Title: The Problems of Philosophy
Subject:
Author: Bertrand Russell
Keywords:
Creator:
PDF Version: 1.2
Page No 1
The Problems of Philosophy
Bertrand Russell
Page No 2
Table of Contents
The Problems of Philosophy..............................................................................................................................1
Bertrand Russell .......................................................................................................................................1
PREFACE ................................................................................................................................................1
CHAPTER I. APPEARANCE AND REALITY ....................................................................................1
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER ...................................................................................5
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER .......................................................................................8
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM ..................................................................................................................12
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY
DESCRIPTION ...................................................................................................................................15
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION ........................................................................................................20
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES ..........................................23
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE ....................................................27
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS ..............................................................................30
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS .............................................................34
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE ................................................................................37
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD ....................................................................................40
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION ........................................44
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE ...........................................47
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY .............................................................................51
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE ...............................................................................................................54
The Problems of Philosophy
i
Page No 3
The Problems of Philosophy
Bertrand Russell
PREFACE
CHAPTER I. APPEARANCE AND REALITY
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE
PREFACE
IN the following pages I have confined myself in the main to those problems of philosophy in regard to
which I thought it possible to say something positive and constructive, since merely negative criticism
seemed out of place. For this reason, theory of knowledge occupies a larger space than metaphysics in the
present volume, and some topics much discussed by philosophers are treated very briefly, if at all.
I have derived valuable assistance from unpublished writings of G. E. Moore and J. M. Keynes: from the
former, as regards the relations of sensedata to physical objects, and from the latter as regards probability
and induction. I have also profited greatly by the criticisms and suggestions of Professor Gilbert Murray.
1912
NOTE TO SEVENTEENTH IMPRESSION
WITH reference to certain statements on pages 44, 75, 131, and 132, it should be remarked that this book was
written in the early part of 1912 when China was still an Empire, and the name of the then late Prime
Minister did begin with the letter B. 1943
CHAPTER I. APPEARANCE AND REALITY
IS there any knowledge in the world which is so certain that no reasonable man could doubt it? This question,
which at first sight might not seem difficult, is really one of the most difficult that can be asked. When we
have realized the obstacles in the way of a straightforward and confident answer, we shall be well launched
The Problems of Philosophy 1
Page No 4
on the study of philosophy for philosophy is merely the attempt to answer such ultimate questions, not
carelessly and dogmatically, as we do in ordinary life and even in the sciences, but critically after exploring
all that makes such questions puzzling, and after realizing all the vagueness and confusion that underlie our
ordinary ideas.
In daily life, we assume as certain many things which, on a closer scrutiny, are found to be so full of apparent
contradictions that only a great amount of thought enables us to know what it is that we really may believe. In
the search for certainty, it is natural to begin with our present experiences, and in some sense, no doubt,
knowledge is to be derived from them. But any statement as to what it is that our immediate experiences
make us know is very likely to be wrong. It seems to me that I am now sitting in a chair, at a table of a certain
shape, on which I see sheets of paper with writing or print. By turning my head I see out of the window
buildings and clouds and the sun. I believe that the sun is about ninetythree million miles from the earth;
that it is a hot globe many times bigger than the earth; that, owing to the earth's rotation, it rises every
morning, and will continue to do so for an indefinite time in the future. I believe that, if any other normal
person comes into my room, he will see the same chairs and tables and books and papers as I see, and that the
table which I see is the same as the table which I feel pressing against my arm. All this seems to be so evident
as to be hardly worth stating, except in answer to a man who doubts whether I know anything. Yet all this
may be reasonably doubted, and all of it requires much careful discussion before we can be sure that we have
stated it in a form that is wholly true.
To make our difficulties plain, let us concentrate attention on the table. To the eye it is oblong, brown and
shiny, to the touch it is smooth and cool and hard; when I tap it, it gives out a wooden sound. Any one else
who sees and feels and hears the table will agree with this description, so that it might seem as if no difficulty
would arise; but as soon as we try to be more precise our troubles begin. Although I believe that the table is
'really' of the same colour all over, the parts that reflect the light look much brighter than the other parts, and
some parts look white because of reflected light. I know that, if I move, the parts that reflect the light will be
different, so that the apparent distribution of colours on the table will change. It follows that if several people
are looking at the table at the same moment, no two of them will see exactly the same distribution of colours,
because no two can see it from exactly the same point of view, and any change in the point of view makes
some change in the way the light is reflected.
For most practical purposes these differences are unimportant, but to the painter they are allimportant: the
painter has to unlearn the habit of thinking that things seem to have the colour which common sense says
they 'really' have, and to learn the habit of seeing things as they appear. Here we have already the beginning
of one of the distinctions that cause most trouble in philosophy the distinction between 'appearance' and
'reality', between what things seem to be and what they are. The painter wants to know what things seem to
be, the practical man and the philosopher want to know what they are; but the philosopher's wish to know this
is stronger than the practical man's, and is more troubled by knowledge as to the difficulties of answering the
question.
To return to the table. It is evident from what we have found, that there is no colour which preeminently
appears to be the colour of the table, or even of any one particular part of the table it appears to be of
different colours from different points of view, and there is no reason for regarding some of these as more
really its colour than others. And we know that even from a given point of view the colour will seem different
by artificial light, or to a colourblind man, or to a man wearing blue spectacles, while in the dark there will
be no colour at all, though to touch and hearing the table will be unchanged. This colour is not something
which is inherent in the table, but something depending upon the table and the spectator and the way the light
falls on the table. When, in ordinary life, we speak of the colour of the table, we only mean the sort of colour
which it will seem to have to a normal spectator from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions of
light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions have just as good a right to be considered
real; and therefore, to avoid favouritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any one
The Problems of Philosophy
The Problems of Philosophy 2
Page No 5
particular colour.
The same thing applies to the texture. With the naked eye one can see the gram, but otherwise the table looks
smooth and even. If we looked at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and valleys,
and all sorts of differences that are imperceptible to the naked eye. Which of these is the 'real' table? We are
naturally tempted to say that what we see through the microscope is more real, but that in turn would be
changed by a still more powerful microscope. If, then, we cannot trust what we see with the naked eye, why
should we trust what we see through a microscope? Thus, again, the confidence in our senses with which we
began deserts us.
The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the 'real' shapes of things, and we
do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see the real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to
learn if we try to draw, a given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view. If our table
is 'really' rectangular, it will look, from almost all points of view, as if it had two acute angles and two obtuse
angles. If opposite sides are parallel, they will look as if they converged to a point away from the spectator; if
they are of equal length, they will look as if the nearer side were longer. All these things are not commonly
noticed in looking at a table, because experience has taught us to construct the 'real' shape from the apparent
shape, and the 'real' shape is what interests us as practical men. But the 'real' shape is not what we see; it is
something inferred from what we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we, move about
the room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the table itself, but only about the
appearance of the table.
Similar difficulties arise when we consider the sense of touch. It is true that the table always gives us a
sensation of hardness, and we feel that it resists pressure. But the sensation we obtain depends upon how hard
we press the table and also upon what part of the body we press with; thus the various sensations due to
various pressures or various parts of the body cannot be supposed to reveal directly any definite property of
the table, but at most to be signs of some property which perhaps causes all the sensations, but is not actually
apparent in any of them. And the same applies still more obviously to the sounds which can be elicited by
rapping the table.
Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience
by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must be
an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two very difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1)
Is there a real table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?
It will help us in considering these questions to have a few simple terms of which the meaning is definite and
clear. Let us give the name of 'sensedata' to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things
as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. We shall give the name 'sensation' to the
experience of being immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we have a sensation
of the colour, but the colour itself is a sensedatum, not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are
immediately aware, and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to know anything about
the table, it must be by means of the sensedata brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc. which
we associate with the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say that the table is the
sensedata, or even that the sensedata are directly properties of the table. Thus a problem arises as to the
relation of the sensedata to the real table, supposing there is such a thing.
The real table, if it exists, we will call a 'physical object'. Thus we have to consider the relation of sensedata
to physical objects. The collection of all physical objects is called 'matter'. Thus our two questions may be
restated as follows: (1) Is there any such thing as matter? (2) If so, what is its nature?
The Problems of Philosophy
The Problems of Philosophy 3
Page No 6
The philosopher who first brought prominently forward the reasons for regarding the immediate objects of
our senses as not existing independently of us was Bishop Berkeley (16851753). His Three Dialogues
between Hylas and Philonous, in Opposition to Sceptics and Atheists, undertake to prove that there is no such
thing as matter at all, and that the world consists of nothing but minds and their ideas. Hylas has hitherto
believed in matter, but he is no match for Philonous, who mercilessly drives him into contradictions and
paradoxes, and makes his own denial of matter seem, in the end, as if it were almost common sense. The
arguments employed are of very different value: some are important and sound, others are confused or
quibbling. But Berkeley retains the merit of having shown that the existence of matter is capable of being
denied without absurdity, and that if there are any things that exist independently of us they cannot be the
immediate objects of our sensations.
There are two different questions involved when we ask whether matter exists, and it is important to keep
them clear. We commonly mean by 'matter' something which is opposed to 'mind', something which we think
of as occupying space and as radically incapable of any sort of thought or consciousness. It is chiefly in this
sense that Berkeley denies matter; that is to say, he does not deny that the sensedata which we commonly
take as signs of the existence of the table are really signs of the existence of something independent of us, but
he does deny that this something is nonmental, that it is neither mind nor ideas entertained by some mind. He
admits that there must be something which continues to exist when we go out of the room or shut our eyes,
and that what we call seeing the table does really give us reason for believing in something which persists
even when we are not seeing it. But he thinks that this something cannot be radically different in nature from
what we see, and cannot be independent of seeing altogether, though it must be independent of our seeing. He
is thus led to regard the 'real' table as an idea in the mind of God. Such an idea has the required permanence
and independence of ourselves, without being as matter would otherwise be something quite
unknowable, in the sense that we can only infer it, and can never be directly and immediately aware of it.
Other philosophers since Berkeley have also held that, although the table does not depend for its existence
upon being seen by me, it does depend upon being seen (or otherwise apprehended in sensation) by some
mind not necessarily the mind of God, but more often the whole collective mind of the universe. This they
hold, as Berkeley does, chiefly because they think there can be nothing real or at any rate nothing known
to be real except minds and their thoughts and feelings. We might state the argument by which they support
their view in some such way as this: 'Whatever can be thought of is an idea in the mind of the person thinking
of it; therefore nothing can be thought of except ideas in minds; therefore anything else is inconceivable, and
what is inconceivable cannot exist.'
Such an argument, in my opinion, is fallacious; and of course those who advance it do not put it so shortly or
so crudely. But whether valid or not, the argument has been very widely advanced in one form or another;
and very many philosophers, perhaps a majority, have held that there is nothing real except minds and their
ideas. Such philosophers are called 'idealists'. When they come to explaining matter, they either say, like
Berkeley, that matter is really nothing but a collection of ideas, or they say, like Leibniz (16461716), that
what appears as matter is really a collection of more or less rudimentary minds.
But these philosophers, though they deny matter as opposed to mind, nevertheless, in another sense, admit
matter. It will be remembered that we asked two questions; namely, (1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If so,
what sort of object can it be? Now both Berkeley and Leibniz admit that there is a real table, but Berkeley
says it is certain ideas in the mind of God, and Leibniz says it is a colony of souls. Thus both of them answer
our first question in the affirmative, and only diverge from the views of ordinary mortals in their answer to
our second question. In fact, almost all philosophers seem to be agreed that there is a real table. they almost
all agree that, however much our sensedata colour, shape, smoothness, etc. may depend upon us, yet
their occurrence is a sign of something existing independently of us, something differing, perhaps, completely
from our sensedata whenever we are in a suitable relation to the real table.
The Problems of Philosophy
The Problems of Philosophy 4
Page No 7
Now obviously this point in which the philosophers are agreed the view that there is a real table, whatever
its nature may be is vitally important, and it will be worth while to consider what reasons there are for
accepting this view before we go on to the further question as to the nature of the real table. Our next chapter,
therefore, will be concerned with the reasons for supposing that there is a real table at all.
Before we go farther it will be well to consider for a moment what it is that we have discovered so far. It has
appeared that, if we take any common object of the sort that is supposed to be known by the senses, what the
senses immediately tell us is not the truth about the object as it is apart from us, but only the truth about
certain sensedata which, so far as we can see, depend upon the relations between us and the object. Thus
what we directly see and feel is merely 'appearance', which we believe to be a sign of some 'reality' behind.
But if the reality is not what appears, have we any means of knowing whether there is any reality at all? And
if so, have we any means of finding out what it is like?
Such questions are bewildering, and it is difficult to know that even the strangest hypotheses may not be true.
Thus our familiar table, which has roused but the slightest thoughts in us hitherto, has become a problem full
of surprising possibilities. The one thing we know about it is that it is not what it seems. Beyond this modest
result, so far, we have the most complete liberty of conjecture. Leibniz tells us it is a community of souls:
Berkeley tells us it is an idea in the mind of God; sober science, scarcely less wonderful, tells us it is a vast
collection of electric charges in violent motion.
Among these surprising possibilities, doubt suggests that perhaps there is no table at all. Philosophy, if it
cannot answer so many questions as we could wish, has at least the power of asking questions which increase
the interest of the world, and show the strangeness and wonder lying just below the surface even in the
commonest things of daily life.
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER
IN this chapter we have to ask ourselves whether, in any sense at all, there is such a thing as matter. Is there a
table which has a certain intrinsic nature, and continues to exist when I am not looking, or is the table merely
a product of my imagination, a dreamtable in a very prolonged dream? This question is of the greatest
importance. For if we cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we cannot be sure of the
independent existence of other people's bodies, and therefore still less of other people's minds, since we have
no grounds for believing in their minds except such as are derived from observing their bodies. Thus if we
cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we shall be left alone in a desert it may be that the
whole outer world is nothing but a dream, and that we alone exist. This is an uncomfortable possibility; but
although it cannot be strictly proved to be false, there is not the slightest reason to suppose that it is true. In
this chapter we have to see why this is the case.
Before we embark upon doubtful matters, let us try to find some more or less fixed point from which to start.
Although we are doubting the physical existence of the table, we are not doubting the existence of the
sensedata which made us think there was a table; we are not doubting that, while we look, a certain colour
and shape appear to us, and while we press, a certain sensation of hardness is experienced by us. All this,
which is psychological, we are not calling in question. In fact, whatever else may be doubtful, some at least
of our immediate experiences seem absolutely certain.
Descartes (15961650), the founder of modern philosophy, invented a method which may still be used with
profit the method of systematic doubt. He determined that he would believe nothing which he did not see
quite clearly and distinctly to be true. Whatever he could bring himself to doubt, he would doubt, until he saw
reason for not doubting it. By applying this method he gradually became convinced that the only existence of
which he could be quite certain was own. He imagined a deceitful demon, who presented unreal things to his
senses in a perpetual phantasmagoria; it might be very improbable that such a demon existed, but still it was
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER 5
Page No 8
possible, and therefore doubt concerning things perceived by the senses was possible.
But doubt concerning his own existence was not possible, for if he did not exist, no demon could deceive
him. If he doubted, he must exist; if he had any experiences whatever, he must exist. Thus his own existence
was an absolute certainty to him. 'I think, therefore I am, ' he said (Cogito, ergo sum); and on the basis of this
certainty he set to work to build up again the world of knowledge which his doubt had laid in ruins. By
inventing the method of doubt, and by showing that subjective things are the most certain, Descartes
performed a great service to philosophy, and one which makes him still useful to all students of the subject.
