be
conducted with distinguished success by people without distinguished powers of the understanding.
When we have reached this view, then we need no longer look upon such a natural idea as the turning an
enemy's position, which has been done a thousand times, and a hundred other similar conceptions, as the
result of a great effort of genius.
Certainly one is accustomed to regard the plain honest soldier as the very opposite of the man of reflection,
full of inventions and ideas, or of the brilliant spirit shining in the ornaments of refined education of every
kind. This antithesis is also by no means devoid of truth; but it does not show that the efficiency of the soldier
consists only in his courage, and that there is no particular energy and capacity of the brain required in
addition to make a man merely what is called a true soldier. We must again repeat that there is nothing more
common than to hear of men losing their energy on being raised to a higher position, to which they do not
feel themselves equal; but we must also remind our readers that we are speaking of preeminent services, of
On War
On War 42
Page No 45
such as give renown in the branch of activity to which they belong. Each grade of command in War therefore
forms its own stratum of requisite capacity of fame and honour.
An immense space lies between a Generalthat is, one at the head of a whole War, or of a theatre of
Warand his Second in Command, for the simple reason that the latter is in more immediate subordination
to a superior authority and supervision, consequently is restricted to a more limited sphere of independent
thought. This is why common opinion sees no room for the exercise of high talent except in high places, and
looks upon an ordinary capacity as sufficient for all beneath: this is why people are rather inclined to look
upon a subordinate General grown grey in the service, and in whom constant discharge of routine duties has
produced a decided poverty of mind, as a man of failing intellect, and, with all respect for his bravery, to
laugh at his simplicity. It is not our object to gain for these brave men a better lotthat would contribute
nothing to their efficiency, and little to their happiness; we only wish to represent things as they are, and to
expose the error of believing that a mere bravo without intellect can make himself distinguished in War.
As we consider distinguished talents requisite for those who are to attain distinction, even in inferior
positions, it naturally follows that we think highly of those who fill with renown the place of Second in
Command of an Army; and their seeming simplicity of character as compared with a polyhistor, with ready
men of business, or with councillors of state, must not lead us astray as to the superior nature of their
intellectual activity. It happens sometimes that men import the fame gained in an inferior position into a
higher one, without in reality deserving it in the new position; and then if they are not much employed, and
therefore not much exposed to the risk of showing their weak points, the judgment does not distinguish very
exactly what degree of fame is really due to them; and thus such men are often the occasion of too low an
estimate being formed of the characteristics required to shine in certain situations.
For each station, from the lowest upwards, to render distinguished services in War, there must be a particular
genius. But the title of genius, history and the judgment of posterity only confer, in general, on those minds
which have shone in the highest rank, that of Commanders inChief. The reason is that here, in point of
fact, the demand on the reasoning and intellectual powers generally is much greater.
To conduct a whole War, or its great acts, which we call campaigns, to a successful termination, there must
be an intimate knowledge of State policy in its higher relations. The conduct of the War and the policy of the
State here coincide, and the General becomes at the same time the Statesman.
We do not give Charles XII. the name of a great genius, because he could not make the power of his sword
subservient to a higher judgment and philosophycould not attain by it to a glorious object. We do not give
that title to Henry IV. (of France), because he did not live long enough to set at rest the relations of different
States by his military activity, and to occupy himself in that higher field where noble feelings and a
chivalrous disposition have less to do in mastering the enemy than in overcoming internal dissension.
In order that the reader may appreciate all that must be comprehended and judged of correctly at a glance by
a General, we refer to the first chapter. We say the General becomes a Statesman, but he must not cease to be
the General. He takes into view all the relations of the State on the one hand; on the other, he must know
exactly what he can do with the means at his disposal.
As the diversity, and undefined limits, of all the circumstances bring a great number of factors into
consideration in War, as the most of these factors can only be estimated according to probability, therefore, if
the Chief of an Army does not bring to bear upon them a mind with an intuitive perception of the truth, a
confusion of ideas and views must take place, in the midst of which the judgment will become bewildered. In
this sense, Buonaparte was right when he said that many of the questions which come before a General for
decision would make problems for a mathematical calculation not unworthy of the powers of Newton or
Euler.
On War
On War 43
Page No 46
What is here required from the higher powers of the mind is a sense of unity, and a judgment raised to such a
compass as to give the mind an extraordinary faculty of vision which in its range allays and sets aside a
thousand dim notions which an ordinary understanding could only bring to light with great effort, and over
which it would exhaust itself. But this higher activity of the mind, this glance of genius, would still not
become matter of history if the qualities of temperament and character of which we have treated did not give
it their support.
Truth alone is but a weak motive of action with men, and hence there is always a great difference between
knowing and action, between science and art. The man receives the strongest impulse to action through the
feelings, and the most powerful succour, if we may use the expression, through those faculties of heart and
mind which we have considered under the terms of resolution, firmness, perseverance, and force of character.
If, however, this elevated condition of heart and mind in the General did not manifest itself in the general
effects resulting from it, and could only be accepted on trust and faith, then it would rarely become matter of
history.
All that becomes known of the course of events in War is usually very simple, and has a great sameness in
appearance; no one on the mere relation of such events perceives the difficulties connected with them which
had to be overcome. It is only now and again, in the memoirs of Generals or of those in their confidence, or
by reason of some special historical inquiry directed to a particular circumstance, that a portion of the many
threads composing the whole web is brought to light. The reflections, mental doubts, and conflicts which
precede the execution of great acts are purposely concealed because they affect political interests, or the
recollection of them is accidentally lost because they have been looked upon as mere scaffolding which had
to be removed on the completion of the building.
If, now, in conclusion, without venturing upon a closer definition of the higher powers of the soul, we should
admit a distinction in the intelligent faculties themselves according to the common ideas established by
language, and ask ourselves what kind of mind comes closest to military genius, then a look at the subject as
well as at experience will tell us that searching rather than inventive minds, comprehensive minds rather than
such as have a special bent, cool rather than fiery heads, are those to which in time of War we should prefer
to trust the welfare of our women and children, the honour and the safety of our fatherland.
CHAPTER IV. OF DANGER IN WAR
USUALLY before we have learnt what danger really is, we form an idea of it which is rather attractive than
repulsive. In the intoxication of enthusiasm, to fall upon the enemy at the chargewho cares then about
bullets and men falling? To throw oneself, blinded by excitement for a moment, against cold death, uncertain
whether we or another shall escape him, and all this close to the golden gate of victory, close to the rich fruit
which ambition thirsts forcan this be difficult? It will not be difficult, and still less will it appear so. But
such moments, which, however, are not the work of a single pulsebeat, as is supposed, but rather like
doctors' draughts, must be taken diluted and spoilt by mixture with timesuch moments, we say, are but
few.
Let us accompany the novice to the battlefield. As we approach, the thunder of the cannon becoming plainer
and plainer is soon followed by the howling of shot, which attracts the attention of the inexperienced. Balls
begin to strike the ground close to us, before and behind. We hasten to the hill where stands the General and
his numerous Staff. Here the close striking of the cannon balls and the bursting of shells is so frequent that
the seriousness of life makes itself visible through the youthful picture of imagination. Suddenly some one
On War
On War 44
Page No 47
known to us fallsa shell strikes amongst the crowd and causes some involuntary movementswe begin to
feel that we are no longer perfectly at ease and collected; even the bravest is at least to some degree confused.
Now, a step farther into the battle which is raging before us like a scene in a theatre, we get to the nearest
General of Division; here ball follows ball, and the noise of our own guns increases the confusion. From the
General of Division to the Brigadier. He, a man of acknowledged bravery, keeps carefully behind a rising
ground, a house, or a treea sure sign of increasing danger. Grape rattles on the roofs of the houses and in
the fields; cannon balls howl over us, and plough the air in all directions, and soon there is a frequent
whistling of musket balls. A step farther towards the troops, to that sturdy infantry which for hours has
maintained its firmness under this heavy fire; here the air is filled with the hissing of balls which announce
their proximity by a short sharp noise as they pass within an inch of the ear, the head, or the breast.
To add to all this, compassion strikes the beating heart with pity at the sight of the maimed and fallen. The
young soldier cannot reach any of these different strata of danger without feeling that the light of reason does
not move here in the same medium, that it is not refracted in the same manner as in speculative
contemplation. Indeed, he must be a very extraordinary man who, under these impressions for the first time,
does not lose the power of making any instantaneous decisions. It is true that habit soon blunts such
impressions; in half in hour we begin to be more or less indifferent to all that is going on around us: but an
ordinary character never attains to complete coolness and the natural elasticity of mind; and so we perceive
that here again ordinary qualities will not sufficea thing which gains truth, the wider the sphere of activity
which is to be filled. Enthusiastic, stoical, natural bravery, great ambition, or also long familiarity with
dangermuch of all this there must be if all the effects produced in this resistant medium are not to fall far
short of that which in the student's chamber may appear only the ordinary standard.
Danger in War belongs to its friction; a correct idea of its influence is necessary for truth of perception, and
therefore it is brought under notice here.
CHAPTER V. OF BODILY EXERTION IN WAR
IF no one were allowed to pass an opinion on the events of War, except at a moment when he is benumbed by
frost, sinking from heat and thirst, or dying with hunger and fatigue, we should certainly have fewer
judgments correct *objectively; but they would be so, SUBJECTIVELY, at least; that is, they would contain
in themselves the exact relation between the person giving the judgment and the object. We can perceive this
by observing how modestly subdued, even spiritless and desponding, is the opinion passed upon the results of
untoward events by those who have been eyewitnesses, but especially if they have been parties concerned.
This is, according to our view, a criterion of the influence which bodily fatigue exercises, and of the
allowance to be made for it in matters of opinion.
Amongst the many things in War for which no tariff can be fixed, bodily effort may be specially reckoned.
Provided there is no waste, it is a coefficient of all the forces, and no one can tell exactly to what extent it
may be carried. But what is remarkable is, that just as only a strong arm enables the archer to stretch the
bowstring to the utmost extent, so also in War it is only by means of a great directing spirit that we can
expect the full power latent in the troops to be developed. For it is one thing if an Army, in consequence of
great misfortunes, surrounded with danger, falls all to pieces like a wall that has been thrown down, and can
only find safety in the utmost exertion of its bodily strength; it is another thing entirely when a victorious
Army, drawn on by proud feelings only, is conducted at the will of its Chief. The same effort which in the
one case might at most excite our pity must in the other call forth our admiration, because it is much more
difficult to sustain.
On War
On War 45
Page No 48
By this comes to light for the inexperienced eye one of those things which put fetters in the dark, as it were,
on the action of the mind, and wear out in secret the powers of the soul.
Although here the question is strictly only respecting the extreme effort required by a Commander from his
Army, by a leader from his followers, therefore of the spirit to demand it and of the art of getting it, still the
personal physical exertion of Generals and of the Chief Commander must not be overlooked. Having brought
the analysis of War conscientiously up to this point, we could not but take account also of the weight of this
small remaining residue.
We have spoken here of bodily effort, chiefly because, like danger, it belongs to the fundamental causes of
friction, and because its indefinite quantity makes it like an elastic body, the friction of which is well known
to be difficult to calculate.
To check the abuse of these considerations, of such a survey of things which aggravate the difficulties of
War, nature has given our judgment a guide in our sensibilities. just as an individual cannot with advantage
refer to his personal deficiencies if he is insulted and illtreated, but may well do so if he has successfully
repelled the affront, or has fully revenged it, so no Commander or Army will lessen the impression of a
disgraceful defeat by depicting the danger, the distress, the exertions, things which would immensely enhance
the glory of a victory. Thus our feeling, which after all is only a higher kind of judgment, forbids us to do
what seems an act of justice to which our judgment would be inclined.
CHAPTER VI. INFORMATION IN WAR
By the word "information" we denote all the knowledge which we have of the enemy and his country;
therefore, in fact, the foundation of all our ideas and actions. Let us just consider the nature of this
foundation, its want of trustworthiness, its changefulness, and we shall soon feel what a dangerous edifice
War is, how easily it may fall to pieces and bury us in its ruins. For although it is a maxim in all books that
we should trust only certain information, that we must be always suspicious, that is only a miserable book
comfort, belonging to that description of knowledge in which writers of systems and compendiums take
refuge for want of anything better to say.
Great part of the information obtained in War is contradictory, a still greater part is false, and by far the
greatest part is of a doubtful character. What is required of an officer is a certain power of discrimination,
which only knowledge of men and things and good judgment can give. The law of probability must be his
guide. This is not a trifling difficulty even in respect of the first plans, which can be formed in the chamber
outside the real sphere of War, but it is enormously increased when in the thick of War itself one report
follows hard upon the heels of another; it is then fortunate if these reports in contradicting each other show a
certain balance of probability, and thus themselves call forth a scrutiny. It is much worse for the
inexperienced when accident does not render him this service, but one report supports another, confirms it,
magnifies it, finishes off the picture with fresh touches of colour, until necessity in urgent haste forces from
us a resolution which will soon be discovered to be folly, all those reports having been lies, exaggerations,
errors, In a few words, most reports are false, and the timidity of men acts as a multiplier of lies and untruths.
As a general rule, every one is more inclined to lend credence to the bad than the good. Every one is inclined
to magnify the bad in some measure, and although the alarms which are thus propagated like the waves of the
sea subside into themselves, still, like them, without any apparent cause they rise again. Firm in reliance on
his own better convictions, the Chief must stand like a rock against which the sea breaks its fury in vain. The
role is not easy; he who is not by nature of a buoyant disposition, or trained by experience in War, and
matured in judgment, may let it be his rule to do violence to his own natural conviction by inclining from the
On War
On War 46
Page No 49
side of fear to that of hope; only by that means will he be able to preserve his balance. This difficulty of
seeing things correctly, which is one of the greatest sources of friction in War, makes things appear quite
different from what was expected. The impression of the senses is stronger than the force of the ideas
resulting from methodical reflection, and this goes so far that no important undertaking was ever yet carried
out without the Commander having to subdue new doubts in himself at the time of commencing the
execution of his work. Ordinary men who follow the suggestions of others become, therefore, generally
undecided on the spot; they think that they have found circumstances different from what they had expected,
and this view gains strength by their again yielding to the suggestions of others. But even the man who has
made his own plans, when he comes to see things with his own eyes will often think he has done wrong. Firm
reliance on self must make him proof against the seeming pressure of the moment; his first conviction will in
the end prove true, when the foreground scenery which fate has pushed on to the stage of War, with its
accompaniments of terrific objects, is drawn aside and the horizon extended. This is one of the great chasms
which separate CONCEPTION from EXECUTION.
CHAPTER VII. FRICTION IN WAR
As long as we have no personal knowledge of War, we cannot conceive where those difficulties lie of which
so much is said, and what that genius and those extraordinary mental powers required in a General have
really to do. All appears so simple, all the requisite branches of knowledge appear so plain, all the
combinations so unimportant, that in comparison with them the easiest problem in higher mathematics
impresses us with a certain scientific dignity. But if we have seen War, all becomes intelligible; and still, after
all, it is extremely difficult to describe what it is which brings about this change, to specify this invisible and
completely efficient factor.
Everything is very simple in War, but the simplest thing is difficult. These difficulties accumulate and
produce a friction which no man can imagine exactly who has not seen War, Suppose now a traveller, who
towards evening expects to accomplish the two stages at the end of his day's journey, four or five leagues,
with posthorses, on the high roadit is nothing. He arrives now at the last station but one, finds no horses,
or very bad ones; then a hilly country, bad roads; it is a dark night, and he is glad when, after a great deal of
trouble, he reaches the next station, and finds there some miserable accommodation. So in War, through the
influence of an infinity of petty circumstances, which cannot properly be described on paper, things
disappoint us, and we fall short of the mark. A powerful iron will overcomes this friction; it crushes the
obstacles, but certainly the machine along with them. We shall often meet with this result. Like an obelisk
towards which the principal streets of a town converge, the strong will of a proud spirit stands prominent and
commanding in the middle of the Art of War.
Friction is the only conception which in a general way corresponds to that which distinguishes real War from
War on paper. The military machine, the Army and all belonging to it, is in fact simple, and appears on this
account easy to manage. But let us reflect that no part of it is in one piece, that it is composed entirely of
individuals, each of which keeps up its own friction in all directions. Theoretically all sounds very well: the
commander of a battalion is responsible for the execution of the order given; and as the battalion by its
discipline is glued together into one piece, and the chief must be a man of acknowledged zeal, the beam turns
on an iron pin with little friction. But it is not so in reality, and all that is exaggerated and false in such a
conception manifests itself at once in War. The battalion always remains composed of a number of men, of
whom, if chance so wills, the most insignificant is able to occasion delay and even irregularity. The danger
which War brings with it, the bodily exertions which it requires, augment this evil so much that they may be
regarded as the greatest causes of it.
On War
On War 47
Page No 50
This enormous friction, which is not concentrated, as in mechanics, at a few points, is therefore everywhere
brought into contact with chance, and thus incidents take place upon which it was impossible to calculate,
their chief origin being chance. As an instance of one such chancethe weather. Here the fog prevents the
enemy from being discovered in time, a battery from firing at the right moment, a report from reaching the
General; there the rain prevents a battalion from arriving at the right time, because instead of for three it had
to march perhaps eight hours; the cavalry from charging effectively because it is stuck fast in heavy ground.
These are only a few incidents of detail by way of elucidation, that the reader may be able to follow the
author, for whole volumes might be written on these difficulties. To avoid this, and still to give a clear
conception of the host of small difficulties to be contended with in War, we might go on heaping up
illustrations, if we were not afraid of being tiresome. But those who have already comprehended us will
permit us to add a few more.
Activity in War is movement in a resistant medium. Just as a man immersed in water is unable to perform
with ease and regularity the most natural and simplest movement, that of walking, so in War, with ordinary
powers, one cannot keep even the line of mediocrity. This is the reason that the correct theorist is like a
swimming master, who teaches on dry land movements which are required in the water, which must appear
grotesque and ludicrous to those who forget about the water. This is also why theorists, who have never
plunged in themselves, or who cannot deduce any generalities from their experience, are unpractical and even
absurd, because they only teach what every one knowshow to walk.
Further, every War is rich in particular facts, while at the same time each is an unexplored sea, full of rocks
which the General may have a suspicion of, but which he has never seen with his eye, and round which,
moreover, he must steer in the night. If a contrary wind also springs up, that is, if any great accidental event
declares itself adverse to him, then the most consummate skill, presence of mind, and energy are required,
whilst to those who only look on from a distance all seems to proceed with the utmost ease. The knowledge
of this friction is a chief part of that so often talked of, experience in War, which is required in a good
General. Certainly he is not the best General in whose mind it assumes the greatest dimensions, who is the
most overawed by it (this includes that class of overanxious Generals, of whom there are so many amongst
the experienced); but a General must be aware of it that he may overcome it, where that is possible, and that
he may not expect a degree of precision in results which is impossible on account of this very friction.
Besides, it can never be learnt theoretically; and if it could, there would still be wanting that experience of
judgment which is called tact, and which is always more necessary in a field full of innumerable small and
diversified objects than in great and decisive cases, when one's own judgment may be aided by consultation
with others. Just as the man of the world, through tact of judgment which has become habit, speaks, acts, and
moves only as suits the occasion, so the officer experienced in War will always, in great and small matters, at
every pulsation of War as we may say, decide and determine suitably to the occasion. Through this
experience and practice the idea comes to his mind of itself that so and so will not suit. And thus he will not
easily place himself in a position by which he is compromised, which, if it often occurs in War, shakes all the
foundations of confidence and becomes extremely dangerous.
It is therefore this friction, or what is so termed here, which makes that which appears easy in War difficult in
reality. As we proceed, we shall often meet with this subject again, and it will hereafter become plain that
besides experience and a strong will, there are still many other rare qualities of the mind required to make a
man a consummate General.
On War
On War 48
Page No 51
CHAPTER VIII. CONCLUDING REMARKS, BOOK I
THOSE things which as elements meet together in the atmosphere of War and make it a resistant medium for
every activity we have designated under the terms danger, bodily effort (exertion), information, and friction.
In their impedient effects they may therefore be comprehended again in the collective notion of a general
friction. Now is there, then, no kind of oil which is capable of diminishing this friction? Only one, and that
one is not always available at the will of the Commander or his Army. It is the habituation of an Army to
War.
Habit gives strength to the body in great exertion, to the mind in great danger, to the judgment against first
impressions. By it a valuable circumspection is generally gained throughout every rank, from the hussar and
rifleman up to the General of Division, which facilitates the work of the Chief Commander.
As the human eye in a dark room dilates its pupil, draws in the little light that there is, partially distinguishes
objects by degrees, and at last knows them quite well, so it is in War with the experienced soldier, whilst the
novice is only met by pitch dark night.
Habituation to War no General can give his Army at once, and the camps of manoeuvre (peace exercises)
furnish but a weak substitute for it, weak in comparison with real experience in War, but not weak in relation
to other Armies in which the training is limited to mere mechanical exercises of routine. So to regulate the
exercises in peace time as to include some of these causes of friction, that the judgment, circumspection, even
resolution of the separate leaders may be brought into exercise, is of much greater consequence than those
believe who do not know the thing by experience. It is of immense importance that the soldier, high or low,
whatever rank he has, should not have to encounter in War those things which, when seen for the first time,
set him in astonishment and perplexity; if he has only met with them one single time before, even by that he
is half acquainted with them. This relates even to bodily fatigues. They should be practised less to accustom
the body to them than the mind. In War the young soldier is very apt to regard unusual fatigues as the
consequence of faults, mistakes, and embarrassment in the conduct of the whole, and to become distressed
and despondent as a consequence. This would not happen if he had been prepared for this beforehand by
exercises in peace.
Another less comprehensive but still very important means of gaining habituation to War in time of peace is
to invite into the service officers of foreign armies who have had experience in War. Peace seldom reigns
over all Europe, and never in all quarters of the world. A State which has been long at peace should,
therefore, always seek to procure some officers who have done good service at the different scenes of
Warfare, or to send there some of its own, that they may get a lesson in War.
However small the number of officers of this description may appear in proportion to the mass, still their
influence is very sensibly felt.[*] Their experience, the bent of their genius, the stamp of their character,
influence their subordinates and comrades; and besides that, if they cannot be placed in positions of superior
command, they may always be regarded as men acquainted with the country, who may be questioned on
many special occasions.
[*] The War of 1870 furnishes a marked illustration. Von Moltke and von Goeben, not to mention many
others, had both seen service in this manner, the former in Turkey and Syria, the latter in Spain
EDITOR.
On War
On War 49
Page No 52
BOOK II. ON THE THEORY OF WAR
CHAPTER I. BRANCHES OF THE ART OF WAR
WAR in its literal meaning is fighting, for fighting alone is the efficient principle in the manifold activity
which in a wide sense is called War. But fighting is a trial of strength of the moral and physical forces by
means of the latter. That the moral cannot be omitted is evident of itself, for the condition of the mind has
always the most decisive influence on the forces employed in War.
The necessity of fighting very soon led men to special inventions to turn the advantage in it in their own
favour: in consequence of these the mode of fighting has undergone great alterations; but in whatever way it
is conducted its conception remains unaltered, and fighting is that which constitutes War.
The inventions have been from the first weapons and equipments for the individual combatants. These have
to be provided and the use of them learnt before the War begins. They are made suitable to the nature of the
fighting, consequently are ruled by it; but plainly the activity engaged in these appliances is a different thing
from the fight itself; it is only the preparation for the combat, not the conduct of the same. That arming and
equipping are not essential to the conception of fighting is plain, because mere wrestling is also fighting.
Fighting has determined everything appertaining to arms and equipment, and these in turn modify the mode
of fighting; there is, therefore, a reciprocity of action between the two.
Nevertheless, the fight itself remains still an entirely special activity, more particularly because it moves in an
entirely special element, namely, in the element of danger.
If, then, there is anywhere a necessity for drawing a line between two different activities, it is here; and in
order to see clearly the importance of this idea, we need only just to call to mind how often eminent personal
fitness in one field has turned out nothing but the most useless pedantry in the other.
It is also in no way difficult to separate in idea the one activity from the other, if we look at the combatant
forces fully armed and equipped as a given means, the profitable use of which requires nothing more than a
knowledge of their general results.
The Art of War is therefore, in its proper sense, the art of making use of the given means in fighting, and we
cannot give it a better name than the "Conduct of War." On the other hand, in a wider sense all activities
which have their existence on account of War, therefore the whole creation of troops, that is levying them,
arming, equipping, and exercising them, belong to the Art of War.
To make a sound theory it is most essential to separate these two activities, for it is easy to see that if every
act of War is to begin with the preparation of military forces, and to presuppose forces so organised as a
primary condition for conducting War, that theory will only be applicable in the few cases to which the force
available happens to be exactly suited. If, on the other hand, we wish to have a theory which shall suit most
cases, and will not be wholly useless in any case, it must be founded on those means which are in most
general use, and in respect to these only on the actual results springing from them.
The conduct of War is, therefore, the formation and conduct of the fighting. If this fighting was a single act,
there would be no necessity for any further subdivision, but the fight is composed of a greater or less number
of single acts, complete in themselves, which we call combats, as we have shown in the first chapter of the
first book, and which form new units. From this arises the totally different activities, that of the
On War
On War 50
Page No 53
FORMATION and CONDUCT of these single combats in themselves, and the COMBINATION of them
with one another, with a view to the ultimate object of the War. The first is called TACTICS, the other
STRATEGY.
This division into tactics and strategy is now in almost general use, and every one knows tolerably well under
which head to place any single fact, without knowing very distinctly the grounds on which the classification
is founded. But when such divisions are blindly adhered to in practice, they must have some deep root. We
have searched for this root, and we might say that it is just the usage of the majority which has brought us to
it. On the other hand, we look upon the arbitrary, unnatural definitions of these conceptions sought to be
established by some writers as not in accordance with the general usage of the terms.
According to our classification, therefore, tactics IS THE THEORY OF THE USE OF MILITARY FORCES
IN COMBAT. Strategy IS THE THEORY OF THE USE OF COMBATS FOR THE OBJECT OF THE
WAR.
The way in which the conception of a single, or independent combat, is more closely determined, the
conditions to which this unit is attached, we shall only be able to explain clearly when we consider the
combat; we must content ourselves for the present with saying that in relation to space, therefore in combats
taking place at the same time, the unit reaches just as far as PERSONAL COMMAND reaches; but in regard
to time, and therefore in relation to combats which follow each other in close succession, it reaches to the
moment when the crisis which takes place in every combat is entirely passed.
That doubtful cases may occur, cases, for instance, in which several combats may perhaps be regarded also as
a single one, will not overthrow the ground of distinction we have adopted, for the same is the case with all
grounds of distinction of real things which are differentiated by a gradually diminishing scale. There may,
therefore, certainly be acts of activity in War which, without any alteration in the point of view, may just as
well be counted strategic as tactical; for example, very extended positions resembling a chain of posts, the
preparations for the passage of a river at several points,
Our classification reaches and covers only the USE OF THE MILITARY FORCE. But now there are in War
a number of activities which are subservient to it, and still are quite different from it; sometimes closely
allied, sometimes less near in their affinity. All these activities relate to the MAINTENANCE OF THE
MILITARY FORCE. In the same way as its creation and training precede its use, so its maintenance is
always a necessary condition. But, strictly viewed, all activities thus connected with it are always to be
regarded only as preparations for fighting; they are certainly nothing more than activities which are very
close to the action, so that they run through the hostile act alternate in importance with the use of the forces.
We have therefore a right to exclude them as well as the other preparatory activities from the Art of War in its
restricted sense, from the conduct of War properly so called; and we are obliged to do so if we would comply
with the first principle of all theory, the elimination of all heterogeneous elements. Who would include in the
real "conduct of War" the whole litany of subsistence and administration, because it is admitted to stand in
constant reciprocal action with the use of the troops, but is something essentially different from it?
We have said, in the third chapter of our first book, that as the fight or combat is the only directly effective
activity, therefore the threads of all others, as they end in it, are included in it. By this we meant to say that to
all others an object was thereby appointed which, in accordance with the laws peculiar to themselves, they
must seek to attain. Here we must go a little closer into this subject.
The subjects which constitute the activities outside of the combat are of various kinds.
The one part belongs, in one respect, to the combat itself, is identical with it, whilst it serves in another
respect for the maintenance of the military force. The other part belongs purely to the subsistence, and has
On War
On War 51
Page No 54
only, in consequence of the reciprocal action, a limited influence on the combats by its results. The subjects
which in one respect belong to the fighting itself are MARCHES, CAMPS, and CANTONMENTS, for they
suppose so many different situations of troops, and where troops are supposed there the idea of the combat
must always be present.
The other subjects, which only belong to the maintenance, are SUBSISTENCE, CARE OF THE SICK, the
SUPPLY AND REPAIR OF ARMS AND EQUIPMENT.
Marches are quite identical with the use of the troops. The act of marching in the combat, generally called
manoeuvring, certainly does not necessarily include the use of weapons, but it is so completely and
necessarily combined with it that it forms an integral part of that which we call a combat. But the march
outside the combat is nothing but the execution of a strategic measure. By the strategic plan is settled WHEN,
WHERE, and WITH WHAT FORCES a battle is to be deliveredand to carry that into execution the march
is the only means.
The march outside of the combat is therefore an instrument of strategy, but not on that account exclusively a
subject of strategy, for as the armed force which executes it may be involved in a possible combat at any
moment, therefore its execution stands also under tactical as well as strategic rules. If we prescribe to a
column its route on a particular side of a river or of a branch of a mountain, then that is a strategic measure,
for it contains the intention of fighting on that particular side of the hill or river in preference to the other, in
case a combat should be necessary during the march.
But if a column, instead of following the road through a valley, marches along the parallel ridge of heights, or
for the convenience of marching divides itself into several columns, then these are tactical arrangements, for
they relate to the manner in which we shall use the troops in the anticipated combat.
The particular order of march is in constant relation with readiness for combat, is therefore tactical in its
nature, for it is nothing more than the first or preliminary disposition for the battle which may possibly take
place.
As the march is the instrument by which strategy apportions its active elements, the combats, but these last
often only appear by their results and not in the details of their real course, it could not fail to happen that in
theory the instrument has often been substituted for the efficient principle. Thus we hear of a decisive skilful
march, allusion being thereby made to those combat combinations to which these marches led. This
substitution of ideas is too natural and conciseness of expression too desirable to call for alteration, but still it
is only a condensed chain of ideas in regard to which we must never omit to bear in mind the full meaning, if
we would avoid falling into error.
We fall into an error of this description if we attribute to strategical combinations a power independent of
tactical results. We read of marches and manoeuvres combined, the object attained, and at the same time not a
word about combat, from which the conclusion is drawn that there are means in War of conquering an enemy
without fighting. The prolific nature of this error we cannot show until hereafter.
But although a march can be regarded absolutely as an integral part of the combat, still there are in it certain
relations which do not belong to the combat, and therefore are neither tactical nor strategic. To these belong
all arrangements which concern only the accommodation of the troops, the construction of bridges, roads,
These are only conditions; under many circumstances they are in very close connection, and may almost
identify themselves with the troops, as in building a bridge in presence of the enemy; but in themselves they
are always activities, the theory of which does not form part of the theory of the conduct of War.
Camps, by which we mean every disposition of troops in concentrated, therefore in battle order, in
On War
On War 52
Page No 55
contradistinction to cantonments or quarters, are a state of rest, therefore of restoration; but they are at the
same time also the strategic appointment of a battle on the spot, chosen; and by the manner in which they are
taken up they contain the fundamental lines of the battle, a condition from which every defensive battle starts;
they are therefore essential parts of both strategy and tactics.
Cantonments take the place of camps for the better refreshment of the troops. They are therefore, like camps,
strategic subjects as regards position and extent; tactical subjects as regards internal organisation, with a view
to readiness to fight.
The occupation of camps and cantonments no doubt usually combines with the recuperation of the troops
another object also, for example, the covering a district of country, the holding a position; but it can very well
be only the first. We remind our readers that strategy may follow a great diversity of objects, for everything
which appears an advantage may be the object of a combat, and the preservation of the instrument with which
War is made must necessarily very often become the object of its partial combinations.
If, therefore, in such a case strategy ministers only to the maintenance of the troops, we are not on that
account out of the field of strategy, for we are still engaged with the use of the military force, because every
disposition of that force upon any point Whatever of the theatre of War is such a use.
But if the maintenance of the troops in camp or quarters calls forth activities which are no employment of the
armed force, such as the construction of huts, pitching of tents, subsistence and sanitary services in camps or
quarters, then such belong neither to strategy nor tactics.
Even entrenchments, the site and preparation of which are plainly part of the order of battle, therefore tactical
subjects, do not belong to the theory of the conduct of War so far as respects the execution of their
construction the knowledge and skill required for such work being, in point of fact, qualities inherent in the
nature of an organised Army; the theory of the combat takes them for granted.
Amongst the subjects which belong to the mere keeping up of an armed force, because none of the parts are
identified with the combat, the victualling of the troops themselves comes first, as it must be done almost
daily and for each individual. Thus it is that it completely permeates military action in the parts constituting
strategywe say parts constituting strategy, because during a battle the subsistence of troops will rarely have
any influence in modifying the plan, although the thing is conceivable enough. The care for the subsistence of
the troops comes therefore into reciprocal action chiefly with strategy, and there is nothing more common
than for the leading strategic features of a campaign and War to be traced out in connection with a view to
this supply. But however frequent and however important these views of supply may be, the subsistence of
the troops always remains a completely different activity from the use of the troops, and the former has only
an influence on the latter by its results.
The other branches of administrative activity which we have mentioned stand much farther apart from the use
of the troops. The care of sick and wounded, highly important as it is for the good of an Army, directly
affects it only in a small portion of the individuals composing it, and therefore has only a weak and indirect
influence upon the use of the rest. The completing and replacing articles of arms and equipment, except so far
as by the organism of the forces it constitutes a continuous activity inherent in themtakes place only
periodically, and therefore seldom affects strategic plans.
We must, however, here guard ourselves against a mistake. In certain cases these subjects may be really of
decisive importance. The distance of hospitals and depo^ts of munitions may very easily be imagined as the
sole cause of very important strategic decisions. We do not wish either to contest that point or to throw it into
the shade. But we are at present occupied not with the particular facts of a concrete case, but with abstract
theory; and our assertion therefore is that such an influence is too rare to give the theory of sanitary measures
On War
On War 53
Page No 56
and the supply of munitions and arms an importance intheory of the conduct of War such as to make it worth
while to include in the theory of the conduct of War the consideration of the different ways and systems
which the above theories may furnish, in the same way as is certainly necessary in regard to victualling
troops.
If we have clearly understood the results of our reflections, then the activities belonging to War divide
themselves into two principal classes, into such as are only "preparations for War" and into the "War itself."
This division must therefore also be made in theory.
The knowledge and applications of skill in the preparations for War are engaged in the creation, discipline,
and maintenance of all the military forces; what general names should be given to them we do not enter into,
but we see that artillery, fortification, elementary tactics, as they are called, the whole organisation and
administration of the various armed forces, and all such things are included. But the theory of War itself
occupies itself with the use of these prepared means for the object of the war. It needs of the first only the
results, that is, the knowledge of the principal properties of the means taken in hand for use. This we call
"The Art of War" in a limited sense, or "Theory of the Conduct of War," or "Theory of the Employment of
Armed Forces," all of them denoting for us the same thing.
The present theory will therefore treat the combat as the real contest, marches, camps, and cantonments as
circumstances which are more or less identical with it. The subsistence of the troops will only come into
consideration like OTHER GIVEN CIRCUMSTANCES in respect of its results, not as an activity belonging
to the combat.
The Art of War thus viewed in its limited sense divides itself again into tactics and strategy. The former
occupies itself with the form of the separate combat, the latter with its use. Both connect themselves with the
circumstances of marches, camps, cantonments only through the combat, and these circumstances are tactical
or strategic according as they relate to the form or to the signification of the battle.
No doubt there will be many readers who will consider superfluous this careful separation of two things lying
so close together as tactics and strategy, because it has no direct effect on the conduct itself of War. We
admit, certainly that it would be pedantry to look for direct effects on the field of battle from a theoretical
distinction.
But the first business of every theory is to clear up conceptions and ideas which have been jumbled together,
and, we may say, entangled and confused; and only when a right understanding is established, as to names
and conceptions, can we hope to progress with clearness and facility, and be certain that author and reader
will always see things from the same point of view. Tactics and strategy are two activities mutually
permeating each other in time and space, at the same time essentially different activities, the inner laws and
mutual relations of which cannot be intelligible at all to the mind until a clear conception of the nature of
each activity is established.
He to whom all this is nothing, must either repudiate all theoretical consideration, OR HIS
UNDERSTANDING HAS NOT AS YET BEEN PAINED by the confused and perplexing ideas resting on
no fixed point of view, leading to no satisfactory result, sometimes dull, sometimes fantastic, sometimes
floating in vague generalities, which we are often obliged to hear and read on the conduct of War, owing to
the spirit of scientific investigation having hitherto been little directed to these subjects.
On War
On War 54
Page No 57
CHAPTER II. ON THE THEORY OF WAR
1. THE FIRST CONCEPTION OF THE "ART OF WAR" WAS MERELY THE PREPARATION OF THE
ARMED FORCES.
FORMERLY by the term "Art of War," or "Science of War," nothing was understood but the totality of those
branches of knowledge and those appliances of skill occupied with material things. The pattern and
preparation and the mode of using arms, the construction of fortifications and entrenchments, the organism of
an army and the mechanism of its movements, were the subjectthese branches of knowledge and skill above
referred to, and the end and aim of them all was the establishment of an armed force fit for use in War. All
this concerned merely things belonging to the material world and a one sided activity only, and it was in fact
nothing but an activity advancing by gradations from the lower occupations to a finer kind of mechanical art.
The relation of all this to War itself was very much the same as the relation of the art of the sword cutler to
the art of using the sword. The employment in the moment of danger and in a state of constant reciprocal
action of the particular energies of mind and spirit in the direction proposed to them was not yet even mooted.
2. TRUE WAR FIRST APPEARS IN THE ART OF SIEGES.
In the art of sieges we first perceive a certain degree of guidance of the combat, something of the action of
the intellectual faculties upon the material forces placed under their control, but generally only so far that it
very soon embodied itself again in new material forms, such as approaches, trenches, counterapproaches,
batteries, and every step which this action of the higher faculties took was marked by some such result; it was
only the thread that was required on which to string these material inventions in order. As the intellect can
hardly manifest itself in this kind of War, except in such things, so therefore nearly all that was necessary was
done in that way.
3. THEN TACTICS TRIED TO FIND ITS WAY IN THE SAME DIRECTION.
Afterwards tactics attempted to give to the mechanism of its joints the character of a general disposition, built
upon the peculiar properties of the instrument, which character leads indeed to the battlefield, but instead of
leading to the free activity of mind, leads to an Army made like an automaton by its rigid formations and
orders of battle, which, movable only by the word of command, is intended to unwind its activities like a
piece of clockwork.
4. THE REAL CONDUCT OF WAR ONLY MADE ITS APPEARANCE INCIDENTALLY AND
INCOGNITO.
The conduct of War properly so called, that is, a use of the prepared means adapted to the most special
requirements, was not considered as any suitable subject for theory, but one which should be left to natural
talents alone. By degrees, as War passed from the handtohand encounters of the middle ages into a more
regular and systematic form, stray reflections on this point also forced themselves into men's minds, but they
mostly appeared only incidentally in memoirs and narratives, and in a certain measure incognito.
5. REFLECTIONS ON MILITARY EVENTS BROUGHT ABOUT THE WANT OF A THEORY.
As contemplation on War continually increased, and its history every day assumed more of a critical
character, the urgent want appeared of the support of fixed maxims and rules, in order that in the
controversies naturally arising about military events the war of opinions might be brought to some one point.
This whirl of opinions, which neither revolved on any central pivot nor according to any appreciable laws,
could not but be very distasteful to people's minds.
On War
On War 55
Page No 58
6. ENDEAVOURS TO ESTABLISH A POSITIVE THEORY.
There arose, therefore, an endeavour to establish maxims, rules, and even systems for the conduct of War. By
this the attainment of a positive object was proposed, without taking into view the endless difficulties which
the conduct of War presents in that respect. The conduct of War, as we have shown, has no definite limits in
any direction, while every system has the circumscribing nature of a synthesis, from which results an
irreconcileable opposition between such a theory and practice.
7. LIMITATION TO MATERIAL OBJECTS.
Writers on theory felt the difficulty of the subject soon enough, and thought themselves entitled to get rid of it
by directing their maxims and systems only upon material things and a onesided activity. Their aim was to
reach results, as in the science for the preparation for War, entirely certain and positive, and therefore only to
take into consideration that which could be made matter of calculation.
8. SUPERIORITY OF NUMBERS.
The superiority in numbers being a material condition, it was chosen from amongst all the factors required to
produce victory, because it could be brought under mathematical laws through combinations of time and
space. It was thought possible to leave out of sight all other circumstances, by supposing them to be equal on
each side, and therefore to neutralise one another. This would have been very well if it had been done to gain
a preliminary knowledge of this one factor, according to its relations, but to make it a rule for ever to consider
superiority of numbers as the sole law; to see the whole secret of the Art of War in the formula, IN A
CERTAIN TIME, AT A CERTAIN POINT, TO BRING UP SUPERIOR MASSESwas a restriction
overruled by the force of realities.
9. VICTUALLING OF TROOPS.
By one theoretical school an attempt was made to systematise another material element also, by making the
subsistence of troops, according to a previously established organism of the Army, the supreme legislator in
the higher conduct of War. In this way certainly they arrived at definite figures, but at figures which rested on
a number of arbitrary calculations, and which therefore could not stand the test of practical application.