But some care is needed in using Descartes' argument. 'I think, therefore I am' says rather more than is strictly
certain. It might seem as though we were quite sure of being the same person today as we were yesterday,
and this is no doubt true in some sense. But the real Self is as hard to arrive at as the real table and does not
seem to have that absolute, convincing certainty that belongs to particular experiences. When I look at my
table and see a certain brown colour, what is quite certain at once is not 'I am seeing a brown colour', but
rather, 'a brown colour is being seen'. This of course involves something (or somebody) which (or who) sees
the brown colour; but it does not of itself involve that more or less permanent person whom we call 'I'. So far
as immediate certainty goes, it might be that the something which sees the brown colour is quite momentary,
and not the same as the something which has some different experience the next moment.
Thus it is our particular thoughts and feelings that have primitive certainty. And this applies to dreams and
hallucinations as well as to normal perceptions: when we dream or see a ghost, we certainly do have the
sensations we think we have, but for various reasons it is held that no physical object corresponds to these
sensations. Thus the certainty of our knowledge of our own experiences does not have to be limited in any
way to allow for exceptional cases. Here, therefore, we have, for what it is worth, a solid basis from which to
begin our pursuit of knowledge.
The problem we have to consider is this: Granted that we are certain of our own sensedata, have we any
reason for regarding them as signs of the existence of something else, which we can call the physical object?
When we have enumerated all the sensedata which we should naturally regard as connected with the table
have we said all there is to say about the table, or is there still something else something not a
sensedatum, something which persists when we go out of the room? Common sense unhesitatingly answers
that there is. What can be bought and sold and pushed about and have a cloth laid on it, and so on, cannot be a
mere collection of sensedata. If the cloth completely hides the table, we shall derive no sensedata from the
table, and therefore, if the table were merely sensedata, it would have ceased to exist, and the cloth would
be suspended in empty air, resting, by a miracle, in the place where the table formerly was. This seems
plainly absurd; but whoever wishes to become a philosopher must learn not to be frightened by absurdities.
One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object in addition to the sensedata, is that we
want the same object for different people. When ten people are sitting round a dinnertable, it seems
preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same tablecloth, the same knives and forks and spoons
and glasses. But the sensedata are private to each separate person; what is immediately present to the sight
of one is not immediately present to the sight of another: they all see things from slightly different points of
view, and therefore see them slightly differently. Thus, if there are to be public neutral objects, which can be
m some sense known to many different people, there must be something over and above the private and
particular sensedata which appear to various people. What reason, then, have we for believing that there are
such public neutral objects?
The first answer that naturally occurs to one is that, although different people may see the table slightly
differently, still they all see more or less similar things when they look at the table, and the variations in what
they see follow the laws of perspective and reflection of light, so that it is easy to arrive at a permanent object
underlying all the different people's sensedata. I bought my table from the former occupant of my room; I
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER 6
Page No 9
could not buy his sensedata, which died when he went away, but I could and did buy the confident
expectation of more or less similar sensedata. Thus it is the fact that different people have similar
sensedata, and that one person in a given place at different times has similar sensedata, which makes us
suppose that over and above the sensedata there is a permanent public object which underlies or causes the
sensedata of various people at various times.
Now in so far as the above considerations depend upon supposing that there are other people besides
ourselves, they beg the very question at issue. Other people are represented to me by certain sensedata, such
as the sight of them or the sound of their voices, and if I had no reason to believe that there were physical
objects independent of my sensedata, I should have no reason to believe that other people exist except as
part of my dream. Thus, when we are trying to show that there must be objects independent of our own
sensedata, we cannot appeal to the testimony of other people, since this testimony itself consists of
sensedata, and does not reveal other people's experiences unless our own sensedata are signs of things
existing independently of us. We must therefore, if possible, find, in our own purely private experiences,
characteristics which show, or tend to show, that there are in the world things other than ourselves and our
private experiences.
In one sense it must be admitted that we can never prove the existence of things other than ourselves and our
experiences. No logical absurdity results from the hypothsis that the world consists of myself and my
thoughts and feelings and sensations, and that everything else is mere fancy. In dreams a very complicated
world may seem to be present, and yet on waking we find it was a delusion; that is to say, we find that the
sensedata in the dream do not appear to have corresponded with such physical objects as we should
naturally infer from our sensedata. (It is true that, when the physical world is assumed, it is possible to find
physical causes for the sensedata in dreams: a door banging, for instance, may cause us to dream of a naval
engagement. But although, in this case, there is a physical cause for the sensedata, there is not a physical
object corresponding to the sensedata in the way in which an actual naval battle would correspond.) There is
no logical impossibility in the supposition that the whole of life is a dream, in which we ourselves create all
the objects that come before us. But although this is not logically impossible, there is no reason whatever to
suppose that it is true; and it is, in fact, a less simple hypothesis, viewed as a means of accounting for the
facts of our own life, than the commonsense hypothesis that there really are objects independent of us,
whose action on us causes our sensations.
The way in which simplicity comes in from supposing that there really are physical objects is easily seen. If
the cat appears at one moment in one part of the room, and at another in another part, it is natural to suppose
that it has moved from the one to the other, passing over a series of intermediate positions. But if it is merely
a set of sensedata, it cannot have ever been in any place where I did not see it; thus we shall have to suppose
that it did not exist at all while I was not looking, but suddenly sprang into being in a new place. If the cat
exists whether I see it or not, we can understand from our own experience how it gets hungry between one
meal and the next; but if it does not exist when I am not seeing it, it seems odd that appetite should grow
during nonexistence as fast as during existence. And if the cat consists only of sensedata, it cannot be
hungry, since no hunger but my own can be a sensedatum to me. Thus the behaviour of the sensedata
which represent the cat to me, though it seems quite natural when regarded as an expression of hunger,
becomes utterly inexplicable when regarded as mere movements and changes of patches of colour, which are
as incapable of hunger as triangle is of playing football.
But the difficulty in the case of the cat is nothing compared to the difficulty in the case of human beings.
When human beings speak that is, when we hear certain noises which we associate with ideas, and
simultaneously see certain motions of lips and expressions of face it is very difficult to suppose that what
we hear is not the expression of a thought, as we know it would be if we emitted the same sounds. Of course
similar things happen in dreams, where we are mistaken as to the existence of other people. But dreams are
more or less suggested by what we call waking life, and are capable of being more or less accounted for on
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER 7
Page No 10
scientific principles if we assume that there really is a physical world. Thus every principle of simplicity
urges us to adopt the natural view, that there really are objects other than ourselves and our sensedata which
have an existence not dependent upon our perceiving them.
Of course it is not by argument that we originally come by our belief in an independent external world. We
find this belief ready in ourselves as soon as we begin to reflect: it is what may be called an instinctive belief.
We should never have been led to question this belief but for the fact that, at any rate in the case of sight, it
seems as if the sensedatum itself were instinctively believed to be the independent object, whereas argument
shows that the object cannot be identical with the sensedatum. This discovery, however which is not at
all paradoxical in the case of taste and smell and sound, and only slightly so in the case of touch leaves
undiminished our instinctive belief that there are objects corresponding to our sensedata. Since this belief
does not lead to any difficulties, but on the contrary tends to simplify and systematize our account of our
experiences, there seems no good reason for rejecting it. We may therefore admit though with a slight
doubt derived from dreams that the external world does really exist, and is not wholly dependent for its
existence upon our continuing to perceive it.
The argument which has led us to this conclusion is doubtless less strong than we could wish, but it is typical
of many philosophical arguments, and it is therefore worth while to consider briefly its general character and
validity. All knowledge, we find, must be built up upon our instinctive beliefs, and if these are rejected,
nothing is left. But among our instinctive beliefs some are much stronger than others, while many have, by
habit and association, become entangled with other beliefs, not really instinctive, but falsely supposed to be
part of what is believed instinctively.
Philosophy should show us the hierarchy of our instinctive beliefs, beginning with those we hold most
strongly, and presenting each as much isolated and as free from irrelevant additions as possible. It should take
care to show that, in the form in which they are finally set forth, our instinctive beliefs do not clash, but form
a harmonious system. There can never be any reason for rejecting one instinctive belief except that it clashes
with others; thus, if they are found to harmonize, the whole system becomes worthy of acceptance.
It is of course possible that all or any of our beliefs may be mistaken, and therefore all ought to be held with
at least some slight element of doubt. But we cannot have reason to reject a belief except on the ground of
some other belief. Hence, by organizing our instinctive beliefs and their consequences, by considering which
among them is most possible, if necessary, to modify or abandon, we can arrive, on the basis of accepting as
our sole data what we instinctively believe, at an orderly systematic organization of our knowledge, in which,
though the possibility of error remains, its likelihood is diminished by the interrelation of the parts and by the
critical scrutiny which has preceded acquiescence.
This function, at least, philosophy can perform. Most philosophers, rightly or wrongly, believe that
philosophy can do much more than this that it can give us knowledge, not otherwise attainable,
concerning the universe as a whole, and concerning the nature of ultimate reality. Whether this be the case or
not, the more modest function we have spoken of can certainly be performed by philosophy, and certainly
suffices, for those who have once begun to doubt the adequacy of common sense, to justify the arduous and
difficult labours that philosophical problems involve.
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER
IN the preceding chapter we agreed, though without being able to find demonstrative reasons, that it is
rational to believe that our sensedata for example, those which we regard as associated with my table
are really signs of the existence of something independent of us and our perceptions. That is to say, over and
above the sensations of colour, hardness, noise, and so on, which make up the appearance of the table to me, I
assume that there is something else, of which these things are appearances. The colour ceases to exist if I shut
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER 8
Page No 11
my eyes, the sensation of hardness ceases to exist if I remove my arm from contact with the table, the sound
ceases to exist if I cease to rap the table with my knuckles. But I do not believe that when all these things
cease the table ceases. On the contrary, I believe that it is because the table exists continuously that all these
sensedata will reappear when I open my eyes, replace my arm, and begin again to rap with my knuckles.
The question we have to consider in this chapter is: What is the nature of this real table, which persists
independently of my perception of it?
To this question physical science gives an answer, somewhat incomplete it is true, and in part still very
hypothetical, but yet deserving of respect so far as it goes. Physical science, more or less unconsciously, has
drifted into the view that all natural phenomena ought to be reduced to motions. Light and heat and sound are
all due to wavemotions, which travel from the body emitting them to the person who sees light or feels heat
or hears sound. That which has the wavemotion is either aether or 'gross matter', but in either case is what
the philosopher would call matter. The only properties which science assigns to it are position in space, and
the power of motion according to the laws of motion. Science does not deny that it may have other properties;
but if so, such other properties are not useful to the man of science, and in no way assist him in explaining the
phenomena.
It is sometimes said that 'light is a form of wavemotion', but this is misleading, for the light which we
immediately see, which we know directly by means of our senses, is not a form of wavemotion, but
something quite different something which we all know if we are not blind, though we cannot describe it
so as to convey our knowledge to a man who is blind. A wavemotion, on the contrary, could quite well be
described to a blind man, since he can acquire a knowledge of space by the sense of touch; and he can
experience a wavemotion by a sea voyage almost as well as we can. But this, which a blind man can
understand, is not what we mean by light: we mean by light just that which a blind man can never understand,
and which we can never describe to him.
Now this something, which all of us who are not blind know, is not, according to science, really to be found
in the outer world: it is something caused by the action of certain waves upon the eyes and nerves and brain
of the person who sees the light. When it is said that light is waves, what is really meant is that waves are the
physical cause of our sensations of light. But light itself, the thing which seeing people experience and blind
people do not, is not supposed by science to form any part of the world that is independent of us and our
senses . And very similar remarks would apply to other kinds of sensations.
It is not only colours and sounds and so on that are absent from the scientific world of matter, but also space
as we get it through sight or touch. It is essential to science that its matter should be in a space, but the space
in which it is cannot be exactly the space we see or feel. To begin with, space as we see it is not the same as
space as we get it by the sense of touch; it is only by experience in infancy that we learn how to touch things
we see, or how to get a sight of things which we feel touching us. But the space of science is neutral as
between touch and sight; thus it cannot be either the space of touch or the space of sight.
Again, different people see the same object as of different shapes, according to their point of view. A circular
coin, for example, though we should always judge it to be circular, will look oval unless we are straight in
front of it. When we judge that it is circular, we are judging that it has a real shape which is not its apparent
shape, but belongs to it intrinsically apart from its appearance. But this real shape, which is what concerns
science, must be in a real space, not the same as anybody's apparent space. The real space is public, the
apparent space is private to the percipient. In different people's private spaces the same object seems to have
different shapes; thus the real space, in which it has its real shape, must be different from the private spaces.
The space of science, therefore, though connected with the spaces we see and feel, is not identical with them,
and the manner of its connexion requires investigation.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER 9
Page No 12
We agreed provisionally that physical objects cannot be quite like our sensedata, but may be regarded as
causing our sensations. These physical objects are in the space of science, which we may call 'physical' space.
It is important to notice that, if our sensations are to be caused by physical objects, there must be a physical
space containing these objects and our senseorgans and nerves and brain. We get a sensation of touch from
an object when we are in contact with it; that is to say, when some part of our body occupies a place in
physical space quite close to the space occupied by the object. We see an object (roughly speaking) when no
opaque body is between the object and our eyes in physical space. Similarly, we only hear or smell or taste an
object when we are sufficiently near to it, or when it touches the tongue, or has some suitable position in
physical space relatively to our body. We cannot begin to state what different sensations we shall derive from
a given object under different circumstances unless we regard the object and our body as both in one physical
space, for it is mainly the relative positions of the object and our body that determine what sensations we
shall derive from the object.
Now our sensedata are situated in our private spaces, either the space of sight or the space of touch or such
vaguer spaces as other senses may give us. If, as science and common sense assume, there is one public
allembracing physical space in which physical objects are, the relative positions of physical objects in
physical space must more or less correspond to the relative positions of sensedata in our private spaces.
There is no difficulty in supposing this to be the case. If we see on a road one house nearer to us than another,
our other senses will bear out the view that it is nearer; for example, it will be reached sooner if we walk
along the road. Other people will agree that the house which looks nearer to us is nearer; the ordnance map
will take the same view; and thus everything points to a spatial relation between the houses corresponding to
the relation between the sensedata which we see when we look at the houses. Thus we may assume that
there is a physical space in which physical objects have spatial relations corresponding to those which the
corresponding sensedata have in our private spaces. It is this physical space which is dealt with in geometry
and assumed in physics and astronomy.
Assuming that there is physical space, and that it does thus correspond to private spaces, what can we know
about it? We can know only what is required in order to secure the correspondence. That is to say, we can
know nothing of what it is like in itself, but we can know the sort of arrangement of physical objects which
results from their spatial relations. We can know, for example, that the earth and moon and sun are in one
straight line during an eclipse, though we cannot know what a physical straight line is in itself, as we know
the look of a straight line in our visual space. Thus we come to know much more about the relations of
distances in physical space than about the distances themselves; we may know that one distance is greater
than another, or that it is along the same straight line as the other, but we cannot have that immediate
acquaintance with physical distances that we have with distances in our private spaces, or with colours or
sounds or other sensedata. We can know all those things about physical space which a man born blind might
know through other people about the space of sight; but the kind of things which a man born blind could
never know about the space of sight we also cannot know about physical space. We can know the properties
of the relations required to preserve the correspondence with sensedata, but we cannot know the nature of
the terms between which the relations hold.