10. BASE.
An ingenious author tried to concentrate in a single conception, that of a BASE, a whole host of objects
amongst which sundry relations even with immaterial forces found their way in as well. The list comprised
the subsistence of the troops, the keeping them complete in numbers and equipment, the security of
communications with the home country, lastly, the security of retreat in case it became necessary; and, first of
all, he proposed to substitute this conception of a base for all these things; then for the base itself to substitute
its own length (extent); and, last of all, to substitute the angle formed by the army with this base: all this was
done to obtain a pure geometrical result utterly useless. This last is, in fact, unavoidable, if we reflect that
none of these substitutions could be made without violating truth and leaving out some of the things
contained in the original conception. The idea of a base is a real necessity for strategy, and to have conceived
it is meritorious; but to make such a use of it as we have depicted is completely inadmissible, and could not
but lead to partial conclusions which have forced these theorists into a direction opposed to common sense,
namely, to a belief in the decisive effect of the enveloping form of attack.
11. INTERIOR LINES.
As a reaction against this false direction, another geometrical principle, that of the socalled interior lines,
On War
On War 56
Page No 59
was then elevated to the throne. Although this principle rests on a sound foundation, on the truth that the
combat is the only effectual means in War, still it is, just on account of its purely geometrical nature, nothing
but another case of onesided theory which can never gain ascendency in the real world.
12. ALL THESE ATTEMPTS ARE OPEN TO OBJECTION.
All these attempts at theory are only to be considered in their analytical part as progress in the province of
truth, but in their synthetical part, in their precepts and rules, they are quite unserviceable.
They strive after determinate quantities, whilst in War all is undetermined, and the calculation has always to
be made with varying quantities.
They direct the attention only upon material forces, while the whole military action is penetrated throughout
by intelligent forces and their effects.
They only pay regard to activity on one side, whilst War is a constant state of reciprocal action, the effects of
which are mutual.
13. AS A RULE THEY EXCLUDE GENIUS.
All that was not attainable by such miserable philosophy, the offspring of partial views, lay outside the
precincts of scienceand was the field of genius, which RAISES ITSELF ABOVE RULES.
Pity the warrior who is contented to crawl about in this beggardom of rules, which are too bad for genius,
over which it can set itself superior, over which it can perchance make merry! What genius does must be the
best of all rules, and theory cannot do better than to show how and why it is so.
Pity the theory which sets itself in opposition to the mind! It cannot repair this contradiction by any humility,
and the humbler it is so much the sooner will ridicule and contempt drive it out of real life.
14. THE DIFFICULTY OF THEORY AS SOON AS MORAL QUANTITIES COME INTO
CONSIDERATION.
Every theory becomes infinitely more difficult from the moment that it touches on the province of moral
quantities. Architecture and painting know quite well what they are about as long as they have only to do
with matter; there is no dispute about mechanical or optical construction. But as soon as the moral activities
begin their work, as soon as moral impressions and feelings are produced, the whole set of rules dissolves
into vague ideas.
The science of medicine is chiefly engaged with bodily phenomena only; its business is with the animal
organism, which, liable to perpetual change, is never exactly the same for two moments. This makes its
practice very difficult, and places the judgment of the physician above his science; but how much more
difficult is the case if a moral effect is added, and how much higher must we place the physician of the mind?
15. THE MORAL QUANTITIES MUST NOT BE EXCLUDED IN WAR.
But now the activity in War is never directed solely against matter; it is always at the same time directed
against the intelligent force which gives life to this matter, and to separate the two from each other is
impossible.
But the intelligent forces are only visible to the inner eye, and this is different in each person, and often
On War
On War 57
Page No 60
different in the same person at different times.
As danger is the general element in which everything moves in War, it is also chiefly by courage, the feeling
of one's own power, that the judgment is differently influenced. It is to a certain extent the crystalline lens
through which all appearances pass before reaching the understanding.
And yet we cannot doubt that these things acquire a certain objective value simply through experience.
Every one knows the moral effect of a surprise, of an attack in flank or rear. Every one thinks less of the
enemy's courage as soon as he turns his back, and ventures much more in pursuit than when pursued. Every
one judges of the enemy's General by his reputed talents, by his age and experience, and shapes his course
accordingly. Every one casts a scrutinising glance at the spirit and feeling of his own and the enemy's troops.
All these and similar effects in the province of the moral nature of man have established themselves by
experience, are perpetually recurring, and therefore warrant our reckoning them as real quantities of their
kind. What could we do with any theory which should leave them out of consideration?
Certainly experience is an indispensable title for these truths. With psychological and philosophical
sophistries no theory, no General, should meddle.
16. PRINCIPAL DIFFICULTY OF A THEORY FOR THE CONDUCT OF WAR.
In order to comprehend clearly the difficulty of the proposition which is contained in a theory for the conduct
of War, and thence to deduce the necessary characteristics of such a theory, we must take a closer view of the
chief particulars which make up the nature of activity in War.
17. FIRST SPECIALITY.MORAL FORCES AND THEIR EFFECTS. (HOSTILE FEELING.)
The first of these specialities consists in the moral forces and effects.
The combat is, in its origin, the expression of HOSTILE FEELING, but in our great combats, which we call
Wars, the hostile feeling frequently resolves itself into merely a hostile VIEW, and there is usually no innate
hostile feeling residing in individual against individual. Nevertheless, the combat never passes off without
such feelings being brought into activity. National hatred, which is seldom wanting in our Wars, is a
substitute for personal hostility in the breast of individual opposed to individual. But where this also is
wanting, and at first no animosity of feeling subsists, a hostile feeling is kindled by the combat itself; for an
act of violence which any one commits upon us by order of his superior, will excite in us a desire to retaliate
and be revenged on him, sooner than on the superior power at whose command the act was done. This is
human, or animal if we will; still it is so. We are very apt to regard the combat in theory as an abstract trial of
strength, without any participation on the part of the feelings, and that is one of the thousand errors which
theorists deliberately commit, because they do not see its consequences.
Besides that excitation of feelings naturally arising from the combat itself, there are others also which do not
essentially belong to it, but which, on account of their relationship, easily unite with itambition, love of
power, enthusiasm of every kind,
18. THE IMPRESSIONS OF DANGER. (COURAGE.)
Finally, the combat begets the element of danger, in which all the activities of War must live and move, like
the bird in the air or the fish in the water. But the influences of danger all pass into the feelings, either
directlythat is, instinctivelyor through the medium of the understanding. The effect in the first case
would be a desire to escape from the danger, and, if that cannot be done, fright and anxiety. If this effect does
On War
On War 58
Page No 61
not take place, then it is COURAGE, which is a counterpoise to that instinct. Courage is, however, by no
means an act of the understanding, but likewise a feeling, like fear; the latter looks to the physical
preservation, courage to the moral preservation. Courage, then, is a nobler instinct. But because it is so, it will
not allow itself to be used as a lifeless instrument, which produces its effects exactly according to prescribed
measure. Courage is therefore no mere counterpoise to danger in order to neutralise the latter in its effects,
but a peculiar power in itself.
19. EXTENT OF THE INFLUENCE OF DANGER.
But to estimate exactly the influence of danger upon the principal actors in War, we must not limit its sphere
to the physical danger of the moment. It dominates over the actor, not only by threatening him, but also by
threatening all entrusted to him, not only at the moment in which it is actually present, but also through the
imagination at all other moments, which have a connection with the present; lastly, not only directly by itself,
but also indirectly by the responsibility which makes it bear with tenfold weight on the mind of the chief
actor. Who could advise, or resolve upon a great battle, without feeling his mind more or less wrought up, or
perplexed by, the danger and responsibility which such a great act of decision carries in itself? We may say
that action in War, in so far as it is real action, not a mere condition, is never out of the sphere of danger.
20. OTHER POWERS OF FEELING.
If we look upon these affections which are excited by hostility and danger as peculiarly belonging to War, we
do not, therefore, exclude from it all others accompanying man in his life's journey. They will also find room
here frequently enough. Certainly we may say that many a petty action of the passions is silenced in this
serious business of life; but that holds good only in respect to those acting in a lower sphere, who, hurried on
from one state of danger and exertion to another, lose sight of the rest of the things of life, BECOME
UNUSED TO DECEIT, because it is of no avail with death, and so attain to that soldierly simplicity of
character which has always been the best representative of the military profession. In higher regions it is
otherwise, for the higher a man's rank, the more he must look around him; then arise interests on every side,
and a manifold activity of the passions of good and bad. Envy and generosity, pride and humility, fierceness
and tenderness, all may appear as active powers in this great drama.
21. PECULIARITY OF MIND.
The peculiar characteristics of mind in the chief actor have, as well as those of the feelings, a high
importance. From an imaginative, flighty, inexperienced head, and from a calm, sagacious understanding,
different things are to be expected.
22. FROM THE DIVERSITY IN MENTAL INDIVIDUALITIES ARISES THE DIVERSITY OF WAYS
LEADING TO THE END.
It is this great diversity in mental individuality, the influence of which is to be supposed as chiefly felt in the
higher ranks, because it increases as we progress upwards, which chiefly produces the diversity of ways
leading to the end noticed by us in the first book, and which gives, to the play of probabilities and chance,
such an unequal share in determining the course of events.
23. SECOND PECULIARITY.LIVING REACTION.
The second peculiarity in War is the living reaction, and the reciprocal action resulting therefrom. We do not
here speak of the difficulty of estimating that reaction, for that is included in the difficulty before mentioned,
of treating the moral powers as quantities; but of this, that reciprocal action, by its nature, opposes anything
like a regular plan. The effect which any measure produces upon the enemy is the most distinct of all the data
On War
On War 59
Page No 62
which action affords; but every theory must keep to classes (or groups) of phenomena, and can never take up
the really individual case in itself: that must everywhere be left to judgment and talent. It is therefore natural
that in a business such as War, which in its planbuilt upon general circumstancesis so often thwarted by
unexpected and singular accidents, more must generally be left to talent; and less use can be made of a
THEORETICAL GUIDE than in any other.
24. THIRD PECULIARITY.UNCERTAINTY OF ALL DATA.
Lastly, the great uncertainty of all data in War is a peculiar difficulty, because all action must, to a certain
extent, be planned in a mere twilight, which in addition not unfrequentlylike the effect of a fog or
moonshine gives to things exaggerated dimensions and an unnatural appearance.
What this feeble light leaves indistinct to the sight talent must discover, or must be left to chance. It is
therefore again talent, or the favour of fortune, on which reliance must be placed, for want of objective
knowledge.
25. POSITIVE THEORY IS IMPOSSIBLE.
With materials of this kind we can only say to ourselves that it is a sheer impossibility to construct for the Art
of War a theory which, like a scaffolding, shall ensure to the chief actor an external support on all sides. In all
those cases in which he is thrown upon his talent he would find himself away from this scaffolding of theory
and in opposition to it, and, however manysided it might be framed, the same result would ensue of which
we spoke when we said that talent and genius act beyond the law, and theory is in opposition to reality.
26. MEANS LEFT BY WHICH A THEORY IS POSSIBLE (THE DIFFICULTIES ARE NOT
EVERYWHERE EQUALLY GREAT).
Two means present themselves of getting out of this difficulty. In the first place, what we have said of the
nature of military action in general does not apply in the same manner to the action of every one, whatever
may be his standing. In the lower ranks the spirit of selfsacrifice is called more into request, but the
difficulties which the understanding and judgment meet with are infinitely less. The field of occurrences is
more confined. Ends and means are fewer in number. Data more distinct; mostly also contained in the
actually visible. But the higher we ascend the more the difficulties increase, until in the
CommanderinChief they reach their climax, so that with him almost everything must be left to genius.
Further, according to a division of the subject in AGREEMENT WITH ITS NATURE, the difficulties are not
everywhere the same, but diminish the more results manifest themselves in the material world, and increase
the more they pass into the moral, and become motives which influence the will. Therefore it is easier to
determine, by theoretical rules, the order and conduct of a battle, than the use to be made of the battle itself.
Yonder physical weapons clash with each other, and although mind is not wanting therein, matter must have
its rights. But in the effects to be produced by battles when the material results become motives, we have only
to do with the moral nature. In a word, it is easier to make a theory for TACTICS than for STRATEGY.
27. THEORY MUST BE OF THE NATURE OF OBSERVATIONS NOT OF DOCTRINE.
The second opening for the possibility of a theory lies in the point of view that it does not necessarily require
to be a DIRECTION for action. As a general rule, whenever an ACTIVITY is for the most part occupied with
the same objects over and over again, with the same ends and means, although there may be trifling
alterations and a corresponding number of varieties of combination, such things are capable of becoming a
subject of study for the reasoning faculties. But such study is just the most essential part of every THEORY,
and has a peculiar title to that name. It is an analytical investigation of the subject that leads to an exact
On War
On War 60
Page No 63
knowledge; and if brought to bear on the results of experience, which in our case would be military history, to
a thorough familiarity with it. The nearer theory attains the latter object, so much the more it passes over from
the objective form of knowledge into the subjective one of skill in action; and so much the more, therefore, it
will prove itself effective when circumstances allow of no other decision but that of personal talents; it will
show its effects in that talent itself. If theory investigates the subjects which constitute War; if it separates
more distinctly that which at first sight seems amalgamated; if it explains fully the properties of the means; if
it shows their probable effects; if it makes evident the nature of objects; if it brings to bear all over the field of
War the light of essentially critical investigationthen it has fulfilled the chief duties of its province. It
becomes then a guide to him who wishes to make himself acquainted with War from books; it lights up the
whole road for him, facilitates his progress, educates his judgment, and shields him from error.
If a man of expertness spends half his life in the endeavour to clear up an obscure subject thoroughly, he will
probably know more about it than a person who seeks to master it in a short time. Theory is instituted that
each person in succession may not have to go through the same labour of clearing the ground and toiling
through his subject, but may find the thing in order, and light admitted on it. It should educate the mind of the
future leader in War, or rather guide him in his selfinstruction, but not accompany him to the field of battle;
just as a sensible tutor forms and enlightens the opening mind of a youth without, therefore, keeping him in
leading strings all through his life.
If maxims and rules result of themselves from the considerations which theory institutes, if the truth accretes
itself into that form of crystal, then theory will not oppose this natural law of the mind; it will rather, if the
arch ends in such a keystone, bring it prominently out; but so does this, only in order to satisfy the
philosophical law of reason, in order to show distinctly the point to which the lines all converge, not in order
to form out of it an algebraical formula for use upon the battlefield; for even these maxims and rules serve
more to determine in the reflecting mind the leading outline of its habitual movements than as landmarks
indicating to it the way in the act of execution.
28. BY THIS POINT OF VIEW THEORY BECOMES POSSIBLE, AND CEASES TO BE IN
CONTRADICTION TO PRACTICE.
Taking this point of view, there is a possibility afforded of a satisfactory, that is, of a useful, theory of the
conduct of War, never coming into opposition with the reality, and it will only depend on rational treatment
to bring it so far into harmony with action that between theory and practice there shall no longer be that
absurd difference which an unreasonable theory, in defiance of common sense, has often produced, but
which, just as often, for giving way to their natural incapacity.
29. THEORY THEREFORE CONSIDERS THE NATURE OF ENDS AND MEANSENDS AND
MEANS IN TACTICS.
Theory has therefore to consider the nature of the means and ends.
In tactics the means are the disciplined armed forces which are to carry on the contest. The object is victory.
The precise definition of this conception can be better explained hereafter in the consideration of the combat.
Here we content ourselves by denoting the retirement of the enemy from the field of battle as the sign of
victory. By means of this victory strategy gains the object for which it appointed the combat, and which
constitutes its special signification. This signification has certainly some influence on the nature of the
victory. A victory which is intended to weaken the enemy's armed forces is a different thing from one which
is designed only to put us in possession of a position. The signification of a combat may therefore have a
sensible influence on the preparation and conduct of it, consequently will be also a subject of consideration in
tactics.
On War
On War 61
Page No 64
30. CIRCUMSTANCES WHICH ALWAYS ATTEND THE APPLICATION OF THE MEANS.
As there are certain circumstances which attend the combat throughout, and have more or less influence upon
its result, therefore these must be taken into consideration in the application of the armed forces.
These circumstances are the locality of the combat (ground), the time of day, and the weather.
31. LOCALITY.
The locality, which we prefer leaving for solution, under the head of "Country and Ground," might, strictly
speaking, be without any influence at all if the combat took place on a completely level and uncultivated
plain.
In a country of steppes such a case may occur, but in the cultivated countries of Europe it is almost an
imaginary idea. Therefore a combat between civilised nations, in which country and ground have no
influence, is hardly conceivable.
32. TIME OF DAY.
The time of day influences the combat by the difference between day and night; but the influence naturally
extends further than merely to the limits of these divisions, as every combat has a certain duration, and great
battles last for several hours. In the preparations for a great battle, it makes an essential difference whether it
begins in the morning or the evening. At the same time, certainly many battles may be fought in which the
question of the time of day is quite immaterial, and in the generality of cases its influence is only trifling.
33. WEATHER.
Still more rarely has the weather any decisive influence, and it is mostly only by fogs that it plays a part.
34. END AND MEANS IN STRATEGY.
Strategy has in the first instance only the victory, that is, the tactical result, as a means to its object, and
ultimately those things which lead directly to peace. The application of its means to this object is at the same
time attended by circumstances which have an influence thereon more or less.
35. CIRCUMSTANCES WHICH ATTEND THE APPLICATION OF THE MEANS OF STRATEGY.
These circumstances are country and ground, the former including the territory and inhabitants of the whole
theatre of war; next the time of the day, and the time of the year as well; lastly, the weather, particularly any
unusual state of the same, severe frost,
36. THESE FORM NEW MEANS.
By bringing these things into combination with the results of a combat, strategy gives this resultand
therefore the combata special signification, places before it a particular object. But when this object is not
that which leads directly to peace, therefore a subordinate one, it is only to be looked upon as a means; and
therefore in strategy we may look upon the results of combats or victories, in all their different significations,
as means. The conquest of a position is such a result of a combat applied to ground. But not only are the
different combats with special objects to be considered as means, but also every higher aim which we may
have in view in the combination of battles directed on a common object is to be regarded as a means. A
winter campaign is a combination of this kind applied to the season.
On War
On War 62
Page No 65
There remain, therefore, as objects, only those things which may be supposed as leading DIRECTLY to
peace, Theory investigates all these ends and means according to the nature of their effects and their mutual
relations.
37. STRATEGY DEDUCES ONLY FROM EXPERIENCE THE ENDS AND MEANS TO BE
EXAMINED.
The first question is, How does strategy arrive at a complete list of these things? If there is to be a
philosophical inquiry leading to an absolute result, it would become entangled in all those difficulties which
the logical necessity of the conduct of War and its theory exclude. It therefore turns to experience, and directs
its attention on those combinations which military history can furnish. In this manner, no doubt, nothing more
than a limited theory can be obtained, which only suits circumstances such as are presented in history. But
this incompleteness is unavoidable, because in any case theory must either have deduced from, or have
compared with, history what it advances with respect to things. Besides, this incompleteness in every case is
more theoretical than real.
One great advantage of this method is that theory cannot lose itself in abstruse disquisitions, subtleties, and
chimeras, but must always remain practical.
38. HOW FAR THE ANALYSIS OF THE MEANS SHOULD BE CARRIED.
Another question is, How far should theory go in its analysis of the means? Evidently only so far as the
elements in a separate form present themselves for consideration in practice. The range and effect of different
weapons is very important to tactics; their construction, although these effects result from it, is a matter of
indifference; for the conduct of War is not making powder and cannon out of a given quantity of charcoal,
sulphur, and saltpetre, of copper and tin: the given quantities for the conduct of War are arms in a finished
state and their effects. Strategy makes use of maps without troubling itself about triangulations; it does not
inquire how the country is subdivided into departments and provinces, and how the people are educated and
governed, in order to attain the best military results; but it takes things as it finds them in the community of
European States, and observes where very different conditions have a notable influence on War.
39. GREAT SIMPLIFICATION OF THE KNOWLEDGE REQUIRED.
That in this manner the number of subjects for theory is much simplified, and the knowledge requisite for the
conduct of War much reduced, is easy to perceive. The very great mass of knowledge and appliances of skill
which minister to the action of War in general, and which are necessary before an army fully equipped can
take the field, unite in a few great results before they are able to reach, in actual War, the final goal of their
activity; just as the streams of a country unite themselves in rivers before they fall into the sea. Only those
activities emptying themselves directly into the sea of War have to be studied by him who is to conduct its
operations.
40. THIS EXPLAINS THE RAPID GROWTH OF GREAT GENERALS, AND WHY A GENERAL IS
NOT A MAN OF LEARNING.
This result of our considerations is in fact so necessary,any other would have made us distrustful of their
accuracy. Only thus is explained how so often men have made their appearance with great success in War,
and indeed in the higher ranks even in supreme Command, whose pursuits had been previously of a totally
different nature; indeed how, as a rule, the most distinguished Generals have never risen from the very
learned or really erudite class of officers, but have been mostly men who, from the circumstances of their
position, could not have attained to any great amount of knowledge. On that account those who have
considered it necessary or even beneficial to commence the education of a future General by instruction in all
On War
On War 63
Page No 66
details have always been ridiculed as absurd pedants. It would be easy to show the injurious tendency of such
a course, because the human mind is trained by the knowledge imparted to it and the direction given to its
ideas. Only what is great can make it great; the little can only make it little, if the mind itself does not reject it
as something repugnant.
41. FORMER CONTRADICTIONS.
Because this simplicity of knowledge requisite in War was not attended to, but that knowledge was always
jumbled up with the whole impedimenta of subordinate sciences and arts, therefore the palpable opposition to
the events of real life which resulted could not be solved otherwise than by ascribing it all to genius, which
requires no theory and for which no theory could be prescribed.
42. ON THIS ACCOUNT ALL USE OF KNOWLEDGE WAS DENIED, AND EVERYTHING ASCRIBED
TO NATURAL TALENTS.
People with whom common sense had the upper hand felt sensible of the immense distance remaining to be
filled up between a genius of the highest order and a learned pedant; and they became in a manner
freethinkers, rejected all belief in theory, and affirmed the conduct of War to be a natural function of man,
which he performs more or less well according as he has brought with him into the world more or less talent
in that direction. It cannot be denied that these were nearer to the truth than those who placed a value on false
knowledge: at the same time it may easily be seen that such a view is itself but an exaggeration. No activity
of the human understanding is possible without a certain stock of ideas; but these are, for the greater part at
least, not innate but acquired, and constitute his knowledge. The only question therefore is, of what kind
should these ideas be; and we think we have answered it if we say that they should be directed on those things
which man has directly to deal with in War.
43. THE KNOWLEDGE MUST BE MADE SUITABLE TO THE POSITION.
Inside this field itself of military activity, the knowledge required must be different according to the station of
the Commander. It will be directed on smaller and more circumscribed objects if he holds an inferior, upon
greater and more comprehensive ones if he holds a higher situation. There are Field Marshals who would not
have shone at the head of a cavalry regiment, and vice versa.
44. THE KNOWLEDGE IN WAR IS VERY SIMPLE, BUT NOT, AT THE SAME TIME, VERY EASY.
But although the knowledge in War is simple, that is to say directed to so few subjects, and taking up those
only in their final results, the art of execution is not, on that account, easy. Of the difficulties to which activity
in War is subject generally, we have already spoken in the first book; we here omit those things which can
only be overcome by courage, and maintain also that the activity of mind, is only simple, and easy in inferior
stations, but increases in difficulty with increase of rank, and in the highest position, in that of
CommanderinChief, is to be reckoned among the most difficult which there is for the human mind.
45. OF THE NATURE OF THIS KNOWLEDGE.
The Commander of an Army neither requires to be a learned explorer of history nor a publicist, but he must
be well versed in the higher affairs of State; he must know, and be able to judge correctly of traditional
tendencies, interests at stake, the immediate questions at issue, and the characters of leading persons; he need
not be a close observer of men, a sharp dissector of human character, but he must know the character, the
feelings, the habits, the peculiar faults and inclinations of those whom he is to command. He need not
understand anything about the make of a carriage, or the harness of a battery horse, but he must know how to
calculate exactly the march of a column, under different circumstances, according to the time it requires.
On War
On War 64
Page No 67
These are matters the knowledge of which cannot be forced out by an apparatus of scientific formula and
machinery: they are only to be gained by the exercise of an accurate judgment in the observation of things
and of men, aided by a special talent for the apprehension of both.
The necessary knowledge for a high position in military. action is therefore distinguished by this, that by
observation, therefore by study and reflection, it is only to be attained through a special talent which as an
intellectual instinct understands how to extract from the phenomena of life only the essence or spirit, as bees
do the honey from the flowers; and that it is also to be gained by experience of life as well as by study and
reflection. Life will never bring forth a Newton or an Euler by its rich teachings, but it may bring forth great
calculators in War, such as Conde' or Frederick.
It is therefore not necessary that, in order to vindicate the intellectual dignity of military activity, we should
resort to untruth and silly pedantry. There never has been a great and distinguished Commander of contracted
mind, but very numerous are the instances of men who, after serving with the greatest distinction in inferior
positions, remained below mediocrity in the highest, from insufficiency of intellectual capacity. That even
amongst those holding the post of CommanderinChief there may be a difference according to the degree of
their plenitude of power is a matter of course.
46. SCIENCE MUST BECOME ART.
Now we have yet to consider one condition which is more necessary for the knowledge of the conduct of War
than for any other, which is, that it must pass completely into the mind and almost completely cease to be
something objective. In almost all other arts and occupations of life the active agent can make use of truths
which he has only learnt once, and in the spirit and sense of which he no longer lives, and which he extracts
from dusty books. Even truths which he has in hand and uses daily may continue something external to
himself, If the architect takes up a pen to settle the strength of a pier by a complicated calculation, the truth
found as a result is no emanation from his own mind. He had first to find the data with labour, and then to
submit these to an operation of the mind, the rule for which he did not discover, the necessity of which he is
perhaps at the moment only partly conscious of, but which he applies, for the most part, as if by mechanical
dexterity. But it is never so in War. The moral reaction, the ever changeful form of things, makes it
necessary for the chief actor to carry in himself the whole mental apparatus of his knowledge, that anywhere
and at every pulsebeat he may be capable of giving the requisite decision from himself. Knowledge must,
by this complete assimilation with his own mind and life, be converted into real power. This is the reason
why everything seems so easy with men distinguished in War, and why everything is ascribed to natural
talent. We say natural talent, in order thereby to distinguish it from that which is formed and matured by
observation and study.
We think that by these reflections we have explained the problem of a theory of the conduct of War; and
pointed out the way to its solution.
Of the two fields into which we have divided the conduct of War, tactics and strategy, the theory of the latter
contains unquestionably, as before observed, the greatest difficulties, because the first is almost limited to a
circumscribed field of objects, but the latter, in the direction of objects leading directly to peace, opens to
itself an unlimited field of possibilities. Since for the most part the CommanderinChief has only to keep
these objects steadily in view, therefore the part of strategy in which he moves is also that which is
particularly subject to this difficulty.
Theory, therefore, especially where it comprehends the highest services, will stop much sooner in strategy
than in tactics at the simple consideration of things, and content itself to assist the Commander to that insight
into things which, blended with his whole thought, makes his course easier and surer, never forces him into
opposition with himself in order to obey an objective truth.
On War
On War 65
Page No 68
CHAPTER III. ART OR SCIENCE OF WAR
1.USAGE STILL UNSETTLED
(POWER AND KNOWLEDGE. SCIENCE WHEN MERE KNOWING; ART, WHEN DOING, IS THE
OBJECT.)
THE choice between these terms seems to be still unsettled, and no one seems to know rightly on what
grounds it should be decided, and yet the thing is simple. We have already said elsewhere that "knowing" is
something different from "doing." The two are so different that they should not easily be mistaken the one for
the other. The "doing" cannot properly stand in any book, and therefore also Art should never be the title of a
book. But because we have once accustomed ourselves to combine in conception, under the name of theory
of Art, or simply Art, the branches of knowledge (which may be separately pure sciences) necessary for the
practice of an Art, therefore it is consistent to continue this ground of distinction, and to call everything Art
when the object is to carry out the "doing" (being able), as for example, Art of building; Science, when
merely knowledge is the object; as Science of mathematics, of astronomy. That in every Art certain complete
sciences may be included is intelligible of itself, and should not perplex us. But still it is worth observing that
there is also no science without a mixture of Art. In mathematics, for instance, the use of figures and of
algebra is an Art, but that is only one amongst many instances. The reason is, that however plain and palpable
the difference is between knowledge and power in the composite results of human knowledge, yet it is
difficult to trace out their line of separation in man himself.
2. DIFFICULTY OF SEPARATING PERCEPTION FROM JUDGMENT.
(ART OF WAR.)
All thinking is indeed Art. Where the logician draws the line, where the premises stop which are the result of
cognitionwhere judgment begins, there Art begins. But more than this even the perception of the mind is
judgment again, and consequently Art; and at last, even the perception by the senses as well. In a word, if it is
impossible to imagine a human being possessing merely the faculty of cognition, devoid of judgment or the
reverse, so also Art and Science can never be completely separated from each other. The more these subtle
elements of light embody themselves in the outward forms of the world, so much the more separate appear
their domains; and now once more, where the object is creation and production, there is the province of Art;
where the object is investigation and knowledge Science holds sway.After all this it results of itself that it
is more fitting to say Art of War than Science of War.
So much for this, because we cannot do without these conceptions. But now we come forward with the
assertion that War is neither an Art nor a Science in the real signification, and that it is just the setting out
from that startingpoint of ideas which has led to a wrong direction being taken, which has caused War to be
put on a par with other arts and sciences, and has led to a number of erroneous analogies.
This has indeed been felt before now, and on that it was maintained that War is a handicraft; but there was
more lost than gained by that, for a handicraft is only an inferior art, and as such is also subject to definite and
rigid laws. In reality the Art of War did go on for some time in the spirit of a handicraftwe allude to the
times of the Condottieribut then it received that direction, not from intrinsic but from external causes; and
military history shows how little it was at that time in accordance with the nature of the thing.
3. WAR IS PART OF THE INTERCOURSE OF THE HUMAN RACE.
We say therefore War belongs not to the province of Arts and Sciences, but to the province of social life. It is
a conflict of great interests which is settled by bloodshed, and only in that is it different from others. It would
On War
On War 66
Page No 69
be better, instead of comparing it with any Art, to liken it to business competition, which is also a conflict of
human interests and activities; and it is still more like State policy, which again, on its part, may be looked
upon as a kind of business competition on a great scale. Besides, State policy is the womb in which War is
developed, in which its outlines lie hidden in a rudimentary state, like the qualities of living creatures in their
germs.[*]
[*] The analogy has become much closer since Clausewitz's time. Now that the first business of the State is
regarded as the development of facilities for trade, War between great nations is only a question of time. No
Hague Conferences can avert itEDITOR.
4. DIFFERENCE.
The essential difference consists in this, that War is no activity of the will, which exerts itself upon inanimate
matter like the mechanical Arts; or upon a living but still passive and yielding subject, like the human mind
and the human feelings in the ideal Arts, but against a living and reacting force. How little the categories of
Arts and Sciences are applicable to such an activity strikes us at once; and we can understand at the same
time how that constant seeking and striving after laws like those which may be developed out of the dead
material world could not but lead to constant errors. And yet it is just the mechanical Arts that some people
would imitate in the Art of War. The imitation of the ideal Arts was quite out of the question, because these
themselves dispense too much with laws and rules, and those hitherto tried, always acknowledged as
insufficient and onesided, are perpetually undermined and washed away by the current of opinions, feelings,
and customs.
Whether such a conflict of the living, as takes place and is settled in War, is subject to general laws, and
whether these are capable of indicating a useful line of action, will be partly investigated in this book; but so
much is evident in itself, that this, like every other subject which does not surpass our powers of
understanding, may be lighted up, and be made more or less plain in its inner relations by an inquiring mind,
and that alone is sufficient to realise the idea of a THEORY.
CHAPTER IV. METHODICISM
IN order to explain ourselves clearly as to the conception of method, and method of action, which play such
an important part in War, we must be allowed to cast a hasty glance at the logical hierarchy through which, as
through regularly constituted official functionaries, the world of action is governed.
LAW, in the widest sense strictly applying to perception as well as action, has plainly something subjective
and arbitrary in its literal meaning, and expresses just that on which we and those things external to us are
dependent. As a subject of cognition, LAW is the relation of things and their effects to one another; as a
subject of the will, it is a motive of action, and is then equivalent to COMMAND or PROHIBITION.
PRINCIPLE is likewise such a law for action, except that it has not the formal definite meaning, but is only
the spirit and sense of law in order to leave the judgment more freedom of application when the diversity of
the real world cannot be laid hold of under the definite form of a law. As the judgment must of itself suggest
the cases in which the principle is not applicable, the latter therefore becomes in that way a real aid or guiding
star for the person acting.
Principle is OBJECTIVE when it is the result of objective truth, and consequently of equal value for all men;
On War
On War 67
Page No 70
it is SUBJECTIVE, and then generally called MAXIM if there are subjective relations in it, and if it therefore
has a certain value only for the person himself who makes it.
RULE is frequently taken in the sense of LAW, and then means the same as Principle, for we say "no rule
without exceptions," but we do not say "no law without exceptions," a sign that with RULE we retain to
ourselves more freedom of application.
In another meaning RULE is the means used of discerning a recondite truth in a particular sign lying close at
hand, in order to attach to this particular sign the law of action directed upon the whole truth. Of this kind are
all the rules of games of play, all abridged processes in mathematics,
DIRECTIONS and INSTRUCTIONS are determinations of action which have an influence upon a number of
minor circumstances too numerous and unimportant for general laws.
Lastly, METHOD, MODE OF ACTING, is an always recurring proceeding selected out of several possible
ones; and METHODICISM (METHODISMUS) is that which is determined by methods instead of by general
principles or particular prescriptions. By this the cases which are placed under such methods must necessarily
be supposed alike in their essential parts. As they cannot all be this, then the point is that at least as many as
possible should be; in other words, that Method should be calculated on the most probable cases.
Methodicism is therefore not founded on determined particular premises, but on the average probability of
cases one with another; and its ultimate tendency is to set up an average truth, the constant and uniform,
application of which soon acquires something of the nature of a mechanical appliance, which in the end does
that which is right almost unwittingly.
The conception of law in relation to perception is not necessary for the conduct of War, because the complex
phenomena of War are not so regular, and the regular are not so complex, that we should gain anything more
by this conception than by the simple truth. And where a simple conception and language is sufficient, to
resort to the complex becomes affected and pedantic. The conception of law in relation to action cannot be
used in the theory of the conduct of War, because owing to the variableness and diversity of the phenomena
there is in it no determination of such a general nature as to deserve the name of law.
But principles, rules, prescriptions, and methods are conceptions indispensable to a theory of the conduct of
War, in so far as that theory leads to positive doctrines, because in doctrines the truth can only crystallise
itself in such forms.
As tactics is the branch of the conduct of War in which theory can attain the nearest to positive doctrine,
therefore these conceptions will appear in it most frequently.
Not to use cavalry against unbroken infantry except in some case of special emergency, only to use firearms
within effective range in the combat, to spare the forces as much as possible for the final strugglethese are
tactical principles. None of them can be applied absolutely in every case, but they must always be present to
the mind of the Chief, in order that the benefit of the truth contained in them may not be lost in cases where
that truth can be of advantage.
If from the unusual cooking by an enemy's camp his movement is inferred, if the intentional exposure of
troops in a combat indicates a false attack, then this way of discerning the truth is called rule, because from a
single visible circumstance that conclusion is drawn which corresponds with the same.
If it is a rule to attack the enemy with renewed vigour, as soon as he begins to limber up his artillery in the
combat, then on this particular fact depends a course of action which is aimed at the general situation of the
enemy as inferred from the above fact, namely, that he is about to give up the fight, that he is commencing to
On War
On War 68
Page No 71
draw off his troops, and is neither capable of making a serious stand while thus drawing off nor of making his
retreat gradually in good order.
REGULATIONS and METHODS bring preparatory theories into the conduct of War, in so far as disciplined
troops are inoculated with them as active principles. The whole body of instructions for formations, drill, and
field service are regulations and methods: in the drill instructions the first predominate, in the field service
instructions the latter. To these things the real conduct of War attaches itself; it takes them over, therefore, as
given modes of proceeding, and as such they must appear in the theory of the conduct of War.
But for those activities retaining freedom in the employment of these forces there cannot be regulations, that
is, definite instructions, because they would do away with freedom of action. Methods, on the other hand, as a
general way of executing duties as they arise, calculated, as we have said, on an average of probability, or as
a dominating influence of principles and rules carried through to application, may certainly appear in the
theory of the conduct of War, provided only they are not represented as something different from what they
are, not as the absolute and necessary modes of action (systems), but as the best of general forms which may
be used as shorter ways in place of a particular disposition for the occasion, at discretion.
But the frequent application of methods will be seen to be most essential and unavoidable in the conduct of
War, if we reflect how much action proceeds on mere conjecture, or in complete uncertainty, because one
side is prevented from learning all the circumstances which influence the dispositions of the other, or
because, even if these circumstances which influence the decisions of the one were really known, there is not,
owing to their extent and the dispositions they would entail, sufficient time for the other to carry out all
necessary counteracting measuresthat therefore measures in War must always be calculated on a certain
number of possibilities; if we reflect how numberless are the trifling things belonging to any single event, and
which therefore should be taken into account along with it, and that therefore there is no other means to
suppose the one counteracted by the other, and to base our arrangements only upon what is of a general
nature and probable; if we reflect lastly that, owing to the increasing number of officers as we descend the
scale of rank, less must be left to the true discernment and ripe judgment of individuals the lower the sphere
of action, and that when we reach those ranks where we can look for no other notions but those which the
regulations of the service and experience afford, we must help them with the methodic forms bordering on
those regulations. This will serve both as a support to their judgment and a barrier against those extravagant
and erroneous views which are so especially to be dreaded in a sphere where experience is so costly.
Besides this absolute need of method in action, we must also acknowledge that it has a positive advantage,
which is that, through the constant repetition of a formal exercise, a readiness, precision, and firmness is
attained in the movement of troops which diminishes the natural friction, and makes the machine move
easier.
Method will therefore be the more generally used, become the more indispensable, the farther down the scale
of rank the position of the active agent; and on the other hand, its use will diminish upwards, until in the
highest position it quite disappears. For this reason it is more in its place in tactics than in strategy.
War in its highest aspects consists not of an infinite number of little events, the diversities in which
compensate each other, and which therefore by a better or worse method are better or worse governed, but of
separate great decisive events which must be dealt with separately. It is not like a field of stalks, which,
without any regard to the particular form of each stalk, will be mowed better or worse, according as the
mowing instrument is good or bad, but rather as a group of large trees, to which the axe must be laid with
judgment, according to the particular form and inclination of each separate trunk.
How high up in military activity the admissibility of method in action reaches naturally determines itself, not
according to actual rank, but according to things; and it affects the highest positions in a less degree, only
On War
On War 69
Page No 72
because these positions have the most comprehensive subjects of activity. A constant order of battle, a
constant formation of advance guards and outposts, are methods by which a General ties not only his
subordinates' hands, but also his own in certain cases. Certainly they may have been devised by himself, and
may be applied by him according to circumstances, but they may also be a subject of theory, in so far as they
are based on the general properties of troops and weapons. On the other hand, any method by which definite
plans for wars or campaigns are to be given out all ready made as if from a machine are absolutely worthless.
As long as there exists no theory which can be sustained, that is, no enlightened treatise on the conduct of
War, method in action cannot but encroach beyond its proper limits in high places, for men employed in these
spheres of activity have not always had the opportunity of educating themselves, through study and through
contact with the higher interests. In the impracticable and inconsistent disquisitions of theorists and critics
they cannot find their way, their sound common sense rejects them, and as they bring with them no
knowledge but that derived from experience, therefore in those cases which admit of, and require, a free
individual treatment they readily make use of the means which experience gives themthat is, an imitation
of the particular methods practised by great Generals, by which a method of action then arises of itself. If we
see Frederick the Great's Generals always making their appearance in the socalled oblique order of battle,
the Generals of the French Revolution always using turning movements with a long, extended line of battle,
and Buonaparte's lieutenants rushing to the attack with the bloody energy of concentrated masses, then we
recognise in the recurrence of the mode of proceeding evidently an adopted method, and see therefore that
method of action can reach up to regions bordering on the highest. Should an improved theory facilitate the
study of the conduct of War, form the mind and judgment of men who are rising to the highest commands,
then also method in action will no longer reach so far, and so much of it as is to be considered indispensable
will then at least be formed from theory itself, and not take place out of mere imitation. However
preeminently a great Commander does things, there is always something subjective in the way he does
them; and if he has a certain manner, a large share of his individuality is contained in it which does not
always accord with the individuality of the person who copies his manner.
At the same time, it would neither be possible nor right to banish subjective methodicism or manner
completely from the conduct of War: it is rather to be regarded as a manifestation of that influence which the
general character of a War has upon its separate events, and to which satisfaction can only be done in that
way if theory is not able to foresee this general character and include it in its considerations. What is more
natural than that the War of the French Revolution had its own way of doing things? and what theory could
ever have included that peculiar method? The evil is only that such a manner originating in a special case
easily outlives itself, becausecontinues whilst circumstances imperceptibly change. This is what theory
should prevent by lucid and rational criticism. When in the year 1806 the Prussian Generals, Prince Louis at
Saalfeld, Tauentzien on the Dornberg near Jena, Grawert before and Ruechel behind Kappellendorf, all threw
themselves into the open jaws of destruction in the oblique order of Frederick the Great, and managed to ruin
Hohenlohe's Army in a way that no Army was ever ruined, even on the field of battle, all this was done
through a manner which had outlived its day, together with the most downright stupidity to which
methodicism ever led.
CHAPTER V. CRITICISM
THE influence of theoretical principles upon real life is produced more through criticism than through
doctrine, for as criticism is an application of abstract truth to real events, therefore it not only brings truth of
this description nearer to life, but also accustoms the understanding more to such truths by the constant
repetition of their application. We therefore think it necessary to fix the point of view for criticism next to
that for theory.
On War
On War 70
Page No 73
From the simple narration of an historical occurrence which places events in chronological order, or at most
only touches on their more immediate causes, we separate the CRITICAL.