With regard to time, our feeling of duration or of the lapse of time is notoriously an unsafe guide as to the
time that has elapsed by the clock. Times when we are bored or suffering pain pass slowly, times when we
are agreeably occupied pass quickly, and times when we are sleeping pass almost as if they did not exist.
Thus, in so far as time is constituted by duration, there is the same necessity for distinguishing a public and a
private time as there was in the case of space. But in so far as time consists in an order of before and after,
there is no need to make such a distinction; the timeorder which events seem to have is, so far as we can see,
the same as the timeorder which they do have. At any rate no reason can be given for supposing that the two
orders are not the same. The same is usually true of space: if a regiment of men are marching along a road,
the shape of the regiment will look different from different points of view, but the men will appear arranged
in the same order from all points of view. Hence we regard the order as true also in physical space, whereas
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER 10
Page No 13
the shape is only supposed to correspond to the physical space so far as is required for the preservation of the
order.
In saying that the timeorder which events seem to have is the same as the timeorder which they really
have, it is necessary to guard against a possible misunderstanding. It must not be supposed that the various
states of different physical objects have the same timeorder as the sensedata which constitute the
perceptions of those objects. Considered as physical objects, the thunder and lightning are simultaneous; that
is to say, the lightning is simultaneous with the disturbance of the air in the place where the disturbance
begins, namely, where the lightning is. But the sensedatum which we call hearing the thunder does not take
place until the disturbance of the air has travelled as far as to where we are. Similarly, it takes about eight
minutes for the sun's light to reach us; thus, when we see the sun we are seeing the sun of eight minutes ago.
So far as our sensedata afford evidence as to the physical sun they afford evidence as to the physical sun of
eight minutes ago; if the physical sun had ceased to exist within the last eight minutes, that would make no
difference to the sensedata which we call 'seeing the sun'. This affords a fresh illustration of the necessity of
distinguishing between sensedata and physical objects.
What we have found as regards space is much the same as what we find in relation to the correspondence of
the sensedata with their physical counterparts. If one object looks blue and another red, we may reasonably
presume that there is some corresponding difference between the physical objects; if two objects both look
blue, we may presume a corresponding similarity. But we cannot hope to be acquainted directly with the
quality in the physical object which makes it look blue or red. Science tells us that this quality is a certain sort
of wavemotion, and this sounds familiar, because we think of wavemotions in the space we see. But the
wavemotions must really be in physical space, with which we have no direct acquaintance; thus the real
wavemotions have not that familiarity which we might have supposed them to have. And what holds for
colours is closely similar to what holds for other sensedata. Thus we find that, although the relations of
physical objects have all sorts of knowable properties, derived from their correspondence with the relations of
sensedata, the physical objects themselves remain unknown in their intrinsic nature, so far at least as can be
discovered by means of the senses. The question remains whether there is any other method of discovering
the intrinsic nature of physical objects.
The most natural, though not ultimately the most defensible, hypothesis to adopt in the first instance, at any
rate as regards visual sensedata, would be that, though physical objects cannot, for the reasons we have been
considering, be exactly like sensedata, yet they may be more or less like. According to this view, physical
objects will, for example, really have colours, and we might, by good luck, see an object as of the colour it
really is. The colour which an object seems to have at any given moment will in general be very similar,
though not quite the same, from many different points of view; we might thus uppose the 'real' colour to be a
sort of medium colour, intermediate between the various shades which appear from the different points of
view.
Such a theory is perhaps not capable of being definitely refuted, but it can be shown to be groundless. To
begin with, it is plain that the colour we see depends only upon the nature of the lightwaves that strike the
eye, and is therefore modified by the medium intervening between us and the object, as well as by the manner
in which light is reflected from the object in the direction of the eye. The intervening air alters colours unless
it is perfectly clear, and any strong reflection will alter them completely. Thus the colour we see is a result of
the ray as it reaches the eye, and not simply a property of the object from which the ray comes. Hence, also,
provided certain waves reach the eye, we shall see a certain colour, whether the object from which the waves
start has any colour or not. Thus it is quite gratuitous to suppose that physical objects have colours, and
therefore there is no justification for making such a supposition. Exactly similar arguments will apply to other
sensedata.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER 11
Page No 14
It remains to ask whether there are any general philosophical arguments enabling us to say that, if matter is
real, it must be of such and such a nature. A explained above, very many philosophers, perhaps most, have
held that whatever is real must be in some sense mental, or at any rate that whatever we can know anything
about must be in some sense mental. Such philosophers are called 'idealists'. Idealists tell us that what appears
as matter is really something mental; namely, either (as Leibniz held) more or less rudimentary minds, or (as
Berkeley contended) ideas in the minds which, as we should commonly say, 'perceive' the matter. Thus
idealists deny the existence of matter as something intrinsically different from mind, though they do not deny
that our sensedata are signs of something which exists independently of our private sensations. In the
following chapter we shall consider briefly the reasons in my opinion fallacious which idealists
advance in favour of their theory.
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM
THE word 'idealism' is used by different philosophers in somewhat different senses. We shall understand by
it the doctrine that whatever exists, or at any rate whatever can be known to exist, must be in some sense
mental. This doctrine, which is very widely held among philosophers, has several forms, and is advocated on
several different grounds. The doctrine is so widely held, and so interesting in itself, that even the briefest
survey of philosophy must give some account of it.
Those who are unaccustomed to philosophical speculation may be inclined to dismiss such a doctrine as
obviously absurd. There is no doubt that common sense regards tables and chairs and the sun and moon and
material objects generally as something radically different from minds and the contents of minds, and as
having an existence which might continue if minds ceased. We think of matter as having existed long before
there were any minds, and it is hard to think of it as a mere product of mental activity. But whether true or
false, idealism is not to be dismissed as obviously absurd.
We have seen that, even if physical objects do have an independent existence, they mus differ very widely
from sensedata, and can only have a correspondence with sensedata, in the same sort of way in which a
catalogue has a correspondence with the things catalogued. Hence common sense leaves us completely in the
dark as to the true intrinsic nature of physical objects, and if there were good reason to regard them as mental,
we could not legitimately reject this opinion merely because it strikes us as strange. The truth about physical
objects must be strange. It may be unattainable, but if any philosopher believes that he has attained it, the fact
that what he offers as the truth is strange ought not to be made a ground of objection to his opinion.
The grounds on which idealism is advocated are generally grounds derived from the theory of knowledge,
that is to say, from a discussion of the conditions which things must satisfy in order that we may be able to
know them. The first serious attempt to establish idealism on such grounds was that of Bishop Berkeley. He
proved first, by arguments which were largely valid, that our sensedata cannot be supposed to have an
existence independent of us, but must be, in part at least, 'in' the mind, in the sense that their existence would
not continue if there were no seeing or hearing or touching or smelling or tasting. So far, his contention was
almost certainly valid, even if some of his arguments were not so. But he went on to argue that sensedata
were the only things of whose existence our perceptions could assure us, and that to be known is to be 'in' a
mind, and therefore to be mental. Hence he concluded that nothing can ever be known except what is in some
mind, and that whatever is known without being in my mind must be in some other mind.
In order to understand his argument, it is necessary to understand his use of the word 'idea'. He gives the
name 'idea' to anything which is immediately known, as, for example, sensedata are known Thus a
particular colour which we see is an idea; so is a voice which we hear, and so on. But the term is not wholly
confined to sensedata. There will also be things remembered or imagined, for with such things also we have
immediate acquaintance at the moment of remembering or imagining. All such immediate data he calls
'ideas'.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM 12
Page No 15
He then proceeds to consider common objects, such as a tree, for instance. He shows that all we know
immediately when we 'perceive' the tree consists of ideas in his sense of the word, and he argues that there is
not the slightest ground for supposing that there is anything real about the tree except what is perceived. Its
being, he says, consists in being perceived: in the Latin of the schoolmen its 'esse' is 'percipi'. He fully admits
that the tree must continue to exist even when we shut our eyes or when no human being is near it. But this
continued existence, he says, is due to the fact that God continues to perceive it; the 'real' tree, which
corresponds to what we called the physical object, consists of ideas in the mind of God, ideas more or less
like those we have when we see the tree, but differing in the fact that they are permanent in God's mind so
long as the tree continues to exist. All our perceptions, according to him, consist in a partial participation in
God's perceptions, and it is because of this participation that different people see more or less the same tree.
Thus apart from minds and their ideas there is nothing in the world, nor is it possible that anything else
should ever be known, since whatever is known is necessarily an idea.
There are in this argument a good many fallacies which have been important in the history of philosophy, and
which it will be as well to bring to light. In the first place, there is a confusion engendered by the use of the
word 'idea'. We think of an idea as essentially something in somebody's mind, and thus when we are told that
a tree consists entirely of ideas, it is natural to suppose that, if so, the tree must be entirely in minds. But the
notion of being 'in' the mind is ambiguous. We speak of bearing a person in mind, not meaning that the
person is in our minds, but that a thought of him is in our minds. When a man says that some business he had
to arrange went clean out of his mind, he does not mean to imply that the business itself was ever in his mind,
but only that a thought of the business was formerly in his mind, but afterwards ceased to be in his mind. And
so when Berkeley says that the tree must be in our minds if we can know it, all that he really has a right to say
is that a thought of the tree must be in our minds. To argue that the tree itself must be in our minds is like
arguing that a person whom we bear in mind is himself in our minds. This confusion may seem too gross to
have been really committed by any competent philosopher, but various attendant circumstances rendered it
possible. In order to see how it was possible, we must go more deeply into the question as to the nature of
ideas.
Before taking up the general question of the nature of ideas, we must disentangle two entirely separate
questions which arise concerning sensedata and physical objects. We saw that, for various reasons of detail,
Berkeley was right in treating the sensedata which constitute our perception of the tree as more or less
subjective, in the sense that they depend upon us as much as upon the tree, and would not exist if the tree
were not being perceived. But this is an entirely different point from the one by which Berkeley seeks to
prove that whatever can be immediately known must be in a mind. For this purpose argument of detail as to
the dependence of sensedata upon us are useless. It is necessary to prove, generally, that by being known,
things are shown to be mental. This is what Berkeley believes himself to have done. It is this question, and
not our previous question as to the difference between sensedata and the physical object, that must now
concern us.
Taking the word 'idea' in Berkeley's sense, there are two quite distinct things to be considered whenever an
idea is before the mind. There is on the one hand the thing of which we are aware say the colour of my
table and on the other hand the actual awareness itself, the mental act of apprehending the thing. The
mental act is undoubtedly mental, but is there any reason to suppose that the thing apprehended is in any
sense mental? Our previous arguments concerning the colour did not prove it to be mental; they only proved
that its existence depends upon the relation of our sense organs to the physical object in our case, the
table. That is to say, they proved that a certain colour will exist, in a certain light, if a normal eye is placed at
a certain point relatively to the table. They did not prove that the colour is in the mind of the percipient.
Berkeley's view, that obviously the colour must be in the mind, seems to depend for its plausibility upon
confusing the thing apprehended with the act of apprehension. Either of these might be called an 'idea';
probably either would have been called an idea by Berkeley. The act is undoubtedly in the mind; hence, when
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM 13
Page No 16
we are thinking of the act, we readily assent to the view that ideas must be in the mind. Then, forgetting that
this was only true when ideas were taken as acts of apprehension, we transfer the proposition that 'ideas are in
the mind' to ideas in the other sense, i.e. to the things apprehended by our acts of apprehension. Thus, by an
unconscious equivocation, we arrive at the conclusion that whatever we can apprehend must be in our minds.
This seems to be the true analysis of Berkeley's argument, and the ultimate fallacy upon which it rests.
This question of the distinction between act and object in our apprehending of things is vitally important,
since our whole power of acquiring knowledge is bound up with it. The faculty of being acquainted with
things other than itself is the main characteristic of a mind. Acquaintance with objects essentially consists in a
relation between the mind and something other than the mind; it is this that constitutes the mind's power of
knowing things. If we say that the things known must be in the mind, we are either unduly limiting the mind's
power of knowing, or we are uttering a mere tautology. We are uttering a mere tautology if we mean by 'in
the mind' the same as by 'before the mind', i.e. if we mean merely being apprehended by the mind. But if we
mean this, we shall have to admit that what, in this sense, is in the mind, may nevertheless be not mental.
Thus when we realize the nature of knowledge, Berkeley's argument is seen to be wrong in substance as well
as in form, and his grounds for supposing that 'ideas' i.e. the objects apprehended must be mental, are
found to have no validity whatever. Hence his grounds in favour of idealism may be dismissed. It remains to
see whether there are any other grounds.
It is often said, as though it were a selfevident truism, that we cannot know that anything exists which we do
not know. It is inferred that whatever can in any way be relevant to our experience must be at least capable of
being known by us; whence it follows that if matter were essentially something with which we could not
become acquainted, matter would be something which we could not know to exist, and which could have for
us no importance whatever. It is generally also implied, for reasons which remain obscure, that what can have
no importance for us cannot be real, and that therefore matter, if it is not composed of minds or of mental
ideas, is impossible and a mere chimaera.
To go into this argument fully at our present stage would be impossible, since it raises points requiring a
considerable preliminary discussion; but certain reasons for rejecting the argument may be noticed at once.
To begin at the end: there is no reason why what cannot have any practical importance for us should not be
real. It is true that, if theoretical importance is included, everything real is of some importance to us, since, as
persons desirous of knowing the truth about the universe, we have some interest in everything that the
universe contains. But if this sort of interest is included, it is not the case that matter has no importance for us,
provided it exists even if we cannot know that it exists. We can, obviously, suspect that it may exist, and
wonder whether it does; hence it is connected with our desire for knowledge, and has the importance of either
satisfying or thwarting this desire.
Again, it is by no means a truism, and is in fact false, that we cannot know that anything exists which we do
not know. The word 'know' is here used in two different senses. (1) In its first use it is applicable to the sort of
knowledge which is opposed to error, the sense in which what we know is true, the sense which applies to our
beliefs and convictions, i.e. to what are called judgements. In this sense of the word we know that something
is the case. This sort of knowledge may be described as knowledge of truths. (2) In the second use of the
word 'know' above, the word applies to our knowledge of things, which we may call acquaintance. This is the
sense in which we know sensedata. (The distinction involved is roughly that between savoir and conna”tre
in French, or between wissen and kennen in German.)
Thus the statement which seemed like a truism becomes, when restated, the following: 'We can never truly
judge that something with which we are not acquainted exists.' This is by no means a truism, but on the
contrary a palpable falsehood. I have not the honour to be acquainted with the Emperor of China, but I truly
judge that he exists. It may be said, of course, that I judge this because of other people's acquaintance with
him. This, however, would be an irrelevant retort, since, if the principle were true, I could not know that any
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM 14
Page No 17
one else is acquainted with him. But further: there is no reason why I should not know of the existence of
something with which nobody is acquainted. This point is important, and demands elucidation.
If I am acquainted with a thing which exists, my acquaintance gives me the knowledge that it exists. But it is
not true that, conversely, whenever I can know that a thing of a certain sort exists, I or some one else must be
acquainted with the thing. What happens, in cases where I have true judgement without acquaintance, is that
the thing is known to me by description, and that, in virtue of some general principle, the existence of a thing
answering to this description can be inferred from the existence of something with which I am acquainted. In
order to understand this point fully, it will be well first to deal with the difference between knowledge by
acquaintance and knowledge by description, and then to consider what knowledge of general principles, if
any, has the same kind of certainty as our knowledge of the existence of our own experiences. These subjects
will be dealt with in the following chapters.
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY
DESCRIPTION
IN the preceding chapter we saw that there are two sorts of knowledge: knowledge of things, and knowledge
of truths. In this chapter we shall be concerned exclusively with knowledge of things, of which in turn we
shall have to distinguish two kinds. Knowledge of things, when it is of the kind we call knowledge by
acquaintance, is essentially simpler than any knowledge of truths, and logically independent of knowledge of
truths, though it would be rash to assume that human beings ever, in fact, have acquaintance with things
without at the same time knowing some truth about them. Knowledge of things by description, on the
contrary, always involves, as we shall find in the course of the present chapter, some knowledge of truths as
its source and ground. But first of all we must make dear what we mean by 'acquaintance' and what we mean
by 'description'.
We shall say that we have acquaintance with anything of which we are directly aware, without the
intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truths. Thus in the presence of my table I am
acquainted with the sensedata that make up the appearance of my table its colour, shape, hardness,
smoothness, etc.; all these are things of which I am immediately conscious when I am seeing and touching
my table. The particular shade of colour that I am seeing may have many things said about it I may say
that it is brown, that it is rather dark, and so on. But such statements, though they make me know truths about
the colour, do not make me know the colour itself any better than I did before: so far a concerns knowledge
of the colour itself, as opposed to knowledge of truths about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely
when I see it, and no further knowledge of it itself is even theoretically possible. Thus the sensedata which
make up the appearance of my table are things with which I have acquaintance, things immediately known to
me just as they are.
My knowledge of the table as a physical object, on the contrary, is not direct knowledge. Such as it is, it is
obtained through acquaintance with the sensedata that make up the appearance of the table. We have seen
that it is possible, without absurdity, to doubt whet there is a table at all, whereas it is not possible to doubt
the sensedata. My knowledge of the table is of the kind which we shall call 'knowledge by description'. The
table is 'the physical object which causes suchandsuch sensedata'. This describes the table by means of
the sensedata. In order to know anything at all about the table, we must know truths connecting it with
things with which we have acquaintance: we must know that 'suchandsuch sensedata are caused by a
physical object'. There is no state of mind in which we are directly aware of the table; all our knowledge of
the table is really knowledge of truths, and the actual thing which is the table is not, strictly speaking, known
to us at all. We know a description and we know that there is just one object to which this description applies,
though the object itself is not directly known to us. In such a case, we say that our knowledge of the object is
knowledge by description.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION 15
Page No 18
All our knowledge, both knowledge of things and knowledge of truths, rests upon acquaintance as its
foundation. It is therefore important to consider what kinds of things there are with which we have
acquaintance.
Sensedata, as we have already seen, are among the things with which we are acquainted; in fact, they supply
the most obvious and striking example of knowledge by acquaintance. But if they were the sole example, our
knowledge would be very much more restricted than it is. We should only know what is now present to our
senses: we could not know anything about the past not even that there was a past nor could we know
any truths about our sensedata, for all knowledge of truths, as we shall show, demands acquaintance with
things which are of an essentially different character from sensedata, the things which are sometimes called
'abstract ideas', but which we shall call 'universals'. We have therefore to consider acquaintance with other
things besides sensedata if we are to obtain any tolerably adequate analysis of our knowledge.
The first extension beyond sensedata to be considered is acquaintance by memory. It is obvious that we
often remember what we have seen or heard or had otherwise present to our senses, and that in such cases we
are still immediately aware of what we remember, in spite of the fact that it appears as past and not as
present. This immediate knowledge by memory is the source of all our knowledge concerning the past:
without it, there could be no knowledge of the past by inference we should never know that there was
anything past to be inferred.
The next extension to be considered is acquaintance by introspection. We are not only aware of things, but
we are often aware of being aware of them. When I see the sun, I am often aware of my seeing the sun; thus
'my seeing the sun' is an object with which I have acquaintance. When I desire food, I may be aware of my
desire for food; thus 'my desiring food' is an object with which I am acquainted. Similarly we may be aware
of our feeling pleasure or pain, and generally of the events which happen in our minds. This kind of
acquaintance, which may be called selfconsciousness, is the source of all our knowledge of mental things. It
is obvious that it is only what goes on in our own minds that can be thus known immediately. What goes on
in the minds of others is known to us through our perception of their bodies, that is, the sensedata in us
which are associated with their bodies. But for our acquaintance with the contents of our own minds, we
should be unable to imagine the minds of others, and therefore we could never arrive at the knowledge that
they have minds. It seems natural to suppose that selfconsciousness is one of the things that distinguish men
from animals: animals, we may suppose, though they have acquaintance with sensedata, never become
aware of this acquaintance. I do not mean that they doubt whether they exist, but that they have never become
conscious of the fact that they have sensations and feelings, nor therefore of the fact that they, the subjects of
their sensations and feelings, exist.
We have spoken of acquaintance with the contents of our minds as selfconsciousness, but it is not, of
course, consciousness of our self: it is consciousness of particular thoughts and feelings. The question
whether we are also acquainted with our bare selves, as opposed to particular thoughts and feelings, is a very
difficult one, upon which it would be rash to speak positively. When we try to look into ourselves we always
seem to come upon some particular thought or feeling, and not upon the 'I' which has the thought or feeling.
Nevertheless there are some reasons for thinking that we are acquainted with the 'I', though the acquaintance
is hard to disentangle from other things. To make clear what sort of reason there is, let us consider for a
moment what our acquaintance with particular thoughts really involves.
When I am acquainted with 'my seeing the sun', it seems plain that I am acquainted with two different things
in relation to each other. On the one hand there is the sensedatum which represents the sun to me, on the
other hand there is that which sees this sensedatum. All acquaintance, such as my acquaintance with the
sensedatum which represents the sun, seems obviously a relation between the person acquainted and the
object with which the person is acquainted. When a case of acquaintance is one with which I can be
acquainted (as I am acquainted with my acquaintance with the sensedatum representing the sun), it is plain
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION 16
Page No 19
that the person acquainted is myself. Thus, when I am acquainted with my seeing the sun, the whole fact with
which I am acquainted is 'Selfacquaintedwithsensedatum'.
Further, we know the truth 'I am acquainted with this sensedatum'. It is hard to see how we could know this
truth, or even understand what is meant by it, unless we were acquainted with something which we call 'I'. It
does not seem necessary to suppose that we are acquainted with a more or less permanent person, the same
today as yesterday, but it does seem as though we must be acquainted with that thing, whatever its nature,
which sees the sun and has acquaintance with sensedata. Thus, in some sense it would seem we must be
acquainted with our Selves as opposed to our particular experiences. But the question is difficult, and
complicated arguments can be adduced on either side. Hence, although acquaintance with ourselves seems
probably to occur, it is not wise to assert that it undoubtedly does occur.
We may therefore sum up as follows what has been said concerning acquaintance with things that exist. We
have acquaintance in sensation with the data of the outer senses, and in introspection with the data of what
may be called the inner sense thoughts, feelings, desires, etc.; we have acquaintance in memory with
things which have been data either of the outer senses or of the inner sense. Further, it is probable, though not
certain, that we have acquaintance with Self, as that which is aware of things or has desires towards things.
In addition to our acquaintance with particular existing things, we also have acquaintance with what we shall
call universals, that is to say, general ideas such as whiteness, diversity, brotherhood, and so on. Every
complete sentence must contain at least one word which stands for a universal, since all verbs have a meaning
which is universal. We shall return to universals later on, in Chapter IX; for the present, it is only necessary to
guard against the supposition that whatever we can be acquainted with must be something particular and
existent. Awareness of universals is called conceiving, and a universal of which we are aware is called a
concept.
It will be seen that among the objects with which we are acquainted are not included physical objects (as
opposed to sensedata), nor other people's minds. These things are known to us by what I call 'knowledge by
description', which we must now consider.
By a 'description' I mean any phrase of the form 'a soandso' or 'the soandso'. A phrase of the form 'a
soandso' I shall call an 'ambiguous' description; a phrase of the form 'the soandso' (in the singular) I
shall call a 'definite' description. Thus 'a man' is an ambiguous description, and 'the man with the iron mask' is
a definite description. There are various problems connected with ambiguous descriptions, but I pass them
by, since they do not directly concern the matter we are discussing, which is the nature of our knowledge
concerning objects in cases where we know that there is an object answering to a definite description, though
we are not acquainted with any such object. This is a matter which is concerned exclusively with definite
descriptions. I shall therefore, in the sequel, speak simply of 'descriptions' when I mean 'definite descriptions'.
Thus a description will mean any phrase of the form 'the soandso' in the singular.
We say that an object is 'known by description' when we know that it is 'the soandso', i.e. when we know
that there is one object, and no more, having a certain property; and it will generally be implied that we do
not have knowledge of the same object by acquaintance. We know that the man with the iron mask existed,
and many propositions are known about him; but we do not know who he was. We know that the candidate
who gets the most votes will be elected, and in this case we are very likely also acquainted (in the only sense
in which one can be acquainted with some one else) with the man who is, in fact, the candidate who will get
most votes; but we do not know which of the candidates he is, i.e. we do do not know any proposition of the
form 'A is the candidate who will get most votes' where A is one of the candidates by name. We shall say that
we have 'merely descriptive knowledge' of the soandso when, although we know that the soandso
exists, and although we may possibly be acquainted with the object which is, in fact, the soandso, yet we
do not know any proposition 'a is the soandso', where a is something with which we are acquainted.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION 17
Page No 20
When we say 'the soandso exists', we mean that there is just one object which is the soandso. The
proposition 'a is the soandso' means that a has the property soandso, and nothing else has. 'Mr. A. is the
Unionist candidate for this constituency' means 'Mr. A. is a Unionist candidate for this constituency, and no
one else is'. 'The Unionist candidate for this constituency exists' means 'some one is a Unionist candidate for
this constituency, and no one else is'. Thus, when we are acquainted with an object which is the soandso,
we know that the soandso exists; but we may know that the soandso exists when we are not acquainted
with any object which we know to be the soandso, and even when we are not acquainted with any object
which, in fact, is the soandso.
Common words, even proper names, are usually really descriptions. That is to say, the thought in the mind of
a person using a proper name correctly can generally only be expressed explicitly if we replace the proper
name by a description. Moreover, the description required to express the thought will vary for different
people, or for the same person at different times. The only thing constant (so long as the name is rightly used)
is the object to which the name applies. But so long as this remains constant, the particular description
involved usually makes no difference to the truth or falsehood of the proposition in which the name appears.
Let us take some illustrations. Suppose some statement made about Bismarck. Assuming that there is such a
thing as direct acquaintance with oneself, Bismarck himself might have used his name directly to designate
the particular person with whom he was acquainted. In this case, if he made a judgement about himself, he
himself might be a constituent of the judgement. Here the proper name has the direct use which it always
wishes to have, as simply standing for a certain object, and not for a description of the object. But if a person
who knew Bismarck made a judgement about him, the case is different. What this person was acquainted
with were certain sensedata which he connected (rightly, we will suppose) with Bismarck's body. His body,
as a physical object, and still more his mind, were only known as the body and the mind connected with these
sensedata. That is, they were known by description. It is, of course, very much a matter of chance which
characteristics of a man's appearance will come into a friend's mind when he thinks of him; thus the
description actually in the friend's mind is accidental. The essential point is that he knows that the various
descriptions all apply to the same entity, in spite of not being acquainted with the entity in question.
When we, who did not know Bismarck, make judgement about him, the description in our minds will
probably be some more or less vague mass of historical knowledge far more, in most cases, than is
required to identify him. But, for the sake of illustration, let us assume that we think of him as 'the first
Chancellor of the German Empire'. Here all the words are abstract except 'German'. The word 'German' will,
again, have different meanings for different people. To some it will recall travels in Germany, to some the
look of Germany on the map, and so on. But if we are to obtain a description which we know to be
applicable, we shall be compelled, at some point, to bring in a reference to a particular with which we are
acquainted. Such reference is involved in any mention of past, present, and future (as opposed to definite
dates), or of here and there, or of what others have told us. Thus it would seem that, in some way or other, a
description known to be applicable to a particular must involve some reference to a particular with which we
are acquainted, if our knowledge about the thing described is not to be merely what follows logically from the
description. or example, 'the most longlived of men' is a description involving only universals, which must
apply to some man, but we can make no judgements concerning this man which involve knowledge about
him beyond what the description gives. If, however, we say, 'The first Chancellor of the German Empire was
an astute diplomatist', we can only be assured of the truth of our judgement in virtue of something with which
we are acquainted usually a testimony heard or read. Apart from the information we convey to others,
apart from the fact about the actual Bismarck, which gives importance to our judgement, the thought we
really have contains the one or more particulars involved, and otherwise consists wholly of concepts.
All names of places London, England, Europe, the Earth, the Solar System similarly involve, when
used, descriptions which start from some one or more particulars with which we are acquainted. I suspect that
even the Universe, as considered by metaphysics, involves such a connexion with particulars. In logic on the
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION 18
Page No 21
contrary, where we are concerned not merely with what does exist, but with whatever might or could exist or
be, no reference to actual particulars is involved.
It would seem that, when we make a statement about something only known by description, we often intend
to make our statement, not in the form involving the description, but about the actual thing described. That is
to say, when we say anything about Bismarck, we should like, if we could, to make the judgement which
Bismarck alone can make, namely, the judgement of which he himself is a constituent. In this we are
necessarily defeated, since the actual Bismarck is unknown to us. But we know that there is an object B,
called Bismarck, and that B was an astute diplomatist. We can thus describe the proposition we should like to
affirm, namely, 'B was an astute diplomat', where B is the object which was Bismarck. If we are describing
Bismarck as 'the first Chancellor of the German Empire', the proposition we should like to affirm may be
described as 'the proposition asserting, concerning the actual object which was the first Chancellor of the
German Empire, that this object an astute diplomatist'. What enables us to communicate in spite of the
varying descriptions we employ is that we know there is a true proposition concerning the actual Bismarck,
and that however we may vary be description (so long as the description is correct) the proposition described
is still the same. This proposition, which is described and is known to be true, is what interests us; but we are
not acquainted with the proposition itself, and do not know it, though we know it is true.
It will be seen that there are various stages in the removal from acquaintance with particulars: there is
Bismarck to people who knew him; Bismarck to those who only know of him through history; the man with
the iron mask; the longestlived of men. These are progressively further removed from acquaintance with
particulars; the first comes as near to acquaintance as is possible in regard to another person; in the second,
we shall still be said to know 'who Bismarck was'; in the third, we do not know who was the man with the
iron mask, though we can know many propositions about him which are not logically deducible from the fact
that he wore an iron mask; in the fourth, finally, we know nothing beyond what is logically deducible from
the definition of the man. There is a similar hierarchy in the region of universals. Many universals like many
particulars, are only known to us by description. But here, as in the case of particulars, knowledge concerning
what is known by description is ultimately reducible to knowledge concerning what is known by
acquaintance.
The fundamental principle in the analysis of propositions containing descriptions is this: Every proposition
which we can understand must be composed wholly of constituents with which we are acquainted.