In this CRITICAL three different operations of the mind may be observed.
First, the historical investigation and determining of doubtful facts. This is properly historical research, and
has nothing in common with theory.
Secondly, the tracing of effects to causes. This is the REAL CRITICAL INQUIRY; it is indispensable to
theory, for everything which in theory is to be established, supported, or even merely explained, by
experience can only be settled in this way.
Thirdly, the testing of the means employed. This is criticism, properly speaking, in which praise and censure
is contained. This is where theory helps history, or rather, the teaching to be derived from it.
In these two last strictly critical parts of historical study, all depends on tracing things to their primary
elements, that is to say, up to undoubted truths, and not, as is so often done, resting halfway, that is, on some
arbitrary assumption or supposition.
As respects the tracing of effect to cause, that is often attended with the insuperable difficulty that the real
causes are not known. In none of the relations of life does this so frequently happen as in War, where events
are seldom fully known, and still less motives, as the latter have been, perhaps purposely, concealed by the
chief actor, or have been of such a transient and accidental character that they have been lost for history. For
this reason critical narration must generally proceed hand in hand with historical investigation, and still such
a want of connection between cause and effect will often present itself, that it does not seem justifiable to
consider effects as the necessary results of known causes. Here, therefore,must occur, that is, historical results
which cannot be made use of for teaching. All that theory can demand is that the investigation should be
rigidly conducted up to that point, and there leave off without drawing conclusions. A real evil springs up
only if the known is made perforce to suffice as an explanation of effects, and thus a false importance is
ascribed to it.
Besides this difficulty, critical inquiry also meets with another great and intrinsic one, which is that the
progress of events in War seldom proceeds from one simple cause, but from several in common, and that it
therefore is not sufficient to follow up a series of events to their origin in a candid and impartial spirit, but
that it is then also necessary to apportion to each contributing cause its due weight. This leads, therefore, to a
closer investigation of their nature, and thus a critical investigation may lead into what is the proper field of
theory.
The critical CONSIDERATION, that is, the testing of the means, leads to the question, Which are the effects
peculiar to the means applied, and whether these effects were comprehended in the plans of the person
directing?
The effects peculiar to the means lead to the investigation of their nature, and thus again into the field of
theory.
We have already seen that in criticism all depends upon attaining to positive truth; therefore, that we must not
stop at arbitrary propositions which are not allowed by others, and to which other perhaps equally arbitrary
assertions may again be opposed, so that there is no end to pros and cons; the whole is without result, and
therefore without instruction.
We have seen that both the search for causes and the examination of means lead into the field of theory; that
On War
On War 71
Page No 74
is, into the field of universal truth, which does not proceed solely from the case immediately under
examination. If there is a theory which can be used, then the critical consideration will appeal to the proofs
there afforded, and the examination may there stop. But where no such theoretical truth is to be found, the
inquiry must be pushed up to the original elements. If this necessity occurs often, it must lead the historian
(according to a common expression) into a labyrinth of details. He then has his hands full, and it is
impossible for him to stop to give the requisite attention everywhere; the consequence is, that in order to set
bounds to his investigation, he adopts some arbitrary assumptions which, if they do not appear so to him, do
so to others, as they are not evident in themselves or capable of proof.
A sound theory is therefore an essential foundation for criticism, and it is impossible for it, without the
assistance of a sensible theory, to attain to that point at which it commences chiefly to be instructive, that is,
where it becomes demonstration, both convincing and sans re'plique.
But it would be a visionary hope to believe in the possibility of a theory applicable to every abstract truth,
leaving nothing for criticism to do but to place the case under its appropriate law: it would be ridiculous
pedantry to lay down as a rule for criticism that it must always halt and turn round on reaching the boundaries
of sacred theory. The same spirit of analytical inquiry which is the origin of theory must also guide the critic
in his work; and it can and must therefore happen that he strays beyond the boundaries of the province of
theory and elucidates those points with which he is more particularly concerned. It is more likely, on the
contrary, that criticism would completely fail in its object if it degenerated into a mechanical application of
theory. All positive results of theoretical inquiry, all principles, rules, and methods, are the more wanting in
generality and positive truth the more they become positive doctrine. They exist to offer themselves for use as
required, and it must always be left for judgment to decide whether they are suitable or not. Such results of
theory must never be used in criticism as rules or norms for a standard, but in the same way as the person
acting should use them, that is, merely as aids to judgment. If it is an acknowledged principle in tactics that in
the usual order of battle cavalry should be placed behind infantry, not in line with it, still it would be folly on
this account to condemn every deviation from this principle. Criticism must investigate the grounds of the
deviation, and it is only in case these are insufficient that it has a right to appeal to principles laid down in
theory. If it is further established in theory that a divided attack diminishes the probability of success, still it
would be just as unreasonable, whenever there is a divided attack and an unsuccessful issue, to regard the
latter as the result of the former, without further investigation into the connection between the two, as where a
divided attack is successful to infer from it the fallacy of that theoretical principle. The spirit of investigation
which belongs to criticism cannot allow either. Criticism therefore supports itself chiefly on the results of the
analytical investigation of theory; what has been made out and determined by theory does not require to be
demonstrated over again by criticism, and it is so determined by theory that criticism may find it ready
demonstrated.
This office of criticism, of examining the effect produced by certain causes, and whether a means applied has
answered its object, will be easy enough if cause and effect, means and end, are all near together.
If an Army is surprised, and therefore cannot make a regular and intelligent use of its powers and resources,
then the effect of the surprise is not doubtful.If theory has determined that in a battle the convergent form
of attack is calculated to produce greater but less certain results, then the question is whether he who employs
that convergent form had in view chiefly that greatness of result as his object; if so, the proper means were
chosen. But if by this form he intended to make the result more certain, and that expectation was founded not
on some exceptional circumstances (in this case), but on the general nature of the convergent form, as has
happened a hundred times, then he mistook the nature of the means and committed an error.
Here the work of military investigation and criticism is easy, and it will always be so when confined to the
immediate effects and objects. This can be done quite at option, if we abstract the connection of the parts with
the whole, and only look at things in that relation.
On War
On War 72
Page No 75
But in War, as generally in the world, there is a connection between everything which belongs to a whole;
and therefore, however small a cause may be in itself, its effects reach to the end of the act of warfare, and
modify or influence the final result in some degree, let that degree be ever so small. In the same manner every
means must be felt up to the ultimate object.
We can therefore trace the effects of a cause as long as events are worth noticing, and in the same way we
must not stop at the testing of a means for the immediate object, but test also this object as a means to a
higher one, and thus ascend the series of facts in succession, until we come to one so absolutely necessary in
its nature as to require no examination or proof. In many cases, particularly in what concerns great and
decisive measures, the investigation must be carried to the final aim, to that which leads immediately to
peace.
It is evident that in thus ascending, at every new station which we reach a new point of view for the judgment
is attained, so that the same means which appeared advisable at one station, when looked at from the next
above it may have to be rejected.
The search for the causes of events and the comparison of means with ends must always go hand in hand in
the critical review of an act, for the investigation of causes leads us first to the discovery of those things
which are worth examining.
This following of the clue up and down is attended with considerable difficulty, for the farther from an event
the cause lies which we are looking for, the greater must be the number of other causes which must at the
same time be kept in view and allowed for in reference to the share which they have in the course of events,
and then eliminated, because the higher the importance of a fact the greater will be the number of separate
forces and circumstances by which it is conditioned. If we have unravelled the causes of a battle being lost,
we have certainly also ascertained a part of the causes of the consequences which this defeat has upon the
whole War, but only a part, because the effects of other causes, more or less according to circumstances, will
flow into the final result.
The same multiplicity of circumstances is presented also in the examination of the means the higher our point
of view, for the higher the object is situated, the greater must be the number of means employed to reach it.
The ultimate object of the War is the object aimed at by all the Armies simultaneously, and it is therefore
necessary that the consideration should embrace all that each has done or could have done.
It is obvious that this may sometimes lead to a wide field of inquiry, in which it is easy to wander and lose the
way, and in which this difficulty prevailsthat a number of assumptions or suppositions must be made about
a variety of things which do not actually appear, but which in all probability did take place, and therefore
cannot possibly be left out of consideration.
When Buonaparte, in 1797,[*] at the head of the Army of Italy, advanced from the Tagliamento against the
Archduke Charles, he did so with a view to force that General to a decisive action before the reinforcements
expected from the Rhine had reached him. If we look, only at the immediate object, the means were well
chosen and justified by the result, for the Archduke was so inferior in numbers that he only made a show of
resistance on the Tagliamento, and when he saw his adversary so strong and resolute, yielded ground, and left
open the passages, of the Norican Alps. Now to what use could Buonaparte turn this fortunate event? To
penetrate into the heart of the Austrian empire itself, to facilitate the advance of the Rhine Armies under
Moreau and Hoche, and open communication with them? This was the view taken by Buonaparte, and from
this point of view he was right. But now, if criticism places itself at a higher point of viewnamely, that of
the French Directory, which body could see and know that the Armies on the Rhine could not commence the
campaign for six weeks, then the advance of Buonaparte over the Norican Alps can only be regarded as an
extremely hazardous measure; for if the Austrians had drawn largely on their Rhine Armies to reinforce their
On War
On War 73
Page No 76
Army in Styria, so as to enable the Archduke to fall upon the Army of Italy, not only would that Army have
been routed, but the whole campaign lost. This consideration, which attracted the serious attention of
Buonaparte at Villach, no doubt induced him to sign the armistice of Leoben with so much readiness.
[*] Compare Hinterlassene Werke, 2nd edition, vol. iv. p. 276 et seq.
If criticism takes a still higher position, and if it knows that the Austrians had no reserves between the Army
of the Archduke Charles and Vienna, then we see that Vienna became threatened by the advance of the Army
of Italy.
Supposing that Buonaparte knew that the capital was thus uncovered, and knew that he still retained the same
superiority in numbers over the Archduke as he had in Styria, then his advance against the heart of the
Austrian States was no longer without purpose, and its value depended on the value which the Austrians
might place on preserving their capital. If that was so great that, rather than lose it, they would accept the
conditions of peace which Buonaparte was ready to offer them, it became an object of the first importance to
threaten Vienna. If Buonaparte had any reason to know this, then criticism may stop there, but if this point
was only problematical, then criticism must take a still higher position, and ask what would have followed if
the Austrians had resolved to abandon Vienna and retire farther into the vast dominions still left to them. But
it is easy to see that this question cannot be answered without bringing into the consideration the probable
movements of the Rhine Armies on both sides. Through the decided superiority of numbers on the side of the
French 130,000 to 80,000there could be little doubt of the result; but then next arises the question, What
use would the Directory make of a victory; whether they would follow up their success to the opposite
frontiers of the Austrian monarchy, therefore to the complete breaking up or overthrow of that power, or
whether they would be satisfied with the conquest of a considerable portion to serve as a security for peace?
The probable result in each case must be estimated, in order to come to a conclusion as to the probable
determination of the Directory. Supposing the result of these considerations to be that the French forces were
much too weak for the complete subjugation of the Austrian monarchy, so that the attempt might completely
reverse the respective positions of the contending Armies, and that even the conquest and occupation of a
considerable district of country would place the French Army in strategic relations to which they were not
equal, then that result must naturally influence the estimate of the position of the Army of Italy, and compel it
to lower its expectations. And this, it was no doubt which influenced Buonaparte, although fully aware of the
helpless condition of the Archduke, still to sign the peace of Campo Formio, which imposed no greater
sacrifices on the Austrians than the loss of provinces which, even if the campaign took the most favourable
turn for them, they could not have reconquered. But the French could not have reckoned on even the
moderate treaty of Campo Formio, and therefore it could not have been their object in making their bold
advance if two considerations had not presented themselves to their view, the first of which consisted in the
question, what degree of value the Austrians would attach to each of the abovementioned results; whether,
notwithstanding the probability of a satisfactory result in either of these cases, would it be worth while to
make the sacrifices inseparable from a continuance of the War, when they could be spared those sacrifices by
a peace on terms not too humiliating? The second consideration is the question whether the Austrian
Government, instead of seriously weighing the possible results of a resistance pushed to extremities, would
not prove completely disheartened by the impression of their present reverses.
The consideration which forms the subject of the first is no idle piece of subtle argument, but a consideration
of such decidedly practical importance that it comes up whenever the plan of pushing War to the utmost
extremity is mooted, and by its weight in most cases restrains the execution of such plans.
The second consideration is of equal importance, for we do not make War with an abstraction but with a
reality, which we must always keep in view, and we may be sure that it was not overlooked by the bold
Buonaparte that is, that he was keenly alive to the terror which the appearance of his sword inspired. It was
reliance on that which led him to Moscow. There it led him into a scrape. The terror of him had been
On War
On War 74
Page No 77
weakened by the gigantic struggles in which he had been engaged; in the year 1797 it was still fresh, and the
secret of a resistance pushed to extremities had not been discovered; nevertheless even in 1797 his boldness
might have led to a negative result if, as already said, he had not with a sort of presentiment avoided it by
signing the moderate peace of Campo Formio.
We must now bring these considerations to a close they will suffice to show the wide sphere, the diversity
and embarrassing nature of the subjects embraced in a critical examination carried to the fullest extent, that is,
to those measures of a great and decisive class which must necessarily be included. It follows from them that
besides a theoretical acquaintance with the subject, natural talent must also have a great influence on the
value of critical examinations, for it rests chiefly with the latter to throw the requisite light on the
interrelations of things, and to distinguish from amongst the endless connections of events those which are
really essential.
But talent is also called into requisition in another way. Critical examination is not merely the appreciation of
those means which have been actually employed, but also of all possible means, which therefore must be
suggested in the first placethat is, must be discovered; and the use of any particular means is not fairly
open to censure until a better is pointed out. Now, however small the number of possible combinations may
be in most cases, still it must be admitted that to point out those which have not been used is not a mere
analysis of actual things, but a spontaneous creation which cannot be prescribed, and depends on the fertility
of genius.
We are far from seeing a field for great genius in a case which admits only of the application of a few simple
combinations, and we think it exceedingly ridiculous to hold up, as is often done, the turning of a position as
an invention showing the highest genius; still nevertheless this creative selfactivity on the part of the critic is
necessary, and it is one of the points which essentially determine the value of critical examination.
When Buonaparte on 30th July, 1796,[*] determined to raise the siege of Mantua, in order to march with his
whole force against the enemy, advancing in separate columns to the relief of the place, and to beat them in
detail, this appeared the surest way to the attainment of brilliant victories. These victories actually followed,
and were afterwards again repeated on a still more brilliant scale on the attempt to relieve the fortress being
again renewed. We hear only one opinion on these achievements, that of unmixed admiration.
[*] Compare Hinterlassene Werke, 2nd edition, vol. iv. p. 107 et seq.
At the same time, Buonaparte could not have adopted this course on the 30th July without quite giving up the
idea of the siege of Mantua, because it was impossible to save the siege train, and it could not be replaced by
another in this campaign. In fact, the siege was converted into a blockade, and the town, which if the siege
had continued must have very shortly fallen, held out for six months in spite of Buonaparte's victories in the
open field.
Criticism has generally regarded this as an evil that was unavoidable, because critics have not been able to
suggest any better course. Resistance to a relieving Army within lines of circumvallation had fallen into such
disrepute and contempt that it appears to have entirely escaped consideration as a means. And yet in the reign
of Louis XIV. that measure was so often used with success that we can only attribute to the force of fashion
the fact that a hundred years later it never occurred to any one even to propose such a measure. If the
practicability of such a plan had ever been entertained for a moment, a closer consideration of circumstances
would have shown that 40,000 of the best infantry in the world under Buonaparte, behind strong lines of
circumvallation round Mantua, had so little to fear from the 50,000 men coming to the relief under Wurmser,
that it was very unlikely that any attempt even would be made upon their lines. We shall not seek here to
establish this point, but we believe enough has been said to show that this means was one which had a right to
a share of consideration. Whether Buonaparte himself ever thought of such a plan we leave undecided;
On War
On War 75
Page No 78
neither in his memoirs nor in other sources is there any trace to be found of his having done so; in no critical
works has it been touched upon, the measure being one which the mind had lost sight of. The merit of
resuscitating the idea of this means is not great, for it suggests itself at once to any one who breaks loose from
the trammels of fashion. Still it is necessary that it should suggest itself for us to bring it into consideration
and compare it with the means which Buonaparte employed. Whatever may be the result of the comparison, it
is one which should not be omitted by criticism.
When Buonaparte, in February, 1814,[*] after gaining the battles at Etoges, ChampAubert, and Montmirail,
left Bluecher's Army, and turning upon Schwartzenberg, beat his troops at Montereau and Mormant, every
one was filled with admiration, because Buonaparte, by thus throwing his concentrated force first upon one
opponent, then upon another, made a brilliant use of the mistakes which his adversaries had committed in
dividing their forces. If these brilliant strokes in different directions failed to save him, it was generally
considered to be no fault of his, at least. No one has yet asked the question, What would have been the result
if, instead of turning from Bluecher upon Schwartzenberg, he had tried another blow at Bluecher, and
pursued him to the Rhine? We are convinced that it would have completely changed the course of the
campaign, and that the Army of the Allies, instead of marching to Paris, would have retired behind the Rhine.
We do not ask others to share our conviction, but no one who understands the thing will doubt, at the mere
mention of this alternative course, that it is one which should not be overlooked in criticism.
[*] Compare Hinterlassene Werks, 2nd edition. vol. vii. p. 193 et seq.
In this case the means of comparison lie much more on the surface than in the foregoing, but they have been
equally overlooked, because onesided views have prevailed, and there has been no freedom of judgment.
From the necessity of pointing out a better means which might have been used in place of those which are
condemned has arisen the form of criticism almost exclusively in use, which contents itself with pointing out
the better means without demonstrating in what the superiority consists. The consequence is that some are not
convinced, that others start up and do the same thing, and that thus discussion arises which is without any
fixed basis for the argument. Military literature abounds with matter of this sort.
The demonstration we require is always necessary when the superiority of the means propounded is not so
evident as to leave no room for doubt, and it consists in the examination of each of the means on its own
merits, and then of its comparison with the object desired. When once the thing is traced back to a simple
truth, controversy must cease, or at all events a new result is obtained, whilst by the other plan the pros and
cons go on for ever consuming each other.
Should we, for example, not rest content with assertion in the case before mentioned, and wish to prove that
the persistent pursuit of Bluecher would have been more advantageous than the turning on Schwartzenberg,
we should support the arguments on the following simple truths:
1. In general it is more advantageous to continue our blows in one and the same direction, because there is a
loss of time in striking in different directions; and at a point where the moral power is already shaken by
considerable losses there is the more reason to expect fresh successes, therefore in that way no part of the
preponderance already gained is left idle.
2. Because Bluecher, although weaker than Schwartzenberg, was, on account of his enterprising spirit, the
more important adversary; in him, therefore, lay the centre of attraction which drew the others along in the
same direction.
3. Because the losses which Bluecher had sustained almost amounted to a defeat, which gave Buonaparte
such a preponderance over him as to make his retreat to the Rhine almost certain, and at the same time no
On War
On War 76
Page No 79
reserves of any consequence awaited him there.
4. Because there was no other result which would be so terrific in its aspects, would appear to the imagination
in such gigantic proportions, an immense advantage in dealing with a Staff so weak and irresolute as that of
Schwartzenberg notoriously was at this time. What had happened to the Crown Prince of Wartemberg at
Montereau, and to Count Wittgenstein at Mormant, Prince Schwartzenberg must have known well enough;
but all the untoward events on Bluecher's distant and separate line from the Marne to the Rhine would only
reach him by the avalanche of rumour. The desperate movements which Buonaparte made upon Vitry at the
end of March, to see what the Allies would do if he threatened to turn them strategically, were evidently done
on the principle of working on their fears; but it was done under far different circumstances, in consequence
of his defeat at Laon and Arcis, and because Bluecher, with 100,000 men, was then in communication with
Schwartzenberg.
There are people, no doubt, who will not be convinced on these arguments, but at all events they cannot retort
by saying, that "whilst Buonaparte threatened Schwartzenberg's base by advancing to the Rhine,
Schwartzenberg at the same time threatened Buonaparte's communications with Paris," because we have
shown by the reasons above given that Schwartzenberg would never have thought of marching on Paris.
With respect to the example quoted by us from the campaign of 1796, we should say: Buonaparte looked
upon the plan he adopted as the surest means of beating the Austrians; but admitting that it was so, still the
object to be attained was only an empty victory, which could have hardly any sensible influence on the fall of
Mantua. The way which we should have chosen would, in our opinion, have been much more certain to
prevent the relief of Mantua; but even if we place ourselves in the position of the French General and assume
that it was not so, and look upon the certainty of success to have been less, the question then amounts to a
choice between a more certain but less useful, and therefore less important, victory on the one hand, and a
somewhat less probable but far more decisive and important victory, on the other hand. Presented in this
form, boldness must have declared for the second solution, which is the reverse of what took place, when the
thing was only superficially viewed. Buonaparte certainly was anything but deficient in boldness, and we
may be sure that he did not see the whole case and its consequences as fully and clearly as we can at the
present time.
Naturally the critic, in treating of the means, must often appeal to military history, as experience is of more
value in the Art of War than all philosophical truth. But this exemplification from history is subject to certain
conditions, of which we shall treat in a special chapter and unfortunately these conditions are so seldom
regarded that reference to history generally only serves to increase the confusion of ideas.
We have still a most important subject to consider, which is, How far criticism in passing judgments on
particular events is permitted, or in duty bound, to make use of its wider view of things, and therefore also of
that which is shown by results; or when and where it should leave out of sight these things in order to place
itself, as far as possible, in the exact position of the chief actor?
If criticism dispenses praise or censure, it should seek to place itself as nearly as possible at the same point of
view as the person acting, that is to say, to collect all he knew and all the motives on which he acted, and, on
the other hand, to leave out of the consideration all that the person acting could not or did not know, and
above all, the result. But this is only an object to aim at, which can never be reached because the state of
circumstances from which an event proceeded can never be placed before the eye of the critic exactly as it lay
before the eye of the person acting. A number of inferior circumstances, which must have influenced the
result, are completely lost to sight, and many a subjective motive has never come to light.
The latter can only be learnt from the memoirs of the chief actor, or from his intimate friends; and in such
things of this kind are often treated of in a very desultory manner, or purpusely misrepresented. Criticism
On War
On War 77
Page No 80
must, therefore, always forego much which was present in the minds of those whose acts are criticised.
On the other hand, it is much more difficult to leave out of sight that which criticism knows in excess. This is
only easy as regards accidental circumstances, that is, circumstances which have been mixed up, but are in no
way necessarily related. But it is very difficult, and, in fact, can never be completely done with regard to
things really essential.
Let us take first, the result. If it has not proceeded from accidental circumstances, it is almost impossible that
the knowledge of it should not have an effect on the judgment passed on events which have preceded it, for
we see these things in the light of this result, and it is to a certain extent by it that we first become acquainted
with them and appreciate them. Military history, with all its events, is a source of instruction for criticism
itself, and it is only natural that criticism should throw that light on things which it has itself obtained from
the consideration of the whole. If therefore it might wish in some cases to leave the result out of the
consideration, it would be impossible to do so completely.
But it is not only in relation to the result, that is, with what takes place at the last, that this embarrassment
arises; the same occurs in relation to preceding events, therefore with the data which furnished the motives to
action. Criticism has before it, in most cases, more information on this point than the principal in the
transaction. Now it may seem easy to dismiss from the consideration everything of this nature, but it is not so
easy as we may think. The knowledge of preceding and concurrent events is founded not only on certain
information, but on a number of conjectures and suppositions; indeed, there is hardly any of the information
respecting things not purely accidental which has not been preceded by suppositions or conjectures destined
to take the place of certain information in case such should never be supplied. Now is it conceivable that
criticism in after times, which has before it as facts all the preceding and concurrent circumstances, should
not allow itself to be thereby influenced when it asks itself the question, What portion of the circumstances,
which at the moment of action were unknown, would it have held to be probable? We maintain that in this
case, as in the case of the results, and for the same reason, it is impossible to disregard all these things
completely.
If therefore the critic wishes to bestow praise or blame upon any single act, he can only succeed to a certain
degree in placing himself in the position of the person whose act he has under review. In many cases he can
do so sufficiently near for any practical purpose, but in many instances it is the very reverse, and this fact
should never be overlooked.
But it is neither necessary nor desirable that criticism should completely identify itself with the person acting.
In War, as in all matters of skill, there is a certain natural aptitude required which is called talent. This may be
great or small. In the first case it may easily be superior to that of the critic, for what critic can pretend to the
skill of a Frederick or a Buonaparte? Therefore, if criticism is not to abstain altogether from offering an
opinion where eminent talent is concerned, it must be allowed to make use of the advantage which its
enlarged horizon affords. Criticism must not, therefore, treat the solution of a problem by a great General like
a sum in arithmetic; it is only through the results and through the exact coincidences of events that it can
recognise with admiration how much is due to the exercise of genius, and that it first learns the essential
combination which the glance of that genius devised.
But for every, even the smallest, act of genius it is necessary that criticism should take a higher point of view,
so that, having at command many objective grounds of decision, it may be as little subjective as possible, and
that the critic may not take the limited scope of his own mind as a standard.
This elevated position of criticism, its praise and blame pronounced with a full knowledge of all the
circumstances, has in itself nothing which hurts our feelings; it only does so if the critic pushes himself
forward, and speaks in a tone as if all the wisdom which he has obtained by an exhaustive examination of the
On War
On War 78
Page No 81
event under consideration were really his own talent. Palpable as is this deception, it is one which people may
easily fall into through vanity, and one which is naturally distasteful to others. It very often happens that
although the critic has no such arrogant pretensions, they are imputed to him by the reader because he has not
expressly disclaimed them, and then follows immediately a charge of a want of the power of critical
judgment.
If therefore a critic points out an error made by a Frederick or a Buonaparte, that does not mean that he who
makes the criticism would not have committed the same error; he may even be ready to grant that had he
been in the place of these great Generals he might have made much greater mistakes; he merely sees this
error from the chain of events, and he thinks that it should not have escaped the sagacity of the General.
This is, therefore, an opinion formed through the connection of events, and therefore through the RESULT.
But there is another quite different effect of the result itself upon the judgment, that is if it is used quite alone
as an example for or against the soundness of a measure. This may be called JUDGMENT ACCORDING TO
THE RESULT. Such a judgment appears at first sight inadmissible, and yet it is not.
When Buonaparte marched to Moscow in 1812, all depended upon whether the taking of the capital, and the
events which preceded the capture, would force the Emperor Alexander to make peace, as he had been
compelled to do after the battle of Friedland in 1807, and the Emperor Francis in 1805 and 1809 after
Austerlitz and Wagram; for if Buonaparte did not obtain a peace at Moscow, there was no alternative but to
returnthat is, there was nothing for him but a strategic defeat. We shall leave out of the question what he
did to get to Moscow, and whether in his advance he did not miss many opportunities of bringing the
Emperor Alexander to peace; we shall also exclude all consideration of the disastrous circumstances which
attended his retreat, and which perhaps had their origin in the general conduct of the campaign. Still the
question remains the same, for however much more brilliant the course of the campaign up to Moscow might
have been, still there was always an uncertainty whether the Emperor Alexander would be intimidated into
making peace; and then, even if a retreat did not contain in itself the seeds of such disasters as did in fact
occur, still it could never be anything else than a great strategic defeat. If the Emperor Alexander agreed to a
peace which was disadvantageous to him, the campaign of 1812 would have ranked with those of Austerlitz,
Friedland, and Wagram. But these campaigns also, if they had not led to peace, would in all probability have
ended in similar catastrophes. Whatever, therefore, of genius, skill, and energy the Conqueror of the World
applied to the task, this last question addressed to fate[*] remained always the same. Shall we then discard the
campaigns of 1805, 1807, 1809, and say on account of the campaign of 1812 that they were acts of
imprudence; that the results were against the nature of things, and that in 1812 strategic justice at last found
vent for itself in opposition to blind chance? That would be an unwarrantable conclusion, a most arbitrary
judgment, a case only half proved, because no human, eye can trace the thread of the necessary connection of
events up to the determination of the conquered Princes.
[*] "Frage an der Schicksal,"a familiar quotation from Schiller.TR.
Still less can we say the campaign of 1812 merited the same success as the others, and that the reason why it
turned out otherwise lies in something unnatural, for we cannot regard the firmness of Alexander as
something unpredictable.
What can be more natural than to say that in the years 1805, 1807, 1809, Buonaparte judged his opponents
correctly, and that in 1812 he erred in that point? On the former occasions, therefore, he was right, in the
latter wrong, and in both cases we judge by the RESULT.
All action in War, as we have already said, is directed on probable, not on certain, results. Whatever is
wanting in certainty must always be left to fate, or chance, call it which you will. We may demand that what
is so left should be as little as possible, but only in relation to the particular casethat is, as little as is
On War
On War 79
Page No 82
possible in this one case, but not that the case in which the least is left to chance is always to be preferred.
That would be an enormous error, as follows from all our theoretical views. There are cases in which the
greatest daring is the greatest wisdom.
Now in everything which is left to chance by the chief actor, his personal merit, and therefore his
responsibility as well, seems to be completely set aside; nevertheless we cannot suppress an inward feeling of
satisfaction whenever expectation realises itself, and if it disappoints us our mind is dissatisfied; and more
than this of right and wrong should not be meant by the judgment which we form from the mere result, or
rather that we find there.
Nevertheless, it cannot be denied that the satisfaction which our mind experiences at success, the pain caused
by failure, proceed from a sort of mysterious feeling; we suppose between that success ascribed to good
fortune and the genius of the chief a fine connecting thread, invisible to the mind's eye, and the supposition
gives pleasure. What tends to confirm this idea is that our sympathy increases, becomes more decided, if the
successes and defeats of the principal actor are often repeated. Thus it becomes intelligible how good luck in
War assumes a much nobler nature than good luck at play. In general, when a fortunate warrior does not
otherwise lessen our interest in his behalf, we have a pleasure in accompanying him in his career.
Criticism, therefore, after having weighed all that comes within the sphere of human reason and conviction,
will let the result speak for that part where the deep mysterious relations are not disclosed in any visible form,
and will protect this silent sentence of a higher authority from the noise of crude opinions on the one hand,
while on the other it prevents the gross abuse which might be made of this last tribunal.
This verdict of the result must therefore always bring forth that which human sagacity cannot discover; and it
will be chiefly as regards the intellectual powers and operations that it will be called into requisition, partly
because they can be estimated with the least certainty, partly because their close connection with the will is
favourable to their exercising over it an important influence. When fear or bravery precipitates the decision,
there is nothing objective intervening between them for our consideration, and consequently nothing by
which sagacity and calculation might have met the probable result.
We must now be allowed to make a few observations on the instrument of criticism, that is, the language
which it uses, because that is to a certain extent connected with the action in War; for the critical examination
is nothing more than the deliberation which should precede action in War. We therefore think it very essential
that the language used in criticism should have the same character as that which deliberation in War must
have, for otherwise it would cease to be practical, and criticism could gain no admittance in actual life.
We have said in our observations on the theory of the conduct of War that it should educate the mind of the
Commander for War, or that its teaching should guide his education; also that it is not intended to furnish him
with positive doctrines and systems which he can use like mental appliances. But if the construction of
scientific formulae is never required, or even allowable, in War to aid the decision on the case presented, if
truth does not appear there in a systematic shape, if it is not found in an indirect way, but directly by the
natural perception of the mind, then it must be the same also in a critical review.
It is true as we have seen that, wherever complete demonstration of the nature of things would be too tedious,
criticism must support itself on those truths which theory has established on the point. But, just as in War the
actor obeys these theoretical truths rather because his mind is imbued with them than because he regards
them as objective inflexible laws, so criticism must also make use of them, not as an external law or an
algebraic formula, of which fresh proof is not required each time they are applied, but it must always throw a
light on this proof itself, leaving only to theory the more minute and circumstantial proof. Thus it avoids a
mysterious, unintelligible phraseology, and makes its progress in plain language, that is, with a clear and
always visible chain of ideas.
On War
On War 80
Page No 83
Certainly this cannot always be completely attained, but it must always be the aim in critical expositions.
Such expositions must use complicated forms of science as sparingly as possible, and never resort to the
construction of scientific aids as of a truth apparatus of its own, but always be guided by the natural and
unbiassed impressions of the mind.
But this pious endeavour, if we may use the expression, has unfortunately seldom hitherto presided over
critical examinations: the most of them have rather been emanations of a species of vanitya wish to make a
display of ideas.
The first evil which we constantly stumble upon is a lame, totally inadmissible application of certain one
sided systems as of a formal code of laws. But it is never difficult to show the onesidedness of such systems,
and this only requires to be done once to throw discredit for ever on critical judgments which are based on
them. We have here to deal with a definite subject, and as the number of possible systems after all can be but
small, therefore also they are themselves the lesser evil.
Much greater is the evil which lies in the pompous retinue of technical termsscientific expressions and
metaphors, which these systems carry in their train, and which like a rabblelike the baggage of an Army
broken away from its Chiefhang about in all directions. Any critic who has not adopted a system, either
because he has not found one to please him, or because he has not yet been able to make himself master of
one, will at least occasionally make use of a piece of one, as one would use a ruler, to show the blunders
committed by a General. The most of them are incapable of reasoning without using as a help here and there
some shreds of scientific military theory. The smallest of these fragments, consisting in mere scientific words
and metaphors, are often nothing more than ornamental flourishes of critical narration. Now it is in the nature
of things that all technical and scientific expressions which belong to a system lose their propriety, if they
ever had any, as soon as they are distorted, and used as general axioms, or as small crystalline talismans,
which have more power of demonstration than simple speech.
Thus it has come to pass that our theoretical and critical books, instead of being straightforward, intelligible
dissertations, in which the author always knows at least what he says and the reader what he reads, are
brimful of these technical terms, which form dark points of interference where author and reader part
company. But frequently they are something worse, being nothing but hollow shells without any kernel. The
author himself has no clear perception of what he means, contents himself with vague ideas, which if
expressed in plain language would be unsatisfactory even to himself.
A third fault in criticism is the MISUSE of HISTORICAL EXAMPLES, and a display of great reading or
learning. What the history of the Art of War is we have already said, and we shall further explain our views
on examples and on military history in general in special chapters. One fact merely touched upon in a very
cursory manner may be used to support the most opposite views, and three or four such facts of the most
heterogeneous description, brought together out of the most distant lands and remote times and heaped up,
generally distract and bewilder the judgment and understanding without demonstrating anything; for when
exposed to the light they turn out to be only trumpery rubbish, made use of to show off the author's learning.
But what can be gained for practical life by such obscure, partly false, confused arbitrary conceptions? So
little is gained that theory on account of them has always been a true antithesis of practice, and frequently a
subject of ridicule to those whose soldierly qualities in the field are above question.
But it is impossible that this could have been the case, if theory in simple language, and by natural treatment
of those things which constitute the Art of making War, had merely sought to establish just so much as
admits of being established; if, avoiding all false pretensions and irrelevant display of scientific forms and
historical parallels, it had kept close to the subject, and gone hand in hand with those who must conduct
affairs in the field by their own natural genius.
On War
On War 81
Page No 84
CHAPTER VI. ON EXAMPLES
EXAMPLES from history make everything clear, and furnish the best description of proof in the empirical
sciences. This applies with more force to the Art of War than to any other. General Scharnhorst, whose
handbook is the best ever written on actual War, pronounces historical examples to be of the first importance,
and makes an admirable use of them himself. Had he survived the War in which he fell,[*] the fourth part of
his revised treatise on artillery would have given a still greater proof of the observing and enlightened spirit
in which he sifted matters of experience.
But such use of historical examples is rarely made by theoretical writers; the way in which they more
commonly make use of them is rather calculated to leave the mind unsatisfied, as well as to offend the
understanding. We therefore think it important to bring specially into view the use and abuse of historical
examples.
[*] General Scharnhorst died in 1813, of a wound received in the battle of Bautzen or Grosz
GorchenEDITOR.
Unquestionably the branches of knowledge which lie at the foundation of the Art of War come under the
denomination of empirical sciences; for although they are derived in a great measure from the nature of
things, still we can only learn this very nature itself for the most part from experience; and besides that, the
practical application is modified by so many circumstances that the effects can never be completely learnt
from the mere nature of the means.
The effects of gunpowder, that great agent in our military activity, were only learnt by experience, and up to
this hour experiments are continually in progress in order to investigate them more fully. That an iron ball to
which powder has given a velocity of 1000 feet in a second, smashes every living thing which it touches in its
course is intelligible in itself; experience is not required to tell us that; but in producing this effect how many
hundred circumstances are concerned, some of which can only be learnt by experience! And the physical is
not the only effect which we have to study, it is the moral which we are in search of, and that can only be
ascertained by experience; and there is no other way of learning and appreciating it but by experience. In the
middle ages, when firearms were first invented, their effect, owing to their rude make, was materially but
trifling compared to what it now is, but their effect morally was much greater. One must have witnessed the
firmness of one of those masses taught and led by Buonaparte, under the heaviest and most unintermittent
cannonade, in order to understand what troops, hardened by long practice in the field of danger, can do, when
by a career of victory they have reached the noble principle of demanding from themselves their utmost
efforts. In pure conception no one would believe it. On the other hand, it is well known that there are troops
in the service of European Powers at the present moment who would easily be dispersed by a few cannon
shots.
But no empirical science, consequently also no theory of the Art of War, can always corroborate its truths by
historical proof; it would also be, in some measure, difficult to support experience by single facts. If any
means is once found efficacious in War, it is repeated; one nation copies another, the thing becomes the
fashion, and in this manner it comes into use, supported by experience, and takes its place in theory, which
contents itself with appealing to experience in general in order to show its origin, but not as a verification of
its truth.
But it is quite otherwise if experience is to be used in order to overthrow some means in use, to confirm what
is doubtful, or introduce something new; then particular examples from history must be quoted as proofs.
Now, if we consider closely the use of historical proofs, four points of view readily present themselves for the
purpose.
On War
On War 82
Page No 85
First, they may be used merely as an EXPLANATION of an idea. In every abstract consideration it is very
easy to be misunderstood, or not to be intelligible at all: when an author is afraid of this, an exemplification
from history serves to throw the light which is wanted on his idea, and to ensure his being intelligible to his
reader.
Secondly, it may serve as an APPLICATION of an idea, because by means of an example there is an
opportunity of showing the action of those minor circumstances which cannot all be comprehended and
explained in any general expression of an idea; for in that consists, indeed, the difference between theory and
experience. Both these cases belong to examples properly speaking, the two following belong to historical
proofs.
Thirdly, a historical fact may be referred to particularly, in order to support what one has advanced. This is in
all cases sufficient, if we have ONLY to prove the POSSIBILITY of a fact or effect.
Lastly, in the fourth place, from the circumstantial detail of a historical event, and by collecting together
several of them, we may deduce some theory, which therefore has its true PROOF in this testimony itself.
For the first of these purposes all that is generally required is a cursory notice of the case, as it is only used
partially. Historical correctness is a secondary consideration; a case invented might also serve the purpose as
well, only historical ones are always to be preferred, because they bring the idea which they illustrate nearer
to practical life.
The second use supposes a more circumstantial relation of events, but historical authenticity is again of
secondary importance, and in respect to this point the same is to be said as in the first case.
For the third purpose the mere quotation of an undoubted fact is generally sufficient. If it is asserted that
fortified positions may fulfil their object under certain conditions, it is only necessary to mention the position
of Bunzelwitz[*] in support of the assertion.
[*] Frederick the Great's celebrated entrenched camp in 1761.
But if, through the narrative of a case in history, an abstract truth is to be demonstrated, then everything in the
case bearing on the demonstration must be analysed in the most searching and complete manner; it must, to a
certain extent, develop itself carefully before the eyes of the reader. The less effectually this is done the
weaker will be the proof, and the more necessary it will be to supply the demonstrative proof which is
wanting in the single case by a number of cases, because we have a right to suppose that the more minute
details which we are unable to give neutralise each other in their effects in a certain number of cases.
If we want to show by example derived from experience that cavalry are better placed behind than in a line
with infantry; that it is very hazardous without a decided preponderance of numbers to attempt an enveloping
movement, with widely separated columns, either on a field of battle or in the theatre of warthat is, either
tactically or strategicallythen in the first of these cases it would not be sufficient to specify some lost
battles in which the cavalry was on the flanks and some gained in which the cavalry was in rear of the
infantry; and in the tatter of these cases it is not sufficient to refer to the battles of Rivoli and Wagram, to the
attack of the Austrians on the theatre of war in Italy, in 1796, or of the French upon the German theatre of
war in the same year. The way in which these orders of battle or plans of attack essentially contributed to
disastrous issues in those particular cases must be shown by closely tracing out circumstances and
occurrences. Then it will appear how far such forms or measures are to be condemned, a point which it is
very necessary to show, for a total condemnation would be inconsistent with truth.
It has been already said that when a circumstantial detail of facts is impossible, the demonstrative power
On War
On War 83
Page No 86
which is deficient may to a certain extent be supplied by the number of cases quoted; but this is a very
dangerous method of getting out of the difficulty, and one which has been much abused. Instead of one
wellexplained example, three or four are just touched upon, and thus a show is made of strong evidence. But
there are matters where a whole dozen of cases brought forward would prove nothing, if, for instance, they
are facts of frequent occurrence, and therefore a dozen other cases with an opposite result might just as easily
be brought forward. If any one will instance a dozen lost battles in which the side beaten attacked in separate
converging columns, we can instance a dozen that have been gained in which the same order was adopted. It
is evident that in this way no result is to be obtained.
Upon carefully considering these different points, it will be seen how easily examples may be misapplied.