We shall not at this stage attempt to answer all the objections which may be urged against this fundamental
principle. For the present, we shall merely point out that, in some way or other, it must be possible to meet
these objections, for it is scarcely conceivable that we can make a judgement or entertain a supposition
without knowing what it is that we are judging or supposing about. We must attach some meaning to the
words we use, if we are to speak significantly and not utter mere noise; and the meaning we attach to our
words must be something with which we are acquainted. Thus when, for example, we make a statement about
Julius Caesar, it is plain that Julius Caesar himself is not before our minds, since we are not acquainted with
him. We have in mind some description of Julius Caesar: 'the man who was assassinated on the Ides of
March', 'the founder of the Roman Empire', or, merely 'the man whose name was Julius Caesar'. (In this last
description, Julius Caesar is a noise or shape with which we are acquainted.) Thus our statement does not
mean quite what it seems to mean, but means something involving, instead of Julius Caesar, some description
of him which is composed wholly of particulars and universals with which we are acquainted.
The chief importance of knowledge by description is that it enables us to pass beyond the limits of our
experience. In spite of the fact that we can only know truths which are wholly composed of terms which we
have experienced in acquaintance, we can yet have knowledge by description of things which we have never
experienced. In view of the very narrow range of our immediate experience, this result is vital, and until it is
understood, much of our knowledge must remain mysterious and therefore doubtful.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION 19
Page No 22
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION
IN almost all our previous discussions we have been concerned in the attempt to get clear as to our data in the
way of knowledge of existence. What things are there in the universe whose existence is known to us owing
to our being acquainted with them? So far, our answer has been that we are acquainted with our sensedata,
and, probably, with ourselves. These we know to exist. And past sensedata which are remembered are
known to have existed in the past. This knowledge supplies our data.
But if we are to be able to draw inferences from these data if we are to know of the existence of matter, of
other people, of the past before our individual memory begins, or of the future, we must know general
principles of some kind by means of which such inferences can be drawn. It must be known to us that the
existence of some one sort of thing, A, is a sign of the existence of some other sort of thing, B, either at the
same time as A or at some earlier or later time, as, for example, thunder is a sign of the earlier existence of
lightning. If this were not known to us, we could never extend our knowledge beyond the sphere of our
private experience; and this sphere, as we have seen, is exceedingly limited. The question we have now to
consider is whether such an extension is possible, and if so, how it is effected.
Let us take as an illustration a matter about which of us, in fact, feel the slightest doubt. We are all convinced
that the sun will rise tomorrow. Why? Is this belief a mere blind outcome of past experience, or can it be
justified as a reasonable belief? It is not find a test by which to judge whether a belief of this kind is
reasonable or not, but we can at least ascertain what sort of general beliefs would suffice, if true, to justify the
judgement that the sun will rise tomorrow, and the many other similar judgements upon which our actions
are based.
It is obvious that if we are asked why we believe it the sun will rise tomorrow, we shall naturally answer,
'Because it always has risen every day'. We have a firm belief that it will rise in the future, because it has
risen in the past. If we are challenged as to why we believe that it will continue to rise as heretofore, we may
appeal to the laws of motion: the earth, we shall say, is a freely rotating body, and such bodies do not cease to
rotate unless something interferes from outside, and there is nothing outside to interfere with thee earth
between now and tomorrow. Of course it might be doubted whether we are quite certain that there is
nothing outside to interfere, but this is not the interesting doubt. The interesting doubt is as to whether the
laws of motion will remain in operation until tomorrow. If this doubt is raised, we find ourselves in the
same position as when the doubt about the sunrise was first raised.
The only reason for believing that the laws of motion remain in operation is that they have operated hitherto,
so far as our knowledge of the past enables us to judge. It is true that we have a greater body of evidence
from the past in favour of the laws of motion than we have in favour of the sunrise, because the sunrise is
merely a particular case of fulfilment of the laws of motion, and there are countless other particular cases. But
the real question is: Do any number of cases of a law being fulfilled in the past afford evidence that it will be
fulfilled in the future? If not, it becomes plain that we have no ground whatever for expecting the sun to rise
tomorrow, or for expecting the bread we shall eat at our next meal not to poison us, or for any of the other
scarcely conscious expectations that control our daily lives. It is to be observed that all such expectations are
only probable; thus we have not to seek for a proof that they must be fulfilled, but only for some reason in
favour of the view that they are likely to be fulfilled.
Now in dealing with this question we must, to begin with, make an important distinction, without which we
should soon become involved in hopeless confusions. Experience has shown us that, hitherto, the frequent
repetition of some uniform succession or coexistence has been a cause of our expecting the same succession
or coexistence on the next occasion. Food that has a certain appearance generally has a certain taste, and it is
a severe shock to our expectations when the familiar appearance is found to be associated with an unusual
taste. Things which we see become associated, by habit, with certain tactile sensations which we expect if we
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION 20
Page No 23
touch them; one of the horrors of a ghost (in many ghoststories) is that it fails to give us any sensations of
touch. Uneducated people who go abroad for the first time are so surprised as to be incredulous when they
find their native language not understood.
And this kind of association is not confined to men; in animals also it is very strong. A horse which has been
often driven along a certain road resists the attempt to drive him in a different direction. Domestic animals
expect food when they see the person who feeds them. We know that all these rather crude expectations of
uniformity are liable to be misleading. The man who has fed the chicken every day throughout its life at last
wrings its neck instead, showing that more refined views as to the uniformity of nature would have been
useful to the chicken.
But in spite of the misleadingness of such expectations, . they nevertheless exist. The mere fact that
something has happened a certain number of times causes animals and men to expect that it will happen
again. Thus our instincts certainly cause us to believe the sun will rise tomorrow, but we may be in no better
a position than the chicken which unexpectedly has its neck wrung. We have therefore to distinguish the fact
that past uniformities cause expectations as to the future, from the question whether there is any reasonable
ground for giving weight to such expectations after the question of their validity has been raised.
The problem we have to discuss is whether there is any reason for believing in what is called 'the uniformity
of nature'. The belief in the uniformity of nature is the belief that everything that has happened or will happen
is an instance of some general law to which there are no exceptions. The crude expectations which we have
been considering are all subject to exceptions, and therefore liable to disappoint those who entertain them.
But science habitually assumes, at least as a working hypothesis, that general rules which have exceptions
can be replaced by general rules which have no exceptions. 'Unsupported bodies in air fall' is a general rule to
which balloons and aeroplanes are exceptions. But the laws of motion and the law of gravitation, which
account for the fact that most bodies fall, also account for the fact that balloons and aeroplanes can rise; thus
the laws of motion and the law of gravitation are not subject to these exceptions.
The belief that the sun will rise tomorrow might be falsified if the earth came suddenly into contact with a
large body which destroyed its rotation; but the laws of motion and the law of gravitation would not be
infringed by such an event. The business of science is to find uniformities, such as the laws of motion and the
law of gravitation, to which, so far as our experience extends, there are no exceptions. In this search science
has been remarkably successful, and it may be conceded that such uniformities have held hitherto. This
brings us back to the question: Have we any reason, assuming that they have always held in the past, to
suppose that they will hold in the future?
It has been argued that we have reason to know that the future will resemble the past, because what was the
future has constantly become the past, and has always been found to resemble the past, so that we really have
experience of the future, namely of times which were formerly future, which we may call past futures. But
such an argument really begs the very question at issue. We have experience of past futures, but not of future
futures, and the question is: Will future futures resemble past futures? This question is not to be answered by
an argument which starts from past futures alone. We have therefore still to seek for some principle which
shall enable us to know that the future will follow the same laws as the past.
The reference to the future in this question is not essential. The same question arises when we apply the laws
that work in our experience to past things of which we have no experience as, for example, in geology, or
in theories as to the origin of the Solar system. The question we really have to ask is: 'When two things have
been found to be often associated, and no instance is known of the one occurring without the other, does the
occurrence of one of the two, in a fresh instance, give any good ground for expecting the other?' On our
answer to this question must depend the validity of the whole of our expectations as to the future, the whole
of the results obtained by induction, and in fact practically all the beliefs upon which our daily life is based.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION 21
Page No 24
It must be conceded, to begin with, that the fact that two things have been found often together and never
apart does not, by itself, suffice to prove demonstratively that they will be found together in the next case we
examine. The most we can hope is that the oftener things are found together, the more probable becomes that
they will be found together another time, and that, if they have been found together often enough, the
probability will amount almost to certainty. It can never quite reach certainty, because we know that in spite
of frequent repetitions there sometimes is a failure at the last, as in the case of the chicken whose neck is
wrung. Thus probability is all we ought to seek.
It might be urged, as against the view we are advocating, that we know all natural phenomena to be subject to
the reign of law, and that sometimes, on the basis of observation, we can see that only one law can possibly
fit the facts of the case. Now to this view there are two answers. The first is that, even if some law which has
no exceptions applies to our case, we can never, in practice, be sure that we have discovered that law and not
one to which there are exceptions. The second is that the reign of law would seem to be itself only probable,
and that our belief that it will hold in the future, or in unexamined cases in the past, is itself based upon the
very principle we are examining.
The principle we are examining may be called the principle of induction, and its two parts may be stated as
follows:
(a) When a thing of a certain sort A has been found to be associated with a thing of a certain other sort B, and
has never been found dissociated from a thing of the sort B, the greater the number of cases in which A and B
have been associated, the greater is the probability that they will be associated in a fresh case in which one of
them is known to be present;
(b) Under the same circumstances, a sufficient number of cases of association will make the probability of a
fresh association nearly a certainty, and will make it approach certainty without limit.
As just stated, the principle applies only to the verification of our expectation in a single fresh instance. But
we want also to know that there is a probability in favour of the general law that things of the sort A are
always associated with things of the sort B, provided a sufficient number of cases of association are known,
and no cases of failure of association are known. The probability of the general law is obviously less than the
probability of the particular case, since if the general law is true, the particular case must also be true,
whereas the particular case may be true without the general law being true. Nevertheless the probability of
the general law is increased by repetitions, just as the probability of the particular case is. We may therefore
repeat the two parts of our principle as regards the general law, thus:
(a)The greater the number of cases in which a thing the sort A has been found associated with a thing the sort
B, the more probable it is (if no cases of failure of association are known) that A is always associated with B;
(b) Under the same circumstances, a sufficient number of cases of the association of A with B will make it
nearly certain that A is always associated with B, and will make this general law approach certainty without
limit.
It should be noted that probability is always relative to certain data. In our case, the data are merely the
known cases of coexistence of A and B. There may be other data, which might be taken into account, which
would gravely alter the probability. For example, a man who had seen a great many white swans might argue
by our principle, that on the data it was probable that all swans were white, and this might be a perfectly
sound argument. The argument is not disproved by the fact that some swans are black, because a thing may
very well happen in spite of the fact that some data render it improbable. In the case of the swans, a man
might know that colour is a very variable characteristic in many species of animals, and that, therefore, an
induction as to colour is peculiarly liable to error. But this knowledge would be a fresh datum, by no means
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION 22
Page No 25
proving that the probability relatively to our previous data had been wrongly estimated. The fact, therefore,
that things often fail to fulfil our expectations is no evidence that our expectations will not probably be
fulfilled in a given case or a given class of cases. Thus our inductive principle is at any rate not capable of
being disproved by an appeal to experience.
The inductive principle, however, is equally incapable of being proved by an appeal to experience.
Experience might conceivably confirm the inductive principle as regards the cases that have been already
examined; but as regards unexamined cases, it is the inductive principle alone that can justify any inference
from what has been examined to what has not been examined. All arguments which, on the basis of
experience, argue as to the future or the unexperienced parts of the past or present, assume the inductive
principle; hence we can never use experience to prove the inductive principle without begging the question.
Thus we must either accept the inductive principle on the ground of its intrinsic evidence, or forgo all
justification of our expectations about the future. If the principle is unsound, we have no reason to expect the
sun to rise tomorrow, to expect bread to be more nourishing than a stone, or to expect that if we throw
ourselves off the roof we shall fall. When we see what looks like our best friend approaching us, we shall
have no reason to suppose that his body is not inhabited by the mind of our worst enemy or of some total
stranger. All our conduct is based upon associations which have worked in the past, and which we therefore
regard as likely to work in the future; and this likelihood is dependent for its validity upon the inductive
principle.
The general principles of science, such as the belief in the reign of law, and the belief that every event must
have a cause, are as completely dependent upon the inductive principle as are the beliefs of daily life All such
general principles are believed because mankind have found innumerable instances of their truth and no
instances of their falsehood. But this affords no evidence for their truth in the future, unless the inductive
principle is assumed.
Thus all knowledge which, on a basis of experience tells us something about what is not experienced, is
based upon a belief which experience can neither confirm nor confute, yet which, at least in its more concrete
applications, appears to be as firmly rooted in us as many of the facts of experience. The existence and
justification of such beliefs for the inductive principle, as we shall see, is not the only example raises
some of the most difficult and most debated problems of philosophy. We will, in the next chapter, consider
briefly what may be said to account for such knowledge, and what is its scope and its degree of certainty.
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES
WE saw in the preceding chapter that the principle of Induction, while necessary to the validity of all
arguments based on experience, is itself not capable of being proved by experience, and yet is unhesitatingly
believed by every one, at least in all its concrete applications. In these characteristics the principle of
induction does not stand alone. There are a number of other principles which cannot be proved or disproved
by experience, but are used in arguments which start from what is experienced.
Some of these principles have even greater evidence than the principle of induction, and the knowledge of
them has the same degree of certainty as the knowledge of the existence of sensedata. They constitute the
means of drawing inferences from what is given in sensation; and if what we infer is to be true, it is just as
necessary that our principles of inference should be true as it is that our data should be true. The principles of
inference are apt to be overlooked because of their very obviousness the assumption involved is assented
to without our realizing that it is an assumption. But it is very important to realize the use of principles of
inference, if a correct theory of knowledge is to be obtained; for our knowledge of them raises interesting and
difficult questions.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES 23
Page No 26
In all our knowledge of general principles, what actually happens is that first of all we realize some particular
application of the principle, and then we realize the particularity is irrelevant, and that there is a generality
which may equally truly be affirmed. This is of course familiar in such matters as teaching arithmetic: 'two
and two are four' is first learnt in the case of some particular pair of couples, and then in some other particular
case, and so on, until at last it becomes possible to see that it is true of any pair of couples. The same thing
happens with logical principles. Suppose two men are discussing what day of the month it is. One of them
says, 'At least you will admit that if yesterday was the 15th today must the 16th.' 'Yes', says the other, 'I
admit that.' 'And you know', the first continues, 'that yesterday was the 15th, because you dined with Jones,
and your diary will tell you that was on the 15th.' 'Yes', says the second; 'therefore today is the 16th'
Now such an argument is not hard to follow; and if it is granted that its premisses are true in fact, no one deny
that the conclusion must also be true. But it depends for its truth upon an instance of a general logical
principle. The logical principle is as follows: 'Suppose it known that if this is true, then that is true. Suppose it
also known that this is true, then it follows that that is true.' When it is the case that if this is true, that is true,
we shall say that this 'implies' that, that that 'follows from' this. Thus our principle states that if this implies
that, and this is true, then that is true. In other words, 'anything implied by a proposition is true', or 'whatever
follows from a true proposition is true'.
This principle is really involved at least, concrete instances of it are involved in all demonstrations.
Whenever one thing which we believe is used to prove something else, which we consequently believe, this
principle is relevant. If any one asks: 'Why should I accept the results of valid arguments based on true
premisses?' we can only answer by appealing to our principle. In fact, the truth of the principle is impossible
to doubt, and its obviousness is so great that at first sight it seems almost trivial. Such principles, however,
are not trivial to the philosopher, for they show that we may have indubitable knowledge which is in no way
derived from objects of sense.
The above principle is merely one of a certain number of selfevident logical principles. Some at least of
these principles must be granted before any argument or proof becomes possible. When some of them have
been granted, others can be proved, though these others, so long as they are simple, are just as obvious as the
principles taken for granted. For no very good reason, three of these principles have been singled out by
tradition under the name of 'Laws of Thought'.
They are as follows:
(1) The law of identity: 'Whatever is, is.'
(2) The law of contradiction: 'Nothing can both be and not be.'
(3) The law of excluded middle: 'Everything must either be or not be.'
These three laws are samples of selfevident logical principles, but are not really more fundamental or more
selfevident than various other similar principles: for instance. the one we considered just now, which states
that what follows from a true premiss is true. The name 'laws of thought' is also misleading, for what is
important is not the fact that we think in accordance with these laws, but the fact that things behave in
accordance with them; in other words, the fact that when we think in accordance with them we think truly.
But this is a large question, to which we return at a later stage.
In addition to the logical principles which enable us to prove from a given premiss that something is certainly
true, there are other logical principles which enable us to prove, from a given premiss, that there is a greater
or less probability that something is true. An example of such principles perhaps the most important
example is the inductive principle, which we considered in the preceding chapter.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES 24
Page No 27
One of the great historic controversies in philosophy is the controversy between the two schools called
respectively 'empiricists' and 'rationalists'. The empiricists who are best represented by the British
philosophers, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume maintained that all our knowledge is derived from experience;
the rationalists who are represented by the continental philosophers of the seventeenth century, especially
Descartes and Leibniz maintained that, in addition to what we know by experience, there are certain
'innate ideas' and 'innate principles', which we know independently of experience. It has now become possible
to decide with some confidence as to the truth or falsehood of these opposing schools. It must be admitted,
for the reasons already stated, that logical principles are known to us, and cannot be themselves proved by
experience, since all proof presupposes them. In this, therefore, which was the most important point of the
controversy, the rationalists were in the right.
On the other hand, even that part of our knowledge which is logically independent of experience (in the sense
that experience cannot prove it) is yet elicited and caused by experience. It is on occasion of particular
experiences that we become aware of the general laws which their connexions exemplify. It would certainly
be absurd to suppose that there are innate principles in the sense that babies are born with a knowledge of
everything which men know and which cannot be deduced from what is experienced. For this reason, the
word 'innate' would not now be employed to describe our knowledge of logical principles. The phrase 'a
priori' is less objectionable, and is more usual in modern writers. Thus, while admitting that all knowledge is
elicited and caused by experience, we shall nevertheless hold that some knowledge is a priori, in the sense
that the experience which makes us think of it does not suffice to prove it, but merely so directs our attention
that we see its truth without requiring any proof from experience.
There is another point of great importance, in which the empiricists were in the right as against the
rationalists. Nothing can be known to exist except by the help of experience. That is to say, if we wish to
prove that something of which we have no direct experience exists, we must have among our premisses the
existence of one or more things of which we have direct experience. Our belief that the Emperor of China
exists, for example, rests upon testimony, and testimony consists, in the last analysis, of sensedata seen or
heard in reading or being spoken to. Rationalists believed that, from general consideration as to what must be,
they could deduce the existence of this or that in the actual world. In this belief they seem to have been
mistaken. All the knowledge that we can acquire a priori concerning existence seems to be hypothetical: it
tells us that if one thing exists, another must exist, or, more generally, that if one proposition is true another
must be true. This is exemplified by principles we have already dealt with, such as 'if this is true, and this
implies that, then that is true', of 'ifthis and that have been repeatedly found connected, they will probably be
connected in the next instance in which one of them is found'. Thus the scope and power of a priori principles
is strictly limited. All knowledge that something exists must be in part dependent on experience. When
anything is known immediately, its existence is known by experience alone; when anything is proved to exist,
without being known immediately, both experience and a priori principles must be required in the proof.
Knowledge is called empirical when it rests wholly or partly upon experience. Thus all knowledge which
asserts existence is empirical, and the only a priori knowledge concerning existence is hypothetical, giving
connexions among things that exist or may exist, but not giving actual existence.
A priori knowledge is not all of the logical kind we hitherto considering. Perhaps the most important example
of nonlogical a priori knowledge is knowledge as to ethical value. I am not speaking of judgements as to
what is useful or as to what is virtuous, for such judgements do require empirical premisses; I am speaking of
judgements as to the intrinsic desirability of things. If something is useful, it must be useful because it secures
some end, the end must, if we have gone far enough, be valuable on its own account, and not merely because
it is useful for some further end. Thus all judgements as to what is useful depend upon judgements as to what
has value on its own account.
We judge, for example, that happiness is more desirable than misery, knowledge than ignorance, goodwill
than hatred, and so on. Such judgements must, in part at least, be immediate and a priori. Like our previous a
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES 25
Page No 28
priori judgements, they may be elicited by experience, and indeed they must be; for it seems not possible to
judge whether anything is intrinsically valuable unless we have experienced something of the same kind. But
it is fairly obvious that they cannot be proved by experience; for the fact that a thing exists or does not exist
cannot prove either that it is good that it should exist or that it is bad. The pursuit of this subject belongs to
ethics, where the impossibility of deducing what ought to be from what is has to established. In the present
connexion, it is only important to realize that knowledge as to what is intrinsically of value is a priori in the
same sense in which logic is a priori, namely in the sense that the truth of such knowledge can be neither
proved nor disproved by experience.
All pure mathematics is a priori, like logic. This strenuously denied by the empirical philosophers, who
maintained that experience was as much the source of our knowledge of arithmetic as of our knowledge of
geography. They maintained that by the repeated experience of seeing two things and two other things, and
finding that altogether they made four things, we were led by induction to the conclusion that two things and
two other things would always make four things altogether. If, however, this were the source of our
knowledge that two and two are four we should proceed differently, in persuading ourselves of its truth, from
the way in which we do actually proceed. In fact, a certain number of instances are needed to make us think
of two abstractly, rather than of two coins or two books or two people, or two of any other specified kind. But
as soon as we are able to divest our thoughts of irrelevant particularity, we become able to see the general
principle that two and two are four; any one instance is seen to be typical and the examination of other
instances becomes unnecessary.*
* Cf. A. N. Whitehead, Introduction to Mathematics (Home University Library).
The same thing is exemplified in geometry. If we want to prove some property of all triangles, we draw some
one triangle and reason about it; but we can avoid making use of any property which it does not share with all
other triangles, and thus, from our particular case, we obtain a general result. We do not, in fact, feel our
certainty that two and two are four increased by fresh instances, because, as soon as we have seen the truth of
this proposition, our certainty becomes so great as to be incapable of growing greater. Moreover, we feel
some quality of necessity about the proposition 'two and two are four', which is absent from even the best
attested empirical generalizations. Such generalizations always remain mere facts: we feel that there might be
a world in which they were false, though in the actual world they happen to be true. In any possible world, on
the contrary, we feel that two and two would be four: this is not a mere fact, but a necessity to which
everything actual and possible must conform.
The case may be made clearer by considering a genuinely empirical generalization, such as 'All men are
mortal.' It is plain that we believe this proposition, in the first place, because there is no known instance of
men living beyond a certain age, and in the second place because there seem to be physiological grounds for
thinking that an organism such as a man's body must sooner or later wear out. Neglecting the second ground,
and considering merely our experience of men's mortality, it is plain that we should not be content with one
quite clearly understood instance of a man dying, whereas, in the case of 'two and two are four', one instance
does suffice, when carefully considered, to persuade us that the same must happen in any other instance. Also
we can be forced to admit, on reflection, that there may be some doubt, however slight, as to whether all men
are mortal. This may be made plain by the attempt to imagine two different worlds, in one of which there are
men who are not mortal, while in the other two and two make five. When Swift invites us to consider the race
of Struldbugs who never die, we are able to acquiesce in imagination. But a world where two and two make
five seems quite on a different level. We feel that such a world, if there were one, would upset the whole
fabric of our knowledge and reduce us to utter doubt.
The fact is that, in simple mathematical judgements such as 'two and two are four', and also in many
judgements of logic, we can know the general proposition without inferring it from instances, although some
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES 26
Page No 29
instance is usually necessary to make clear to us what the general proposition means. This is why there is real
utility in the process of deduction, which goes from the general to the general, or from the general to the
particular, as well as in the process of induction, which goes from the particular to the particular, or from the
particular to the general. It is an old debate among philosophers whether deduction ever gives new
knowledge. We can now see that in certain cases, least, it does do so. If we already know that two and two
always make four, and we know that Brown and Jones are two, and so are Robinson and Smith, we can
deduce that Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith are four. This is new knowledge, not contained in our
premisses, because the general proposition, 'two and two are four, never told us there were such people as
Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith, and the particular premisses do not tell us that there were four of
them, whereas the particular proposition deduced does tell us both these things.
But the newness of the knowledge is much less certain if we take the stock instance of deduction that is
always given in books on logic, namely, 'All men are mortal; Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal.'
In this case, what we really know beyond reasonable doubt is that certain men, A, B, C, were mortal, since, in
fact, they have died. If Socrates is one of these men, it is foolish to go the roundabout way through 'all men
are mortal' to arrive at the conclusion that probably Socrates is mortal. If Socrates is not one of the men on
whom our induction is based, we shall still do better to argue straight from our A, B, C, to Socrates, than to
go round by the general proposition, 'all men are mortal'. For the probability that Socrates is mortal is greater,
on our data, than the probability that all men are mortal. (This is obvious, because if all men are mortal, so is
Socrates; but if Socrates is mortal, it does not follow that all men are mortal.) Hence we shall reach the
conclusion that Socrates is mortal with a greater approach to certainty if we make our argument purely
inductive than if we go by way of 'all men are mortal' and then use deduction.
This illustrates the difference between general propositions known a priori, such as 'two and two are four',
and empirical generalizations such as 'all men are mortal'. In regard to the former, deduction is the right mode
of argument, whereas in regard to the latter, induction is always theoretically preferable, and warrants a
greater confidence in the truth of our conclusion, because all empirical generalizations are more uncertain
than the instances of them.
We have now seen that there are propositions known a priori, and that among them are the propositions of
logic and pure mathematics, as well as the fundamental propositions of ethics. The question which must next
occupy us is this: How is it possible that there should be such knowledge? And more particularly, how can
there be knowledge of general propositions in cases where we have not examined all the instances, and
indeed never can examine them all, because their number is infinite? These questions, which were first
brought prominently forward by the German philosopher Kant (17241804), are very difficult, and
historically very important.
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE
IMMANUEL KANT is generally regarded as the greatest of the modern philosophers. Though he lived
through the Seven Years War and the French Revolution, he never interrupted his teaching of philosophy at
Konigsberg in East Prussia. His most distinctive contribution was the invention of what he called the 'critical'
philosophy, which, assuming as a datum that there is knowledge of various kinds, inquired how such
knowledge comes to be possible, and deduced, from the answer to this inquiry, many metaphysical results as
to the nature of the world. Whether these results were valid may well be doubted. But Kant undoubtedly
deserves credit for two things: first, for having perceived that we have a priori knowledge which is not purely
'analytic', i.e. such that the opposite would be selfcontradictory; and secondly, for having made evident the
philosophical importance of the theory of knowledge.
Before the time of Kant, it was generally held that whatever knowledge was a priori must be 'analytic'. What
this word means will be best illustrated by examples. If I say, 'A bald man is a man', 'A plane figure is a
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE 27
Page No 30
figure', 'A bad poet is a poet', I make a purely analytic judgement: the subject spoken about is given as having
at least two properties, of which one is singled out to be asserted of it. Such propositions as the above are
trivial, and would never be enunciated in real life except by an orator preparing the way for a piece of
sophistry. They are called 'analytic' because the predicate is obtained by merely analysing the subject. Before
the time of Kant it was thought that all judgements of which we could be certain a priori were of this kind:
that in all of them there was a predicate which was only part of the subject of which it was asserted. If this
were so, we should be involved in a definite contradiction if we attempted to deny thinging that could be
known a priori. 'A bald man is not bald' would assert and deny baldness of the same man, and would
therefore contradict itself. Thus according to the philosophers before Kant, the law of contradiction, which
asserts that nothing can at the same time have and not have a certain property, sufficed to establish the truth
of all a priori knowledge.
Hume (171176), who preceded Kant, accepting the usual view as to what makes knowledge a priori,
discovered that, in many cases which had previously been supposed analytic, and notably in the case of cause
and effect, the connexion was really synthetic. Before Hume, rationalists at least had supposed that the effect
could be logically deduced from the cause, if only we had sufficient knowledge. Hume argued correctly,
as would now be generally admitted that this could not be done. Hence he inferred the far more doubtful
proposition that nothing could be known a priori about the connexion of cause and effect. Kant, who had
been educated in the rationalist tradition, was much perturbed by Hume's scepticism, and endeavoured to find
an answer to it. He perceived that not only the connexion of cause and effect, but all the propositions of
arithmetic and geometry, are 'synthetic' i.e. not analytic: in all these propositions, no analysis of the subject
will reveal the predicate. His stock instance was the proposition 7 + 5 = 12. He pointed out, quite truly, that 7
and 5 have to be put together to give 12: the idea of 12 is not contained in them, nor even in the idea of
adding them together. Thus he was led to the conclusion that all pure mathematics, though a priori, is
synthetic; and this conclusion raised a new problem of which he endeavoured to find the solution.
The question which Kant put at the beginning of his philosophy, namely 'How is pure mathematics possible?'
is an interesting and difficult one, to which every philosophy which is not purely sceptical must find some
answer. The answer of the pure empiricists, that our mathematical knowledge is derived by induction from
particular instances, we have already seen to be inadequate, for two reasons: first, that the validity of the
inductive principle itself cannot be proved by induction; secondly, that the general propositions of
mathematics, such as 'two and two always make four', can obviously be known with certainty by
consideration of a single instance, and gain nothing by enumeration of other cases in which they have been
found to be true. Thus our knowledge of the general propositions of mathematics (and the same applies to
logic) must be accounted for otherwise than our (merely probable) knowledge of empirical generalizations
such as 'all men are mortal'.
The problem arises through the fact that such knowledge is general, whereas all experience is particular. It
seems strange that we should apparently be able to know some truths in advance about particular things of
which we have as yet no experience; but it cannot easily be doubted that logic and arithmetic will apply to
such things. We do not know who will be the inhabitants of London a hundred years hence; but we know that
any two of them and any other two of them will make four of them. This apparent power of anticipating facts
about things of which we have no experience is certainly surprising. Kant's solution of the problem, though
not valid in my opinion, is interesting. It is, however, very difficult, and is differently understood by different
philosophers. We can, therefore, only give the merest outline of it, and even that will be thought misleading
by many exponents of Kant's system.