An occurrence which, instead of being carefully analysed in all its parts, is superficially noticed, is like an
object seen at a great distance, presenting the same appearance on each side, and in which the details of its
parts cannot be distinguished. Such examples have, in reality, served to support the most contradictory
opinions. To some Daun's campaigns are models of prudence and skill. To others, they are nothing but
examples of timidity and want of resolution. Buonaparte's passage across the Noric Alps in 1797 may be
made to appear the noblest resolution, but also as an act of sheer temerity. His strategic defeat in 1812 may be
represented as the consequence either of an excess, or of a deficiency, of energy. All these opinions have
been broached, and it is easy to see that they might very well arise, because each person takes a different
view of the connection of events. At the same time these antagonistic opinions cannot be reconciled with
each other, and therefore one of the two must be wrong.
Much as we are obliged to the worthy Feuquieres for the numerous examples introduced in his
memoirspartly because a number of historical incidents have thus been preserved which might otherwise
have been lost, and partly because he was one of the first to bring theoretical, that is, abstract, ideas into
connection with the practical in war, in so far that the cases brought forward may be regarded as intended to
exemplify and confirm what is theoretically assertedyet, in the opinion of an impartial reader, he will
hardly be allowed to have attained the object he proposed to himself, that of proving theoretical principles by
historical examples. For although he sometimes relates occurrences with great minuteness, still he falls short
very often of showing that the deductions drawn necessarily proceed from the inner relations of these events.
Another evil which comes from the superficial notice of historical events, is that some readers are either
wholly ignorant of the events, or cannot call them to remembrance sufficiently to be able to grasp the author's
meaning, so that there is no alternative between either accepting blindly what is said, or remaining
unconvinced.
It is extremely difficult to put together or unfold historical events before the eyes of a reader in such a way as
is necessary, in order to be able to use them as proofs; for the writer very often wants the means, and can
neither afford the time nor the requisite space; but we maintain that, when the object is to establish a new or
doubtful opinion, one single example, thoroughly analysed, is far more instructive than ten which are
superficially treated. The great mischief of these superficial representations is not that the writer puts his story
forward as a proof when it has only a false title, but that he has not made himself properly acquainted with
the subject, and that from this sort of slovenly, shallow treatment of history, a hundred false views and
attempts at the construction of theories arise, which would never have made their appearance if the writer had
looked upon it as his duty to deduce from the strict connection of events everything new which he brought to
market, and sought to prove from history.
When we are convinced of these difficulties in the use of historical examples, and at the same time of the
necessity (of making use of such examples), then we shall also come to the conclusion that the latest military
history is naturally the best field from which to draw them, inasmuch as it alone is sufficiently authentic and
detailed.
On War
On War 84
Page No 87
In ancient times, circumstances connected with War, as well as the method of carrying it on, were different;
therefore its events are of less use to us either theoretically or practically; in addition to which, military
history, like every other, naturally loses in the course of time a number of small traits and lineaments
originally to be seen, loses in colour and life, like a wornout or darkened picture; so that perhaps at last only
the large masses and leading features remain, which thus acquire undue proportions.
If we look at the present state of warfare, we should say that the Wars since that of the Austrian succession
are almost the only ones which, at least as far as armament, have still a considerable similarity to the present,
and which, notwithstanding the many important changes which have taken place both great and small, are
still capable of affording much instruction. It is quite otherwise with the War of the Spanish succession, as
the use of firearms had not then so far advanced towards perfection, and cavalry still continued the most
important arm. The farther we go back, the less useful becomes military history, as it gets so much the more
meagre and barren of detail. The most useless of all is that of the old world.
But this uselessness is not altogether absolute, it relates only to those subjects which depend on a knowledge
of minute details, or on those things in which the method of conducting war has changed. Although we know
very little about the tactics in the battles between the Swiss and the Austrians, the Burgundians and French,
still we find in them unmistakable evidence that they were the first in which the superiority of a good infantry
over the best cavalry was, displayed. A general glance at the time of the Condottieri teaches us how the whole
method of conducting War is dependent on the instrument used; for at no period have the forces used in War
had so much the characteristics of a special instrument, and been a class so totally distinct from the rest of the
national community. The memorable way in which the Romans in the second Punic War attacked the
Carthaginan possessions in Spain and Africa, while Hannibal still maintained himself in Italy, is a most
instructive subject to study, as the general relations of the States and Armies concerned in this indirect act of
defence are sufficiently well known.
But the more things descend into particulars and deviate in character from the most general relations, the less
we can look for examples and lessons of experience from very remote periods, for we have neither the means
of judging properly of corresponding events, nor can we apply them to our completely different method of
War.
Unfortunately, however, it has always been the fashion with historical writers to talk about ancient times. We
shall not say how far vanity and charlatanism may have had a share in this, but in general we fail to discover
any honest intention and earnest endeavour to instruct and convince, and we can therefore only look upon
such quotations and references as embellishments to fill up gaps and hide defects.
It would be an immense service to teach the Art of War entirely by historical examples, as Feuquieres
proposed to do; but it would be full work for the whole life of a man, if we reflect that he who undertakes it
must first qualify himself for the task by a long personal experience in actual War.
Whoever, stirred by ambition, undertakes such a task, let him prepare himself for his pious undertaking as for
a long pilgrimage; let him give up his time, spare no sacrifice, fear no temporal rank or power, and rise above
all feelings of personal vanity, of false shame, in order, according to the French code, to speak THE TRUTH,
THE WHOLE TRUTH, AND NOTHING BUT THE TRUTH.
On War
On War 85
Page No 88
BOOK III. OF STRATEGY IN GENERAL
CHAPTER I. STRATEGY
IN the second chapter of the second book, Strategy has been defined as "the employment of the battle as the
means towards the attainment of the object of the War." Properly speaking it has to do with nothing but the
battle, but its theory must include in this consideration the instrument of this real activitythe armed
forcein itself and in its principal relations, for the battle is fought by it, and shows its effects upon it in
turn. It must be well acquainted with the battle itself as far as relates to its possible results, and those mental
and moral powers which are the most important in the use of the same.
Strategy is the employment of the battle to gain the end of the War; it must therefore give an aim to the whole
military action, which must be in accordance with the object of the War; in other words, Strategy forms the
plan of the War, and to this end it links together the series of acts which are to lead to the final decision, that,
is to say, it makes the plans for the separate campaigns and regulates the combats to be fought in each. As
these are all things which to a great extent can only be determined on conjectures some of which turn out
incorrect, while a number of other arrangements pertaining to details cannot be made at all beforehand, it
follows, as a matter of course, that Strategy must go with the Army to the field in order to arrange particulars
on the spot, and to make the modifications in the general plan, which incessantly become necessary in War.
Strategy can therefore never take its hand from the work for a moment.
That this, however, has not always been the view taken is evident from the former custom of keeping
Strategy in the cabinet and not with the Army, a thing only allowable if the cabinet is so near to the Army
that it can be taken for the chief headquarters of the Army.
Theory will therefore attend on Strategy in the determination of its plans, or, as we may more properly say, it
will throw a light on things in themselves, and on their relations to each other, and bring out prominently the
little that there is of principle or rule.
If we recall to mind from the first chapter how many things of the highest importance War touches upon, we
may conceive that a consideration of all requires a rare grasp of mind.
A Prince or General who knows exactly how to organise his War according to his object and means, who
does neither too little nor too much, gives by that the greatest proof of his genius. But the effects of this talent
are exhibited not so much by the invention of new modes of action, which might strike the eye immediately,
as in the successful final result of the whole. It is the exact fulfilment of silent suppositions, it is the noiseless
harmony of the whole action which we should admire, and which only makes itself known in the total result.
inquirer who, tracing back from the final result, does not perceive the signs of that harmony is one who is apt
to seek for genius where it is not, and where it cannot be found.
The means and forms which Strategy uses are in fact so extremely simple, so well known by their constant
repetition, that it only appears ridiculous to sound common sense when it hears critics so frequently speaking
of them with highflown emphasis. Turning a flank, which has been done a thousand times, is regarded here
as a proof of the most brilliant genius, there as a proof of the most profound penetration, indeed even of the
most comprehensive knowledge. Can there be in the bookworld more absurd productions?[*]
[*] This paragraph refers to the works of Lloyd, Buelow, indeed to all the eighteenthcentury writers, from
whose influence we in England are not even yet free.ED.
On War
On War 86
Page No 89
It is still more ridiculous if, in addition to this, we reflect that the same critic, in accordance with prevalent
opinion, excludes all moral forces from theory, and will not allow it to be concerned with anything but the
material forces, so that all must be confined to a few mathematical relations of equilibrium and
preponderance, of time and space, and a few lines and angles. If it were nothing more than this, then out of
such a miserable business there would not be a scientific problem for even a schoolboy.
But let us admit: there is no question here about scientific formulas and problems; the relations of material
things are all very simple; the right comprehension of the moral forces which come into play is more difficult.
Still, even in respect to them, it is only in the highest branches of Strategy that moral complications and a
great diversity of quantities and relations are to be looked for, only at that point where Strategy borders on
political science, or rather where the two become one, and there, as we have before observed, they have more
influence on the "how much" and "how little" is to be done than on the form of execution. Where the latter is
the principal question, as in the single acts both great and small in War, the moral quantities are already
reduced to a very small number.
Thus, then, in Strategy everything is very simple, but not on that account very easy. Once it is determined
from the relations of the State what should and may be done by War, then the way to it is easy to find; but to
follow that way straightforward, to carry out the plan without being obliged to deviate from it a thousand
times by a thousand varying influences, requires, besides great strength of character, great clearness and
steadiness of mind, and out of a thousand men who are remarkable, some for mind, others for penetration,
others again for boldness or strength of will, perhaps not one will combine in himself all those qualities
which are required to raise a man above mediocrity in the career of a general.
It may sound strange, but for all who know War in this respect it is a fact beyond doubt, that much more
strength of will is required to make an important decision in Strategy than in tactics. In the latter we are
hurried on with the moment; a Commander feels himself borne along in a strong current, against which he
durst not contend without the most destructive consequences, he suppresses the rising fears, and boldly
ventures further. In Strategy, where all goes on at a slower rate, there is more room allowed for our own
apprehensions and those of others, for objections and remonstrances, consequently also for unseasonable
regrets; and as we do not see things in Strategy as we do at least half of them in tactics, with the living eye,
but everything must be conjectured and assumed, the convictions produced are less powerful. The
consequence is that most Generals, when they should act, remain stuck fast in bewildering doubts.
Now let us cast a glance at historyupon Frederick the Great's campaign of 1760, celebrated for its fine
marches and manoeuvres: a perfect masterpiece of Strategic skill as critics tell us. Is there really anything to
drive us out of our wits with admiration in the King's first trying to turn Daun's right flank, then his left, then
again his right, ? Are we to see profound wisdom in this? No, that we cannot, if we are to decide naturally
and without affectation. What we rather admire above all is the sagacity of the King in this respect, that while
pursuing a great object with very limited means, he undertook nothing beyond his powers, and JUST
ENOUGH to gain his object. This sagacity of the General is visible not only in this campaign, but throughout
all the three Wars of the Great King!
To bring Silesia into the safe harbour of a well guaranteed peace was his object.
At the head of a small State, which was like other States in most things, and only ahead of them in some
branches of administration; he could not be an Alexander, and, as Charles XII, he would only, like him, have
broken his head. We find, therefore, in the whole of his conduct of War, a controlled power, always well
balanced, and never wanting in energy, which in the most critical moments rises to astonishing deeds, and the
next moment oscillates quietly on again in subordination to the play of the most subtil political influences.
Neither vanity, thirst for glory, nor vengeance could make him deviate from his course, and this course alone
it is which brought him to a fortunate termination of the contest.
On War
On War 87
Page No 90
These few words do but scant justice to this phase of the genius of the great General; the eyes must be fixed
carefully on the extraordinary issue of the struggle, and the causes which brought about that issue must be
traced out, in order thoroughly to understand that nothing but the King's penetrating eye brought him safely
out of all his dangers.
This is one feature in this great Commander which we admire in the campaign of 1760and in all others, but
in this especiallybecause in none did he keep the balance even against such a superior hostile force, with
such a small sacrifice.
Another feature relates to the difficulty of execution. Marches to turn a flank, right or left, are easily
combined; the idea of keeping a small force always well concentrated to be able to meet the enemy on equal
terms at any point, to multiply a force by rapid movement, is as easily conceived as expressed; the mere
contrivance in these points, therefore, cannot excite our admiration, and with respect to such simple things,
there is nothing further than to admit that they are simple.
But let a General try to do these things like Frederick the Great. Long afterwards authors, who were
eyewitnesses, have spoken of the danger, indeed of the imprudence, of the King's camps, and doubtless, at the
time he pitched them, the danger appeared three times as great as afterwards.
It was the same with his marches, under the eyes, nay, often under the cannon of the enemy's Army; these
camps were taken up, these marches made, not from want of prudence, but because in Daun's system, in his
mode of drawing up his Army, in the responsibility which pressed upon him, and in his character, Frederick
found that security which justified his camps and marches. But it required the King's boldness, determination,
and strength of will to see things in this light, and not to be led astray and intimidated by the danger of which
thirty years after people still wrote and spoke. Few Generals in this situation would have believed these
simple strategic means to be practicable.
Again, another difficulty in execution lay in this, that the King's Army in this campaign was constantly in
motion. Twice it marched by wretched crossroads, from the Elbe into Silesia, in rear of Daun and pursued
by Lascy (beginning of July, beginning of August). It required to be always ready for battle, and its marches
had to be organised with a degree of skill which necessarily called forth a proportionate amount of exertion.
Although attended and delayed by thousands of waggons, still its subsistence was extremely difficult. In
Silesia, for eight days before the battle of Leignitz, it had constantly to march, defiling alternately right and
left in front of the enemy:this costs great fatigue, and entails great privations.
Is it to be supposed that all this could have been done without producing great friction in the machine? Can
the mind of a Commander elaborate such movements with the same ease as the hand of a land surveyor uses
the astrolabe? Does not the sight of the sufferings of their hungry, thirsty comrades pierce the hearts of the
Commander and his Generals a thousand times? Must not the murmurs and doubts which these cause reach
his ear? Has an ordinary man the courage to demand such sacrifices, and would not such efforts most
certainly demoralise the Army, break up the bands of discipline, and, in short, undermine its military virtue, if
firm reliance on the greatness and infallibility of the Commander did not compensate for all? Here, therefore,
it is that we should pay respect; it is these miracles of execution which we should admire. But it is impossible
to realise all this in its full force without a foretaste of it by experience. He who only knows War from books
or the drillground cannot realise the whole effect of this counterpoise in action; WE BEG HIM,
THEREFORE, TO ACCEPT FROM US ON FAITH AND TRUST ALL THAT HE IS UNABLE TO
SUPPLY FROM ANY PERSONAL EXPERIENCES OF HIS OWN.
This illustration is intended to give more clearness to the course of our ideas, and in closing this chapter we
will only briefly observe that in our exposition of Strategy we shall describe those separate subjects which
appear to us the most important, whether of a moral or material nature; then proceed from the simple to the
On War
On War 88
Page No 91
complex, and conclude with the inner connection of the whole act of War, in other words, with the plan for a
War or campaign.
OBSERVATION.
In an earlier manuscript of the second book are the following passages endorsed by the author himself to be
used for the first Chapter of the second Book: the projected revision of that chapter not having been made, the
passages referred to are introduced here in full.
By the mere assemblage of armed forces at a particular point, a battle there becomes possible, but does not
always take place. Is that possibility now to be regarded as a reality and therefore an effective thing?
Certainly, it is so by its results, and these effects, whatever they may be, can never fail.
1. POSSIBLE COMBATS ARE ON ACCOUNT OF THEIR RESULTS TO BE LOOKED UPON AS REAL
ONES.
If a detachment is sent away to cut off the retreat of a flying enemy, and the enemy surrenders in consequence
without further resistance, still it is through the combat which is offered to him by this detachment sent after
him that he is brought to his decision.
If a part of our Army occupies an enemy's province which was undefended, and thus deprives the enemy of
very considerable means of keeping up the strength of his Army, it is entirely through the battle which our
detached body gives the enemy to expect, in case he seeks to recover the lost province, that we remain in
possession of the same.
In both cases, therefore, the mere possibility of a battle has produced results, and is therefore to be classed
amongst actual events. Suppose that in these cases the enemy has opposed our troops with others superior in
force, and thus forced ours to give up their object without a combat, then certainly our plan has failed, but the
battle which we offered at (either of) those points has not on that account been without effect, for it attracted
the enemy's forces to that point. And in case our whole undertaking has done us harm, it cannot be said that
these positions, these possible battles, have been attended with no results; their effects, then, are similar to
those of a lost battle.
In this manner we see that the destruction of the enemy's military forces, the overthrow of the enemy's power,
is only to be done through the effect of a battle, whether it be that it actually takes place, or that it is merely
offered, and not accepted.
2. TWOFOLD OBJECT OF THE COMBAT.
But these effects are of two kinds, direct and indirect they are of the latter, if other things intrude themselves
and become the object of the combatthings which cannot be regarded as the destruction of enemy's force,
but only leading up to it, certainly by a circuitous road, but with so much the greater effect. The possession of
provinces, towns, fortresses, roads, bridges, magazines, may be the IMMEDIATE object of a battle, but never
the ultimate one. Things of this description can never be, looked upon otherwise than as means of gaining
greater superiority, so as at last to offer battle to the enemy in such a way that it will be impossible for him to
accept it. Therefore all these things must only be regarded as intermediate links, steps, as it were, leading up
to the effectual principle, but never as that principle itself.
3. EXAMPLE.
In 1814, by the capture of Buonaparte's capital the object of the War was attained. The political divisions
On War
On War 89
Page No 92
which had their roots in Paris came into active operation, and an enormous split left the power of the Emperor
to collapse of itself. Nevertheless the point of view from which we must look at all this is, that through these
causes the forces and defensive means of Buonaparte were suddenly very much diminished, the superiority of
the Allies, therefore, just in the same measure increased, and any further resistance then became
IMPOSSIBLE. It was this impossibility which produced the peace with France. If we suppose the forces of
the Allies at that moment diminished to a like extent through external causes; if the superiority vanishes,
then at the same time vanishes also all the effect and importance of the taking of Paris.
We have gone through this chain of argument in order to show that this is the natural and only true view of
the thing from which it derives its importance. It leads always back to the question, What at any given
moment of the War or campaign will be the probable result of the great or small combats which the two sides
might offer to each other? In the consideration of a plan for a campaign, this question only is decisive as to
the measures which are to be taken all through from the very commencement.
4. WHEN THIS VIEW IS NOT TAKEN, THEN A FALSE VALUE IS GIVEN TO OTHER THINGS.
If we do not accustom ourselves to look upon War, and the single campaigns in a War, as a chain which is all
composed of battles strung together, one of which always brings on another; if we adopt the idea that the
taking of a certain geographical point, the occupation of an undefended province, is in itself anything; then
we are very likely to regard it as an acquisition which we may retain; and if we look at it so, and not as a term
in the whole series of events, we do not ask ourselves whether this possession may not lead to greater
disadvantages hereafter. How often we find this mistake recurring in military history.
We might say that, just as in commerce the merchant cannot set apart and place in security gains from one
single transaction by itself, so in War a single advantage cannot be separated from the result of the whole.
Just as the former must always operate with the whole bulk of his means, just so in War, only the sum total
will decide on the advantage or disadvantage of each item.
If the mind's eye is always directed upon the series of combats, so far as they can be seen beforehand, then it
is always looking in the right direction, and thereby the motion of the force acquires that rapidity, that is to
say, willing and doing acquire that energy which is suitable to the matter, and which is not to be thwarted or
turned aside by extraneous influences.[*]
[*] The whole of this chapter is directed against the theories of the Austrian Staff in 1814. It may be taken as
the foundation of the modern teaching of the Prussian General Staff. See especially von Kammer.ED.
CHAPTER II. ELEMENTS OF STRATEGY
THE causes which condition the use of the combat in Strategy may be easily divided into elements of
different kinds, such as the moral, physical, mathematical, geographical and statistical elements.
The first class includes all that can be called forth by moral qualities and effects; to the second belong the
whole mass of the military force, its organisation, the proportion of the three arms, to the third, the angle of
the lines of operation, the concentric and eccentric movements in as far as their geometrical nature has any
value in the calculation; to the fourth, the influences of country, such as commanding points, hills, rivers,
woods, roads, lastly, to the fifth, all the means of supply. The separation of these things once for all in the
mind does good in giving clearness and helping us to estimate at once, at a higher or lower value, the
different classes as we pass onwards. For, in considering them separately, many lose of themselves their
On War
On War 90
Page No 93
borrowed importance; one feels, for instance, quite plainly that the value of a base of operations, even if we
look at nothing in it but its relative position to the line of operations, depends much less in that simple form
on the geometrical element of the angle which they form with one another, than on the nature of the roads and
the country through which they pass.
But to treat upon Strategy according to these elements would be the most unfortunate idea that could be
conceived, for these elements are generally manifold, and intimately connected with each other in every
single operation of War. We should lose ourselves in the most soulless analysis, and as if in a horrid dream,
we should be for ever trying in vain to build up an arch to connect this base of abstractions with facts
belonging to the real world. Heaven preserve every theorist from such an undertaking! We shall keep to the
world of things in their totality, and not pursue our analysis further than is necessary from time to time to
give distinctness to the idea which we wish to impart, and which has come to us, not by a speculative
investigation, but through the impression made by the realities of War in their entirety.
CHAPTER III. MORAL FORCES
WE must return again to this subject, which is touched upon in the third chapter of the second book, because
the moral forces are amongst the most important subjects in War. They form the spirit which permeates the
whole being of War. These forces fasten themselves soonest and with the greatest affinity on to the Will
which puts in motion and guides the whole mass of powers, uniting with it as it were in one stream, because
this is a moral force itself. Unfortunately they will escape from all bookanalysis, for they will neither be
brought into numbers nor into classes, and require to be both seen and felt.
The spirit and other moral qualities which animate an Army, a General, or Governments, public opinion in
provinces in which a War is raging, the moral effect of a victory or of a defeat, are things which in
themselves vary very much in their nature, and which also, according as they stand with regard to our object
and our relations, may have an influence in different ways.
Although little or nothing can be said about these things in books, still they belong to the theory of the Art of
War, as much as everything else which constitutes War. For I must here once more repeat that it is a
miserable philosophy if, according to the old plan, we establish rules and principles wholly regardless of all
moral forces, and then, as soon as these forces make their appearance, we begin to count exceptions which we
thereby establish as it were theoretically, that is, make into rules; or if we resort to an appeal to genius, which
is above all rules, thus giving out by implication, not only that rules were only made for fools, but also that
they themselves are no better than folly.
Even if the theory of the Art of War does no more in reality than recall these things to remembrance, showing
the necessity of allowing to the moral forces their full value, and of always taking them into consideration, by
so doing it extends its borders over the region of immaterial forces, and by establishing that point of view,
condemns beforehand every one who would endeavour to justify himself before its judgment seat by the mere
physical relations of forces.
Further out of regard to all other socalled rules, theory cannot banish the moral forces beyond its frontier,
because the effects of the physical forces and the moral are completely fused, and are not to be decomposed
like a metal alloy by a chemical process. In every rule relating to the physical forces, theory must present to
the mind at the same time the share which the moral powers will have in it, if it would not be led to
categorical propositions, at one time too timid and contracted, at another too dogmatical and wide. Even the
most matteroffact theories have, without knowing it, strayed over into this moral kingdom; for, as an
example, the effects of a victory cannot in any way be explained without taking into consideration the moral
On War
On War 91
Page No 94
impressions. And therefore the most of the subjects which we shall go through in this book are composed half
of physical, half of moral causes and effects, and we might say the physical are almost no more than the
wooden handle, whilst the moral are the noble metal, the real brightpolished weapon.
The value of the moral powers, and their frequently incredible influence, are best exemplified by history, and
this is the most generous and the purest nourishment which the mind of the General can extract from it.At
the same time it is to be observed, that it is less demonstrations, critical examinations, and learned treatises,
than sentiments, general impressions, and single flashing sparks of truth, which yield the seeds of knowledge
that are to fertilise the mind.
We might go through the most important moral phenomena in War, and with all the care of a diligent
professor try what we could impart about each, either good or bad. But as in such a method one slides too
much into the commonplace and trite, whilst real mind quickly makes its escape in analysis, the end is that
one gets imperceptibly to the relation of things which everybody knows. We prefer, therefore, to remain here
more than usually incomplete and rhapsodical, content to have drawn attention to the importance of the
subject in a general way, and to have pointed out the spirit in which the views given in this book have been
conceived.
CHAPTER IV. THE CHIEF MORAL POWERS
THESE are The Talents of the Commander; The Military Virtue of the Army; Its National feeling. Which of
these is the most important no one can tell in a general way, for it is very difficult to say anything in general
of their strength, and still more difficult to compare the strength of one with that of another. The best plan is
not to undervalue any of them, a fault which human judgment is prone to, sometimes on one side, sometimes
on another, in its whimsical oscillations. It is better to satisfy ourselves of the undeniable efficacy of these
three things by sufficient evidence from history.
It is true, however, that in modern times the Armies of European states have arrived very much at a par as
regards discipline and fitness for service, and that the conduct of War hasas philosophers would
saynaturally developed itself, thereby become a method, common as it were to all Armies, so that even
from Commanders there is nothing further to be expected in the way of application of special means of Art,
in the limited sense (such as Frederick the Second's oblique order). Hence it cannot be denied that, as matters
now stand, greater scope is afforded for the influence of National spirit and habituation of an army to War. A
long peace may again alter all this.[*]
[*] Written shortly after the Great Napoleonic campaigns.
The national spirit of an Army (enthusiasm, fanatical zeal, faith, opinion) displays itself most in mountain
warfare, where every one down to the common soldier is left to himself. On this account, a mountainous
country is the best campaigning ground for popular levies.
Expertness of an Army through training, and that welltempered courage which holds the ranks together as if
they had been cast in a mould, show their superiority in an open country.
The talent of a General has most room to display itself in a closely intersected, undulating country. In
mountains he has too little command over the separate parts, and the direction of all is beyond his powers; in
open plains it is simple and does not exceed those powers.
On War
On War 92
Page No 95
According to these undeniable elective affinities, plans should be regulated.
CHAPTER V. MILITARY VIRTUE OF AN ARMY
THIS is distinguished from mere bravery, and still more from enthusiasm for the business of War. The first is
certainly a necessary constituent part of it, but in the same way as bravery, which is a natural gift in some
men, may arise in a soldier as a part of an Army from habit and custom, so with him it must also have a
different direction from that which it has with others. It must lose that impulse to unbridled activity and
exercise of force which is its characteristic in the individual, and submit itself to demands of a higher kind, to
obedience, order, rule, and method. Enthusiasm for the profession gives life and greater fire to the military
virtue of an Army, but does not necessarily constitute a part of it.
War is a special business, and however general its relations may be, and even if all the male population of a
country, capable of bearing arms, exercise this calling, still it always continues to be different and separate
from the other pursuits which occupy the life of man.To be imbued with a sense of the spirit and nature of
this business, to make use of, to rouse, to assimilate into the system the powers which should be active in it,
to penetrate completely into the nature of the business with the understanding, through exercise to gain
confidence and expertness in it, to be completely given up to it, to pass out of the man into the part which it is
assigned to us to play in War, that is the military virtue of an Army in the individual.
However much pains may be taken to combine the soldier and the citizen in one and the same individual,
whatever may be done to nationalise Wars, and however much we may imagine times have changed since the
days of the old Condottieri, never will it be possible to do away with the individuality of the business; and if
that cannot be done, then those who belong to it, as long as they belong to it, will always look upon
themselves as a kind of guild, in the regulations, laws and customs in which the "Spirit of War" by preference
finds its expression. And so it is in fact. Even with the most decided inclination to look at War from the
highest point of view, it would be very wrong to look down upon this corporate spirit (e'sprit de corps) which
may and should exist more or less in every Army. This corporate spirit forms the bond of union between the
natural forces which are active in that which we have called military virtue. The crystals of military virtue
have a greater affinity for the spirit of a corporate body than for anything else.
An Army which preserves its usual formations under the heaviest fire, which is never shaken by imaginary
fears, and in the face of real danger disputes the ground inch by inch, which, proud in the feeling of its
victories, never loses its sense of obedience, its respect for and confidence in its leaders, even under the
depressing effects of defeat; an Army with all its physical powers, inured to privations and fatigue by
exercise, like the muscles of an athlete; an Army which looks upon all its toils as the means to victory, not as
a curse which hovers over its standards, and which is always reminded of its duties and virtues by the short
catechism of one idea, namely the HONOUR OF ITS ARMS; Such an Army is imbued with the true
military spirit.
Soldiers may fight bravely like the Vende'ans, and do great things like the Swiss, the Americans, or
Spaniards, without displaying this military virtue. A Commander may also be successful at the head of
standing Armies, like Eugene and Marlborough, without enjoying the benefit of its assistance; we must not,
therefore, say that a successful War without it cannot be imagined; and we draw especial attention to that
point, in order the more to individualise the conception which is here brought forward, that the idea may not
dissolve into a generalisation and that it may not be thought that military virtue is in the end everything. It is
not so. Military virtue in an Army is a definite moral power which may be supposed wanting, and the
influence of which may therefore be estimatedlike any instrument the power of which may be calculated.
On War
On War 93
Page No 96
Having thus characterised it, we proceed to consider what can be predicated of its influence, and what are the
means of gaining its assistance.
Military virtue is for the parts, what the genius of the Commander is for the whole. The General can only
guide the whole, not each separate part, and where he cannot guide the part, there military virtue must be its
leader. A General is chosen by the reputation of his superior talents, the chief leaders of large masses after
careful probation; but this probation diminishes as we descend the scale of rank, and in just the same measure
we may reckon less and less upon individual talents; but what is wanting in this respect military virtue should
supply. The natural qualities of a warlike people play just this part: BRAVERY, APTITUDE, POWERS OF
ENDURANCE and ENTHUSIASM.
These properties may therefore supply the place of military virtue, and vice versa, from which the following
may be deduced:
1. Military virtue is a quality of standing Armies only, but they require it the most. In national risings its
place is supplied by natural qualities, which develop themselves there more rapidly.
2. Standing Armies opposed to standing Armies, can more easily dispense with it, than a standing Army
opposed to a national insurrection, for in that case, the troops are more scattered, and the divisions left more
to themselves. But where an Army can be kept concentrated, the genius of the General takes a greater place,
and supplies what is wanting in the spirit of the Army. Therefore generally military virtue becomes more
necessary the more the theatre of operations and other circumstances make the War complicated, and cause
the forces to be scattered.
From these truths the only lesson to be derived is this, that if an Army is deficient in this quality, every
endeavour should be made to simplify the operations of the War as much as possible, or to introduce double
efficiency in the organisation of the Army in some other respect, and not to expect from the mere name of a
standing Army, that which only the veritable thing itself can give.
The military virtue of an Army is, therefore, one of the most important moral powers in War, and where it is
wanting, we either see its place supplied by one of the others, such as the great superiority of generalship or
popular enthusiasm, or we find the results not commensurate with the exertions made.How much that is
great, this spirit, this sterling worth of an army, this refining of ore into the polished metal, has already done,
we see in the history of the Macedonians under Alexander, the Roman legions under Cesar, the Spanish
infantry under Alexander Farnese, the Swedes under Gustavus Adolphus and Charles XII, the Prussians
under Frederick the Great, and the French under Buonaparte. We must purposely shut our eyes against all
historical proof, if we do not admit, that the astonishing successes of these Generals and their greatness in
situations of extreme difficulty, were only possible with Armies possessing this virtue.
This spirit can only be generated from two sources, and only by these two conjointly; the first is a succession
of campaigns and great victories; the other is, an activity of the Army carried sometimes to the highest pitch.
Only by these, does the soldier learn to know his powers. The more a General is in the habit of demanding
from his troops, the surer he will be that his demands will be answered. The soldier is as proud of overcoming
toil, as he is of surmounting danger. Therefore it is only in the soil of incessant activity and exertion that the
germ will thrive, but also only in the sunshine of victory. Once it becomes a STRONG TREE, it will stand
against the fiercest storms of misfortune and defeat, and even against the indolent inactivity of peace, at least
for a time. It can therefore only be created in War, and under great Generals, but no doubt it may last at least
for several generations, even under Generals of moderate capacity, and through considerable periods of
peace.
With this generous and noble spirit of union in a line of veteran troops, covered with scars and thoroughly
On War
On War 94
Page No 97
inured to War, we must not compare the selfesteem and vanity of a standing Army,[*] held together merely
by the glue of serviceregulations and a drill book; a certain plodding earnestness and strict discipline may
keep up military virtue for a long time, but can never create it; these things therefore have a certain value, but
must not be overrated. Order, smartness, good will, also a certain degree of pride and high feeling, are
qualities of an Army formed in time of peace which are to be prized, but cannot stand alone. The whole
retains the whole, and as with glass too quickly cooled, a single crack breaks the whole mass. Above all, the
highest spirit in the world changes only too easily at the first check into depression, and one might say into a
kind of rhodomontade of alarm, the French sauve que peut.Such an Army can only achieve something
through its leader, never by itself. It must be led with double caution, until by degrees, in victory and
hardships, the strength grows into the full armour. Beware then of confusing the SPIRIT of an Army with its
temper.
[*] Clausewitz is, of course, thinking of the longservice standing armies of his own youth. Not of the
shortservice standing armies of today (EDITOR).
CHAPTER VI. BOLDNESS
THE place and part which boldness takes in the dynamic system of powers, where it stands opposed to
Foresight and prudence, has been stated in the chapter on the certainty of the result in order thereby to show,
that theory has no right to restrict it by virtue of its legislative power.
But this noble impulse, with which the human soul raises itself above the most formidable dangers, is to be
regarded as an active principle peculiarly belonging to War. In fact, in what branch of human activity should
boldness have a right of citizenship if not in War?
From the transportdriver and the drummer up to the General, it is the noblest of virtues, the true steel which
gives the weapon its edge and brilliancy.
Let us admit in fact it has in War even its own prerogatives. Over and above the result of the calculation of
space, time, and quantity, we must allow a certain percentage which boldness derives from the weakness of
others, whenever it gains the mastery. It is therefore, virtually, a creative power. This is not difficult to
demonstrate philosophically. As often as boldness encounters hesitation, the probability of the result is of
necessity in its favour, because the very state of hesitation implies a loss of equilibrium already. It is only
when it encounters cautious foresightwhich we may say is just as bold, at all events just as strong and
powerful as itselfthat it is at a disadvantage; such cases, however, rarely occur. Out of the whole multitude
of prudent men in the world, the great majority are so from timidity.
Amongst large masses, boldness is a force, the special cultivation of which can never be to the detriment of
other forces, because the great mass is bound to a higher will by the framework and joints of the order of
battle and of the service, and therefore is guided by an intelligent power which is extraneous. Boldness is
therefore here only like a spring held down until its action is required.
The higher the rank the more necessary it is that boldness should be accompanied by a reflective mind, that it
may not be a mere blind outburst of passion to no purpose; for with increase of rank it becomes always less a
matter of selfsacrifice and more a matter of the preservation of others, and the good of the whole. Where
regulations of the service, as a kind of second nature, prescribe for the masses, reflection must be the guide of
the General, and in his case individual boldness in action may easily become a fault. Still, at the same time, it
is a fine failing, and must not be looked at in the same light as any other. Happy the Army in which an
On War
On War 95
Page No 98
untimely boldness frequently manifests itself; it is an exuberant growth which shows a rich soil. Even
foolhardiness, that is boldness without an object, is not to be despised; in point of fact it is the same energy of
feeling, only exercised as a kind of passion without any cooperation of the intelligent faculties. It is only
when it strikes at the root of obedience, when it treats with contempt the orders of superior authority, that it
must be repressed as a dangerous evil, not on its own account but on account of the act of disobedience, for
there is nothing in War which is of GREATER IMPORTANCE THAN OBEDIENCE.
The reader will readily agree with us that, supposing an equal degree of discernment to be forthcoming in a
certain number of cases, a thousand times as many of them will end in disaster through overanxiety as
through boldness.
One would suppose it natural that the interposition of a reasonable object should stimulate boldness, and
therefore lessen its intrinsic merit, and yet the reverse is the case in reality.
The intervention of lucid thought or the general supremacy of mind deprives the emotional forces of a great
part of their power. On that account BOLDNESS BECOMES OF RARER OCCURRENCE THE HIGHER
WE ASCEND THE SCALE OF RANK, for whether the discernment and the understanding do or do not
increase with these ranks still the Commanders, in their several stations as they rise, are pressed upon more
and more severely by objective things, by relations and claims from without, so that they become the more
perplexed the lower the degree of their individual intelligence. This so far as regards War is the chief
foundation of the truth of the French proverb:
"Tel brille au second qui s' e'clipse an premier."
Almost all the Generals who are represented in history as merely having attained to mediocrity, and as
wanting in decision when in supreme command, are men celebrated in their antecedent career for their
boldness and decision.[*]
[*] Beaulieu, Benedek, Bazaine, Buller, Melas, Mack.
In those motives to bold action which arise from the pressure of necessity we must make a distinction.
Necessity has its degrees of intensity. If it lies near at hand, if the person acting is in the pursuit of his object
driven into great dangers in order to escape others equally great, then we can only admire his resolution,
which still has also its value. If a young man to show his skill in horsemanship leaps across a deep cleft, then
he is bold; if he makes the same leap pursued by a troop of headchopping Janissaries he is only resolute. But
the farther off the necessity from the point of action, the greater the number of relations intervening which the
mind has to traverse; in order to realise them, by so much the less does necessity take from boldness in
action. If Frederick the Great, in the year 1756, saw that War was inevitable, and that he could only escape
destruction by being beforehand with his enemies, it became necessary for him to commence the War
himself, but at the same time it was certainly very bold: for few men in his position would have made up their
minds to do so.
Although Strategy is only the province of Generalsin Chief or Commanders in the higher positions, still
boldness in all the other branches of an Army is as little a matter of indifference to it as their other military
virtues. With an Army belonging to a bold race, and in which the spirit of boldness has been always
nourished, very different things may be undertaken than with one in which this virtue, is unknown; for that
reason we have considered it in connection with an Army. But our subject is specially the boldness of the
General, and yet we have not much to say about it after having described this military virtue in a general way
to the best of our ability.
The higher we rise in a position of command, the more of the mind, understanding, and penetration
On War
On War 96
Page No 99
predominate in activity, the more therefore is boldness, which is a property of the feelings, kept in subjection,
and for that reason we find it so rarely in the highest positions, but then, so much the more should it be
admired. Boldness, directed by an overruling intelligence, is the stamp of the hero: this boldness does not
consist in venturing directly against the nature of things, in a downright contempt of the laws of probability,
but, if a choice is once made, in the rigorous adherence to that higher calculation which genius, the tact of
judgment, has gone over with the speed of lightning. The more boldness lends wings to the mind and the
discernment, so much the farther they will reach in their flight, so much the more comprehensive will be the
view, the more exact the result, but certainly always only in the sense that with greater objects greater
dangers are connected. The ordinary man, not to speak of the weak and irresolute, arrives at an exact result so
far as such is possible without ocular demonstration, at most after diligent reflection in his chamber, at a
distance from danger and responsibility. Let danger and responsibility draw close round him in every
direction, then he loses the power of comprehensive vision, and if he retains this in any measure by the
influence of others, still he will lose his power of DECISION, because in that point no one can help him.
We think then that it is impossible to imagine a distinguished General without boldness, that is to say, that no
man can become one who is not born with this power of the soul, and we therefore look upon it as the first
requisite for such a career. How much of this inborn power, developed and moderated through education and
the circumstances of life, is left when the man has attained a high position, is the second question. The greater
this power still is, the stronger will genius be on the wing, the higher will be its flight. The risks become
always greater, but the purpose grows with them. Whether its lines proceed out of and get their direction from
a distant necessity, or whether they converge to the keystone of a building which ambition has planned,
whether Frederick or Alexander acts, is much the same as regards the critical view. If the one excites the
imagination more because it is bolder, the other pleases the understanding most, because it has in it more
absolute necessity.
We have still to advert to one very important circumstance.
The spirit of boldness can exist in an Army, either because it is in the people, or because it has been generated
in a successful War conducted by able Generals. In the latter case it must of course be dispensed with at the
commencement.
Now in our days there is hardly any other means of educating the spirit of a people in this respect, except by
War, and that too under bold Generals. By it alone can that effeminacy of feeling be counteracted, that
propensity to seek for the enjoyment of comfort, which cause degeneracy in a people rising in prosperity and
immersed in an extremely busy commerce.
A Nation can hope to have a strong position in the political world only if its character and practice in actual
War mutually support each other in constant reciprocal action.
CHAPTER VII. PERSEVERANCE
THE reader expects to hear of angles and lines, and finds, instead of these citizens of the scientific world,
only people out of common life, such as he meets with every day in the street. And yet the author cannot
make up his mind to become a hair's breadth more mathematical than the subject seems to him to require, and
he is not alarmed at the surprise which the reader may show.
In War more than anywhere else in the world things happen differently to what we had expected, and look
differently when near, to what they did at a distance. With what serenity the architect can watch his work
On War
On War 97
Page No 100
gradually rising and growing into his plan. The doctor although much more at the mercy of mysterious
agencies and chances than the architect, still knows enough of the forms and effects of his means. In War, on
the other hand, the Commander of an immense whole finds himself in a constant whirlpool of false and true
information, of mistakes committed through fear, through negligence, through precipitation, of
contraventions of his authority, either from mistaken or correct motives, from ill will, true or false sense of
duty, indolence or exhaustion, of accidents which no mortal could have foreseen. In short, he is the victim of
a hundred thousand impressions, of which the most have an intimidating, the fewest an encouraging
tendency. By long experience in War, the tact is acquired of readily appreciating the value of these incidents;
high courage and stability of character stand proof against them, as the rock resists the beating of the waves.
He who would yield to these impressions would never carry out an undertaking, and on that account
PERSEVERANCE in the proposed object, as long as there is no decided reason against it, is a most necessary
counterpoise. Further, there is hardly any celebrated enterprise in War which was not achieved by endless
exertion, pains, and privations; and as here the weakness of the physical and moral man is ever disposed to
yield, only an immense force of will, which manifests itself in perseverance admired by present and future
generations, can conduct to our goal.