What Kant maintained was that in all our experience there are two elements to be distinguished, the one due
to the object (i.e. to what we have called the 'physical object'), the other due to our own nature. We saw, in
discussing matter and sensedata, that the physical object is different from the associated sensedata, and
that the sensedata are to be regarded as resulting from an interaction between the physical object and
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE 28
Page No 31
ourselves. So far, we are in agreement with Kant. But what is distinctive of Kant is the way in which he
apportions the shares of ourselves and the physical object respectively. He considers that the crude material
given in sensation the colour, hardness etc. is due to the object, and that what we supply is the
arrangement in space and time, and all the relations between sensedata which result from comparison or
from considering one as the cause of the other or in any other way. His chief reason in favour of this view is
that we seem to have a priori knowledge as to space and time and causality and comparison, but not as to the
actual crude material of sensation. We can be sure, he says, that anything we shall ever experience must show
the characteristics affirmed of it in our a priori knowledge, because these characteristics are due to our own
nature, and therefore nothing can ever come into our experience without acquiring these characteristics.
The physical object, which he calls the 'thing in itself',* he regards as essentially unknowable; what can be
known is the object as we have it in experience, which he calls the 'phenomenon'. The phenomenon, being a
joint product of us and the thing in itself, is sure to have those characteristics which are due to us, and is
therefore sure to conform to our a priori knowledge. Hence this knowledge, though true of all actual and
possible experience, must not be supposed to apply outside experience. Thus in spite of the existence of a
priori knowledge, we cannot know anything about the thing in itself or about what is not an actual or possible
object of experience. In this way he tries to reconcile and harmonize the contentions of the rationalists with
the arguments of the empiricists.
* Kant's 'thing in itself' is identical in definition with the physical object, namely,
it is the cause of sensations. In the properties deduced from the definition it is not identical, since Kant held
(in spite of some inconsistency as regards cause) that we can know that none of the categories are applicable
to the 'thing in itself'.
Apart from minor grounds on which Kant's philosophy may be criticized, there is one main objection which
seems fatal to any attempt to deal with the problem of a priori knowledge by his method. The thing to be
accounted for is our certainty that the facts must always conform to logic and arithmetic. To say that logic
and arithmetic are contributed by us does not account for this. Our nature is as much a fact of the existing
world as anything, and there can be no certainty that it will remain constant. It might happen, if Kant is right,
that tomorrow our nature would so change as to make two and two become five. This possibility seems
never to have occurred to him, yet it is one which utterly destroys the certainty and universality which he is
anxious to vindicate for arithmetical propositions. It is true that this possibility, formally, is inconsistent with
the Kantian view that time itself is a form imposed by the subject upon phenomena, so that our real Self is not
in time and has no tomorrow. But he will still have to suppose that the timeorder of phenomena is
determined by characteristics of what is behind phenomena, and this suffices for the substance of our
argument.
Reflection, moreover, seems to make it clear that, if there is any truth in our arithmetical beliefs, they must
apply to things equally whether we think of them or not. Two physical objects and two other physical objects
must make four physical objects, even if physical objects cannot be experienced. To assert this is certainly
within the scope of what we mean when we state that two and two are four. Its truth is just as indubitable as
the truth of the assertion that two phenomena and two other phenomena make four phenomena. Thus Kant's
solution unduly limits the scope of a priori propositions, in addition to failing in the attempt at explaining
their certainty.
Apart from the special doctrines advocated by Kant, it is very common among philosophers to regard what is
a priori as in some sense mental, as concerned rather with the way we must think than with any fact of the
outer world. We noted in the preceding chapter the three principles commonly called 'laws of thought'. The
view which led to their being so named is a natural one, but there are strong reasons for thinking that it is
erroneous. Let us take as an illustration the law of contradiction. This is commonly stated in the form
'Nothing can both be and not be', which is intended to express the fact that nothing can at once have and not
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE 29
Page No 32
have a given quality. Thus, for example, if a tree is a beech it cannot also be not a beech; if my table is
rectangular it cannot also be not rectangular, and so on.
Now what makes it natural to call this principle a law of thought is that it is by thought rather than by
outward observation that we persuade ourselves of its necessary truth. When we have seen that a tree is a
beech, we do not need to look again in order to ascertain whether it is also not a beech; thought alone makes
us know that this is impossible. But the conclusion that the law of contradiction is a law of thought is
nevertheless erroneous. What we believe, when we believe the law of contradiction, is not that the mind is so
made that it must believe the law of contradiction. This belief is a subsequent result of psychological
reflection, which presupposes the belief in the law of contradiction. The belief in the law of contradiction is a
belief about things, not only about thoughts. It is not, e.g., the belief that if we think a certain tree is a beech,
we cannot at the same time think that it is not a beech; it is the belief that if a tree is a beech, it cannot at the
same time be not a beech. Thus the law of contradiction is about things, and not merely about thoughts; and
although belief in the law of contradiction is a thought, the law of contradiction itself is not a thought, but a
fact concerning the things in the world. If this, which we believe when we believe the law of contradiction,
were not true of the things in the world, the fact that we were compelled to think it true would not save the
law of contradiction from being false; and this shows that the law is not a law of thought.
A similar argument applies to any other a priori judgement. When we judge that two and two are four, we are
not making a judgement about our thoughts, but about all actual or possible couples. The fact that our minds
are so constituted as to believe that two and two are four, though it is true, is emphatically not what we assert
when we assert that two and two are four. And no fact about the constitution of our minds could make it true
that two and two are four. Thus our a priori knowledge, if it is not erroneous, is not merely knowledge about
the constitution of our minds, but is applicable to whatever the world may contain, both what is mental and
what is nonmental.
The fact seems to be that all our a priori knowledge is concerned with entities which do not, properly
speaking exist, either in the mental or in the physical world. These entities are such as can be named by parts
of speech which are not substantives; they are such entities as qualities and relations. Suppose, for instance,
that I am in my room. I exist, and my room exists; but does 'in' exist? Yet obviously the word 'in' has a
meaning; it denotes a relation which holds between me and my room. This relation is something, although we
cannot say that it exists in the same sense in which I and my room exist. The relation 'in' is something which
we can think about and understand, for, if we could not understand it, we could not understand the sentence 'I
am in my room'. Many philosophers, following Kant, have maintained that relations are the work of the mind,
that things in themselves have no relations, but that the mind brings them together in one act of thought and
thus produces the relations which it judges them to have.
This view, however, seems open to objections similar to those which we urged before against Kant. It seems
plain that it is not thought which produces the truth of the proposition 'I am in my room'. It may be true that
an earwig is in my room, even if neither I nor the earwig nor any one else is aware of this truth; for this truth
concerns only the earwig and the room, and does not depend upon anything else. Thus relations, as we shall
see more fully in the next chapter, must be placed in a world which is neither mental nor physical. This world
is of great importance to philosophy, and in particular to the problems of a priori knowledge. In the next
chapter we shall proceed to develop its nature and its bearing upon the questions with which we have been
dealing.
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS
AT the end of the preceding chapter we saw that such entities as relations appear to have a being which is in
some way different from that of physical objects, and also different from that of minds and from that of
sensedata. In the present chapter we have to consider what is the nature of this kind of being, and also what
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS 30
Page No 33
objects there are that have this kind of being. We will begin with the latter question.
The problem with which we are now concerned is a very old one, since it was brought into philosophy by
Plato. Plato's 'theory of ideas' is an attempt to solve this very problem, and in my opinion it is one of the most
successful attempts hitherto made. The theory to be advocated in what follows is largely Plato's, with merely
such modifications as time has shown to be necessary.
The way the problem arose for Plato was more or less as follows. Let us consider, say, such a notion as
justice. If we ask ourselves what justice is, it is natural to proceed by considering this, that, and the other just
act, with a view to discovering what they have in common. They must all, in some sense, partake of a
common nature, which will be found in whatever is just and in nothing else. This common nature, in virtue of
which they are all just, will be justice itself, the pure essence the admixture of which with facts of ordinary
life produces the multiplicity of just acts. Similarly with any other word which may be applicable to common
facts, such as 'whiteness' for example. The word will be applicable to a number of particular things because
they all participate in a common nature or essence. This pure essence is what Plato calls an 'idea' or 'form'. (It
must not be supposed that 'ideas', in his sense, exist in minds, though they may be apprehended by minds.)
The 'idea' justice is not identical with anything that is just: it is something other than particular things, which
particular things partake of. Not being particular, it cannot itself exist in the world of sense. Moreover it is not
fleeting or changeable like the things of sense: it is eternally itself, immutable and indestructible.
Thus Plato is led to a suprasensible world, more real than the common world of sense, the unchangeable
world of ideas, which alone gives to the world of sense whatever pale reflection of reality may belong to it.
The truly real world, for Plato, is the world of ideas; for whatever we may attempt to say about things in the
world of sense, we can only succeed in saying that they participate in such and such ideas, which, therefore,
constitute all their character. Hence it is easy to pass on into a mysticism. We may hope, in a mystic
illumination, to see the ideas as we see objects of sense; and we may imagine that the ideas exist in heaven.
These mystical developments are very natural, but the basis of the theory is in logic, and it is as based in logic
that we have to consider it.
The word 'idea' has acquired, in the course of time, many associations which are quite misleading when
applied to Plato's 'ideas'. We shall therefore use the word 'universal' instead of the word 'idea', to describe
what Plato meant. The essence of the sort of entity that Plato meant is that it is opposed to the particular
things that are given in sensation. We speak of whatever is given in sensation, or is of the same nature as
things given in sensation, as a particular; by opposition to this, a universal will be anything which may be
shared by many particulars, and has those characteristics which, as we saw, distinguish justice and whiteness
from just acts and white things.
When we examine common words, we find that, broadly speaking, proper names stand for particulars, while
other substantives, adjectives, prepositions, and verbs stand for universals. Pronouns stand for particulars, but
are ambiguous: it is only by the context or the circumstances that we know what particulars they stand for.
The word 'now' stands for a particular, namely the present moment; but like pronouns, it stands for an
ambiguous particular, because the present is always changing.
It will be seen that no sentence can be made up without at least one word which denotes a universal. The
nearest approach would be some such statement as 'I like this'. But even here the word 'like' denotes a
universal, for I may like other things, and other people may like things. Thus all truths involve universals, and
all knowledge of truths involves acquaintance with universals.
Seeing that nearly all the words to be found in the dictionary stand for universals, it is strange that hardly
anybody except students of philosophy ever realizes that there are such entities as universals. We do not
naturally dwell upon those words in a sentence which do not stand for particulars; and if we are forced to
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS 31
Page No 34
dwell upon a word which stands for a universal, we naturally think of it as standing for some one of the
particulars that come under the universal. When, for example, we hear the sentence, 'Charles I's head was cut
off', we may naturally enough think of Charles I, of Charles I's head, and of the operation of cutting of his
head, which are all particulars; but we do not naturally dwell upon what is meant by the word 'head' or the
word 'cut', which is a universal. We feel such words to be incomplete and insubstantial; they seem to demand
a context before anything can be done with them. Hence we succeed in avoiding all notice of universals as
such, until the study of philosophy forces them upon our attention.
Even among philosophers, we may say, broadly, that only those universals which are named by adjectives or
substantives have been much or often recognized, while those named by verbs and prepositions have been
usually overlooked. This omission has had a very great effect upon philosophy; it is hardly too much to say
that most metaphysics, since Spinoza, has been largely determined by it. The way this has occurred is, in
outline, as follows: Speaking generally, adjectives and common nouns express qualities or properties of
single things, whereas prepositions and verbs tend to express relations between two or more things. Thus the
neglect of prepositions and verbs led to the belief that every proposition can be regarded as attributing a
property to a single thing, rather than as expressing a relation between two or more things. Hence it was
supposed that, ultimately, there can be no such entities as relations between things. Hence either there can be
only one thing in the universe, or, if there are many things, they cannot possibly interact in any way, since
any interaction would be a relation, and relations are impossible.
The first of these views, advocated by Spinoza and held in our own day by Bradley and many other
philosophers, is called monism; the second, advocated Leibniz but not very common nowadays, is called
monadism, because each of the isolated things is cd a monad. Both these opposing philosophies, interesting
as they are, result, in my opinion, from an undue attention to one sort of universals, namely the sort
represented by adjectives and substantives rather than by verbs and prepositions.
As a matter of fact, if any one were anxious to deny altogether that there are such things as universals, we
should find that we cannot strictly prove that there are such entities as qualities, i.e. the universals represented
by adjectives and substantives, whereas we can prove that there must be relations, i.e. the sort of universals
generally represented by verbs and prepositions. Let us take in illustration the universal whiteness. If we
believe that there is such a universal, we shall say that things are white because they have the quality of
whiteness. This view, however, was strenuously denied by Berkeley and Hume, who have been followed in
this by later empiricists. The form which their denial took was to deny that there are such things as 'abstract
ideas'. When we want to think of whiteness, they said, we form an image of some particular white thing, and
reason concerning this particular, taking care not to deduce anything concerning it which we cannot see to be
equally true of any other white thing. As an account of our actual mental processes, this is no doubt largely
true. In geometry, for example, when we wish to prove something about all triangles, we draw a particular
triangle and reason about it, taking care not to use any characteristic which it does not share with other
triangles. The beginner, in order to avoid error, often finds it useful to draw several triangles, as unlike each
other as possible, in order to make sure that his reasoning is equally applicable to all of them. But a difficulty
emerges as soon as we ask ourselves how we know that a thing is white or a triangle. If we wish to avoid the
universals whiteness and triangularity, we shall choose some particular patch of white or some particular
triangle, and say that anything is white or a triangle if it has the right sort of resemblance to our chosen
particular. But then the resemblance required will have to be a universal. Since there are many white things,
the resemblance must hold between many pairs of particular white things; and this is the characteristic of a
universal. It will be useless to say that there is a different resemblance for each pair, for then we shall have to
say that these resemblances resemble each other, and thus at last we shall be forced to admit resemblance as a
universal. The relation of resemblance, therefore, must be a true universal. And having been forced to admit
this universal, we find that it is no longer worth while to invent difficult and unplausible theories to avoid the
admission of such universals as whiteness and triangularity.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS 32
Page No 35
Berkeley and Hume failed to perceive this refutation of their rejection of 'abstract ideas', because, like their
adversaries, they only thought of qualities, and altogether ignored relations as universals. We have therefore
here another respect in which the rationalists appear to have been in the right as against the empiricists,
although, owing to the neglect or denial of relations, the deductions made by rationalists were, if anything,
more apt to be mistaken than those made by empiricists.
Having now seen that there must be such entities as universals, the next point to be proved is that their being
is not merely mental. By this is meant that whatever being belongs to them is independent of their being
thought of or in any way apprehended by minds. We have already touched on this subject at the end of the
preceding chapter, but we must now consider more fully what sort of being it is that belongs universals.
Consider such a proposition as 'Edinburgh is north London'. Here we have a relation between two places, and
it seems plain that the relation subsists independently of our knowledge of it. When we come to know that
Edinburgh is north of London, we come to know something which has to do only with Edinburgh and
London: we do not cause the truth of the proposition by coming to know it, on the contrary we merely
apprehend a fact which was there before we knew it. The part of the earth's surface where Edinburgh stands
would be north of the part where London stands, even if there were no human being to know about north and
south, and even if there were no minds at all in the universe. This is, of course, denied by many philosophers,
either for Berkeley's reasons or for Kant's. But we have already considered these reasons, and decided that
they are inadequate. We may therefore now assume it to be true that nothing mental is presupposed in the fact
that Edinburgh is north of London. But this fact involves the relation 'north of', which is a universal; and it
would be impossible for the whole fact to involve nothing mental if the relation 'north of', which is a
constituent part of the fact, did involve anything mental. Hence we must admit that the relation, like the terms
it relates, is not dependent upon thought, but belongs to the independent world which thought apprehends but
does not create.