CHAPTER VIII. SUPERIORITY OF NUMBERS
THIS is in tactics, as well as in Strategy, the most general principle of victory, and shall be examined by us
first in its generality, for which we may be permitted the following exposition:
Strategy fixes the point where, the time when, and the numerical force with which the battle is to be fought.
By this triple determination it has therefore a very essential influence on the issue of the combat. If tactics has
fought the battle, if the result is over, let it be victory or defeat, Strategy makes such use of it as can be made
in accordance with the great object of the War. This object is naturally often a very distant one, seldom does
it lie quite close at hand. A series of other objects subordinate themselves to it as means. These objects, which
are at the same time means to a higher purpose, may be practically of various kinds; even the ultimate aim of
the whole War may be a different one in every case. We shall make ourselves acquainted with these things
according as we come to know the separate objects which they come, in contact with; and it is not our
intention here to embrace the whole subject by a complete enumeration of them, even if that were possible.
We therefore let the employment of the battle stand over for the present.
Even those things through which Strategy has an influence on the issue of the combat, inasmuch as it
establishes the same, to a certain extent decrees them, are not so simple that they can be embraced in one
single view. For as Strategy appoints time, place and force, it can do so in practice in many ways, each of
which influences in a different manner the result of the combat as well as its consequences. Therefore we
shall only get acquainted with this also by degrees, that is, through the subjects which more closely determine
the application.
If we strip the combat of all modifications which it may undergo according to its immediate purpose and the
circumstances from which it proceeds, lastly if we set aside the valour of the troops, because that is a given
quantity, then there remains only the bare conception of the combat, that is a combat without form, in which
we distinguish nothing but the number of the combatants.
This number will therefore determine victory. Now from the number of things above deducted to get to this
point, it is shown that the superiority in numbers in a battle is only one of the factors employed to produce
victory that therefore so far from having with the superiority in number obtained all, or even only the
principal thing, we have perhaps got very little by it, according as the other circumstances which cooperate
On War
On War 98
Page No 101
happen to vary.
But this superiority has degrees, it may be imagined as twofold, threefold or fourfold, and every one sees, that
by increasing in this way, it must (at last) overpower everything else.
In such an aspect we grant, that the superiority in numbers is the most important factor in the result of a
combat, only it must be sufficiently great to be a counterpoise to all the other cooperating circumstances.
The direct result of this is, that the greatest possible number of troops should be brought into action at the
decisive point.
Whether the troops thus brought are sufficient or not, we have then done in this respect all that our means
allowed. This is the first principle in Strategy, therefore in general as now stated, it is just as well suited for
Greeks and Persians, or for Englishmen and Mahrattas, as for French and Germans. But we shall take a
glance at our relations in Europe, as respects War, in order to arrive at some more definite idea on this
subject.
Here we find Armies much more alike in equipment, organisation, and practical skill of every kind. There
only remains a difference in the military virtue of Armies, and in the talent of Generals which may fluctuate
with time from side to side. If we go through the military history of modern Europe, we find no example of a
Marathon.
Frederick the Great beat 80,000 Austrians at Leuthen with about 30,000 men, and at Rosbach with 25,000
some 50,000 allies; these are however the only instances of victories gained against an enemy double, or
more than double in numbers. Charles XII, in the battle of Narva, we cannot well quote, for the Russians
were at that time hardly to be regarded as Europeans, also the principal circumstances, even of the battle, are
too little known. Buonaparte had at Dresden 120,000 against 220,000, therefore not the double. At Kollin,
Frederick the Great did not succeed, with 30,000 against 50,000 Austrians, neither did Buonaparte in the
desperate battle of Leipsic, where he was 160,000 strong, against 280,000.
From this we may infer, that it is very difficult in the present state of Europe, for the most talented General to
gain a victory over an enemy double his strength. Now if we see double numbers prove such a weight in the
scale against the greatest Generals, we may be sure, that in ordinary cases, in small as well as great combats,
an important superiority of numbers, but which need not be over two to one, will be sufficient to ensure the
victory, however disadvantageous other circumstances may be. Certainly, we may imagine a defile which
even tenfold would not suffice to force, but in such a case it can be no question of a battle at all.
We think, therefore, that under our conditions, as well as in all similar ones, the superiority at the decisive
point is a matter of capital importance, and that this subject, in the generality of cases, is decidedly the most
important of all. The strength at the decisive point depends on the absolute strength of the Army, and on skill
in making use of it.
The first rule is therefore to enter the field with an Army as strong as possible. This sounds very like a
commonplace, but still it is really not so.
In order to show that for a long time the strength of forces was by no means regarded as a chief point, we
need only observe, that in most, and even in the most detailed histories of the Wars in the eighteenth century,
the strength of the Armies is either not given at all, or only incidentally, and in no case is any special value
laid upon it. Tempelhof in his history of the Seven Years' War is the earliest writer who gives it regularly, but
at the same time he does it only very superficially.
Even Massenbach, in his manifold critical observations on the Prussian campaigns of 179394 in the Vosges,
On War
On War 99
Page No 102
talks a great deal about hills and valleys, roads and footpaths, but does not say a syllable about mutual
strength.
Another proof lies in a wonderful notion which haunted the heads of many critical historians, according to
which there was a certain size of an Army which was the best, a normal strength, beyond which the forces in
excess were burdensome rather than serviceable.[*]
[*] Tempelhof and Montalembert are the first we recollect as examples the first in a passage of his first
part, page 148; the other in his correspondence relative to the plan of operations of the Russians in 1759.
Lastly, there are a number of instances to be found, in which all the available forces were not really brought
into the battle,[*] or into the War, because the superiority of numbers was not considered to have that
importance which in the nature of things belongs to it.
[*] The Prussians at Jena, 1806. Wellington at Waterloo.
If we are thoroughly penetrated with the conviction that with a considerable superiority of numbers
everything possible is to be effected, then it cannot fail that this clear conviction reacts on the preparations for
the War, so as to make us appear in the field with as many troops as possible, and either to give us ourselves
the superiority, or at least to guard against the enemy obtaining it. So much for what concerns the absolute
force with which the War is to be conducted.
The measure of this absolute force is determined by the Government; and although with this determination
the real action of War commences, and it forms an essential part of the Strategy of the War, still in most cases
the General who is to command these forces in the War must regard their absolute strength as a given
quantity, whether it be that he has had no voice in fixing it, or that circumstances prevented a sufficient
expansion being given to it.
There remains nothing, therefore, where an absolute superiority is not attainable, but to produce a relative one
at the decisive point, by making skilful use of what we have.
The calculation of space and time appears as the most essential thing to this endand this has caused that
subject to be regarded as one which embraces nearly the whole art of using military forces. Indeed, some
have gone so far as to ascribe to great strategists and tacticians a mental organ peculiarly adapted to this
point.
But the calculation of time and space, although it lies universally at the foundation of Strategy, and is to a
certain extent its daily bread, is still neither the most difficult, nor the most decisive one.
If we take an unprejudiced glance at military history, we shall find that the instances in which mistakes in
such a calculation have proved the cause of serious losses are very rare, at least in Strategy. But if the
conception of a skilful combination of time and space is fully to account for every instance of a resolute and
active Commander beating several separate opponents with one and the same army (Frederick the Great,
Buonaparte), then we perplex ourselves unnecessarily with conventional language. For the sake of clearness
and the profitable use of conceptions, it is necessary that things should always be called by their right names.
The right appreciation of their opponents (Daun, Schwartzenberg), the audacity to leave for a short space of
time a small force only before them, energy in forced marches, boldness in sudden attacks, the intensified
activity which great souls acquire in the moment of danger, these are the grounds of such victories; and what
have these to do with the ability to make an exact calculation of two such simple things as time and space?
On War
On War 100
Page No 103
But even this ricochetting play of forces, "when the victories at Rosbach and Montmirail give the impulse to
victories at Leuthen and Montereau," to which great Generals on the defensive have often trusted, is still, if
we would be clear and exact, only a rare occurrence in history.
Much more frequently the relative superioritythat is, the skilful assemblage of superior forces at the
decisive pointhas its foundation in the right appreciation of those points, in the judicious direction which
by that means has been given to the forces from the very first, and in the resolution required to sacrifice the
unimportant to the advantage of the importantthat is, to keep the forces concentrated in an overpowering
mass. In this, Frederick the Great and Buonaparte are particularly characteristic.
We think we have now allotted to the superiority in numbers the importance which belongs to it; it is to be
regarded as the fundamental idea, always to be aimed at before all and as far as possible.
But to regard it on this account as a necessary condition of victory would be a complete misconception of our
exposition; in the conclusion to be drawn from it there lies nothing more than the value which should attach
to numerical strength in the combat. If that strength is made as great as possible, then the maxim is satisfied;
a review of the total relations must then decide whether or not the combat is to be avoided for want of
sufficient force.[*]
[*] Owing to our freedom from invasion, and to the condition which arise in our Colonial Wars, we have not
yet, in England, arrived at a correct appreciation of the value of superior numbers in War, and still adhere to
the idea of an Army just "big enough," which Clausewitz has so unsparingly ridiculed. (EDITOR.)
CHAPTER IX. THE SURPRISE
FROM the subject of the foregoing chapter, the general endeavour to attain a relative superiority, there
follows another endeavour which must consequently be just as general in its nature: this is the SURPRISE of
the enemy. It lies more or less at the foundation of all undertakings, for without it the preponderance at the
decisive point is not properly conceivable.
The surprise is, therefore, not only the means to the attainment of numerical superiority; but it is also to be
regarded as a substantive principle in itself, on account of its moral effect. When it is successful in a high
degree, confusion and broken courage in the enemy's ranks are the consequences; and of the degree to which
these multiply a success, there are examples enough, great and small. We are not now speaking of the
particular surprise which belongs to the attack, but of the endeavour by measures generally, and especially by
the distribution of forces, to surprise the enemy, which can be imagined just as well in the defensive, and
which in the tactical defence particularly is a chief point.
We say, surprise lies at the foundation of all undertakings without exception, only in very different degrees
according to the nature of the undertaking and other circumstances.
This difference, indeed, originates in the properties or peculiarities of the Army and its Commander, in those
even of the Government.
Secrecy and rapidity are the two factors in this product and these suppose in the Government and the
Commander inChief great energy, and on the part of the Army a high sense of military duty. With
effeminacy and loose principles it is in vain to calculate upon a surprise. But so general, indeed so
indispensable, as is this endeavour, and true as it is that it is never wholly unproductive of effect, still it is not
On War
On War 101
Page No 104
the less true that it seldom succeeds to a REMARKABLE degree, and this follows from the nature of the idea
itself. We should form an erroneous conception if we believed that by this means chiefly there is much to be
attained in War. In idea it promises a great deal; in the execution it generally sticks fast by the friction of the
whole machine.
In tactics the surprise is much more at home, for the very natural reason that all times and spaces are on a
smaller scale. It will, therefore, in Strategy be the more feasible in proportion as the measures lie nearer to the
province of tactics, and more difficult the higher up they lie towards the province of policy.
The preparations for a War usually occupy several months; the assembly of an Army at its principal positions
requires generally the formation of depo^ts and magazines, and long marches, the object of which can be
guessed soon enough.
It therefore rarely happens that one State surprises another by a War, or by the direction which it gives the
mass of its forces. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, when War turned very much upon sieges, it
was a frequent aim, and quite a peculiar and important chapter in the Art of War, to invest a strong place
unexpectedly, but even that only rarely succeeded.[*]
[*] Railways, steamships, and telegraphs have, however, enormously modified the relative importance and
practicability of surprise. (EDITOR.)
On the other hand, with things which can be done in a day or two, a surprise is much more conceivable, and,
therefore, also it is often not difficult thus to gain a march upon the enemy, and thereby a position, a point of
country, a road, But it is evident that what surprise gains in this way in easy execution, it loses in the efficacy,
as the greater the efficacy the greater always the difficulty of execution. Whoever thinks that with such
surprises on a small scale, he may connect great resultsas, for example, the gain of a battle, the capture of
an important magazinebelieves in something which it is certainly very possible to imagine, but for which
there is no warrant in history; for there are upon the whole very few instances where anything great has
resulted from such surprises; from which we may justly conclude that inherent difficulties lie in the way of
their success.
Certainly, whoever would consult history on such points must not depend on sundry battle steeds of historical
critics, on their wise dicta and selfcomplacent terminology, but look at facts with his own eyes. There is, for
instance, a certain day in the campaign in Silesia, 1761, which, in this respect, has attained a kind of
notoriety. It is the 22nd July, on which Frederick the Great gained on Laudon the march to Nossen, near
Neisse, by which, as is said, the junction of the Austrian and Russian armies in Upper Silesia became
impossible, and, therefore, a period of four weeks was gained by the King. Whoever reads over this
occurrence carefully in the principal histories,[*] and considers it impartially, will, in the march of the 22nd
July, never find this importance; and generally in the whole of the fashionable logic on this subject, he will
see nothing but contradictions; but in the proceedings of Laudon, in this renowned period of manoeuvres,
much that is unaccountable. How could one, with a thirst for truth, and clear conviction, accept such
historical evidence?
[*] Tempelhof, The Veteran, Frederick the Great. Compare also (Clausewitz) "Hinterlassene Werke," vol. x.,
p. 158.
When we promise ourselves great effects in a campaign from the principle of surprising, we think upon great
activity, rapid resolutions, and forced marches, as the means of producing them; but that these things, even
when forthcoming in a very high degree, will not always produce the desired effect, we see in examples given
byGenerals, who may be allowed to have had the greatest talent in the use of these means, Frederick the
Great and Buonaparte. The first when he left Dresden so suddenly in July 1760, and falling upon Lascy, then
On War
On War 102
Page No 105
turned against Dresden, gained nothing by the whole of that intermezzo, but rather placed his affairs in a
condition notably worse, as the fortress Glatz fell in the meantime.
In 1813, Buonaparte turned suddenly from Dresden twice against Bluecher, to say nothing of his incursion
into Bohemia from Upper Lusatia, and both times without in the least attaining his object. They were blows
in the air which only cost him time and force, and might have placed him in a dangerous position in Dresden.
Therefore, even in this field, a surprise does not necessarily meet with great success through the mere
activity, energy, and resolution of the Commander; it must be favoured by other circumstances. But we by no
means deny that there can be success; we only connect with it a necessity of favourable circumstances,
which, certainly do not occur very frequently, and which the Commander can seldom bring about himself.
Just those two Generals afford each a striking illustration of this. We take first Buonaparte in his famous
enterprise against Bluecher's Army in February 1814, when it was separated from the Grand Army, and
descending the Marne. It would not be easy to find a two days' march to surprise the enemy productive of
greater results than this; Bluecher's Army, extended over a distance of three days' march, was beaten in detail,
and suffered a loss nearly equal to that of defeat in a great battle. This was completely the effect of a surprise,
for if Bluecher had thought of such a near possibility of an attack from Buonaparte[*] he would have
organised his march quite differently. To this mistake of Bluecher's the result is to be attributed. Buonaparte
did not know all these circumstances, and so there was a piece of good fortune that mixed itself up in his
favour.
[*] Bluecher believed his march to be covered by Pahlen's Cossacks, but these had been withdrawn without
warning to him by the Grand Army Headquarters under Schwartzenberg.
It is the same with the battle of Liegnitz, 1760. Frederick the Great gained this fine victory through altering
during the night a position which he had just before taken up. Laudon was through this completely surprised,
and lost 70 pieces of artillery and 10,000 men. Although Frederick the Great had at this time adopted the
principle of moving backwards and forwards in order to make a battle impossible, or at least to disconcert the
enemy's plans, still the alteration of position on the night of the 1415 was not made exactly with that
intention, but as the King himself says, because the position of the 14th did not please him. Here, therefore,
also chance was hard at work; without this happy conjunction of the attack and the change of position in the
night, and the difficult nature of the country, the result would not have been the same.
Also in the higher and highest province of Strategy there are some instances of surprises fruitful in results.
We shall only cite the brilliant marches of the Great Elector against the Swedes from Franconia to Pomerania
and from the Mark (Brandenburg) to the Pregel in 1757, and the celebrated passage of the Alps by
Buonaparte, 1800. In the latter case an Army gave up its whole theatre of war by a capitulation, and in 1757
another Army was very near giving up its theatre of war and itself as well. Lastly, as an instance of a War
wholly unexpected, we may bring forward the invasion of Silesia by Frederick the Great. Great and powerful
are here the results everywhere, but such events are not common in history if we do not confuse with them
cases in which a State, for want of activity and energy (Saxony 1756, and Russia, 1812), has not completed
its preparations in time.
Now there still remains an observation which concerns the essence of the thing. A surprise can only be
effected by that party which gives the law to the other; and he who is in the right gives the law. If we surprise
the adversary by a wrong measure, then instead of reaping good results, we may have to bear a sound blow in
return; in any case the adversary need not trouble himself much about our surprise, he has in our mistake the
means of turning off the evil. As the offensive includes in itself much more positive action than the defensive,
so the surprise is certainly more in its place with the assailant, but by no means invariably, as we shall
hereafter see. Mutual surprises by the offensive and defensive may therefore meet, and then that one will
On War
On War 103
Page No 106
have the advantage who has hit the nail on the head the best.
So should it be, but practical life does not keep to this line so exactly, and that for a very simple reason. The
moral effects which attend a surprise often convert the worst case into a good one for the side they favour,
and do not allow the other to make any regular determination. We have here in view more than anywhere else
not only the chief Commander, but each single one, because a surprise has the effect in particular of greatly
loosening unity, so that the individuality of each separate leader easily comes to light.
Much depends here on the general relation in which the two parties stand to each other. If the one side
through a general moral superiority can intimidate and outdo the other, then he can make use of the surprise
with more success, and even reap good fruit where properly he should come to ruin.
CHAPTER X. STRATAGEM
STRATAGEM implies a concealed intention, and therefore is opposed to straightforward dealing, in the
same way as wit is the opposite of direct proof. It has therefore nothing in common with means of persuasion,
of self interest, of force, but a great deal to do with deceit, because that likewise conceals its object. It is
itself a deceit as well when it is done, but still it differs from what is commonly called deceit, in this respect
that there is no direct breach of word. The deceiver by stratagem leaves it to the person himself whom he is
deceiving to commit the errors of understanding which at last, flowing into ONE result, suddenly change the
nature of things in his eyes. We may therefore say, as nit is a sleight of hand with ideas and conceptions, so
stratagem is a sleight of hand with actions.
At first sight it appears as if Strategy had not improperly derived its name from stratagem; and that, with all
the real and apparent changes which the whole character of War has undergone since the time of the Greeks,
this term still points to its real nature.
If we leave to tactics the actual delivery of the blow, the battle itself, and look upon Strategy as the art of
using this means with skill, then besides the forces of the character, such as burning ambition which always
presses like a spring, a strong will which hardly bends there seems no subjective quality so suited to guide
and inspire strategic activity as stratagem. The general tendency to surprise, treated of in the foregoing
chapter, points to this conclusion, for there is a degree of stratagem, be it ever so small, which lies at the
foundation of every attempt to surprise.
But however much we feel a desire to see the actors in War outdo each other in hidden activity, readiness,
and stratagem, still we must admit that these qualities show themselves but little in history, and have rarely
been able to work their way to the surface from amongst the mass of relations and circumstances.
The explanation of this is obvious, and it is almost identical with the subject matter of the preceding chapter.
Strategy knows no other activity than the regulating of combat with the measures which relate to it. It has no
concern, like ordinary life, with transactions which consist merely of wordsthat is, in expressions,
declarations, But these, which are very inexpensive, are chiefly the means with which the wily one takes in
those he practises upon.
That which there is like it in War, plans and orders given merely as makebelievers, false reports sent on
purpose to the enemyis usually of so little effect in the strategic field that it is only resorted to in particular
cases which offer of themselves, therefore cannot be regarded as spontaneous action which emanates from
On War
On War 104
Page No 107
the leader.
But such measures as carrying out the arrangements for a battle, so far as to impose upon the enemy, require
a considerable expenditure of time and power; of course, the greater the impression to be made, the greater
the expenditure in these respects. And as this is usually not given for the purpose, very few demonstrations,
socalled, in Strategy, effect the object for which they are designed. In fact, it is dangerous to detach large
forces for any length of time merely for a trick, because there is always the risk of its being done in vain, and
then these forces are wanted at the decisive point.
The chief actor in War is always thoroughly sensible of this sober truth, and therefore he has no desire to play
at tricks of agility. The bitter earnestness of necessity presses so fully into direct action that there is no room
for that game. In a word, the pieces on the strategical chessboard want that mobility which is the element of
stratagem and subtility.
The conclusion which we draw, is that a correct and penetrating eye is a more necessary and more useful
quality for a General than craftiness, although that also does no harm if it does not exist at the expense of
necessary qualities of the heart, which is only too often the case.
But the weaker the forces become which are under the command of Strategy, so much the more they become
adapted for stratagem, so that to the quite feeble and little, for whom no prudence, no sagacity is any longer
sufficient at the point where all art seems to forsake him, stratagem offers itself as a last resource. The more
helpless his situation, the more everything presses towards one single, desperate blow, the more readily
stratagem comes to the aid of his boldness. Let loose from all further calculations, freed from all concern for
the future, boldness and stratagem intensify each other, and thus collect at one point an infinitesimal
glimmering of hope into a single ray, which may likewise serve to kindle a flame.
CHAPTER XI. ASSEMBLY OF FORCES IN SPACE
THE best Strategy is ALWAYS TO BE VERY STRONG, first generally then at the decisive point.
Therefore, apart from the energy which creates the Army, a work which is not always done by the General,
there is no more imperative and no simpler law for Strategy than to KEEP THE FORCES
CONCENTRATED.No portion is to be separated from the main body unless called away by some urgent
necessity. On this maxim we stand firm, and look upon it as a guide to be depended upon. What are the
reasonable grounds on which a detachment of forces may be made we shall learn by degrees. Then we shall
also see that this principle cannot have the same general effects in every War, but that these are different
according to the means and end.
It seems incredible, and yet it has happened a hundred times, that troops have been divided and separated
merely through a mysterious feeling of conventional manner, without any clear perception of the reason.
If the concentration of the whole force is acknowledged as the norm, and every division and separation as an
exception which must be justified, then not only will that folly be completely avoided, but also many an
erroneous ground for separating troops will be barred admission.
On War
On War 105
Page No 108
CHAPTER XII. ASSEMBLY OF FORCES IN TIME
WE have here to deal with a conception which in real life diffuses many kinds of illusory light. A clear
definition and development of the idea is therefore necessary, and we hope to be allowed a short analysis.
War is the shock of two opposing forces in collision with each other, from which it follows as a matter of
course that the stronger not only destroys the other, but carries it forward with it in its movement. This
fundamentally admits of no successive action of powers, but makes the simultaneous application of all forces
intended for the shock appear as a primordial law of War.
So it is in reality, but only so far as the struggle resembles also in practice a mechanical shock, but when it
consists in a lasting, mutual action of destructive forces, then we can certainly imagine a successive action of
forces. This is the case in tactics, principally because firearms form the basis of all tactics, but also for other
reasons as well. If in a fire combat 1000 men are opposed to 500, then the gross loss is calculated from the
amount of the enemy's force and our own; 1000 men fire twice as many shots as 500, but more shots will take
effect on the 1000 than on the 500 because it is assumed that they stand in closer order than the other. If we
were to suppose the number of hits to be double, then the losses on each side would be equal. From the 500
there would be for example 200 disabled, and out of the body of 1000 likewise the same; now if the 500 had
kept another body of equal number quite out of fire, then both sides would have 800 effective men; but of
these, on the one side there would be 500 men quite fresh, fully supplied with ammunition, and in their full
vigour; on the other side only 800 all alike shaken in their order, in want of sufficient ammunition and
weakened in physical force. The assumption that the 1000 men merely on account of their greater number
would lose twice as many as 500 would have lost in their place, is certainly not correct; therefore the greater
loss which the side suffers that has placed the half of its force in reserve, must be regarded as a disadvantage
in that original formation; further it must be admitted, that in the generality of cases the 1000 men would
have the advantage at the first commencement of being able to drive their opponent out of his position and
force him to a retrograde movement; now, whether these two advantages are a counterpoise to the
disadvantage of finding ourselves with 800 men to a certain extent disorganised by the combat, opposed to an
enemy who is not materially weaker in numbers and who has 500 quite fresh troops, is one that cannot be
decided by pursuing an analysis further, we must here rely upon experience, and there will scarcely be an
officer experienced in War who will not in the generality of cases assign the advantage to that side which has
the fresh troops.
In this way it becomes evident how the employment of too many forces in combat may be disadvantageous;
for whatever advantages the superiority may give in the first moment, we may have to pay dearly for in the
next.
But this danger only endures as long as the disorder, the state of confusion and weakness lasts, in a word, up
to the crisis which every combat brings with it even for the conqueror. Within the duration of this relaxed
state of exhaustion, the appearance of a proportionate number of fresh troops is decisive.
But when this disordering effect of victory stops, and therefore only the moral superiority remains which
every victory gives, then it is no longer possible for fresh troops to restore the combat, they would only be
carried along in the general movement; a beaten Army cannot be brought back to victory a day after by
means of a strong reserve. Here we find ourselves at the source of a highly material difference between
tactics and strategy.
The tactical results, the results within the four corners of the battle, and before its close, lie for the most part
within the limits of that period of disorder and weakness. But the strategic result, that is to say, the result of
the total combat, of the victories realised, let them be small or great, lies completely (beyond) outside of that
period. It is only when the results of partial combats have bound themselves together into an independent
On War
On War 106
Page No 109
whole, that the strategic result appears, but then, the state of crisis is over, the forces have resumed their
original form, and are now only weakened to the extent of those actually destroyed (placed hors de combat).
The consequence of this difference is, that tactics can make a continued use of forces, Strategy only a
simultaneous one.[*]
[*] See chaps. xiii., and xiv., Book III and chap. xxix. Book V.TR.
If I cannot, in tactics, decide all by the first success, if I have to fear the next moment, it follows of itself that
I employ only so much of my force for the success of the first moment as appears sufficient for that object,
and keep the rest beyond the reach of fire or conflict of any kind, in order to be able to oppose fresh troops to
fresh, or with such to overcome those that are exhausted. But it is not so in Strategy. Partly, as we have just
shown, it has not so much reason to fear a reaction after a success realised, because with that success the
crisis stops; partly all the forces strategically employed are not necessarily weakened. Only so much of them
as have been tactically in conflict with the enemy's force, that is, engaged in partial combat, are weakened by
it; consequently, only so much as was unavoidably necessary, but by no means all which was strategically in
conflict with the enemy, unless tactics has expended them unnecessarily. Corps which, on account of the
general superiority in numbers, have either been little or not at all engaged, whose presence alone has assisted
in the result, are after the decision the same as they were before, and for new enterprises as efficient as if they
had been entirely inactive. How greatly such corps which thus constitute our excess may contribute to the
total success is evident in itself; indeed, it is not difficult to see how they may even diminish considerably the
loss of the forces engaged in tactical, conflict on our side.
If, therefore, in Strategy the loss does not increase with the number of the troops employed, but is often
diminished by it, and if, as a natural consequence, the decision in our favor is, by that means, the more
certain, then it follows naturally that in Strategy we can never employ too many forces, and consequently also
that they must be applied simultaneously to the immediate purpose.
But we must vindicate this proposition upon another ground. We have hitherto only spoken of the combat
itself; it is the real activity in War, but men, time, and space, which appear as the elements of this activity,
must, at the same time, be kept in view, and the results of their influence brought into consideration also.
Fatigue, exertion, and privation constitute in War a special principle of destruction, not essentially belonging
to contest, but more or less inseparably bound up with it, and certainly one which especially belongs to
Strategy. They no doubt exist in tactics as well, and perhaps there in the highest degree; but as the duration of
the tactical acts is shorter, therefore the small effects of exertion and privation on them can come but little
into consideration. But in Strategy on the other hand, where time and space, are on a larger scale, their
influence is not only always very considerable, but often quite decisive. It is not at all uncommon for a
victorious Army to lose many more by sickness than on the field of battle.
If, therefore, we look at this sphere of destruction in Strategy in the same manner as we have considered that
of fire and close combat in tactics, then we may well imagine that everything which comes within its vortex
will, at the end of the campaign or of any other strategic period, be reduced to a state of weakness, which
makes the arrival of a fresh force decisive. We might therefore conclude that there is a motive in the one case
as well as the other to strive for the first success with as few forces as possible, in order to keep up this fresh
force for the last.
In order to estimate exactly this conclusion, which, in many cases in practice, will have a great
appearancetruth, we must direct our attention to the separate ideas which it contains. In the first place, we
must not confuse the notion of reinforcement with that of fresh unused troops. There are few campaigns at the
end of which an increase of force is not earnestly desired by the conqueror as well as the conquered, and
On War
On War 107
Page No 110
indeed should appear decisive; but that is not the point here, for that increase of force could not be necessary
if the force had been so much larger at the first. But it would be contrary to all experience to suppose that an
Army coming fresh into the field is to be esteemed higher in point of moral value than an Army already in the
field, just as a tactical reserve is more to be esteemed than a body of troops which has been already severely
handled in the fight. Just as much as an unfortunate campaign lowers the courage and moral powers of an
Army, a successful one raises these elements in their value. In the generality of cases, therefore, these
influences are compensated, and then there remains over and above as clear gain the habituation to War. We
should besides look more here to successful than to unsuccessful campaigns, because when the greater
probability of the latter may be seen beforehand, without doubt forces are wanted, and, therefore, the
reserving a portion for future use is out of the question.
This point being settled, then the question is, Do the losses which a force sustains through fatigues and
privations increase in proportion to the size of the force, as is the case in a combat? And to that we answer
"No."
The fatigues of War result in a great measure from the dangers with which every moment of the act of War is
more or less impregnated. To encounter these dangers at all points, to proceed onwards with security in the
execution of one's plans, gives employment to a multitude of agencies which make up the tactical and
strategic service of the Army. This service is more difficult the weaker an Army is, and easier as its numerical
superiority over that of the enemy increases. Who can doubt this? A campaign against a much weaker enemy
will therefore cost smaller efforts than against one just as strong or stronger.
So much for the fatigues. It is somewhat different with the privations; they consist chiefly of two things, the
want of food, and the want of shelter for the troops, either in quarters or in suitable camps. Both these wants
will no doubt be greater in proportion as the number of men on one spot is greater. But does not the
superiority in force afford also the best means of spreading out and finding more room, and therefore more
means of subsistence and shelter?
If Buonaparte, in his invasion of Russia in 1812, concentrated his Army in great masses upon one single road
in a manner never heard of before, and thus caused privations equally unparalleled, we must ascribe it to his
maxim THAT IT IS IMPOSSIBLE TO BE TOO STRONG AT THE DECISIVE POINT. Whether in this
instance he did not strain the principle too far is a question which would be out of place here; but it is certain
that, if he had made a point of avoiding the distress which was by that means brought about, he had only to
advance on a greater breadth of front. Room was not wanted for the purpose in Russia, and in very few cases
can it be wanted. Therefore, from this no ground can be deduced to prove that the simultaneous employment
of very superior forces must produce greater weakening. But now, supposing that in spite of the general relief
afforded by setting apart a portion of the Army, wind and weather and the toils of War had produced a
diminution even on the part which as a spare force had been reserved for later use, still we must take a
comprehensive general view of the whole, and therefore ask, Will this diminution of force suffice to
counterbalance the gain in forces, which we, through our superiority in numbers, may be able to make in
more ways than one?
But there still remains a most important point to be noticed. In a partial combat, the force required to obtain a
great result can be approximately estimated without much difficulty, and, consequently, we can form an idea
of what is superfluous. In Strategy this may be said to be impossible, because the strategic result has no such
welldefined object and no such circumscribed limits as the tactical. Thus what can be looked upon in tactics
as an excess of power, must be regarded in Strategy as a means to give expansion to success, if opportunity
offers for it; with the magnitude of the success the gain in force increases at the same time, and in this way
the superiority of numbers may soon reach a point which the most careful economy of forces could never
have attained.
On War
On War 108
Page No 111
By means of his enormous numerical superiority, Buonaparte was enabled to reach Moscow in 1812, and to
take that central capital. Had he by means of this superiority succeeded in completely defeating the Russian
Army, he would, in all probability, have concluded a peace in Moscow which in any other way was much
less attainable. This example is used to explain the idea, not to prove it, which would require a circumstantial
demonstration, for which this is not the place.[*]
[*] Compare Book VII., second edition, p. 56.
All these reflections bear merely upon the idea of a successive employment of forces, and not upon the
conception of a reserve properly so called, which they, no doubt, come in contact with throughout, but which,
as we shall see in the following chapter, is connected with some other considerations.
What we desire to establish here is, that if in tactics the military force through the mere duration of actual
employment suffers a diminution of power, if time, therefore, appears as a factor in the result, this is not the
case in Strategy in a material degree. The destructive effects which are also produced upon the forces in
Strategy by time, are partly diminished through their mass, partly made good in other ways, and, therefore, in
Strategy it cannot be an object to make time an ally on its own account by bringing troops successively into
action.
We say on "its own account," for the influence which time, on account of other circumstances which it brings
about but which are different from itself can have, indeed must necessarily have, for one of the two parties, is
quite another thing, is anything but indifferent or unimportant, and will be the subject of consideration
hereafter.
The rule which we have been seeking to set forth is, therefore, that all forces which are available and destined
for a strategic object should be SIMULTANEOUSLY applied to it; and this application will be so much the
more complete the more everything is compressed into one act and into one movement.
But still there is in Strategy a renewal of effort and a persistent action which, as a chief means towards the
ultimate success, is more particularly not to be overlooked, it is the CONTINUAL DEVELOPMENT OF
NEW FORCES. This is also the subject of another chapter, and we only refer to it here in order to prevent the
reader from having something in view of which we have not been speaking.
We now turn to a subject very closely connected with our present considerations, which must be settled
before full light can be thrown on the whole, we mean the STRATEGIC RESERVE.
CHAPTER XIII. STRATEGIC RESERVE
A RESERVE has two objects which are very distinct from each other, namely, first, the prolongation and
renewal of the combat, and secondly, for use in case of unforeseen events. The first object implies the utility
of a successive application of forces, and on that account cannot occur in Strategy. Cases in which a corps is
sent to succour a point which is supposed to be about to fall are plainly to be placed in the category of the
second object, as the resistance which has to be offered here could not have been sufficiently foreseen. But a
corps which is destined expressly to prolong the combat, and with that object in view is placed in rear, would
be only a corps placed out of reach of fire, but under the command and at the disposition of the General
Commanding in the action, and accordingly would be a tactical and not a strategic reserve.
But the necessity for a force ready for unforeseen events may also take place in Strategy, and consequently
On War
On War 109
Page No 112
there may also be a strategic reserve, but only where unforeseen events are imaginable. In tactics, where the
enemy's measures are generally first ascertained by direct sight, and where they may be concealed by every
wood, every fold of undulating ground, we must naturally always be alive, more or less, to the possibility of
unforeseen events, in order to strengthen, subsequently, those points which appear too weak, and, in fact, to
modify generally the disposition of our troops, so as to make it correspond better to that of the enemy.
Such cases must also happen in Strategy, because the strategic act is directly linked to the tactical. In Strategy
also many a measure is first adopted in consequence of what is actually seen, or in consequence of uncertain
reports arriving from day to day, or even from hour to hour, and lastly, from the actual results of the combats
it is, therefore, an essential condition of strategic command that, according to the degree of uncertainty,
forces must be kept in reserve against future contingencies.
In the defensive generally, but particularly in the defence of certain obstacles of ground, like rivers, hills,
such contingencies, as is well known, happen constantly.
But this uncertainty diminishes in proportion as the strategic activity has less of the tactical character, and
ceases almost altogether in those regions where it borders on politics.
The direction in which the enemy leads his columns to the combat can be perceived by actual sight only;
where he intends to pass a river is learnt from a few preparations which are made shortly before; the line by
which he proposes to invade our country is usually announced by all the newspapers before a pistol shot has
been fired. The greater the nature of the measure the less it will take the enemy by surprise. Time and space
are so considerable, the circumstances out of which the action proceeds so public and little susceptible of
alteration, that the coming event is either made known in good time, or can be discovered with reasonable
certainty.
On the other hand the use of a reserve in this province of Strategy, even if one were available, will always be
less efficacious the more the measure has a tendency towards being one of a general nature.
We have seen that the decision of a partial combat is nothing in itself, but that all partial combats only find
their complete solution in the decision of the total combat.
But even this decision of the total combat has only a relative meaning of many different gradations, according
as the force over which the victory has been gained forms a more or less great and important part of the
whole. The lost battle of a corps may be repaired by the victory of the Army. Even the lost battle of an Army
may not only be counterbalanced by the gain of a more important one, but converted into a fortunate event
(the two days of Kulm, August 29 and 30, 1813[*]). No one can doubt this; but it is just as clear that the
weight of each victory (the successful issue of each total combat) is so much the more substantial the more
important the part conquered, and that therefore the possibility of repairing the loss by subsequent events
diminishes in the same proportion. In another place we shall have to examine this more in detail; it suffices
for the present to have drawn attention to the indubitable existence of this progression.
[*] Refers to the destruction of Vandamme's column, which had been sent unsupported to intercept the retreat
of the Austrians and Prussians from Dresdenbut was forgotten by Napoleon.EDITOR.
If we now add lastly to these two considerations the third, which is, that if the persistent use of forces in
tactics always shifts the great result to the end of the whole act,law of the simultaneous use of the forces in
Strategy, on the contrary, lets the principal result (which need not be the final one) take place almost always
at the commencement of the great (or whole) act, then in these three results we have grounds sufficient to
find strategic reserves always more superfluous, always more useless, always more dangerous, the more
general their destination.
On War
On War 110
Page No 113
The point where the idea of a strategic reserve begins to become inconsistent is not difficult to determine: it
lies in the SUPREME DECISION. Employment must be given to all the forces within the space of the
supreme decision, and every reserve (active force available) which is only intended for use after that decision
is opposed to common sense.
If, therefore, tactics has in its reserves the means of not only meeting unforeseen dispositions on the part of
the enemy, but also of repairing that which never can be foreseen, the result of the combat, should that be
unfortunate; Strategy on the other hand must, at least as far as relates to the capital result, renounce the use of
these means. As A rule, it can only repair the losses sustained at one point by advantages gained at another, in
a few cases by moving troops from one point to another; the idea of preparing for such reverses by placing
forces in reserve beforehand, can never be entertained in Strategy.
We have pointed out as an absurdity the idea of a strategic reserve which is not to cooperate in the capital
result, and as it is so beyond a doubt, we should not have been led into such an analysis as we have made in
these two chapters, were it not that, in the disguise of other ideas, it looks like something better, and
frequently makes its appearance. One person sees in it the acme of strategic sagacity and foresight; another
rejects it, and with it the idea of any reserve, consequently even of a tactical one. This confusion of ideas is
transferred to real life, and if we would see a memorable instance of it we have only to call to mind that
Prussia in 1806 left a reserve of 20,000 men cantoned in the Mark, under Prince Eugene of Wurtemberg,
which could not possibly reach the Saale in time to be of any use, and that another force Of 25,000 men
belonging to this power remained in East and South Prussia, destined only to be put on a warfooting
afterwards as a reserve.
After these examples we cannot be accused of having been fighting with windmills.
CHAPTER XIV. ECONOMY OF FORCES
THE road of reason, as we have said, seldom allows itself to be reduced to a mathematical line by principles
and opinions. There remains always a certain margin. But it is the same in all the practical arts of life. For the
lines of beauty there are no abscissae and ordinates; circles and ellipses are not described by means of their
algebraical formulae. The actor in War therefore soon finds he must trust himself to the delicate tact of
judgment which, founded on natural quickness of perception, and educated by reflection, almost
unconsciously seizes upon the right; he soon finds that at one time he must simplify the law (by reducing it)
to some prominent characteristic points which form his rules; that at another the adopted method must
become the staff on which he leans.
As one of these simplified characteristic points as a mental appliance, we look upon the principle of watching
continually over the cooperation of all forces, or in other words, of keeping constantly in view that no part
of them should ever be idle. Whoever has forces where the enemy does not give them sufficient employment,
whoever has part of his forces on the marchthat is, allows them to lie deadwhile the enemy's are
fighting, he is a bad manager of his forces. In this sense there is a waste of forces, which is even worse than
their employment to no purpose. If there must be action, then the first point is that all parts act, because the
most purposeless activity still keeps employed and destroys a portion of the enemy's force, whilst troops
completely inactive are for the moment quite neutralised. Unmistakably this idea is bound up with the
principles contained in the last three chapters, it is the same truth, but seen from a somewhat more
comprehensive point of view and condensed into a single conception.
On War
On War 111
Page No 114
CHAPTER XV. GEOMETRICAL ELEMENT
THE length to which the geometrical element or form in the disposition of military force in War can become
a predominant principle, we see in the art of fortification, where geometry looks after the great and the little.
Also in tactics it plays a great part. It is the basis of elementary tactics, or of the theory of moving troops; but
in field fortification, as well as in the theory of positions, and of their attack, its angles and lines rule like law
givers who have to decide the contest. Many things here were at one time misapplied, and others were mere
fribbles; still, however, in the tactics of the present day, in which in every combat the aim is to surround the
enemy, the geometrical element has attained anew a great importance in a very simple, but constantly
recurring application. Nevertheless, in tactics, where all is more movable, where the moral forces, individual
traits, and chance are more influential than in a war of sieges, the geometrical element can never attain to the
same degree of supremacy as in the latter. But less still is its influence in Strategy; certainly here, also, form
in the disposition of troops, the shape of countries and states is of great importance; but the geometrical
element is not decisive, as in fortification, and not nearly so important as in tactics.The manner in which
this influence exhibits itself, can only be shown by degrees at those places where it makes its appearance, and
deserves notice. Here we wish more to direct attention to the difference which there is between tactics and
Strategy in relation to it.
In tactics time and space quickly dwindle to their absolute minimum. If a body of troops is attacked in flank
and rear by the enemy, it soon gets to a point where retreat no longer remains; such a position is very close to
an absolute impossibility of continuing the fight; it must therefore extricate itself from it, or avoid getting into
it. This gives to all combinations aiming at this from the first commencement a great efficiency, which
chiefly consists in the disquietude which it causes the enemy as to consequences. This is why the geometrical
disposition of the forces is such an important factor in the tactical product.
In Strategy this is only faintly reflected, on account of the greater space and time. We do not fire from one
theatre of war upon another; and often weeks and months must pass before a strategic movement designed to
surround the enemy can be executed. Further, the distances are so great that the probability of hitting the right
point at last, even with the best arrangements, is but small.
In Strategy therefore the scope for such combinations, that is for those resting on the geometrical element, is
much smaller, and for the same reason the effect of an advantage once actually gained at any point is much
greater. Such advantage has time to bring all its effects to maturity before it is disturbed, or quite neutralised
therein, by any counteracting apprehensions. We therefore do not hesitate to regard as an established truth,
that in Strategy more depends on the number and the magnitude of the victorious combats, than on the form
of the great lines by which they are connected.
A view just the reverse has been a favourite theme of modern theory, because a greater importance was
supposed to be thus given to Strategy, and, as the higher functions of the mind were seen in Strategy, it was
thought by that means to ennoble War, and, as it was saidthrough a new substitution of ideasto make it
more scientific. We hold it to be one of the principal uses of a complete theory openly to expose such
vagaries, and as the geometrical element is the fundamental idea from which theory usually proceeds,
therefore we have expressly brought out this point in strong relief.
CHAPTER XVI. ON THE SUSPENSION OF THE ACT IN WARFARE
IF one considers War as an act of mutual destruction, we must of necessity imagine both parties as making
some progress; but at the same time, as regards the existing moment, we must almost as necessarily suppose
On War
On War 112
Page No 115
the one party in a state of expectation, and only the other actually advancing, for circumstances can never be
actually the same on both sides, or continue so. In time a change must ensue, from which it follows that the
present moment is more favourable to one side than the other. Now if we suppose that both commanders have
a full knowledge of this circumstance, then the one has a motive for action, which at the same time is a
motive for the other to wait; therefore, according to this it cannot be for the interest of both at the same time
to advance, nor can waiting be for the interest of both at the same time. This opposition of interest as regards
the object is not deduced here from the principle of general polarity, and therefore is not in opposition to the
argument in the fifth chapter of the second book; it depends on the fact that here in reality the same thing is at
once an incentive or motive to both commanders, namely the probability of improving or impairing their
position by future action.
But even if we suppose the possibility of a perfect equality of circumstances in this respect, or if we take into
account that through imperfect knowledge of their mutual position such an equality may appear to the two
Commanders to subsist, still the difference of political objects does away with this possibility of suspension.
One of the parties must of necessity be assumed politically to be the aggressor, because no War could take
place from defensive intentions on both sides. But the aggressor has the positive object, the defender merely a
negative one. To the first then belongs the positive action, for it is only by that means that he can attain the
positive object; therefore, in cases where both parties are in precisely similar circumstances, the aggressor is
called upon to act by virtue of his positive object.
Therefore, from this point of view, a suspension in the act of Warfare, strictly speaking, is in contradiction
with the nature of the thing; because two Armies, being two incompatible elements, should destroy one
another unremittingly, just as fire and water can never put themselves in equilibrium, but act and react upon
one another, until one quite disappears. What would be said of two wrestlers who remained clasped round
each other for hours without making a movement. Action in War, therefore, like that of a clock which is
wound up, should go on running down in regular motion.But wild as is the nature of War it still wears the
chains of human weakness, and the contradiction we see here, viz., that man seeks and creates dangers which
he fears at the same time will astonish no one.
If we cast a glance at military history in general, we find so much the opposite of an incessant advance
towards the aim, that STANDING STILL and DOING NOTHING is quite plainly the NORMAL
CONDITION of an Army in the midst of War, ACTING, the EXCEPTION. This must almost raise a doubt
as to the correctness of our conception. But if military history leads to this conclusion when viewed in the
mass the latest series of campaigns redeems our position. The War of the French Revolution shows too
plainly its reality, and only proves too clearly its necessity. In these operations, and especially in the
campaigns of Buonaparte, the conduct of War attained to that unlimited degree of energy which we have
represented as the natural law of the element. This degree is therefore possible, and if it is possible then it is
necessary.
How could any one in fact justify in the eyes of reason the expenditure of forces in War, if acting was not the
object? The baker only heats his oven if he has bread to put into it; the horse is only yoked to the carriage if
we mean to drive; why then make the enormous effort of a War if we look for nothing else by it but like
efforts on the part of the enemy?
So much in justification of the general principle; now as to its modifications, as far as they lie in the nature of
the thing and are independent of special cases.
There are three causes to be noticed here, which appear as innate counterpoises and prevent the overrapid or
uncontrollable movement of the wheelwork.
The first, which produces a constant tendency to delay, and is thereby a retarding principle, is the natural
On War
On War 113
Page No 116
timidity and want of resolution in the human mind, a kind of inertia in the moral world, but which is
produced not by attractive, but by repellent forces, that is to say, by dread of danger and responsibility.
In the burning element of War, ordinary natures appear to become heavier; the impulsion given must
therefore be stronger and more frequently repeated if the motion is to be a continuous one. The mere idea of
the object for which arms have been taken up is seldom sufficient to overcome this resistant force, and if a
warlike enterprising spirit is not at the head, who feels himself in War in his natural element, as much as a
fish in the ocean, or if there is not the pressure from above of some great responsibility, then standing still
will be the order of the day, and progress will be the exception.
The second cause is the imperfection of human perception and judgment, which is greater in War than
anywhere, because a person hardly knows exactly his own position from one moment to another, and can
only conjecture on slight grounds that of the enemy, which is purposely concealed; this often gives rise to the
case of both parties looking upon one and the same object as advantageous for them, while in reality the
interest of one must preponderate; thus then each may think he acts wisely by waiting another moment, as we
have already said in the fifth chapter of the second book.
The third cause which catches hold, like a ratchet wheel in machinery, from time to time producing a
complete standstill, is the greater strength of the defensive form. A may feel too weak to attack B, from
which it does not follow that B is strong enough for an attack on A. The addition of strength, which the
defensive gives is not merely lost by assuming the offensive, but also passes to the enemy just as, figuratively
expressed, the difference of a + b and a b is equal to 2b. Therefore it may so happen that both parties, at one
and the same time, not only feel themselves too weak to attack, but also are so in reality.
Thus even in the midst of the act of War itself, anxious sagacity and the apprehension of too great danger find
vantage ground, by means of which they can exert their power, and tame the elementary impetuosity of War.
However, at the same time these causes without an exaggeration of their effect, would hardly explain the long
states of inactivity which took place in military operations, in former times, in Wars undertaken about
interests of no great importance, and in which inactivity consumed ninetenths of the time that the troops
remained under arms. This feature in these Wars, is to be traced principally to the influence which the
demands of the one party, and the condition, and feeling of the other, exercised over the conduct of the
operations, as has been already observed in the chapter on the essence and object of War.
These things may obtain such a preponderating influence as to make of War a halfandhalf affair. A War is
often nothing more than an armed neutrality, or a menacing attitude to support negotiations or an attempt to
gain some small advantage by small exertions, and then to wait the tide of circumstances, or a disagreeable
treaty obligation, which is fulfilled in the most niggardly way possible.
In all these cases in which the impulse given by interest is slight, and the principle of hostility feeble, in
which there is no desire to do much, and also not much to dread from the enemy; in short, where no powerful
motives press and drive, cabinets will not risk much in the game; hence this tame mode of carrying on War,
in which the hostile spirit of real War is laid in irons.
The more War becomes in this manner devitalised so much the more its theory becomes destitute of the
necessary firm pivots and buttresses for its reasoning; the necessary is constantly diminishing, the accidental
constantly increasing.
Nevertheless in this kind of Warfare, there is also a certain shrewdness, indeed, its action is perhaps more
diversified, and more extensive than in the other. Hazard played with realeaux of gold seems changed into a
game of commerce with groschen. And on this field, where the conduct of War spins out the time with a
On War
On War 114
Page No 117
number of small flourishes, with skirmishes at outposts, half in earnest half in jest, with long dispositions
which end in nothing with positions and marches, which afterwards are designated as skilful only because
their infinitesimally small causes are lost, and common sense can make nothing of them, here on this very
field many theorists find the real Art of War at home: in these feints, parades, half and quarter thrusts of
former Wars, they find the aim of all theory, the supremacy of mind over matter, and modern Wars appear to
them mere savage fisticuffs, from which nothing is to be learnt, and which must be regarded as mere
retrograde steps towards barbarism. This opinion is as frivolous as the objects to which it relates. Where great
forces and great passions are wanting, it is certainly easier for a practised dexterity to show its game; but is
then the command of great forces, not in itself a higher exercise of the intelligent faculties? Is then that kind
of conventional swordexercise not comprised in and belonging to the other mode of conducting War? Does
it not bear the same relation to it as the motions upon a ship to the motion of the ship itself? Truly it can take
place only under the tacit condition that the adversary does no better. And can we tell, how long he may
choose to respect those conditions? Has not then the French Revolution fallen upon us in the midst of the
fancied security of our old system of War, and driven us from Chalons to Moscow? And did not Frederick the
Great in like manner surprise the Austrians reposing in their ancient habits of War, and make their monarchy
tremble? Woe to the cabinet which, with a shillyshally policy, and a routineridden military system, meets
with an adversary who, like the rude element, knows no other law than that of his intrinsic force. Every
deficiency in energy and exertion is then a weight in the scales in favour of the enemy; it is not so easy then
to change from the fencing posture into that of an athlete, and a slight blow is often sufficient to knock down
the whole.
The result of all the causes now adduced is, that the hostile action of a campaign does not progress by a
continuous, but by an intermittent movement, and that, therefore, between the separate bloody acts, there is a
period of watching, during which both parties fall into the defensive, and also that usually a higher object
causes the principle of aggression to predominate on one side, and thus leaves it in general in an advancing
position, by which then its proceedings become modified in some degree.
CHAPTER XVII. ON THE CHARACTER OF MODERN WAR
THE attention which must be paid to the character of War as it is now made, has a great influence upon all
plans, especially on strategic ones.
Since all methods formerly usual were upset by Buonaparte's luck and boldness, and firstrate Powers almost
wiped out at a blow; since the Spaniards by their stubborn resistance have shown what the general arming of
a nation and insurgent measures on a great scale can effect, in spite of weakness and porousness of individual
parts; since Russia, by the campaign of 1812 has taught us, first, that an Empire of great dimensions is not to
be conquered (which might have been easily known before), secondly, that the probability of final success
does not in all cases diminish in the same measure as battles, capitals, and provinces are lost (which was
formerly an incontrovertible principle with all diplomatists, and therefore made them always ready to enter at
once into some bad temporary peace), but that a nation is often strongest in the heart of its country, if the
enemy's offensive power has exhausted itself, and with what enormous force the defensive then springs over
to the offensive; further, since Prussia (1813) has shown that sudden efforts may add to an Army sixfold by
means of the militia, and that this militia is just as fit for service abroad as in its own country; since all
these events have shown what an enormous factor the heart and sentiments of a Nation may be in the product
of its political and military strength, in fine, since governments have found out all these additional aids, it is
not to be expected that they will let them lie idle in future Wars, whether it be that danger threatens their own
existence, or that restless ambition drives them on.
On War
On War 115
Page No 118
That a War which is waged with the whole weight of the national power on each side must be organised
differently in principle to those where everything is calculated according to the relations of standing Armies
to each other, it is easy to perceive. Standing Armies once resembled fleets, the land force the sea force in
their relations to the remainder of the State, and from that the Art of War on shore had in it something of
naval tactics, which it has now quite lost.
CHAPTER XVIII. TENSION AND REST
The Dynamic Law of War
WE have seen in the sixteenth chapter of this book, how, in most campaigns, much more time used to be
spent in standing still and inaction than in activity.
Now, although, as observed in the preceding chapter we see quite a different character in the present form of
War, still it is certain that real action will always be interrupted more or less by long pauses; and this leads to
the necessity of our examining more closely the nature of these two phases of War.
If there is a suspension of action in War, that is, if neither party wills something positive, there is rest, and
consequently equilibrium, but certainly an equilibrium in the largest signification, in which not only the
moral and physical warforces, but all relations and interests, come into calculation. As soon as ever one of
the two parties proposes to himself a new positive object, and commences active steps towards it, even if it is
only by preparations, and as soon as the adversary opposes this, there is a tension of powers; this lasts until
the decision takes placethat is, until one party either gives up his object or the other has conceded it to him.
This decisionthe foundation of which lies always in the combatcombinations which are made on each
side is followed by a movement in one or other direction.
When this movement has exhausted itself, either in the difficulties which had to be mastered, in overcoming
its own internal friction, or through new resistant forces of rest takes place or a new tension with a decision,
and then a new movement, in most cases in the opposite direction.
This speculative distinction between equilibrium, tension, and motion is more essential for practical action
than may at first sight appear.
In a state of rest and of equilibrium a varied kind of activity may prevail on one side that results from
opportunity, and does not aim at a great alteration. Such an activity may contain important combatseven
pitched battlesbut yet it is still of quite a different nature, and on that account generally different in its
effects.
If a state of tension exists, the effects of the decision are always greater partly because a greater force of will
and a greater pressure of circumstances manifest themselves therein; partly because everything has been
prepared and arranged for a great movement. The decision in such cases resembles the effect of a mine well
closed and tamped, whilst an event in itself perhaps just as great, in a state of rest, is more or less like a mass
of powder puffed away in the open air.
At the same time, as a matter of course, the state of tension must be imagined in different degrees of intensity,
and it may therefore approach gradually by many steps towards the state of rest, so that at the last there is a
very slight difference between them.
On War
On War 116
Page No 119
Now the real use which we derive from these reflections is the conclusion that every measure which is taken
during a state of tension is more important and more prolific in results than the same measure could be in a
state of equilibrium, and that this importance increases immensely in the highest degrees of tension.
The cannonade of Valmy, September 20, 1792, decided more than the battle of Hochkirch, October 14, 1758.
In a tract of country which the enemy abandons to us because he cannot defend it, we can settle ourselves
differently from what we should do if the retreat of the enemy was only made with the view to a decision
under more favourable circumstances. Again, a strategic attack in course of execution, a faulty position, a
single false march, may be decisive in its consequence; whilst in a state of equilibrium such errors must be of
a very glaring kind, even to excite the activity of the enemy in a general way.
Most bygone Wars, as we have already said, consisted, so far as regards the greater part of the time, in this
state of equilibrium, or at least in such short tensions with long intervals between them, and weak in their
effects, that the events to which they gave rise were seldom great successes, often they were theatrical
exhibitions, got up in honour of a royal birthday (Hochkirch), often a mere satisfying of the honour of the
arms (Kunersdorf), or the personal vanity of the commander (Freiberg).
That a Commander should thoroughly understand these states, that he should have the tact to act in the spirit
of them, we hold to be a great requisite, and we have had experience in the campaign of 1806 how far it is
sometimes wanting. In that tremendous tension, when everything pressed on towards a supreme decision, and
that alone with all its consequences should have occupied the whole soul of the Commander, measures were
proposed and even partly carried out (such as the reconnaissance towards Franconia), which at the most
might have given a kind of gentle play of oscillation within a state of equilibrium. Over these blundering
schemes and views, absorbing the activity of the Army, the really necessary means, which could alone save,
were lost sight of.
But this speculative distinction which we have made is also necessary for our further progress in the
construction of our theory, because all that we have to say on the relation of attack and defence, and on the
completion of this doublesided act, concerns the state of the crisis in which the forces are placed during the
tension and motion, and because all the activity which can take place during the condition of equilibrium can
only be regarded and treated as a corollary; for that crisis is the real War and this state of equilibrium only its
reflection.
BOOK IV. THE COMBAT
CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTORY
HAVING in the foregoing book examined the subjects which may be regarded as the efficient elements of
War, we shall now turn our attention to the combat as the real activity in Warfare, which, by its physical and
moral effects, embraces sometimes more simply, sometimes in a more complex manner, the object of the
whole campaign. In this activity and in its effects these elements must therefore, reappear.
The formation of the combat is tactical in its nature; we only glance at it here in a general way in order to get
acquainted with it in its aspect as a whole. In practice the minor or more immediate objects give every
combat a characteristic form; these minor objects we shall not discuss until hereafter. But these peculiarities
are in comparison to the general characteristics of a combat mostly only insignificant, so that most combats
On War
On War 117
Page No 120
are very like one another, and, therefore, in order to avoid repeating that which is general at every stage, we
are compelled to look into it here, before taking up the subject of its more special application.
In the first place, therefore, we shall give in the next chapter, in a few words, the characteristics of the
modern battle in its tactical course, because that lies at the foundation of our conceptions of what the battle
really is.
CHAPTER II. CHARACTER OF THE MODERN BATTLE
ACCORDING to the notion we have formed of tactics and strategy, it follows, as a matter of course, that if
the nature of the former is changed, that change must have an influence on the latter. If tactical facts in one
case are entirely different from those in another, then the strategic, must be so also, if they are to continue
consistent and reasonable. It is therefore important to characterise a general action in its modern form before
we advance with the study of its employment in strategy.
What do we do now usually in a great battle? We place ourselves quietly in great masses arranged contiguous
to and behind one another. We deploy relatively only a small portion of the whole, and let it wring itself out
in a firecombat which lasts for several hours, only interrupted now and again, and removed hither and
thither by separate small shocks from charges with the bayonet and cavalry attacks. When this line has
gradually exhausted part of its warlike ardour in this manner and there remains nothing more than the cinders,
it is withdrawn[*] and replaced by another.
[*] The relief of the fighting line played a great part in the battles of the SmoothBore era; it was necessitated
by the fouling of the muskets, physical fatigue of the men and consumption of ammunition, and was
recognised as both necessary and advisable by Napoleon himself.EDITOR.
In this manner the battle on a modified principle burns slowly away like wet powder, and if the veil of night
commands it to stop, because neither party can any longer see, and neither chooses to run the risk of blind
chance, then an account is taken by each side respectively of the masses remaining, which can be called still
effective, that is, which have not yet quite collapsed like extinct volcanoes; account is taken of the ground
gained or lost, and of how stands the security of the rear; these results with the special impressions as to
bravery and cowardice, ability and stupidity, which are thought to have been observed in ourselves and in the
enemy are collected into one single total impression, out of which there springs the resolution to quit the field
or to renew the combat on the morrow.
This description, which is not intended as a finished picture of a modern battle, but only to give its general
tone, suits for the offensive and defensive, and the special traits which are given, by the object proposed, the
country, may be introduced into it, without materially altering the conception.
But modern battles are not so by accident; they are so because the parties find themselves nearly on a level as
regards military organisation and the knowledge of the Art of War, and because the warlike element inflamed
by great national interests has broken through artificial limits and now flows in its natural channel. Under
these two conditions, battles will always preserve this character.
This general idea of the modern battle will be useful to us in the sequel in more places than one, if we want to
estimate the value of the particular coefficients of strength, country, It is only for general, great, and
decisive combats, and such as come near to them that this description stands good; inferior ones have
changed their character also in the same direction but less than great ones. The proof of this belongs to
On War
On War 118
Page No 121
tactics; we shall, however, have an opportunity hereafter of making this subject plainer by giving a few
particulars.
CHAPTER III. THE COMBAT IN GENERAL
THE Combat is the real warlike activity, everything else is only its auxiliary; let us therefore take an attentive
look at its nature.
Combat means fighting, and in this the destruction or conquest of the enemy is the object, and the enemy, in
the particular combat, is the armed force which stands opposed to us.
This is the simple idea; we shall return to it, but before we can do that we must insert a series of others.
If we suppose the State and its military force as a unit, then the most natural idea is to imagine the War also
as one great combat, and in the simple relations of savage nations it is also not much otherwise. But our Wars
are made up of a number of great and small simultaneous or consecutive combats, and this severance of the
activity into so many separate actions is owing to the great multiplicity of the relations out of which War
arises with us.
In point of fact, the ultimate object of our Wars the, political one, is not always quite a simple one; and even
were it so, still the action is bound up with such a number of conditions and considerations to be taken into
account, that the object can no longer be attained by one single great act but only through a number of greater
or smaller acts which are bound up into a whole; each of these separate acts is therefore a part of a whole, and
has consequently a special object by which it is bound to this whole.
We have already said that every strategic act can be referred to the idea of a combat, because it is an
employment of the military force, and at the root of that there always lies the idea of fighting. We may
therefore reduce every military activity in the province of Strategy to the unit of single combats, and occupy
ourselves with the object of these only; we shall get acquainted with these special objects by degrees as we
come to speak of the causes which produce them; here we content ourselves with saying that every combat,
great or small, has its own peculiar object in subordination to the main object. If this is the case then, the
destruction and conquest of the enemy is only to be regarded as the means of gaining this object; as it
unquestionably is.
But this result is true only in its form, and important only on account of the connection which the ideas have
between themselves, and we have only sought it out to get rid of it at once.
What is overcoming the enemy? Invariably the destruction of his military force, whether it be by death, or
wounds, or any means; whether it be completely or only to such a degree that he can no longer continue the
contest; therefore as long as we set aside all special objects of combats, we may look upon the complete or
partial destruction of the enemy as the only object of all combats.
Now we maintain that in the majority of cases, and especially in great battles, the special object by which the
battle is individualised and bound up with the great whole is only a weak modification of that general object,
or an ancillary object bound up with it, important enough to individualise the battle, but always insignificant
in comparison with that general object; so that if that ancillary object alone should be obtained, only an
unimportant part of the purpose of the combat is fulfilled. If this assertion is correct, then we see that the idea,
according to which the destruction of the enemy's force is only the means, and something else always the
On War
On War 119
Page No 122
object, can only be true in form, but, that it would lead to false conclusions if we did not recollect that this
destruction of the enemy's force is comprised in that object, and that this object is only a weak modification
of it. Forgetfulness of this led to completely false views before the Wars of the last period, and created
tendencies as well as fragments of systems, in which theory thought it raised itself so much the more above
handicraft, the less it supposed itself to stand in need of the use of the real instrument, that is the destruction
of the enemy's force.
Certainly such a system could not have arisen unless supported by other false suppositions, and unless in
place of the destruction of the enemy, other things had been substituted to which an efficacy was ascribed
which did not rightly belong to them. We shall attack these falsehoods whenever occasion requires, but we
could not treat of the combat without claiming for it the real importance and value which belong to it, and
giving warning against the errors to which merely formal truth might lead.
But now how shall we manage to show that in most cases, and in those of most importance, the destruction of
the enemy's Army is the chief thing? How shall we manage to combat that extremely subtle idea, which
supposes it possible, through the use of a special artificial form, to effect by a small direct destruction of the
enemy's forces a much greater destruction indirectly, or by means of small but extremely welldirected blows
to produce such paralysation of the enemy's forces, such a command over the enemy's will, that this mode of
proceeding is to be viewed as a great shortening of the road? Undoubtedly a victory at one point may be of
more value than at another. Undoubtedly there is a scientific arrangement of battles amongst themselves,
even in Strategy, which is in fact nothing but the Art of thus arranging them. To deny that is not our intention,
but we assert that the direct destruction of the enemy's forces is everywhere predominant; we contend here
for the overruling importance of this destructive principle and nothing else.
We must, however, call to mind that we are now engaged with Strategy, not with tactics, therefore we do not
speak of the means which the former may have of destroying at a small expense a large body of the enemy's
forces, but under direct destruction we understand the tactical results, and that, therefore, our assertion is that
only great tactical results can lead to great strategical ones, or, as we have already once before more distinctly
expressed it, THE TACTICAL SUCCESSES are of paramount importance in the conduct of War.
The proof of this assertion seems to us simple enough, it lies in the time which every complicated (artificial)
combination requires. The question whether a simple attack, or one more carefully prepared, i.e., more
artificial, will produce greater effects, may undoubtedly be decided in favour of the latter as long as the
enemy is assumed to remain quite passive. But every carefully combined attack requires time for its
preparation, and if a counter stroke by the enemy intervenes, our whole design may be upset. Now if the
enemy should decide upon some simple attack, which can be executed in a shorter time, then he gains the
initiative, and destroys the effect of the great plan. Therefore, together with the expediency of a complicated
attack we must consider all the dangers which we run during its preparation, and should only adopt it if there
is no reason to fear that the enemy will disconcert our scheme. Whenever this is the case we must ourselves
choose the simpler, i.e., quicker way, and lower our views in this sense as far as the character, the relations of
the enemy, and other circumstances may render necessary. If we quit the weak impressions of abstract ideas
and descend to the region of practical life, then it is evident that a bold, courageous, resolute enemy will not
let us have time for widereaching skilful combinations, and it is just against such a one we should require
skill the most. By this it appears to us that the advantage of simple and direct results over those that are
complicated is conclusively shown.
Our opinion is not on that account that the simple blow is the best, but that we must not lift the arm too far for
the time given to strike, and that this condition will always lead more to direct conflict the more warlike our
opponent is. Therefore, far from making it our aim to gain upon the enemy by complicated plans, we must
rather seek to be beforehand with him by greater simplicity in our designs.
On War
On War 120
Page No 123
If we seek for the lowest foundationstones of these converse propositions we find that in the one it is ability,
in the other, courage. Now, there is something very attractive in the notion that a moderate degree of courage
joined to great ability will produce greater effects than moderate ability with great courage. But unless we
suppose these elements in a disproportionate relation, not logical, we have no right to assign to ability this
advantage over courage in a field which is called danger, and which must be regarded as the true domain of
courage.
After this abstract view we shall only add that experience, very far from leading to a different conclusion, is
rather the sole cause which has impelled us in this direction, and given rise to such reflections.
Whoever reads history with a mind free from prejudice cannot fail to arrive at a conviction that of all military
virtues, energy in the conduct of operations has always contributed the most to the glory and success of arms.
How we make good our principle of regarding the destruction of the enemy's force as the principal object, not
only in the War as a whole but also in each separate combat, and how that principle suits all the forms and
conditions necessarily demanded by the relations out of which War springs, the sequel will show. For the
present all that we desire is to uphold its general importance, and with this result we return again to the
combat.
CHAPTER IV. THE COMBAT IN GENERAL (CONTINUATION)
IN the last chapter we showed the destruction of the enemy as the true object of the combat, and we have
sought to prove by a special consideration of the point, that this is true in the majority of cases, and in respect
to the most important battles, because the destruction of the enemy's Army is always the preponderating
object in War. The other objects which may be mixed up with this destruction of the enemy's force, and may
have more or less influence, we shall describe generally in the next chapter, and become better acquainted
with by degrees afterwards; here we divest the combat of them entirely, and look upon the destruction of the
enemy as the complete and sufficient object of any combat.
What are we now to understand by destruction of the enemy's Army? A diminution of it relatively greater
than that on our own side. If we have a great superiority in numbers over the enemy, then naturally the same
absolute amount of loss on both sides is for us a smaller one than for him, and consequently may be regarded
in itself as an advantage. As we are here considering the combat as divested of all (other) objects, we must
also exclude from our consideration the case in which the combat is used only indirectly for a greater
destruction of the enemy's force; consequently also, only that direct gain which has been made in the mutual
process of destruction, is to be regarded as the object, for this is an absolute gain, which runs through the
whole campaign, and at the end of it will always appear as pure profit. But every other kind of victory over
our opponent will either have its motive in other objects, which we have completely excluded here, or it will
only yield a temporary relative advantage. An example will make this plain.
If by a skilful disposition we have reduced our opponent to such a dilemma, that he cannot continue the
combat without danger, and after some resistance he retires, then we may say, that we have conquered him at
that point; but if in this victory we have expended just as many forces as the enemy, then in closing the
account of the campaign, there is no gain remaining from this victory, if such a result can be called a victory.
Therefore the overcoming the enemy, that is, placing him in such a position that he must give up the fight,
counts for nothing in itself, and for that reason cannot come under the definition of object. There remains,
therefore, as we have said, nothing over except the direct gain which we have made in the process of
destruction; but to this belong not only the losses which have taken place in the course of the combat, but also
On War
On War 121
Page No 124
those which, after the withdrawal of the conquered part, take place as direct consequences of the same.
Now it is known by experience, that the losses in physical forces in the course of a battle seldom present a
great difference between victor and vanquished respectively, often none at all, sometimes even one bearing
an inverse relation to the result, and that the most decisive losses on the side of the vanquished only
commence with the retreat, that is, those which the conqueror does not share with him. The weak remains of
battalions already in disorder are cut down by cavalry, exhausted men strew the ground, disabled guns and
broken caissons are abandoned, others in the bad state of the roads cannot be removed quickly enough, and
are captured by the enemy's troops, during the night numbers lose their way, and fall defenceless into the
enemy's hands, and thus the victory mostly gains bodily substance after it is already decided. Here would be a
paradox, if it did not solve itself in the following manner.
The loss in physical force is not the only one which the two sides suffer in the course of the combat; the
moral forces also are shaken, broken, and go to ruin. It is not only the loss in men, horses and guns, but in
order, courage, confidence, cohesion and plan, which come into consideration when it is a question whether
the fight can be still continued or not. It is principally the moral forces which decide here, and in all cases in
which the conqueror has lost as heavily as the conquered, it is these alone.
The comparative relation of the physical losses is difficult to estimate in a battle, but not so the relation of the
moral ones. Two things principally make it known. The one is the loss of the ground on which the fight has
taken place, the other the superiority of the enemy's. The more our reserves have diminished as compared
with those of the enemy, the more force we have used to maintain the equilibrium; in this at once, an evident
proof of the moral superiority of the enemy is given which seldom fails to stir up in the soul of the
Commander a certain bitterness of feeling, and a sort of contempt for his own troops. But the principal thing
is, that men who have been engaged for a long continuance of time are more or less like burntout cinders;
their ammunition is consumed; they have melted away to a certain extent; physical and moral energies are
exhausted, perhaps their courage is broken as well. Such a force, irrespective of the diminution in its number,
if viewed as an organic whole, is very different from what it was before the combat; and thus it is that the loss
of moral force may be measured by the reserves that have been used as if it were on a footrule.
Lost ground and want of fresh reserves, are, therefore, usually the principal causes which determine a retreat;
but at the same time we by no means exclude or desire to throw in the shade other reasons, which may lie in
the interdependence of parts of the Army, in the general plan,
Every combat is therefore the bloody and destructive measuring of the strength of forces, physical and moral;
whoever at the close has the greatest amount of both left is the conqueror.
In the combat the loss of moral force is the chief cause of the decision; after that is given, this loss continues
to increase until it reaches its culminatingpoint at the close of the whole act. This then is the opportunity the
victor should seize to reap his harvest by the utmost possible restrictions of his enemy's forces, the real object
of engaging in the combat. On the beaten side, the loss of all order and control often makes the prolongation
of resistance by individual units, by the further punishment they are certain to suffer, more injurious than
useful to the whole. The spirit of the mass is broken; the original excitement about losing or winning, through
which danger was forgotten, is spent, and to the majority danger now appears no longer an appeal to their
courage, but rather the endurance of a cruel punishment. Thus the instrument in the first moment of the
enemy's victory is weakened and blunted, and therefore no longer fit to repay danger by danger.
This period, however, passes; the moral forces of the conquered will recover by degrees, order will be
restored, courage will revive, and in the majority of cases there remains only a small part of the superiority
obtained, often none at all. In some cases, even, although rarely, the spirit of revenge and intensified hostility
may bring about an opposite result. On the other hand, whatever is gained in killed, wounded, prisoners, and
On War
On War 122
Page No 125
guns captured can never disappear from the account.
The losses in a battle consist more in killed and wounded; those after the battle, more in artillery taken and
prisoners. The first the conqueror shares with the conquered, more or less, but the second not; and for that
reason they usually only take place on one side of the conflict, at least, they are considerably in excess on one
side.
Artillery and prisoners are therefore at all times regarded as the true trophies of victory, as well as its
measure, because through these things its extent is declared beyond a doubt. Even the degree of moral
superiority may be better judged of by them than by any other relation, especially if the number of killed and
wounded is compared therewith; and here arises a new power increasing the moral effects.
We have said that the moral forces, beaten to the ground in the battle and in the immediately succeeding
movements, recover themselves gradually, and often bear no traces of injury; this is the case with small
divisions of the whole, less frequently with large divisions; it may, however, also be the case with the main
Army, but seldom or never in the State or Government to which the Army belongs. These estimate the
situation more impartially, and from a more elevated point of view, and recognise in the number of trophies
taken by the enemy, and their relation to the number of killed and wounded, only too easily and well, the
measure of their own weakness and inefficiency.
In point of fact, the lost balance of moral power must not be treated lightly because it has no absolute value,
and because it does not of necessity appear in all cases in the amount of the results at the final close; it may
become of such excessive weight as to bring down everything with an irresistible force. On that account it
may often become a great aim of the operations of which we shall speak elsewhere. Here we have still to
examine some of its fundamental relations.
The moral effect of a victory increases, not merely in proportion to the extent of the forces engaged, but in a
progressive ratiothat is to say, not only in extent, but also in its intensity. In a beaten detachment order is
easily restored. As a single frozen limb is easily revived by the rest of the body, so the courage of a defeated
detachment is easily raised again by the courage of the rest of the Army as soon as it rejoins it. If, therefore,
the effects of a small victory are not completely done away with, still they are partly lost to the enemy. This is
not the case if the Army itself sustains a great defeat; then one with the other fall together. A great fire attains
quite a different heat from several small ones.
Another relation which determines the moral value of a victory is the numerical relation of the forces which
have been in conflict with each other. To beat many with few is not only a double success, but shows also a
greater, especially a more general superiority, which the conquered must always be fearful of encountering
again. At the same time this influence is in reality hardly observable in such a case. In the moment of real
action, the notions of the actual strength of the enemy are generally so uncertain, the estimate of our own
commonly so incorrect, that the party superior in numbers either does not admit the disproportion, or is very
far from admitting the full truth, owing to which, he evades almost entirely the moral disadvantages which
would spring from it. It is only hereafter in history that the truth, long suppressed through ignorance, vanity,
or a wise discretion, makes its appearance, and then it certainly casts a lustre on the Army and its Leader, but
it can then do nothing more by its moral influence for events long past.
If prisoners and captured guns are those things by which the victory principally gains substance, its true
crystallisations, then the plan of the battle should have those things specially in view; the destruction of the
enemy by death and wounds appears here merely as a means to an end.
How far this may influence the dispositions in the battle is not an affair of Strategy, but the decision to fight
the battle is in intimate connection with it, as is shown by the direction given to our forces, and their general
On War
On War 123
Page No 126
grouping, whether we threaten the enemy's flank or rear, or he threatens ours. On this point, the number of
prisoners and captured guns depends very much, and it is a point which, in many cases, tactics alone cannot
satisfy, particularly if the strategic relations are too much in opposition to it.
The risk of having to fight on two sides, and the still more dangerous position of having no line of retreat left
open, paralyse the movements and the power of resistance; further, in case of defeat, they increase the loss,
often raising it to its extreme point, that is, to destruction. Therefore, the rear being endangered makes defeat
more probable, and, at the same time, more decisive.
From this arises, in the whole conduct of the War,especially in great and small combats, a perfect instinct to
secure our own line of retreat and to seize that of the enemy; this follows from the conception of victory,
which, as we have seen, is something beyond mere slaughter.
In this effort we see, therefore, the first immediate purpose in the combat, and one which is quite universal.
No combat is imaginable in which this effort, either in its double or single form, does not go hand in hand
with the plain and simple stroke of force. Even the smallest troop will not throw itself upon its enemy without
thinking of its line of retreat, and, in most cases, it will have an eye upon that of the enemy also.
We should have to digress to show how often this instinct is prevented from going the direct road, how often
it must yield to the difficulties arising from more important considerations: we shall, therefore, rest contented
with affirming it to be a general natural law of the combat.
It is, therefore, active; presses everywhere with its natural weight, and so becomes the pivot on which almost
all tactical and strategic manoeuvres turn.
If we now take a look at the conception of victory as a whole, we find in it three elements:
1. The greater loss of the enemy in physical power.
2. In moral power.
3. His open avowal of this by the relinquishment of his intentions.
The returns made up on each side of losses in killed and wounded, are never exact, seldom truthful, and in
most cases, full of intentional misrepresentations. Even the statement of the number of trophies is seldom to
be quite depended on; consequently, when it is not considerable it may also cast a doubt even on the reality of
the victory. Of the loss in moral forces there is no reliable measure, except in the trophies: therefore, in many
cases, the giving up the contest is the only real evidence of the victory. It is, therefore, to be regarded as a
confession of inferiorityas the lowering of the flag, by which, in this particular instance, right and
superiority are conceded to the enemy, and this degree of humiliation and disgrace, which, however, must be
distinguished from all the other moral consequences of the loss of equilibrium, is an essential part of the
victory. It is this part alone which acts upon the public opinion outside the Army, upon the people and the
Government in both belligerent States, and upon all others in any way concerned.
But renouncement of the general object is not quite identical with quitting the field of battle, even when the
battle has been very obstinate and long kept up; no one says of advanced posts, when they retire after an
obstinate combat, that they have given up their object; even in combats aimed at the destruction of the
enemy's Army, the retreat from the battlefield is not always to be regarded as a relinquishment of this aim, as
for instance, in retreats planned beforehand, in which the ground is disputed foot by foot; all this belongs to
that part of our subject where we shall speak of the separate object of the combat; here we only wish to draw
attention to the fact that in most cases the giving up of the object is very difficult to distinguish from the
On War
On War 124
Page No 127
retirement from the battlefield, and that the impression produced by the latter, both in and out of the Army, is
not to be treated lightly.
For Generals and Armies whose reputation is not made, this is in itself one of the difficulties in many
operations, justified by circumstances when a succession of combats, each ending in retreat, may appear as a
succession of defeats, without being so in reality, and when that appearance may exercise a very depressing
influence. It is impossible for the retreating General by making known his real intentions to prevent the moral
effect spreading to the public and his troops, for to do that with effect he must disclose his plans completely,
which of course would run counter to his principal interests to too great a degree.
In order to draw attention to the special importance of this conception of victory we shall only refer to the
battle of Soor,[*] the trophies from which were not important (a few thousand prisoners and twenty guns),
and where Frederick proclaimed his victory by remaining for five days after on the field of battle, although
his retreat into Silesia had been previously determined on, and was a measure natural to his whole situation.
According to his own account, he thought he would hasten a peace by the moral effect of his victory. Now
although a couple of other successes were likewise required, namely, the battle at Katholisch Hennersdorf, in
Lusatia, and the battle of Kesseldorf, before this peace took place, still we cannot say that the moral effect of
the battle of Soor was nil.
[*] Soor, or Sohr, Sept. 30, 1745; Hennersdorf, Nov. 23, 1745; Kealteldorf, Dec. 15, 1745, all in the Second
Silesian War.
If it is chiefly the moral force which is shaken by defeat, and if the number of trophies reaped by the enemy
mounts up to an unusual height, then the lost combat becomes a rout, but this is not the necessary
consequence of every victory. A rout only sets in when the moral force of the defeated is very severely
shaken then there often ensues a complete incapability of further resistance, and the whole action consists of
giving way, that is of flight.
Jena and Belle Alliance were routs, but not so Borodino.
Although without pedantry we can here give no single line of separation, because the difference between the
things is one of degrees, yet still the retention of the conception is essential as a central point to give clearness
to our theoretical ideas and it is a want in our terminology that for a victory over the enemy tantamount to a
rout, and a conquest of the enemy only tantamount to a simple victory, there is only one and the same word to
use.
CHAPTER V. ON THE SIGNIFICATION OF THE COMBAT
HAVING in the preceding chapter examined the combat in its absolute form, as the miniature picture of the
whole War, we now turn to the relations which it bears to the other parts of the great whole. First we inquire
what is more precisely the signification of a combat.
As War is nothing else but a mutual process of destruction, then the most natural answer in conception, and
perhaps also in reality, appears to be that all the powers of each party unite in one great volume and all results
in one great shock of these masses. There is certainly much truth in this idea, and it seems to be very
advisable that we should adhere to it and should on that account look upon small combats at first only as
necessary loss, like the shavings from a carpenter's plane. Still, however, the thing cannot be settled so easily.
On War
On War 125
Page No 128
That a multiplication of combats should arise from a fractioning of forces is a matter of course, and the more
immediate objects of separate combats will therefore come before us in the subject of a fractioning of forces;
but these objects, and together with them, the whole mass of combats may in a general way be brought under
certain classes, and the knowledge of these classes will contribute to make our observations more intelligible.
Destruction of the enemy's military forces is in reality the object of all combats; but other objects may be
joined thereto, and these other objects may be at the same time predominant; we must therefore draw a
distinction between those in which the destruction of the enemy's forces is the principal object, and those in
which it is more the means. The destruction of the enemy's force, the possession of a place or the possession
of some object may be the general motive for a combat, and it may be either one of these alone or several
together, in which case however usually one is the principal motive. Now the two principal forms of War, the
offensive and defensive, of which we shall shortly speak, do not modify the first of these motives, but they
certainly do modify the other two, and therefore if we arrange them in a scheme they would appear thus:
OFFENSIVE. DEFENSIVE. 1. Destruction of enemy's 1. Destruction of enemy's force. force. 2. Conquest of
a place. 2. Defence of a place. 3. Conquest of some object. 3. Defence of some object.
These motives, however, do not seem to embrace completely the whole of the subject, if we recollect that
there are reconnaissances and demonstrations, in which plainly none of these three points is the object of the
combat. In reality we must, therefore, on this account be allowed a fourth class. Strictly speaking, in
reconnaissances in which we wish the enemy to show himself, in alarms by which we wish to wear him out,
in demonstrations by which we wish to prevent his leaving some point or to draw him off to another, the
objects are all such as can OF THE THREE OBJECTS SPECIFIED IN THE TABLE, usually of the second;
for the enemy whose aim is to reconnoitre must draw up his force as if he really intended to attack and defeat
us, or drive us off, But this pretended object is not the real one, and our present question is only as to the
latter; therefore, we must to the above three objects of the offensive further add a fourth, which is to lead the
enemy to make a false conclusion. That offensive means are conceivable in connection with this object, lies
in the nature of the thing.
On the other hand we must observe that the defence of a place may be of two kinds, either absolute, if as a
general question the point is not to be given up, or relative if it is only required for a certain time. The latter
happens perpetually in the combats of advanced posts and rear guards.
That the nature of these different intentions of a combat must have an essential influence on the dispositions
which are its preliminaries, is a thing clear in itself. We act differently if our object is merely to drive an
enemy's post out of its place from what we should if our object was to beat him completely; differently, if we
mean to defend a place to the last extremity from what we should do if our design is only to detain the enemy
for a certain time. In the first case we trouble ourselves little about the line of retreat, in the latter it is the
principal point,
But these reflections belong properly to tactics, and are only introduced here by way of example for the sake
of greater clearness. What Strategy has to say on the different objects of the combat will appear in the
chapters which touch upon these objects. Here we have only a few general observations to make, first, that
the importance of the object decreases nearly in the order as they stand above, therefore, that the first of these
objects must always predominate in the great battle; lastly, that the two last in a defensive battle are in reality
such as yield no fruit, they are, that is to say, purely negative, and can, therefore, only be serviceable,
indirectly, by facilitating something else which is positive. IT IS, THEREFORE, A BAD SIGN OF THE
STRATEGIC SITUATION IF BATTLES OF THIS KIND BECOME TOO FREQUENT.
On War
On War 126
Page No 129
CHAPTER VI. DURATION OF THE COMBAT
IF we consider the combat no longer in itself but in relation to the other forces of War, then its duration
acquires a special importance.
This duration is to be regarded to a certain extent as a second subordinate success. For the conqueror the
combat can never be finished too quickly, for the vanquished it can never last too long. A speedy victory
indicates a higher power of victory, a tardy decision is, on the side of the defeated, some compensation for
the loss.
This is in general true, but it acquires a practical importance in its application to those combats, the object of
which is a relative defence.
Here the whole success often lies in the mere duration. This is the reason why we have included it amongst
the strategic elements.
The duration of a combat is necessarily bound up with its essential relations. These relations are, absolute
magnitude of force, relation of force and of the different arms mutually, and nature of the country. Twenty
thousand men do not wear themselves out upon one another as quickly as two thousand: we cannot resist an
enemy double or three times our strength as long as one of the same strength; a cavalry combat is decided
sooner than an infantry combat; and a combat between infantry only, quicker than if there is artillery[*] as
well; in hills and forests we cannot advance as quickly as on a level country; all this is clear enough.
[*] The increase in the relative range of artillery and the introduction of shrapnel has altogether modified this
conclusion.
From this it follows, therefore, that strength, relation of the three arms, and position, must be considered if
the combat is to fulfil an object by its duration; but to set up this rule was of less importance to us in our
present considerations than to connect with it at once the chief results which experience gives us on the
subject.
Even the resistance of an ordinary Division of 8000 to 10,000 men of all arms even opposed to an enemy
considerably superior in numbers, will last several hours, if the advantages of country are not too
preponderating, and if the enemy is only a little, or not at all, superior in numbers, the combat will last half a
day. A Corps of three or four Divisions will prolong it to double the time; an Army of 80,000 or 100,000 to
three or four times. Therefore the masses may be left to themselves for that length of time, and no separate
combat takes place if within that time other forces can be brought up, whose cooperation mingles then at
once into one stream with the results of the combat which has taken place.
These calculations are the result of experience; but it is important to us at the same time to characterise more
particularly the moment of the decision, and consequently the termination.
CHAPTER VII. DECISION OF THE COMBAT
No battle is decided in a single moment, although in every battle there arise moments of crisis, on which the
result depends. The loss of a battle is, therefore, a gradual falling of the scale. But there is in every combat a
point of time
On War
On War 127
Page No 130
[*] Under the then existing conditions of armament understood. This point is of supreme importance, as
practically the whole conduct of a great battle depends on a correct solution of this questionviz., How long
can a given command prolong its resistance? If this is incorrectly answered in practicethe whole
manoeuvre depending on it may collapsee.g., Kouroupatkin at LiaoYang, September 1904.
when it may be regarded as decided, in such a way that the renewal of the fight would be a new battle, not a
continuation of the old one. To have a clear notion on this point of time, is very important, in order to be able
to decide whether, with the prompt assistance of reinforcements, the combat can again be resumed with
advantage.
Often in combats which are beyond restoration new forces are sacrificed in vain; often through neglect the
decision has not been seized when it might easily have been secured. Here are two examples, which could not
be more to the point:
When the Prince of Hohenlohe, in 1806, at Jena,[*] with 35,000 men opposed to from 60,000 to 70,000,
under Buonaparte, had accepted battle, and lost itbut lost it in such a way that the 35,000 might be
regarded as dissolvedGeneral Ruchel undertook to renew the fight with about 12,000; the consequence
was that in a moment his force was scattered in like manner.
[*] October 14, 1806.
On the other hand, on the same day at Auerstadt, the Prussians maintained a combat with 25,000, against
Davoust, who had 28,000, until midday, without success, it is true, but still without the force being reduced
to a state of dissolution without even greater loss than the enemy, who was very deficient in cavalry;but
they neglected to use the reserve of 18,000, under General Kalkreuth, to restore the battle which, under these
circumstances, it would have been impossible to lose.
Each combat is a whole in which the partial combats combine themselves into one total result. In this total
result lies the decision of the combat. This success need not be exactly a victory such as we have denoted in
the sixth chapter, for often the preparations for that have not been made, often there is no opportunity if the
enemy gives way too soon, and in most cases the decision, even when the resistance has been obstinate, takes
place before such a degree of success is attained as would completely satisfy the idea of a victory.
We therefore ask, Which is commonly the moment of the decision, that is to say, that moment when a fresh,
effective, of course not disproportionate, force, can no longer turn a disadvantageous battle?
If we pass over false attacks, which in accordance with their nature are properly without decision, then
1. If the possession of a movable object was the object of the combat, the loss of the same is always the
decision.
2. If the possession of ground was the object of the combat, then the decision generally lies in its loss. Still
not always, only if this ground is of peculiar strength, ground which is easy to pass over, however important
it may be in other respects, can be retaken without much danger.
3. But in all other cases, when these two circumstances have not already decided the combat, therefore,
particularly in case the destruction of the enemy's force is the principal object, the decision is reached at that
moment when the conqueror ceases to feel himself in a state of disintegration, that is, of unserviceableness to
a certain extent, when therefore, there is no further advantage in using the successive efforts spoken of in the
twelfth chapter of the third book. On this ground we have given the strategic unity of the battle its place here.
On War
On War 128
Page No 131
A battle, therefore, in which the assailant has not lost his condition of order and perfect efficiency at all, or, at
least, only in a small part of his force, whilst the opposing forces are, more or less, disorganised throughout,
is also not to be retrieved; and just as little if the enemy has recovered his efficiency.
The smaller, therefore, that part of a force is which has really been engaged, the greater that portion which as
reserve has contributed to the result only by its presence. so much the less will any new force of the enemy
wrest again the victory from our hands, and that Commander who carries out to the furthest with his Army
the principle of conducting the combat with the greatest economy of forces, and making the most of the moral
effect of strong reserves, goes the surest way to victory. We must allow that the French, in modern times,
especially when led by Buonaparte, have shown a thorough mastery in this.
Further, the moment when the crisisstage of the combat ceases with the conqueror, and his original state of
order is restored, takes place sooner the smaller the unit he controls. A picket of cavalry pursuing an enemy at
full gallop will in a few minutes resume its proper order, and the crisis ceases. A whole regiment of cavalry
requires a longer time. It lasts still longer with infantry, if extended in single lines of skirmishers, and longer
again with Divisions of all arms, when it happens by chance that one part has taken one direction and another
part another direction, and the combat has therefore caused a loss of the order of formation, which usually
becomes still worse from no part knowing exactly where the other is. Thus, therefore, the point of time when
the conqueror has collected the instruments he has been using, and which are mixed up and partly out of
order, the moment when he has in some measure rearranged them and put them in their proper places, and
thus brought the battleworkshop into a little order, this moment, we say, is always later, the greater the total
force.
Again, this moment comes later if night overtakes the conqueror in the crisis, and, lastly, it comes later still if
the country is broken and thickly wooded. But with regard to these two points, we must observe that night is
also a great means of protection, and it is only seldom that circumstances favour the expectation of a
successful result from a night attack, as on March 10, 1814, at Laon,[*] where York against Marmont gives
us an example completely in place here. In the same way a wooded and broken country will afford protection
against a reaction to those who are engaged in the long crisis of victory. Both, therefore, the night as well as
the wooded and broken country are obstacles which make the renewal of the same battle more difficult
instead of facilitating it.
[*] The celebrated charge at night upon Marmont's Corps.
Hitherto, we have considered assistance arriving for the losing side as a mere increase of force, therefore, as a
reinforcement coming up directly from the rear, which is the most usual case. But the case is quite different if
these fresh forces come upon the enemy in flank or rear.
On the effect of flank or rear attacks so far as they belong to Strategy, we shall speak in another place: such a
one as we have here in view, intended for the restoration of the combat, belongs chiefly to tactics, and is only
mentioned because we are here speaking of tactical results, our ideas, therefore, must trench upon the
province of tactics.
By directing a force against the enemy's flank and rear its efficacy may be much intensified; but this is so far
from being a necessary result always that the efficacy may, on the other hand, be just as much weakened. The
circumstances under which the combat has taken place decide upon this part of the plan as well as upon every
other, without our being able to enter thereupon here. But, at the same time, there are in it two things of
importance for our subject: first, FLANK AND REAR ATTACKS HAVE, AS A RULE, A MORE
FAVOURABLE EFFECT ON THE CONSEQUENCES OF THE DECISION THAN UPON THE
DECISION ITSELF. Now as concerns the retrieving a battle, the first thing to be arrived at above all is a
favourable decision and not magnitude of success. In this view one would therefore think that a force which
On War
On War 129
Page No 132
comes to reestablish our combat is of less assistance if it falls upon the enemy in flank and rear, therefore
separated from us, than if it joins itself to us directly; certainly, cases are not wanting where it is so, but we
must say that the majority are on the other side, and they are so on account of the second point which is here
important to us.
This second point IS THE MORAL EFFECT OF THE SURPRISE, WHICH, AS A RULE, A
REINFORCEMENT COMING UP TO REESTABLISH A COMBAT HAS GENERALLY IN ITS
FAVOUR. Now the effect of a surprise is always heightened if it takes place in the flank or rear, and an
enemy completely engaged in the crisis of victory in his extended and scattered order, is less in a state to
counteract it. Who does not feel that an attack in flank or rear, which at the commencement of the battle,
when the forces are concentrated and prepared for such an event would be of little importance, gains quite
another weight in the last moment of the combat.
We must, therefore, at once admit that in most cases a reinforcement coming up on the flank or rear of the
enemy will be more efficacious, will be like the same weight at the end of a longer lever, and therefore that
under these circumstances, we may undertake to restore the battle with the same force which employed in a
direct attack would be quite insufficient. Here results almost defy calculation, because the moral forces gain
completely the ascendency. This is therefore the right field for boldness and daring.
The eye must, therefore, be directed on all these objects, all these moments of cooperating forces must be
taken into consideration, when we have to decide in doubtful cases whether or not it is still possible to restore
a combat which has taken an unfavourable turn.
If the combat is to be regarded as not yet ended, then the new contest which is opened by the arrival of
assistance fuses into the former; therefore they flow together into one common result, and the first
disadvantage vanishes completely out of the calculation. But this is not the case if the combat was already
decided; then there are two results separate from each other. Now if the assistance which arrives is only of a
relative strength, that is, if it is not in itself alone a match for the enemy, then a favourable result is hardly to
be expected from this second combat: but if it is so strong that it can undertake the second combat without
regard to the first, then it may be able by a favourable issue to compensate or even overbalance the first
combat, but never to make it disappear altogether from the account.
At the battle of Kunersdorf,[*] Frederick the Great at the first onset carried the left of the Russian position,
and took seventy pieces of artillery; at the end of the battle both were lost again, and the whole result of the
first combat was wiped out of the account. Had it been possible to stop at the first success, and to put off the
second part of the battle to the coming day, then, even if the King had lost it, the advantages of the first would
always have been a set off to the second.
[*] August 12, 1759.
But when a battle proceeding disadvantageously is arrested and turned before its conclusion, its minus result
on our side not only disappears from the account, but also becomes the foundation of a greater victory. If, for
instance, we picture to ourselves exactly the tactical course of the battle, we may easily see that until it is
finally concluded all successes in partial combats are only decisions in suspense, which by the capital
decision may not only be destroyed, but changed into the opposite. The more our forces have suffered, the
more the enemy will have expended on his side; the greater, therefore, will be the crisis for the enemy, and
the more the superiority of our fresh troops will tell. If now the total result turns in our favour, if we wrest
from the enemy the field of battle and recover all the trophies again, then all the forces which he has
sacrificed in obtaining them become sheer gain for us, and our former defeat becomes a steppingstone to a
greater triumph. The most brilliant feats which with victory the enemy would have so highly prized that the
loss of forces which they cost would have been disregarded, leave nothing now behind but regret at the
On War
On War 130
Page No 133
sacrifice entailed. Such is the alteration which the magic of victory and the curse of defeat produces in the
specific weight of the same elements.
Therefore, even if we are decidedly superior in strength, and are able to repay the enemy his victory by a
greater still, it is always better to forestall the conclusion of a disadvantageous combat, if it is of
proportionate importance, so as to turn its course rather than to deliver a second battle.
FieldMarshal Daun attempted in the year 1760 to come to the assistance of General Laudon at Leignitz,
whilst the battle lasted; but when he failed, he did not attack the King next day, although he did not want for
means to do so.
For these reasons serious combats of advance guards which precede a battle are to be looked upon only as
necessary evils, and when not necessary they are to be avoided.[*]
[*] This, however, was not Napoleon's view. A vigorous attack of his advance guard he held to be necessary
always, to fix the enemy's attention and "paralyse his independent willpower." It was the failure to make
this point which, in August 1870, led von Moltke repeatedly into the very jaws of defeat, from which only the
lethargy of Bazaine on the one hand and the initiative of his subordinates, notably of von Alvensleben,
rescued him. This is the essence of the new Strategic Doctrine of the French General Staff. See the works of
Bonnal, Foch,
We have still another conclusion to examine.
If on a regular pitched battle, the decision has gone against one, this does not constitute a motive for
determining on a new one. The determination for this new one must proceed from other relations. This
conclusion, however, is opposed by a moral force, which we must take into account: it is the feeling of rage
and revenge. From the oldest FieldMarshal to the youngest drummerboy this feeling is general, and,
therefore, troops are never in better spirits for fighting than when they have to wipe out a stain. This is,
however, only on the supposition that the beaten portion is not too great in proportion to the whole, because
otherwise the above feeling is lost in that of powerlessness.
There is therefore a very natural tendency to use this moral force to repair the disaster on the spot, and on that
account chiefly to seek another battle if other circumstances permit. It then lies in the nature of the case that
this second battle must be an offensive one.
In the catalogue of battles of secondrate importance there are many examples to be found of such retaliatory
battles; but great battles have generally too many other determining causes to be brought on by this weaker
motive.
Such a feeling must undoubtedly have led the noble Bluecher with his third Corps to the field of battle on
February 14, 1814, when the other two had been beaten three days before at Montmirail. Had he known that
he would have come upon Buonaparte in person, then, naturally, preponderating reasons would have
determined him to put off his revenge to another day: but he hoped to revenge himself on Marmont, and
instead of gaining the reward of his desire for honourable satisfaction, he suffered the penalty of his
erroneous calculation.
On the duration of the combat and the moment of its decision depend the distances from each other at which
those masses should be placed which are intended to fight IN CONJUNCTION WITH each other. This
disposition would be a tactical arrangement in so far as it relates to one and the same battle; it can, however,
only be regarded as such, provided the position of the troops is so compact that two separate combats cannot
be imagined, and consequently that the space which the whole occupies can be regarded strategically as a
On War
On War 131
Page No 134
mere point. But in War, cases frequently occur where even those forces intended to fight IN UNISON must
be so far separated from each other that while their union for one common combat certainly remains the
principal object, still the occurrence of separate combats remains possible. Such a disposition is therefore
strategic.
Dispositions of this kind are: marches in separate masses and columns, the formation of advance guards, and
flanking columns, also the grouping of reserves intended to serve as supports for more than one strategic
point; the concentration of several Corps from widely extended cantonments, We can see that the necessity
for these arrangements may constantly arise, and may consider them something like the small change in the
strategic economy, whilst the capital battles, and all that rank with them are the gold and silver pieces.
CHAPTER VIII. MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING AS TO A BATTLE
NO battle can take place unless by mutual consent; and in this idea, which constitutes the whole basis of a
duel, is the root of a certain phraseology used by historical writers, which leads to many indefinite and false
conceptions.
According to the view of the writers to whom we refer, it has frequently happened that one Commander has
offered battle to the other, and the latter has not accepted it.
But the battle is a very modified duel, and its foundation is not merely in the mutual wish to fight, that is in
consent, but in the objects which are bound up with the battle: these belong always to a greater whole, and
that so much the more, as even the whole war considered as a "combatunit" has political objects and
conditions which belong to a higher standpoint. The mere desire to conquer each other therefore falls into
quite a subordinate relation, or rather it ceases completely to be anything of itself, and only becomes the
nerve which conveys the impulse of action from the higher will.
Amongst the ancients, and then again during the early period of standing Armies, the expression that we had
offered battle to the enemy in vain, had more sense in it than it has now. By the ancients everything was
constituted with a view to measuring each other's strength in the open field free from anything in the nature
of a hindrance,[*] and the whole Art of War consisted in the organisation, and formation of the Army, that is
in the order of battle.
[*] Note the custom of sending formal challenges, fix time and place for action, and "enhazelug" the
battlefield in AngloSaxon times.ED,
Now as their Armies regularly entrenched themselves in their camps, therefore the position in a camp was
regarded as something unassailable, and a battle did not become possible until the enemy left his camp, and
placed himself in a practicable country, as it were entered the lists.
If therefore we hear about Hannibal having offered battle to Fabius in vain, that tells us nothing more as
regards the latter than that a battle was not part of his plan, and in itself neither proves the physical nor moral
superiority of Hannibal; but with respect to him the expression is still correct enough in the sense that
Hannibal really wished a battle.
In the early period of modern Armies, the relations were similar in great combats and battles. That is to say,
great masses were brought into action, and managed throughout it by means of an order of battle, which like a
great helpless whole required a more or less level plain and was neither suited to attack, nor yet to defence in
On War
On War 132
Page No 135
a broken, close or even mountainous country. The defender therefore had here also to some extent the means
of avoiding battle. These relations although gradually becoming modified, continued until the first Silesian
War, and it was not until the Seven Years' War that attacksan enemy posted in a difficult country gradually
became feasible, and of ordinary occurrence: ground did not certainly cease to be a principle of strength to
those making use of its aid, but it was no longer a charmed circle, which shut out the natural forces of War.
During the past thirty years War has perfected itself much more in this respect, and there is no longer
anything which stands in the way of a General who is in earnest about a decision by means of battle; he can
seek out his enemy, and attack him: if he does not do so he cannot take credit for having wished to fight, and
the expression he offered a battle which his opponent did not accept, therefore now means nothing more than
that he did not find circumstances advantageous enough for a battle, an admission which the above
expression does not suit, but which it only strives to throw a veil over.
It is true the defensive side can no longer refuse a battle, yet he may still avoid it by giving up his position,
and the role with which that position was connected: this is however half a victory for the offensive side, and
an acknowledgment of his superiority for the present.
This idea in connection with the cartel of defiance can therefore no longer be made use of in order by such
rhodomontade to qualify the inaction of him whose part it is to advance, that is, the offensive. The defender
who as long as he does not give way, must have the credit of willing the battle, may certainly say, he has
offered it if he is not attacked, if that is not understood of itself.
But on the other hand, he who now wishes to, and can retreat cannot easily be forced to give battle. Now as
the advantages to the aggressor from this retreat are often not sufficient, and a substantial victory is a matter
of urgent necessity for him, in that way the few means which there are to compel such an opponent also to
give battle are often sought for and applied with particular skill.
The principal means for this arefirst SURROUNDING the enemy so as to make his retreat impossible, or
at least so difficult that it is better for him to accept battle; and, secondly, SURPRISING him. This last way,
for which there was a motive formerly in the extreme difficulty of all movements, has become in modern
times very inefficacious.
From the pliability and manoeuvring capabilities of troops in the present day, one does not hesitate to
commence a retreat even in sight of the enemy, and only some special obstacles in the nature of the country
can cause serious difficulties in the operation.
As an example of this kind the battle of Neresheim may be given, fought by the Archduke Charles with
Moreau in the Rauhe Alp, August 11, 1796, merely with a view to facilitate his retreat, although we freely
confess we have never been able quite to understand the argument of the renowned general and author
himself in this case.
The battle of Rosbach[*] is another example, if we suppose the commander of the allied army had not really
the intention of attacking Frederick the Great.
[*] November 5, 1757.
Of the battle of Soor,[*] the King himself says that it was only fought because a retreat in the presence of the
enemy appeared to him a critical operation; at the same time the King has also given other reasons for the
battle.
[*] Or Sohr, September 30, 1745.
On War
On War 133
Page No 136
On the whole, regular night surprises excepted, such cases will always be of rare occurrence, and those in
which an enemy is compelled to fight by being practically surrounded, will happen mostly to single corps
only, like Mortier's at Durrenstein 1809, and Vandamme at Kulm, 1813.
CHAPTER IX. THE BATTLE[*]
[*] Clausewitz still uses the word "die Hauptschlacht" but modern usage employs only the word "die
Schlacht" to designate the decisive act of a whole campaignencounters arising from the collision or troops
marching towards the strategic culmination of each portion or the campaign are spoken of either as "Treffen,"
i.e., "engagements" or "Gefecht," i.e., "combat" or "action." Thus technically, Gravelotte was a "Schlacht,"
i.e., "battle," but Spicheren, Woerth, Borny, even Vionville were only "Treffen."
ITS DECISION
WHAT is a battle? A conflict of the main body, but not an unimportant one about a secondary object, not a
mere attempt which is given up when we see betimes that our object is hardly within our reach: it is a conflict
waged with all our forces for the attainment of a decisive victory.
Minor objects may also be mixed up with the principal object, and it will take many different tones of colour
from the circumstances out of which it originates, for a battle belongs also to a greater whole of which it is
only a part, but because the essence of War is conflict, and the battle is the conflict of the main Armies, it is
always to be regarded as the real centre of gravity of the War, and therefore its distinguishing character is,
that unlike all other encounters, it is arranged for, and undertaken with the sole purpose of obtaining a
decisive victory.
This has an influence on the MANNER OF ITS DECISION, on the EFFECT OF THE VICTORY
CONTAINED IN IT, and determines THE VALUE WHICH THEORY IS TO ASSIGN TO IT AS A
MEANS TO AN END.
On that account we make it the subject of our special consideration, and at this stage before we enter upon the
special ends which may be bound up with it, but which do not essentially alter its character if it really
deserves to be termed a battle.
If a battle takes place principally on its own account, the elements of its decision must be contained in itself;
in other words, victory must be striven for as long as a possibility or hope remains. It must not, therefore, be
given up on account of secondary circumstances, but only and alone in the event of the forces appearing
completely insufficient.
Now how is that precise moment to be described?
If a certain artificial formation and cohesion of an Army is the principal condition under which the bravery of
the troops can gain a victory, as was the case during a great part of the period of the modern Art of War,
THEN THE BREAKING UP OF THIS FORMATION is the decision. A beaten wing which is put out of
joint decides the fate of all that was connected with it. If as was the case at another time the essence of the
defence consists in an intimate alliance of the Army with the ground on which it fights and its obstacles, so
that Army and position are only one, then the CONQUEST of AN ESSENTIAL POINT in this position is the
decision. It is said the key of the position is lost, it cannot therefore be defended any further; the battle cannot
be continued. In both cases the beaten Armies are very much like the broken strings of an instrument which
On War
On War 134
Page No 137
cannot do their work.
That geometrical as well as this geographical principle which had a tendency to place an Army in a state of
crystallising tension which did not allow of the available powers being made use of up to the last man, have
at least so far lost their influence that they no longer predominate. Armies are still led into battle in a certain
order, but that order is no longer of decisive importance; obstacles of ground are also still turned to account to
strengthen a position, but they are no longer the only support.
We attempted in the second chapter of this book to take a general view of the nature of the modern battle.
According to our conception of it, the order of battle is only a disposition of the forces suitable to the
convenient use of them, and the course of the battle a mutual slow wearing away of these forces upon one
another, to see which will have soonest exhausted his adversary.
The resolution therefore to give up the fight arises, in a battle more than in any other combat, from the
relation of the fresh reserves remaining available; for only these still retain all their moral vigour, and the
cinders of the battered, knockedabout battalions, already burnt out in the destroying element, must not be
placed on a level with them; also lost ground as we have elsewhere said, is a standard of lost moral force; it
therefore comes also into account, but more as a sign of loss suffered than for the loss itself, and the number
of fresh reserves is always the chief point to be looked at by both Commanders.
In general, an action inclines in one direction from the very commencement, but in a manner little observable.
This direction is also frequently given in a very decided manner by the arrangements which have been made
previously, and then it shows a want of discernment in that General who commences battle under these
unfavourable circumstances without being aware of them. Even when this does not occur it lies in the nature
of things that the course of a battle resembles rather a slow disturbance of equilibrium which commences
soon, but as we have said almost imperceptibly at first, and then with each moment of time becomes stronger
and more visible, than an oscillating to and fro, as those who are misled by mendacious descriptions usually
suppose.
But whether it happens that the balance is for a long time little disturbed, or that even after it has been lost on
one side it rights itself again, and is then lost on the other side, it is certain at all events that in most instances
the defeated General foresees his fate long before he retreats, and that cases in which some critical event acts
with unexpected force upon the course of the whole have their existence mostly in the colouring with which
every one depicts his lost battle.
We can only here appeal to the decision of unprejudiced men of experience, who will, we are sure, assent to
what we have said, and answer for us to such of our readers as do not know War from their own experience.
To develop the necessity of this course from the nature of the thing would lead us too far into the province of
tactics, to which this branch of the subject belongs; we are here only concerned with its results.
If we say that the defeated General foresees the unfavourable result usually some time before he makes up his
mind to give up the battle, we admit that there are also instances to the contrary, because otherwise we should
maintain a proposition contradictory in itself. If at the moment of each decisive tendency of a battle it should
be considered as lost, then also no further forces should be used to give it a turn, and consequently this
decisive tendency could not precede the retreat by any length of time. Certainly there are instances of battles
which after having taken a decided turn to one side have still ended in favour of the other; but they are rare,
not usual; these exceptional cases, however, are reckoned upon by every General against whom fortune
declares itself, and he must reckon upon them as long as there remains a possibility of a turn of fortune. He
hopes by stronger efforts, by raising the remaining moral forces, by surpassing himself, or also by some
fortunate chance that the next moment will bring a change, and pursues this as far as his courage and his
judgment can agree. We shall have something more to say on this subject, but before that we must show what
On War
On War 135
Page No 138
are the signs of the scales turning.
The result of the whole combat consists in the sum total of the results of all partial combats; but these results
of separate combats are settled by different considerations.
First by the pure moral power in the mind of the leading officers. If a General of Division has seen his
battalions forced to succumb, it will have an influence on his demeanour and his reports, and these again will
have an influence on the measures of the CommanderinChief; therefore even those unsuccessful partial
combats which to all appearance are retrieved, are not lost in their results, and the impressions from them
sum themselves up in the mind of the Commander without much trouble, and even against his will.
Secondly, by the quicker melting away of our troops, which can be easily estimated in the slow and
relatively[*] little tumultuary course of our battles.
[*] Relatively, that is say to the shock of former days.
Thirdly, by lost ground.
All these things serve for the eye of the General as a compass to tell the course of the battle in which he is
embarked. If whole batteries have been lost and none of the enemy's taken; if battalions have been
overthrown by the enemy's cavalry, whilst those of the enemy everywhere present impenetrable masses; if the
line of fire from his order of battle wavers involuntarily from one point to another; if fruitless efforts have
been made to gain certain points, and the assaulting battalions each, time been scattered by welldirected
volleys of grape and case;if our artillery begins to reply feebly to that of the enemyif the battalions
under fire diminish unusually, fast, because with the wounded crowds of unwounded men go to the rear;if
single Divisions have been cut off and made prisoners through the disruption of the plan of the battle;if the
line of retreat begins to be endangered: the Commander may tell very well in which direction he is going with
his battle. The longer this direction continues, the more decided it becomes, so much the more difficult will
be the turning, so much the nearer the moment when he must give up the battle. We shall now make some
observations on this moment.
We have already said more than once that the final decision is ruled mostly by the relative number of the
fresh reserves remaining at the last; that Commander who sees his adversary is decidedly superior to him in
this respect makes up his mind to retreat. It is the characteristic of modern battles that all mischances and
losses which take place in the course of the same can be retrieved by fresh forces, because the arrangement of
the modern order of battle, and the way in which troops are brought into action, allow of their use almost
generally, and in each position. So long, therefore, as that Commander against whom the issue seems to
declare itself still retains a superiority in reserve force, he will not give up the day. But from the moment that
his reserves begin to become weaker than his enemy's, the decision may be regarded as settled, and what he
now does depends partly on special circumstances, partly on the degree of courage and perseverance which
he personally possesses, and which may degenerate into foolish obstinacy. How a Commander can attain to
the power of estimating correctly the still remaining reserves on both sides is an affair of skilful practical
genius, which does not in any way belong to this place; we keep ourselves to the result as it forms itself in his
mind. But this conclusion is still not the moment of decision properly, for a motive which only arises
gradually does not answer to that, but is only a general motive towards resolution, and the resolution itself
requires still some special immediate causes. Of these there are two chief ones which constantly recur, that is,
the danger of retreat, and the arrival of night.
If the retreat with every new step which the battle takes in its course becomes constantly in greater danger,
and if the reserves are so much diminished that they are no longer adequate to get breathing room, then there
is nothing left but to submit to fate, and by a wellconducted retreat to save what, by a longer delay ending in
On War
On War 136
Page No 139
flight and disaster, would be lost.
But night as a rule puts an end to all battles, because a night combat holds out no hope of advantage except
under particular circumstances; and as night is better suited for a retreat than the day, so, therefore, the
Commander who must look at the retreat as a thing inevitable, or as most probable, will prefer to make use of
the night for his purpose.
That there are, besides the above two usual and chief causes, yet many others also, which are less or more
individual and not to be overlooked, is a matter of course; for the more a battle tends towards a complete
upset of equilibrium the more sensible is the influence of each partial result in hastening the turn. Thus the
loss of a battery, a successful charge of a couple of regiments of cavalry, may call into life the resolution to
retreat already ripening.
As a conclusion to this subject, we must dwell for a moment on the point at which the courage of the
Commander engages in a sort of conflict with his reason.
If, on the one hand the overbearing pride of a victorious conqueror, if the inflexible will of a naturally
obstinate spirit, if the strenuous resistance of noble feelings will not yield the battlefield, where they must
leave their honour, yet on the other hand, reason counsels not to give up everything, not to risk the last upon
the game, but to retain as much over as is necessary for an orderly retreat. However highly we must esteem
courage and firmness in War, and however little prospect there is of victory to him who cannot resolve to
seek it by the exertion of all his power, still there is a point beyond which perseverance can only be termed
desperate folly, and therefore can meet with no approbation from any critic. In the most celebrated of all
battles, that of BelleAlliance, Buonaparte used his last reserve in an effort to retrieve a battle which was past
being retrieved. He spent his last farthing, and then, as a beggar, abandoned both the battlefield and his
crown.
CHAPTER X. EFFECTS OF VICTORY (continuation)
ACCORDING to the point from which our view is taken, we may feel as much astonished at the
extraordinary results of some great battles as at the want of results in others. We shall dwell for a moment on
the nature of the effect of a great victory.
Three things may easily be distinguished here: the effect upon the instrument itself, that is, upon the Generals
and their Armies; the effect upon the States interested in the War; and the particular result of these effects as
manifested in the subsequent course of the campaign.
If we only think of the trifling difference which there usually is between victor and vanquished in killed,
wounded, prisoners, and artillery lost on the field of battle itself, the consequences which are developed out
of this insignificant point seem often quite incomprehensible, and yet, usually, everything only happens quite
naturally.
We have already said in the seventh chapter that the magnitude of a victory increases not merely in the same
measure as the vanquished forces increase in number, but in a higher ratio. The moral effects resulting from
the issue of a great battle are greater on the side of the conquered than on that of the conqueror: they lead to
greater losses in physical force, which then in turn react on the moral element, and so they go on mutually
supporting and intensifying each other. On this moral effect we must therefore lay special weight. It takes an
opposite direction on the one side from that on the other; as it undermines the energies of the conquered so it
On War
On War 137
Page No 140
elevates the powers and energy of the conqueror. But its chief effect is upon the vanquished, because here it
is the direct cause of fresh losses, and besides it is homogeneous in nature with danger, with the fatigues, the
hardships, and generally with all those embarrassing circumstances by which War is surrounded, therefore
enters into league with them and increases by their help, whilst with the conqueror all these things are like
weights which give a higher swing to his courage. It is therefore found, that the vanquished sinks much
further below the original line of equilibrium than the conqueror raises himself above it; on this account, if
we speak of the effects of victory we allude more particularly to those which manifest themselves in the
army. If this effect is more powerful in an important combat than in a smaller one, so again it is much more
powerful in a great battle than in a minor one. The great battle takes place for the sake of itself, for the sake of
the victory which it is to give, and which is sought for with the utmost effort. Here on this spot, in this very
hour, to conquer the enemy is the purpose in which the plan of the War with all its threads converges, in
which all distant hopes, all dim glimmerings of the future meet, fate steps in before us to give an answer to
the bold question.This is the state of mental tension not only of the Commander but of his whole Army
down to the lowest waggondriver, no doubt in decreasing strength but also in decreasing importance.
According to the nature of the thing, a great battle has never at any time been an unprepared, unexpected,
blind routine service, but a grand act, which, partly of itself and partly from the aim of the Commander,
stands out from amongst the mass of ordinary efforts, sufficiently to raise the tension of all minds to a higher
degree. But the higher this tension with respect to the issue, the more powerful must be the effect of that
issue.
Again, the moral effect of victory in our battles is greater than it was in the earlier ones of modern military
history. If the former are as we have depicted them, a real struggle of forces to the utmost, then the sum total
of all these forces, of the physical as well as the moral, must decide more than certain special dispositions or
mere chance.
A single fault committed may be repaired next time; from good fortune and chance we can hope for more
favour on another occasion; but the sum total of moral and physical powers cannot be so quickly altered, and,
therefore, what the award of a victory has decided appears of much greater importance for all futurity. Very
probably, of all concerned in battles, whether in or out of the Army, very few have given a thought to this
difference, but the course of the battle itself impresses on the minds of all present in it such a conviction, and
the relation of this course in public documents, however much it may be coloured by twisting particular
circumstances, shows also, more or less, to the world at large that the causes were more of a general than of a
particular nature.
He who has not been present at the loss of a great battle will have difficulty in forming for himself a living or
quite true idea of it, and the abstract notions of this or that small untoward affair will never come up to the
perfect conception of a lost battle. Let us stop a moment at the picture.
The first thing which overpowers the imaginationand we may indeed say, also the understandingis the
diminution of the masses; then the loss of ground, which takes place always, more or less, and, therefore, on
the side of the assailant also, if he is not fortunate; then the rupture of the original formation, the jumbling
together of troops, the risks of retreat, which, with few exceptions may always be seen sometimes in a less
sometimes in a greater degree; next the retreat, the most part of which commences at night, or, at least, goes
on throughout the night. On this first march we must at once leave behind, a number of men completely worn
out and scattered about, often just the bravest, who have been foremost in the fight who held out the longest:
the feeling of being conquered, which only seized the superior officers on the battlefield, now spreads
through all ranks, even down to the common soldiers, aggravated by the horrible idea of being obliged to
leave in the enemy's hands so many brave comrades, who but a moment since were of such value to us in the
battle, and aggravated by a rising distrust of the chief, to whom, more or less, every subordinate attributes as
a fault the fruitless efforts he has made; and this feeling of being conquered is no ideal picture over which one
On War
On War 138
Page No 141
might become master; it is an evident truth that the enemy is superior to us; a truth of which the causes might
have been so latent before that they were not to be discovered, but which, in the issue, comes out clear and
palpable, or which was also, perhaps, before suspected, but which in the want of any certainty, we had to
oppose by the hope of chance, reliance on good fortune, Providence or a bold attitude. Now, all this has
proved insufficient, and the bitter truth meets us harsh and imperious.
All these feelings are widely different from a panic, which in an army fortified by military virtue never, and
in any other, only exceptionally, follows the loss of a battle. They must arise even in the best of Armies, and
although long habituation to War and victory together with great confidence in a Commander may modify
them a little here and there, they are never entirely wanting in the first moment. They are not the pure
consequences of lost trophies; these are usually lost at a later period, and the loss of them does not become
generally known so quickly; they will therefore not fail to appear even when the scale turns in the slowest and
most gradual manner, and they constitute that effect of a victory upon which we can always count in every
case.
We have already said that the number of trophies intensifies this effect.
It is evident that an Army in this condition, looked at as an instrument, is weakened! How can we expect that
when reduced to such a degree that, as we said before, it finds new enemies in all the ordinary difficulties of
making War, it will be able to recover by fresh efforts what has been lost! Before the battle there was a real or
assumed equilibrium between the two sides; this is lost, and, therefore, some external assistance is requisite
to restore it; every new effort without such external support can only lead to fresh losses.
Thus, therefore, the most moderate victory of the chief Army must tend to cause a constant sinking of the
scale on the opponent's side, until new external circumstances bring about a change. If these are not near, if
the conqueror is an eager opponent, who, thirsting for glory, pursues great aims, then a firstrate
Commander, and in the beaten Army a true military spirit, hardened by many campaigns are required, in
order to stop the swollen stream of prosperity from bursting all bounds, and to moderate its course by small
but reiterated acts of resistance, until the force of victory has spent itself at the goal of its career.
And now as to the effect of defeat beyond the Army, upon the Nation and Government! It is the sudden
collapse of hopes stretched to the utmost, the downfall of all selfreliance. In place of these extinct forces,
fear, with its destructive properties of expansion, rushes into the vacuum left, and completes the prostration.
It is a real shock upon the nerves, which one of the two athletes receives from the electric spark of victory.
And that effect, however different in its degrees, is never completely wanting. Instead of every one hastening
with a spirit of determination to aid in repairing the disaster, every one fears that his efforts will only be in
vain, and stops, hesitating with himself, when he should rush forward; or in despondency he lets his arm
drop, leaving everything to fate.
The consequence which this effect of victory brings forth in the course of the War itself depend in part on the
character and talent of the victorious General, but more on the circumstances from which the victory
proceeds, and to which it leads. Without boldness and an enterprising spirit on the part of the leader, the most
brilliant victory will lead to no great success, and its force exhausts itself all the sooner on circumstances, if
these offer a strong and stubborn opposition to it. How very differently from Daun, Frederick the Great would
have used the victory at Kollin; and what different consequences France, in place of Prussia, might have
given a battle of Leuthen!
The conditions which allow us to expect great results from a great victory we shall learn when we come to
the subjects with which they are connected; then it will be possible to explain the disproportion which
appears at first sight between the magnitude of a victory and its results, and which is only too readily
attributed to a want of energy on the part of the conqueror. Here, where we have to do with the great battle in
On War
On War 139
Page No 142
itself, we shall merely say that the effects now depicted never fail to attend a victory, that they mount up with
the intensive strength of the victorymount up more the more the whole strength of the Army has been
concentrated in it, the more the whole military power of the Nation is contained in that Army, and the State in
that military power.
But then the question may be asked, Can theory accept this effect of victory as absolutely necessary?must
it not rather endeavour to find out counteracting means capable of neutralising these effects? It seems quite
natural to answer this question in the affirmative; but heaven defend us from taking that wrong course of
most theories, out of which is begotten a mutually devouring Pro et Contra.
Certainly that effect is perfectly necessary, for it has its foundation in the nature of things, and it exists, even
if we find means to struggle against it; just as the motion of a cannon ball is always in the direction of the
terrestrial, although when fired from east to west part of the general velocity is destroyed by this opposite
motion.
All War supposes human weakness, and against that it is directed.
Therefore, if hereafter in another place we examine what is to be done after the loss of a great battle, if we
bring under review the resources which still remain, even in the most desperate cases, if we should express a
belief in the possibility of retrieving all, even in such a case; it must not be supposed we mean thereby that
the effects of such a defeat can by degrees be completely wiped out, for the forces and means used to repair
the disaster might have been applied to the realisation of some positive object; and this applies both to the
moral and physical forces.
Another question is, whether, through the loss of a great battle, forces are not perhaps roused into existence,
which otherwise would never have come to life. This case is certainly conceivable, and it is what has actually
occurred with many Nations. But to produce this intensified reaction is beyond the province of military art,
which can only take account of it where it might be assumed as a possibility.
If there are cases in which the fruits of a victory appear rather of a destructive nature in consequence of the
reaction of the forces which it had the effect of rousing into activitycases which certainly are very
exceptional then it must the more surely be granted, that there is a difference in the effects which one and
the same victory may produce according to the character of the people or state, which has been conquered.
CHAPTER XI. THE USE OF THE BATTLE (continued)
WHATEVER form the conduct of War may take in particular cases, and whatever we may have to admit in
the sequel as necessary respecting it: we have only to refer to the conception of War to be convinced of what
follows:
1. The destruction of the enemy's military force, is the leading principle of War, and for the whole chapter of
positive action the direct way to the object.
2. This destruction of the enemy's force, must be principally effected by means of battle.
3. Only great and general battles can produce great results.
4. The results will be greatest when combats unite themselves in one great battle.
On War
On War 140
Page No 143
5. It is only in a great battle that the GeneralinChief commands in person, and it is in the nature of things,
that he should place more confidence in himself than in his subordinates.
From these truths a double law follows, the parts of which mutually support each other; namely, that the
destruction of the enemy's military force is to be sought for principally by great battles, and their results; and
that the chief object of great battles must be the destruction of the enemy's military force.
No doubt the annihilationprinciple is to be found more or less in other meansgranted there are instances
in which through favourable circumstances in a minor combat, the destruction of the enemy's forces has been
disproportionately great (Maxen), and on the other hand in a battle, the taking or holding a single post may be
predominant in importance as an objectbut as a general rule it remains a paramount truth, that battles are
only fought with a view to the destruction of the enemy's Army, and that this destruction can only be effected
by their means.
The battle may therefore be regarded as War concentrated, as the centre of effort of the whole War or
campaign. As the sun's rays unite in the focus of the concave mirror in a perfect image, and in the fulness of
their heat; to the forces and circumstances of War, unite in a focus in the great battle for one concentrated
utmost effort.
The very assemblage of forces in one great whole, which takes place more or less in all Wars, indicates an
intention to strike a decisive blow with this whole, either voluntarily as assailant, or constrained by the
opposite party as defender. When this great blow does not follow, then some modifying, and retarding
motives have attached themselves to the original motive of hostility, and have weakened, altered or
completely checked the movement. But also, even in this condition of mutual inaction which has been the
keynote in so many Wars, the idea of a possible battle serves always for both parties as a point of direction,
a distant focus in the construction of their plans. The more War is War in earnest, the more it is a venting of
animosity and hostility, a mutual struggle to overpower, so much the more will all activities join deadly
contest, and also the more prominent in importance becomes the battle.
In general, when the object aimed at is of a great and positive nature, one therefore in which the interests of
the enemy are deeply concerned, the battle offers itself as the most natural means; it is, therefore, also the
best as we shall show more plainly hereafter: and, as a rule, when it is evaded from aversion to the great
decision, punishment follows.
The positive object belong to the offensive, and therefore the battle is also more particularly his means. But
without examining the conception of offensive and defensive more minutely here, we must still observe that,
even for the defender in most cases, there is no other effectual means with which to meet the exigencies of his
situation, to solve the problem presented to him.
The battle is the bloodiest way of solution. True, it is not merely reciprocal slaughter, and its effect is more a
killing of the enemy's courage than of the enemy's soldiers, as we shall see more plainly in the next
chapterbut still blood is always its price, and slaughter its character as well as name;[*] from this the
humanity in the General's mind recoils with horror.
[*] "Schlacht", from schlachten = to slaughter.
But the soul of the man trembles still more at the thought of the decision to be given with one single blow. IN
ONE POINT of space and time all action is here pressed together, and at such a moment there is stirred up
within us a dim feeling as if in this narrow space all our forces could not develop themselves and come into
activity, as if we had already gained much by mere time, although this time owes us nothing at all. This is all
mere illusion, but even as illusion it is something, and the same weakness which seizes upon the man in
On War
On War 141
Page No 144
every, other momentous decision may well be felt more powerfully by the General, when he must stake
interests of such enormous weight upon one venture.
Thus, then, Statesmen and Generals have at all times endeavoured to avoid the decisive battle, seeking either
to attain their aim without it, or dropping that aim unperceived. Writers on history and theory have then
busied themselves to discover in some other feature in these campaigns not only an equivalent for the
decision by battle which has been avoided, but even a higher art. In this way, in the present age, it came very
near to this, that a battle in the economy of War was looked upon as an evil, rendered necessary through some
error committed,a morbid paroxysm to which a regular prudent system of War would never lead: only those
Generals were to deserve laurels who knew how to carry on War without spilling blood, and the theory of
Wara real business for Brahminswas to be specially directed to teaching this.
Contemporary history has destroyed this illusion,[*] but no one can guarantee that it will not sooner or later
reproduce itself, and lead those at the head of affairs to perversities which please man's weakness, and
therefore have the greater affinity for his nature. Perhaps, byand by, Buonaparte's campaigns and battles
will be looked upon as mere acts of barbarism and stupidity, and we shall once more turn with satisfaction
and confidence to the dresssword of obsolete and musty institutions and forms. If theory gives a caution
against this, then it renders a real service to those who listen to its warning voice. MAY WE SUCCEED IN
LENDING A HAND TO THOSE WHO IN OUR DEAR NATIVE LAND ARE CALLED UPON TO
SPEAK WITH AUTHORITY ON THESE MATTERS, THAT WE MAY BE THEIR GUIDE INTO THIS
FIELD OF INQUIRY, AND EXCITE THEM TO MAKE A CANDID EXAMINATION OF THE
SUBJECT.[**]
[*] On the Continent only, it still preserves full vitality in the minds of British politicians and
pressmen.EDITOR.
[**] This prayer was abundantly grantedvide the German victories of 1870.EDITOR.
Not only the conception of War but experience also leads us to look for a great decision only in a great battle.
From time immemorial, only great victories have led to great successes on the offensive side in the absolute
form, on the defensive side in a manner more or less satisfactory. Even Buonaparte would not have seen the
day of Ulm, unique in its kind, if he had shrunk from shedding blood; it is rather to be regarded as only a
second crop from the victorious events in his preceding campaigns. It is not only bold, rash, and
presumptuous Generals who have sought to complete their work by the great venture of a decisive battle, but
also fortunate ones as well; and we may rest satisfied with the answer which they have thus given to this vast
question.
Let us not hear of Generals who conquer without bloodshed. If a bloody slaughter is a horrible sight, then that
is a ground for paying more respect to War, but not for making the sword we wear blunter and blunter by
degrees from feelings of humanity, until some one steps in with one that is sharp and lops off the arm from
our body.
We look upon a great battle as a principal decision, but certainly not as the only one necessary for a War or a
campaign. Instances of a great battle deciding a whole campaign, have been frequent only in modern times,
those which have decided a whole War, belong to the class of rare exceptions.
A decision which is brought about by a great battle depends naturally not on the battle itself, that is on the
mass of combatants engaged in it, and on the intensity of the victory, but also on a number of other relations
between the military forces opposed to each other, and between the States to which these forces belong. But
at the same time that the principal mass of the force available is brought to the great duel, a great decision is
also brought on, the extent of which may perhaps be foreseen in many respects, though not in all, and which
On War
On War 142
Page No 145
although not the only one, still is the FIRST decision, and as such, has an influence on those which succeed.
Therefore a deliberately planned great battle, according to its relations, is more or less, but always in some
degree, to be regarded as the leading means and central point of the whole system. The more a General takes
the field in the true spirit of War as well as of every contest, with the feeling and the idea, that is the
conviction, that he must and will conquer, the more he will strive to throw every weight into the scale in the
first battle, hope and strive to win everything by it. Buonaparte hardly ever entered upon a War without
thinking of conquering his enemy at once in the first battle,[*] and Frederick the Great, although in a more
limited sphere, and with interests of less magnitude at stake, thought the same when, at the head of a small
Army, he sought to disengage his rear from the Russians or the Federal Imperial Army.
[*] This was Moltke's essential idea in his preparations for the War of 1870. See his secret memorandum
issued to G.O.C.s on May 7. 1870, pointing to a battle on the Upper Saar as his primary purpose. EDITOR.
The decision which is given by the great battle, depends, we have said, partly on the battle itself, that is on the
number of troops engaged, and partly on the magnitude of the success.
How the General may increase its importance in respect to the first point is evident in itself and we shall
merely observe that according to the importance of the great battle, the number of cases which are decided
along with it increases, and that therefore Generals who, confident in themselves have been lovers of great
decisions, have always managed to make use of the greater part of their troops in it without neglecting on that
account essential points elsewhere.
As regards the consequences or speaking more correctly the effectiveness of a victory, that depends chiefly
on four points:
1. On the tactical form adopted as the order of battle.
2. On the nature of the country.
3. On the relative proportions of the three arms.
4. On the relative strength of the two Armies.
A battle with parallel fronts and without any action against a flank will seldom yield as great success as one
in which the defeated Army has been turned, or compelled to change front more or less. In a broken or hilly
country the successes are likewise smaller, because the power of the blow is everywhere less.
If the cavalry of the vanquished is equal or superior to that of the victor, then the effects of the pursuit are
diminished, and by that great part of the results of victory are lost.
Finally it is easy to understand that if superior numbers are on the side of the conqueror, and he uses his
advantage in that respect to turn the flank of his adversary, or compel him to change front, greater results will
follow than if the conqueror had been weaker in numbers than the vanquished. The battle of Leuthen may
certainly be quoted as a practical refutation of this principle, but we beg permission for once to say what we
otherwise do not like, NO RULE WITHOUT AN EXCEPTION.
In all these ways, therefore, the Commander has the means of giving his battle a decisive character; certainly
he thus exposes himself to an increased amount of danger, but his whole line of action is subject to that
dynamic law of the moral world.
There is then nothing in War which can be put in comparison with the great battle in point of importance,
On War
On War 143
Page No 146
AND THE ACME OF STRATEGIC ABILITY IS DISPLAYED IN THE PROVISION OF MEANS FOR
THIS GREAT EVENT, IN THE SKILFUL DETERMINATION OF PLACE AND TIME, AND
DIRECTION OF TROOPS, AND ITS THE GOOD USE MADE OF SUCCESS.
But it does not follow from the importance of these things that they must be of a very complicated and
recondite nature; all is here rather simple, the art of combination by no means great; but there is great need of
quickness in judging of circumstances, need of energy, steady resolution, a youthful spirit of
enterpriseheroic qualities, to which we shall often have to refer. There is, therefore, but little wanted here
of that which can be taught by books and there is much that, if it can be taught at all, must come to the
General through some other medium than printer's type.
The impulse towards a great battle, the voluntary, sure progress to it, must proceed from a feeling of innate
power and a clear sense of the necessity; in other words, it must proceed from inborn courage and from
perceptions sharpened by contact with the higher interests of life.
Great examples are the best teachers, but it is certainly a misfortune if a cloud of theoretical prejudices comes
between, for even the sunbeam is refracted and tinted by the clouds. To destroy such prejudices, which many
a time rise and spread themselves like a miasma, is an imperative duty of theory, for the misbegotten
offspring of human reason can also be in turn destroyed by pure reason.
CHAPTER XII. STRATEGIC MEANS OF UTILISING VICTORY
THE more difficult part, viz., that of perfectly preparing the victory, is a silent service of which the merit
belongs to Strategy and yet for which it is hardly sufficiently commended. It appears brilliant and full of
renown by turning to good account a victory gained.
What may be the special object of a battle, how it is connected with the whole system of a War, whither the
career of victory may lead according to the nature of circumstances, where its culminatingpoint liesall
these are things which we shall not enter upon until hereafter. But under any conceivable circumstances the
fact holds good, that without a pursuit no victory can have a great effect, and that, however short the career of
victory may be, it must always lead beyond the first steps in pursuit; and in order to avoid the frequent
repetition of this, we shall now dwell for a moment on this necessary supplement of victory in general.
The pursuit of a beaten Army commences at the moment that Army, giving up the combat, leaves its position;
all previous movements in one direction and another belong not to that but to the progress of the battle itself.
Usually victory at the moment here described, even if it is certain, is still as yet small and weak in its
proportions, and would not rank as an event of any great positive advantage if not completed by a pursuit on
the first day. Then it is mostly, as we have before said, that the trophies which give substance to the victory
begin to be gathered up. Of this pursuit we shall speak in the next place.
Usually both sides come into action with their physical powers considerably deteriorated, for the movements
immediately preceding have generally the character of very urgent circumstances. The efforts which the
forging out of a great combat costs, complete the exhaustion; from this it follows that the victorious party is
very little less disorganised and out of his original formation than the vanquished, and therefore requires time
to reform, to collect stragglers, and issue fresh ammunition to those who are without. All these things place
the conqueror himself in the state of crisis of which we have already spoken. If now the defeated force is only
a detached portion of the enemy's Army, or if it has otherwise to expect a considerable reinforcement, then
the conqueror may easily run into the obvious danger of having to pay dear for his victory, and this
On War
On War 144
Page No 147
consideration, in such a case, very soon puts an end to pursuit, or at least restricts it materially. Even when a
strong accession of force by the enemy is not to be feared, the conqueror finds in the above circumstances a
powerful check to the vivacity of his pursuit. There is no reason to fear that the victory will be snatched
away, but adverse combats are still possible, and may diminish the advantages which up to the present have
been gained. Moreover, at this moment the whole weight of all that is sensuous in an Army, its wants and
weaknesses, are dependent on the will of the Commander. All the thousands under his command require rest
and refreshment, and long to see a stop put to toil and danger for the present; only a few, forming an
exception, can see and feel beyond the present moment, it is only amongst this little number that there is
sufficient mental vigour to think, after what is absolutely necessary at the moment has been done, upon those
results which at such a moment only appear to the rest as mere embellishments of victoryas a luxury of
triumph. But all these thousands have a voice in the council of the General, for through the various steps of
the military hierarchy these interests of the sensuous creature have their sure conductor into the heart of the
Commander. He himself, through mental and bodily fatigue, is more or less weakened in his natural activity,
and thus it happens then that, mostly from these causes, purely incidental to human nature, less is done than
might have been done, and that generally what is done is to be ascribed entirely to the THIRST FOR
GLORY, the energy, indeed also the HARD HEARTEDNESS of the GeneralinChief. It is only thus we
can explain the hesitating manner in which many Generals follow up a victory which superior numbers have
given them. The first pursuit of the enemy we limit in general to the extent of the first day, including the
night following the victory. At the end of that period the necessity of rest ourselves prescribes a halt in any
case.
This first pursuit has different natural degrees.
The first is, if cavalry alone are employed; in that case it amounts usually more to alarming and watching
than to pressing the enemy in reality, because the smallest obstacle of ground is generally sufficient to check
the pursuit. Useful as cavalry may be against single bodies of broken demoralised troops, still when opposed
to the bulk of the beaten Army it becomes again only the auxiliary arm, because the troops in retreat can
employ fresh reserves to cover the movement, and, therefore, at the next trifling obstacle of ground, by
combining all arms they can make a stand with success. The only exception to this is in the case of an army in
actual flight in a complete state of dissolution.
The second degree is, if the pursuit is made by a strong advanceguard composed of all arms, the greater part
consisting naturally of cavalry. Such a pursuit generally drives the enemy as far as the nearest strong position
for his rearguard, or the next position affording space for his Army. Neither can usually be found at once,
and, therefore, the pursuit can be carried further; generally, however, it does not extend beyond the distance
of one or at most a couple of leagues, because otherwise the advance guard would not feel itself sufficiently
supported. The third and most vigorous degree is when the victorious Army itself continues to advance as far
as its physical powers can endure. In this case the beaten Army will generally quit such ordinary positions as
a country usually offers on the mere show of an attack, or of an intention to turn its flank; and the rearguard
will be still less likely to engage in an obstinate resistance.
In all three cases the night, if it sets in before the conclusion of the whole act, usually puts an end to it, and
the few instances in which this has not taken place, and the pursuit has been continued throughout the night,
must be regarded as pursuits in an exceptionally vigorous form.
If we reflect that in fighting by night everything must be, more or less, abandoned to chance, and that at the
conclusion of a battle the regular cohesion and order of things in an army must inevitably be disturbed, we
may easily conceive the reluctance of both Generals to carrying on their business under such disadvantageous
conditions. If a complete dissolution of the vanquished Army, or a rare superiority of the victorious Army in
military virtue does not ensure success, everything would in a manner be given up to fate, which can never be
for the interest of any one, even of the most foolhardy General. As a rule, therefore, night puts an end to
On War
On War 145
Page No 148
pursuit, even when the battle has only been decided shortly before darkness sets in. This allows the conquered
either time for rest and to rally immediately, or, if he retreats during the night it gives him a march in
advance. After this break the conquered is decidedly in a better condition; much of that which had been
thrown into confusion has been brought again into order, ammunition has been renewed, the whole has been
put into a fresh formation. Whatever further encounter now takes place with the enemy is a new battle not a
continuation of the old, and although it may be far from promising absolute success, still it is a fresh combat,
and not merely a gathering up of the debris by the victor.
When, therefore, the conqueror can continue the pursuit itself throughout the night, if only with a strong
advance guard composed of all arms of the service, the effect of the victory is immensely increased, of this
the battles of Leuthen and La Belle Alliance[*] are examples.
[*] Waterloo.
The whole action of this pursuit is mainly tactical, and we only dwell upon it here in order to make plain the
difference which through it may be produced in the effect of a victory.
This first pursuit, as far as the nearest stoppingpoint, belongs as a right to every conqueror, and is hardly in
any way connected with his further plans and combinations. These may considerably diminish the positive
results of a victory gained with the main body of the Army, but they cannot make this first use of it
impossible; at least cases of that kind, if conceivable at all, must be so uncommon that they should have no
appreciable influence on theory. And here certainly we must say that the example afforded by modern Wars
opens up quite a new field for energy. In preceding Wars, resting on a narrower basis, and altogether more
circumscribed in their scope, there were many unnecessary conventional restrictions in various ways, but
particularly in this point. THE CONCEPTION, HONOUR OF VICTORY seemed to Generals so much by far
the chief thing that they thought the less of the complete destruction of the enemy's military force, as in point
of fact that destruction of force appeared to them only as one of the many means in War, not by any means as
the principal, much less as the only means; so that they the more readily put the sword in its sheath the
moment the enemy had lowered his. Nothing seemed more natural to them than to stop the combat as soon as
the decision was obtained, and to regard all further carnage as unnecessary cruelty. Even if this false
philosophy did not determine their resolutions entirely, still it was a point of view by which representations of
the exhaustion of all powers, and physical impossibility of continuing the struggle, obtained readier evidence
and greater weight. Certainly the sparing one's own instrument of victory is a vital question if we only
possess this one, and foresee that soon the time may arrive when it will not be sufficient for all that remains
to be done, for every continuation of the offensive must lead ultimately to complete exhaustion. But this
calculation was still so far false, as the further loss of forces by a continuance of the pursuit could bear no
proportion to that which the enemy must suffer. That view, therefore, again could only exist because the
military forces were not considered the vital factor. And so we find that in former Wars real heroes
onlysuch as Charles XII., Marlborough, Eugene, Frederick the Greatadded a vigorous pursuit to their
victories when they were decisive enough, and that other Generals usually contented themselves with the
possession of the field of battle. In modern times the greater energy infused into the conduct of Wars through
the greater importance of the circumstances from which they have proceeded has thrown down these
conventional barriers; the pursuit has become an allimportant business for the conqueror; trophies have on
that account multiplied in extent, and if there are cases also in modern Warfare in which this has not been the
case, still they belong to the list of exceptions, and are to be accounted for by peculiar circumstances.
At Gorschen[*] and Bautzen nothing but the superiority of the allied cavalry prevented a complete rout, at
Gross Beeren and Dennewitz the illwill of Bernadotte, the Crown Prince of Sweden; at Laon the enfeebled
personal condition of Bluecher, who was then seventy years old and at the moment confined to a dark room
owing to an injury to his eyes.
On War
On War 146
Page No 149
[*] Gorschen or Lutzen, May 2, 1813; Gross Beeren and Dennewitz, August 22, 1813; Bautzen. May 22,
1913; Laon, March 10 1813.
But Borodino is also an illustration to the point here, and we cannot resist saying a few more words about it,
partly because we do not consider the circumstances are explained simply by attaching blame to Buonaparte,
partly because it might appear as if this, and with it a great number of similar cases, belonged to that class
which we have designated as so extremely rare, cases in which the general relations seize and fetter the
General at the very beginning of the battle. French authors in particular, and great admirers of Buonaparte
(Vaudancourt, Chambray, Se'gur), have blamed him decidedly because he did not drive the Russian Army
completely off the field, and use his last reserves to scatter it, because then what was only a lost battle would
have been a complete rout. We should be obliged to diverge too far to describe circumstantially the mutual
situation of the two Armies; but this much is evident, that when Buonaparte passed the Niemen with his
Army the same corps which afterwards fought at Borodino numbered 300,000 men, of whom now only
120,000 remained, he might therefore well be apprehensive that he would not have enough left to march upon
Moscow, the point on which everything seemed to depend. The victory which he had just gained gave him
nearly a certainty of taking that capital, for that the Russians would be in a condition to fight a second battle
within eight days seemed in the highest degree improbable; and in Moscow he hoped to find peace. No doubt
the complete dispersion of the Russian Army would have made this peace much more certain; but still the
first consideration was to get to Moscow, that is, to get there with a force with which he should appear
dictator over the capital, and through that over the Empire and the Government. The force which he brought
with him to Moscow was no longer sufficient for that, as shown in the sequel, but it would have been still less
so if, in scattering the Russian Army, he had scattered his own at the same time. Buonaparte was thoroughly
alive to all this, and in our eyes he stands completely justified. But on that account this case is still not to be
reckoned amongst those in which, through the general relations, the General is interdicted from following up
his victory, for there never was in his case any question of mere pursuit. The victory was decided at four
o'clock in the afternoon, but the Russians still occupied the greater part of the field of battle; they were not
yet disposed to give up the ground, and if the attack had been renewed, they would still have offered a most
determined resistance, which would have undoubtedly ended in their complete defeat, but would have cost
the conqueror much further bloodshed. We must therefore reckon the Battle of Borodino as amongst battles,
like Bautzen, left unfinished. At Bautzen the vanquished preferred to quit the field sooner; at Borodino the
conqueror preferred to content himself with a half victory, not because the decision appeared doubtful, but
because he was not rich enough to pay for the whole.
Returning now to our subject, the deduction from our reflections in relation to the first stage of pursuit is, that
the energy thrown into it chiefly determines the value of the victory; that this pursuit is a second act of the
victory, in many cases more important also than the first, and that strategy, whilst here approaching tactics to
receive from it the harvest of success, exercises the first act of her authority by demanding this completion of
the victory.
But further, the effects of victory are very seldom found to stop with this first pursuit; now first begins the
real career to which victory lent velocity. This course is conditioned as we have already said, by other
relations of which it is not yet time to speak. But we must here mention, what there is of a general character
in the pursuit in order to avoid repetition when the subject occurs again.
In the further stages of pursuit, again, we can distinguish three degrees: the simple pursuit, a hard pursuit, and
a parallel march to intercept.
The simple FOLLOWING or PURSUING causes the enemy to continue his retreat, until he thinks he can risk
another battle. It will therefore in its effect suffice to exhaust the advantages gained, and besides that, all that
the enemy cannot carry with him, sick, wounded, and disabled from fatigue, quantities of baggage, and
carriages of all kinds, will fall into our hands, but this mere following does not tend to heighten the disorder
On War
On War 147
Page No 150
in the enemy's Army, an effect which is produced by the two following causes.
If, for instance, instead of contenting ourselves with taking up every day the camp the enemy has just
vacated, occupying just as much of the country as he chooses to abandon, we make our arrangements so as
every day to encroach further, and accordingly with our advance guard organised for the purpose, attack his
rearguard every time it attempts to halt, then such a course will hasten his retreat, and consequently tend to
increase his disorganisation.This it will principally effect by the character of continuous flight, which his
retreat will thus assume. Nothing has such a depressing influence on the soldier, as the sound of the enemy's
cannon afresh at the moment when, after a forced march he seeks some rest; if this excitement is continued
from day to day for some time, it may lead to a complete rout. There lies in it a constant admission of being
obliged to obey the law of the enemy, and of being unfit for any resistance, and the consciousness of this
cannot do otherwise than weaken the moral of an Army in a high degree. The effect of pressing the enemy in
this way attains a maximum when it drives the enemy to make night marches. If the conqueror scares away
the discomfited opponent at sunset from a camp which has just been taken up either for the main body of the
Army, or for the rearguard, the conquered must either make a night march, or alter his position in the night,
retiring further away, which is much the same thing; the victorious party can on the other hand pass the night
in quiet.
The arrangement of marches, and the choice of positions depend in this case also upon so many other things,
especially on the supply of the Army, on strong natural obstacles in the country, on large towns, that it would
be ridiculous pedantry to attempt to show by a geometrical analysis how the pursuer, being able to impose his
laws on the retreating enemy, can compel him to march at night while he takes his rest. But nevertheless it is
true and practicable that marches in pursuit may be so planned as to have this tendency, and that the efficacy
of the pursuit is very much enchanced thereby. If this is seldom attended to in the execution, it is because
such a procedure is more difficult for the pursuing Army, than a regular adherence to ordinary marches in the
daytime. To start in good time in the morning, to encamp at midday, to occupy the rest of the day in
providing for the ordinary wants of the Army, and to use the night for repose, is a much more convenient
method than to regulate one's movements exactly according to those of the enemy, therefore to determine
nothing till the last moment, to start on the march, sometimes in the morning, sometimes in the evening, to be
always for several hours in the presence of the enemy, and exchanging cannon shots with him, and keeping
up skirmishing fire, to plan manoeuvres to turn him, in short, to make the whole outlay of tactical means
which such a course renders necessary. All that naturally bears with a heavy weight on the pursuing Army,
and in War, where there are so many burdens to be borne, men are always inclined to strip off those which do
not seem absolutely necessary. These observations are true, whether applied to a whole Army or as in the
more usual case, to a strong advanceguard. For the reasons just mentioned, this second method of pursuit,
this continued pressing of the enemy pursued is rather a rare occurrence; even Buonaparte in his Russian
campaign, 1812, practised it but little, for the reasons here apparent, that the difficulties and hardships of this
campaign, already threatened his Army with destruction before it could reach its object; on the other hand,
the French in their other campaigns have distinguished themselves by their energy in this point also.
Lastly, the third and most effectual form of pursuit is, the parallel march to the immediate object of the
retreat.
Every defeated Army will naturally have behind it, at a greater or less distance, some point, the attainment of
which is the first purpose in view, whether it be that failing in this its further retreat might be compromised,
as in the case of a defile, or that it is important for the point itself to reach it before the enemy, as in the case
of a great city, magazines, or, lastly, that the Army at this point will gain new powers of defence, such as a
strong position, or junction with other corps.
Now if the conqueror directs his march on this point by a lateral road, it is evident how that may quicken the
retreat of the beaten Army in a destructive manner, convert it into hurry, perhaps into flight.[*] The
On War
On War 148
Page No 151
conquered has only three ways to counteract this: the first is to throw himself in front of the enemy, in order
by an unexpected attack to gain that probability of success which is lost to him in general from his position;
this plainly supposes an enterprising bold General, and an excellent Army, beaten but not utterly defeated;
therefore, it can only be employed by a beaten Army in very few cases.
[*] This point is exceptionally well treated by von Bernhardi in his "Cavalry in Future Wars." London:
Murray, 1906.
The second way is hastening the retreat; but this is just what the conqueror wants, and it easily leads to
immoderate efforts on the part of the troops, by which enormous losses are sustained, in stragglers, broken
guns, and carriages of all kinds.
The third way is to make a detour, and get round the nearest point of interception, to march with more ease at
a greater distance from the enemy, and thus to render the haste required less damaging. This last way is the
worst of all, it generally turns out like a new debt contracted by an insolvent debtor, and leads to greater
embarrassment. There are cases in which this course is advisable; others where there is nothing else left; also
instances in which it has been successful; but upon the whole it is certainly true that its adoption is usually
influenced less by a clear persuasion of its being the surest way of attaining the aim than by another
inadmissible motive this motive is the dread of encountering the enemy. Woe to the Commander who
gives in to this! However much the moral of his Army may have deteriorated, and however well founded may
be his apprehensions of being at a disadvantage in any conflict with the enemy, the evil will only be made
worse by too anxiously avoiding every possible risk of collision. Buonaparte in 1813 would never have
brought over the Rhine with him the 30,000 or 40,000 men who remained after the battle of Hanau,[*] if he
had avoided that battle and tried to pass the Rhine at Mannheim or Coblenz. It is just by means of small
combats carefully prepared and executed, and in which the defeated army being on the defensive, has always
the assistance of the groundit is just by these that the moral strength of the Army can first be resuscitated.
[*] At Hanau (October 30, 1813), the Bavarians some 50,000 strong threw themselves across the line of
Napoleon's retreat from Leipsic. By a masterly use of its artillery the French tore the Bavarians asunder and
marched on over their bodies.EDITOR.
The beneficial effect of the smallest successes is incredible; but with most Generals the adoption of this plan
implies great selfcommand. The other way, that of evading all encounter, appears at first so much easier,
that there is a natural preference for its adoption. It is therefore usually just this system of evasion which best,
promotes the view of the pursuer, and often ends with the complete downfall of the pursued; we must,
however, recollect here that we are speaking of a whole Army, not of a single Division, which, having been
cut off, is seeking to join the main Army by making a de'tour; in such a case circumstances are different, and
success is not uncommon. But there is one condition requisite to the success of this race of two Corps for an
object, which is that a Division of the pursuing army should follow by the same road which the pursued has
taken, in order to pick up stragglers, and keep up the impression which the presence of the enemy never fails
to make. Bluecher neglected this in his, in other respects unexceptionable, pursuit after La Belle Alliance.
Such marches tell upon the pursuer as well as the pursued, and they are not advisable if the enemy's Army
rallies itself upon another considerable one; if it has a distinguished General at its head, and if its destruction
is not already well prepared. But when this means can be adopted, it acts also like a great mechanical power.
The losses of the beaten Army from sickness and fatigue are on such a disproportionate scale, the spirit of the
Army is so weakened and lowered by the constant solicitude about impending ruin, that at last anything like a
well organised stand is out of the question; every day thousands of prisoners fall into the enemy's hands
without striking a blow. In such a season of complete good fortune, the conqueror need not hesitate about
dividing his forces in order to draw into the vortex of destruction everything within reach of his Army, to cut
off detachments, to take fortresses unprepared for defence, to occupy large towns, He may do anything until a
On War
On War 149
Page No 152
new state of things arises, and the more he ventures in this way the longer will it be before that change will
take place. is no want of examples of brilliant results from grand decisive victories, and of great and vigorous
pursuits in the wars of Buonaparte. We need only quote Jena 1806, Ratisbonne 1809, Leipsic 1813, and
Belle Alliance 1815.
CHAPTER XIII. RETREAT AFTER A LOST BATTLE
IN a lost battle the power of an Army is broken, the moral to a greater degree than the physical. A second
battle unless fresh favourable circumstances come into play, would lead to a complete defeat, perhaps, to
destruction. This is a military axiom. According to the usual course the retreat is continued up to that point
where the equilibrium of forces is restored, either by reinforcements, or by the protection of strong fortresses,
or by great defensive positions afforded by the country, or by a separation of the enemy's force. The
magnitude of the losses sustained, the extent of the defeat, but still more the character of the enemy, will
bring nearer or put off the instant of this equilibrium. How many instances may be found of a beaten Army
rallied again at a short distance, without its circumstances having altered in any way since the battle. The
cause of this may be traced to the moral weakness of the adversary, or to the preponderance gained in the
battle not having been sufficient to make lasting impression.
To profit by this weakness or mistake of the enemy, not to yield one inch breadth more than the pressure of
circumstances demands, but above all things, in order to keep up the moral forces to as advantageous a point
as possible, a slow retreat, offering incessant resistance, and bold courageous counterstrokes, whenever the
enemy seeks to gain any excessive advantages, are absolutely necessary. Retreats of great Generals and of
Armies inured to War have always resembled the retreat of a wounded lion, such is, undoubtedly, also the
best theory.
It is true that at the moment of quitting a dangerous position we have often seen trifling formalities observed
which caused a waste of time, and were, therefore, attended with danger, whilst in such cases everything
depends on getting out of the place speedily. Practised Generals reckon this maxim a very important one. But
such cases must not be confounded with a general retreat after a lost battle. Whoever then thinks by a few
rapid marches to gain a start, and more easily to recover a firm standing, commits a great error. The first
movements should be as small as possible, and it is a maxim in general not to suffer ourselves to be dictated
to by the enemy. This maxim cannot be followed without bloody fighting with the enemy at our heels, but the
gain is worth the sacrifice; without it we get into an accelerated pace which soon turns into a headlong rush,
and costs merely in stragglers more men than rearguard combats, and besides that extinguishes the last
remnants of the spirit of resistance.
A strong rearguard composed of picked troops, commanded by the bravest General, and supported by the
whole Army at critical moments, a careful utilisation of ground, strong ambuscades wherever the boldness of
the enemy's advanceguard, and the ground, afford opportunity; in short, the preparation and the system of
regular small battles,these are the means of following this principle.
The difficulties of a retreat are naturally greater or less according as the battle has been fought under more or
less favourable circumstances, and according as it has been more or less obstinately contested. The battle of
Jena and La BelleAlliance show how impossible anything like a regular retreat may become, if the last man
is used up against a powerful enemy.
Now and again it has been suggested[*] to divide for the purpose of retreating, therefore to retreat in separate
divisions or even eccentrically. Such a separation as is made merely for convenience, and along with which
On War
On War 150
Page No 153
concentrated action continues possible and is kept in view, is not what we now refer to; any other kind is
extremely dangerous, contrary to the nature of the thing, and therefore a great error. Every lost battle is a
principle of weakness and disorganisation; and the first and immediate desideratum is to concentrate, and in
concentration to recover order, courage, and confidence. The idea of harassing the enemy by separate corps
on both flanks at the moment when he is following up his victory, is a perfect anomaly; a fainthearted
pedant might be overawed by his enemy in that manner, and for such a case it may answer; but where we are
not sure of this failing in our opponent it is better let alone. If the strategic relations after a battle require that
we should cover ourselves right and left by detachments, so much must be done, as from circumstances is
unavoidable, but this fractioning must always be regarded as an evil, and we are seldom in a state to
commence it the day after the battle itself.
[*] Allusion is here made to the works of Lloyd Bullow and others.
If Frederick the Great after the battle of Kollin,[*] and the raising of the siege of Prague retreated in three
columns that was done not out of choice, but because the position of his forces, and the necessity of covering
Saxony, left him no alternative, Buonaparte after the battle of Brienne,[**] sent Marmont back to the Aube,
whilst he himself passed the Seine, and turned towards Troyes; but that this did not end in disaster, was solely
owing to the circumstance that the Allies, instead of pursuing divided their forces in like manner, turning
with the one part (Bluecher) towards the Marne, while with the other (Schwartzenberg), from fear of being
too weak, they advanced with exaggerated caution.
[*] June 19, 1757.
[**] January 30, 1814.
CHAPTER XIV. NIGHT FIGHTING
THE manner of conducting a combat at night, and what concerns the details of its course, is a tactical subject;
we only examine it here so far as in its totality it appears as a special strategic means.
Fundamentally every night attack is only a more vehement form of surprise. Now at the first look of the thing
such an attack appears quite preeminently advantageous, for we suppose the enemy to be taken by surprise,
the assailant naturally to be prepared for everything which can happen. What an inequality! Imagination
paints to itself a picture of the most complete confusion on the one side, and on the other side the assailant
only occupied in reaping the fruits of his advantage. Hence the constant creation of schemes for night attacks
by those who have not to lead them, and have no responsibility, whilst these attacks seldom take place in
reality.
These ideal schemes are all based on the hypothesis that the assailant knows the arrangements of the defender
because they have been made and announced beforehand, and could not escape notice in his reconnaissances,
and inquiries; that on the other hand, the measures of the assailant, being only taken at the moment of
execution, cannot be known to the enemy. But the last of these is not always quite the case, and still less is
the first. If we are not so near the enemy as to have him completely under our eye, as the Austrians had
Frederick the Great before the battle of Hochkirch (1758), then all that we know of his position must always
be imperfect, as it is obtained by reconnaissances, patrols, information from prisoners, and spies, sources on
which no firm reliance can be placed because intelligence thus obtained is always more or less of an old date,
and the position of the enemy may have been altered in the meantime. Moreover, with the tactics and mode of
encampment of former times it was much easier than it is now to examine the position of the enemy. A line
On War
On War 151
Page No 154
of tents is much easier to distinguish than a line of huts or a bivouac; and an encampment on a line of front,
fully and regularly drawn out, also easier than one of Divisions formed in columns, the mode often used at
present. We may have the ground on which a Division bivouacs in that manner completely under our eye, and
yet not be able to arrive at any accurate idea.
But the position again is not all that we want to know the measures which the defender may take in the course
of the combat are just as important, and do not by any means consist in mere random shots. These measures
also make night attacks more difficult in modern Wars than formerly, because they have in these campaigns
an advantage over those already taken. In our combats the position of the defender is more temporary than
definitive, and on that account the defender is better able to surprise his adversary with unexpected blows,
than he could formerly.[*]
[*] All these difficulties obviously become increased as the power of the weapons in use tends to keep the
combatants further apart.EDITOR.
Therefore what the assailant knows of the defensive previous to a night attack, is seldom or never sufficient
to supply the want of direct observation.
But the defender has on his side another small advantage as well, which is that he is more at home than the
assailant, on the ground which forms his position, and therefore, like the inhabitant of a room, will find his
way about it in the dark with more ease than a stranger. He knows better where to find each part of his force,
and therefore can more readily get at it than is the case with his adversary.
From this it follows, that the assailant in a combat at night feels the want of his eyes just as much as the
defender, and that therefore, only particular reasons can make a night attack advisable.
Now these reasons arise mostly in connection with subordinate parts of an Army, rarely with the Army itself;
it follows that a night attack also as a rule can only take place with secondary combats, and seldom with great
battles.
We may attack a portion of the enemy's Army with a very superior force, consequently enveloping it with a
view either to take the whole, or to inflict very severe loss on it by an unequal combat, provided that other
circumstances are in our favour. But such a scheme can never succeed except by a great surprise, because no
fractional part of the enemy's Army would engage in such an unequal combat, but would retire instead. But a
surprise on an important scale except in rare instances in a very close country, can only be effected at night. If
therefore we wish to gain such an advantage as this from the faulty disposition of a portion of the enemy's
Army, then we must make use of the night, at all events, to finish the preliminary part even if the combat
itself should not open till towards daybreak. This is therefore what takes place in all the little enterprises by
night against outposts, and other small bodies, the main point being invariably through superior numbers, and
getting round his position, to entangle him unexpectedly in such a disadvantageous combat, that he cannot
disengage himself without great loss.
The larger the body attacked the more difficult the undertaking, because a strong force has greater resources
within itself to maintain the fight long enough for help to arrive.
On that account the whole of the enemy's Army can never in ordinary cases be the object of such an attack
for although it has no assistance to expect from any quarter outside itself, still, it contains within itself
sufficient means of repelling attacks from several sides particularly in our day, when every one from the
commencement is prepared for this very usual form of attack. Whether the enemy can attack us on several
sides with success depends generally on conditions quite different from that of its being done unexpectedly;
without entering here into the nature of these conditions, we confine ourselves to observing, that with turning
On War
On War 152
Page No 155
an enemy, great results, as well as great dangers are connected; that therefore, if we set aside special
circumstances, nothing justifies it but a great superiority, just such as we should use against a fractional part
of the enemy's Army.
But the turning and surrounding a small fraction of the enemy, and particularly in the darkness of night, is
also more practicable for this reason, that whatever we stake upon it, and however superior the force used
may be, still probably it constitutes only a limited portion of our Army, and we can sooner stake that than the
whole on the risk of a great venture. Besides, the greater part or perhaps the whole serves as a support and
rallyingpoint for the portion risked, which again very much diminishes the danger of the enterprise.
Not only the risk, but the difficulty of execution as well confines night enterprises to small bodies. As
surprise is the real essence of them so also stealthy approach is the chief condition of execution: but this is
more easily done with small bodies than with large, and for the columns of a whole Army is seldom
practicable. For this reason such enterprises are in general only directed against single outposts, and can only
be feasible against greater bodies if they are without sufficient outposts, like Frederick the Great at
Hochkirch.[*] This will happen seldomer in future to Armies themselves than to minor divisions.
[*] October 14, 1758.
In recent times, when War has been carried on with so much more rapidity and vigour, it has in consequence
often happened that Armies have encamped very close to each other, without having a very strong system of
outposts, because those circumstances have generally occurred just at the crisis which precedes a great
decision.
But then at such times the readiness for battle on both sides is also more perfect; on the other hand, in former
Wars it was a frequent practice for armies to take up camps in sight of each other, when they had no other
object but that of mutually holding each other in check, consequently for a longer period. How often
Frederick the Great stood for weeks so near to the Austrians, that the two might have exchanged cannon shots
with each other.
But these practices, certainly more favourable to night attacks, have been discontinued in later days; and
armies being now no longer in regard to subsistence and requirements for encampment, such independent
bodies complete in themselves, find it necessary to keep usually a day's march between themselves and the
enemy. If we now keep in view especially the night attack of an army, it follows that sufficient motives for it
can seldom occur, and that they fall under one or other of the following classes.
1. An unusual degree of carelessness or audacity which very rarely occurs, and when it does is compensated
for by a great superiority in moral force.
2. A panic in the enemy's army, or generally such a degree of superiority in moral force on our side, that this
is sufficient to supply the place of guidance in action.
3. Cutting through an enemy's army of superior force, which keeps us enveloped, because in this all depends
on surprise. and the object of merely making a passage by force, allows a much greater concentration of
forces.
4. Finally, in desperate cases, when our forces have such a disproportion to the enemy's, that we see no
possibility of success, except through extraordinary daring.
But in all these cases there is still the condition that the enemy's army is under our eyes, and protected by no
advanceguard.
On War
On War 153
Page No 156
As for the rest, most night combats are so conducted as to end with daylight, so that only the approach and
the first attack are made under cover of darkness, because the assailant in that manner can better profit by the
consequences of the state of confusion into which he throws his adversary; and combats of this description
which do not commence until daybreak, in which the night therefore is only made use of to approach, are not
to be counted as night combats,
On War
On War 154
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. On War, page = 4