This conclusion, however, is met by the difficulty that the relation 'north of' does not seem to exist in the
same sense in which Edinburgh and London exist. If we ask 'Where and when does this relation exist?' the
answer must be 'Nowhere and nowhen'. There is no place or time where we can find the relation 'north of'. It
does not exist in Edinburgh any more than in London, for it relates the two and is neutral as between them.
Nor can we say that it exists at any particular time. Now everything that can be apprehended by the senses or
by introspection exists at some particular time. Hence the relation 'north of' is radically different from such
things. It is neither in space nor in time, neither material nor mental; yet it is something.
It is largely the very peculiar kind of being that belongs to universals which has led many people to suppose
that they are really mental. We can think of a universal, and our thinking then exists in a perfectly ordinary
sense, like any other mental act. Suppose, for example, that we are thinking of whiteness. Then in one sense it
may be said that whiteness is 'in our mind'. We have here the same ambiguity as we noted in discussing
Berkeley in Chapter IV. In the strict sense, it is not whiteness that is in our mind, but the act of thinking of
whiteness. The connected ambiguity in the word 'idea', which we noted at the same time, also causes
confusion here. In one sense of this word, namely the sense in which it denotes the object of an act of
thought, whiteness is an 'idea'. Hence, if the ambiguity is not guarded against, we may come to think that
whiteness is an 'idea' in the other sense, i.e. an act of thought; and thus we come to think that whiteness is
mental. But in so thinking, we rob it of its essential quality of universality. One man's act of thought is
necessarily a different thing from another man's; one man's act of thought at one time is necessarily a
different thing from the same man's act of thought at another time. Hence, if whiteness were the thought as
opposed to its object, no two different men could think of it, and no one man could think of it twice. That
which many different thoughts of whiteness have in common is their object, and this object is different from
all of them. Thus universals are not thoughts, though when known they are the objects of thoughts.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS 33
Page No 36
We shall find it convenient only to speak of things existing when they are in time, that is to say, when we can
point to some time at which they exist (not excluding the possibility of their existing at all times). Thus
thoughts and feelings, minds and physical objects exist. But universals do not exist in this sense; we shall say
that they subsist or have being, where 'being' is opposed to 'existence' as being timeless. The world of
universals, therefore, may also be described as the world of being. The world of being is unchangeable, rigid,
exact, delightful to the mathematician, the logician, the builder of metaphysical systems, and all who love
perfection more than life. The world of existence is fleeting, vague, without sharp boundaries, without any
clear plan or arrangement, but it contains all thoughts and feelings, all the data of sense, and all physical
objects, everything that can do either good or harm, everything that makes any difference to the value of life
and the world. According to our temperaments, we shall prefer the contemplation of the one or of the other.
The one we do not prefer will probably seem to us a pale shadow of the one we prefer, and hardly worthy to
be regarded as in any sense real. But the truth is that both have the same claim on our impartial attention, both
are real, and both are important to the metaphysician. Indeed no sooner have we distinguished the two worlds
than it becomes necessary to consider their relations.
But first of all we must examine our knowledge of universals. This consideration will occupy us in the
following chapter, where we shall find that it solves the problem of a priori knowledge, from which we were
first led to consider universals.
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS
IN regard to one man's knowledge at a given time, universals, like particulars, may be divided into those
known by acquaintance, those known only by description, and those not known either by acquaintance or by
description.
Let us consider first the knowledge of universals by acquaintance. It is obvious, to begin with, that we are
acquainted with such universals as white, red, black, sweet, sour, loud, hard, etc., i.e. with qualities which are
exemplified in sensedata. When we see a white patch, we are acquainted, in the first instance, with the
particular patch; but by seeing many white patches, we easily learn to abstract the whiteness which they all
have in common, and in learning to do this we are learning to be acquainted with whiteness. A similar
process will make us acquainted with any other universal of the same sort. Universals of this sort may be
called 'sensible qualities'. They can be apprehended with less effort of abstraction than any others, and they
seem less removed from particulars than other universals are.
We come next to relations. The easiest relations to apprehend are those which hold between the different
parts of a single complex sensedatum. For example, I can see at a glance the whole of the page on which I
am writing; thus the whole page is included in one sensedatum. But I perceive that some parts of the page
are to the left of other parts, and some parts are above other parts. The process of abstraction in this case
seems to proceed somewhat as follows: I see successively a number of sensedata in which one part is to the
left of another; I perceive, as in the case of different white patches, that all these sensedata have something
in common, and by abstraction I find that what they have in common is a certain relation between their parts,
namely the relation which I call 'being to the left of'. In this way I become acquainted with the universal
relation.
In like manner I become aware of the relation of before and after in time. Suppose I hear a chime of bells:
when the last bell of the chime sounds, I can retain the whole chime before my mind, and I can perceive that
the earlier bells came before the later ones. Also in memory I perceive that what I am remembering came
before the present time. From either of these sources I can abstract the universal relation of before and after,
just as I abstracted the universal relation 'being to the left of'. Thus timerelations, like spacerelations, are
among those with which we are acquainted.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS 34
Page No 37
Another relation with which we become acquainted in much the same way is resemblance. If I see
simultaneously two shades of green, I can see that they resemble each other; if I also see a shade of red at the
same time, I can see that the two greens have more resemblance to each other than either has to the red. In
this way I become acquainted with the universal resemblance or similarity.
Between universals, as between particulars, there relations of which we may be immediately aware. We have
just seen that we can perceive that the resemblance between two shades of green is greater than the
resemblance between a shade of red and a shade of green. Here we are dealing with a relation, namely
'greater than', between two relations. Our knowledge of such relations, though it requires more power of
abstraction than is required for perceiving the qualities of sensedata, appears to be equally immediate, and
(at least in some cases) equally indubitable. Thus there is immediate knowledge concerning universals well as
concerning sensedata.
Returning now to the problem of a priori knowledge, which we left unsolved when we began the
consideration of universals, we find ourselves in a position to deal with it in a much more satisfactory manner
than was possible before. Let us revert to the proposition 'two and two are four'. It is fairly obvious, in view
of what has been said, that this proposition states a relation between the universal 'two' and the universal
'four'. This suggests a proposition which we shall now endeavour to establish: namely, All a priori knowledge
deals exclusively with the relations of universals. This proposition is of great importance, and goes a long
way towards solving our previous difficulties concerning a priori knowledge.
The only case in which it might seem, at first sight, as if our proposition were untrue, is the case in which an
a priori proposition states that all of one class of particulars belong to some other class, or (what comes the
same thing) that all particulars having some one property also have some other. In this case it might seem as
though we were dealing with the particulars that have the property rather than with the property. The
proposition 'two and two are four' is really a case in point, for this may be stated in the form 'any two and any
other two are four', or 'any collection formed of two twos is a collection of four'. If we can show that such
statements as this really deal only with universals, our proposition may be regarded as proved.
One way of discovering what a proposition deals with is to ask ourselves what words we must understand
in other words, what objects we must be acquainted with in order to see what the proposition means. As
soon as we see what the proposition means, even if we do not yet know whether it is true or false, it is evident
that we must have acquaintance with whatever is really dealt with by the proposition. By applying this test, it
appears that many propositions which might seem to be concerned with particulars are really concerned only
with universals. In the special case of 'two and two are four', even when we interpret it as meaning 'any
collection formed of two twos is a collection of four', it is plain that we can understand the proposition, i.e.
we can see what it is that it asserts, as soon as we know what is meant by 'collection' and 'two' and 'four' . It is
quite unnecessary to know all the couples in the world: if it were necessary, obviously we could never
understand the proposition, since the couples are infinitely numerous and therefore cannot all be known to us.
Thus although our general statement implies statements about particular couples, as soon as we know that
there are such particular couples, yet it does not itself assert or imply that there are such particular couples,
and thus fails to make any statement whatever about actual particular couple. The statement made is about
'couple', the universal, and not about this or that couple.
Thus the statement 'two and two are four' deals exclusively with universals, and therefore may be known by
anybody who is acquainted with the universals concerned and can perceive the relation between them which
the statement asserts. It must be taken as a fact, discovered by reflecting upon our knowledge, that we have
the power of sometimes perceiving such relations between universals, and therefore of sometimes knowing
general a priori propositions such as those of arithmetic and logic. The thing that seemed mysterious, when
we formerly considered such knowledge, was that it seemed to anticipate and control experience. This,
however, we can now see to have been an error. No fact concerning anything capable of being experienced
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS 35
Page No 38
can be known independently of experience. We know a priori that two things and two other things together
make four things, but we do not know a priori that if Brown and Jones are two, and Robinson and Smith are
two, then Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith are four. The reason is that this proposition cannot be
understood at all unless we know that there are such people as Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith,
and this we can only know by experience. Hence, although our general proposition is a priori, all its
applications to actual particulars involve experience and therefore contain an empirical element. In this way
what seemed mysterious in our a priori knowledge is seen to have been based upon an error.
It will serve to make the point dearer if we contrast our genuine a priori judgement with an empirical
generalization, such as 'all men are mortals'. Here as before, we can understand what the proposition means as
soon as we understand the universals involved, namely man and mortal. It is obviously unnecessary to have
an individual acquaintance with the whole human race in order to understand what our proposition means.
Thus the difference between an a priori general proposition and an empirical generalization does not come in
the meaning of the proposition; it comes in the nature of the evidence for it. In the empirical case, the
evidence consists in the particular instances. We believe that all men are mortal because we know that there
are innumerable instances of men dying, and no instances of their living beyond a certain age. We do not
believe it because we see a connexion between the universal man and the universal mortal. It is true that if
physiology can prove, assuming the general laws that govern living bodies, that no living organism can last
for ever, that gives a connexion between man and mortality which would enable us to assert our proposition
without appealing to the special evidence of men dying. But that only means that our generalization has been
subsumed under a wider generalization, for which the evidence is still of the same kind, though more
extensive. The progress of science is constantly producing such subsumptions, and therefore giving a
constantly wider inductive basis for scientific generalizations. But although this gives a greater degree of
certainty, it does not give a different kind: the ultimate ground remains inductive, i.e. derived from instances,
and not an a priori connexion of universals such as we have in logic and arithmetic.
Two opposite points are to be observed concerning a priori general propositions. The first is that, if many
particular instances are known, our general proposition may be arrived at in the first instance by induction,
and the connexion of universals may be only subsequently perceived. For example, it is known that if we
draw perpendiculars to the sides of a triangle from the opposite angles, all three perpendiculars meet in a
point. It would be quite possible to be first led to this proposition by actually drawing perpendiculars in many
cases, and finding that they always met in a point; this experience might lead us to look for the general proof
and find it. Such cases are common in the experience of every mathematician.
The other point is more interesting, and of more philosophical importance. It is, that we may sometimes know
a general proposition in cases where we do not know a single instance of it. Take such a case as the
following: We know that any two numbers can be multiplied together, and will give a third called their
product. We know that all pairs of integers the product of which is less than 100 have been actually
multiplied together, and the value of the product recorded in the multiplication table. But we also know that
the number of integers is infinite, and that only a finite number of pairs of integers ever have been or ever
will be thought of by human beings. Hence it follows that there are pairs of integers which never have been
and never will be thought of by human beings, and that all of them deal with integers the product of which is
over 100. Hence we arrive at the proposition: 'All products of two integers, which never have been and never
will be thought of by any human being, are over 100.' Here is a general proposition of which the truth is
undeniable, and yet, from the very nature of the case, we can never give an instance; because any two
numbers we may think of are excluded by the terms of the proposition.
This possibility, of knowledge of general propositions of which no instance can be given, is often denied,
because it is not perceived that the knowledge of such propositions only requires a knowledge of the relations
of universals, and does not require any knowledge of instances of the universals in question. Yet the
knowledge of such general propositions is quite vital to a great deal of what is generally admitted to be
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS 36
Page No 39
known. For example, we saw, in our early chapters, that knowledge of physical objects, as opposed to
sensedata, is only obtained by an inference, and that they are not things with which we are acquainted.
Hence we can never know any proposition of the form 'this is a physical object', where 'this' is something
immediately known. It follows that all our knowledge concerning physical objects is such that no actual
instance can be given. We can give instances of the associated sensedata, but we cannot give instances of
the actual physical objects. Hence our knowledge as to physical objects depends throughout upon this
possibility of general knowledge where no instance can be given. And the same applies to our knowledge of
other people's minds, or of any other class of things of which no instance is known to us by acquaintance.
We may now take a survey of the sources of our knowledge, as they have appeared in the course of our
analysis. We have first to distinguish knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. In each there are two
kinds, one immediate and one derivative. Our immediate knowledge of things, which we called acquaintance,
consists of two sorts, according as the things known are particulars or universals. Among particulars, we have
acquaintance with sensedata and (probably) with ourselves. Among universals, there seems to be no
principle by which we can decide which can be known by acquaintance, but it is clear that among those that
can be so known are sensible qualities, relations of space and time, similarity, and certain abstract logical
universals. Our derivative knowledge of things, which we call knowledge by description, always involves
both acquaintance with something and knowledge of truths. Our immediate knowledge of truths may be
called intuitive knowledge, and the truths so known may be called selfevident truths. Among such truths are
included those which merely state what is given in sense, and also certain abstract logical and arithmetical
principles, and (though with less certainty) some ethical propositions. Our derivative knowledge of truths
consists of everything that we can deduce from selfevident truths by the use of selfevident principles of
deduction.
If the above account is correct, all our knowledge of truths depends upon our intuitive knowledge. It therefore
becomes important to consider the nature and scope of intuitive knowledge, in much the same way as, at an
earlier stage, we considered the nature and scope of knowledge by acquaintance. But knowledge of truths
raises a further problem, which does not arise in regard to knowledge of things, namely the problem of error.
Some of our beliefs turn out to be erroneous, and therefore it becomes necessary to consider how, if at all, we
can distinguish knowledge from error. This problem does not arise with regard to knowledge by
acquaintance, for, whatever may be the object of acquaintance, even in dreams and hallucinations, there is no
error involved so long as we do not go beyond the immediate object: error can only arise when we regard the
immediate object, i.e. the sensedatum, as the mark of some physical object. Thus the problems connected
with knowledge of truths are more difficult than those connected with knowledge of things. As the first of the
problems connected with knowledge of truths, let us examine the nature and scope of our intuitive
judgements.
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE
THERE is a common impression that everything that we believe ought to be capable of proof, or at least of
being shown to be highly probable. It is felt by many that a belief for which no reason can be given is an
unreasonable belief. In the main, this view is just. Almost all our common beliefs are either inferred, or
capable of being inferred, from other beliefs which may be regarded as giving the reason for them. As a rule,
the reason has been forgotten, or has even never been consciously present to our minds. Few of us ever ask
ourselves, for example, what reason there is to suppose the food we are just going to eat will not turn out to
be poison. Yet we feel, when challenged, that a perfectly good reason could be found, even if we are not
ready with it at the moment. And in this belief we are usually justified.
But let us imagine some insistent Socrates, who, whatever reason we give him, continues to demand a reason
for the reason. We must sooner or later, and probably before very long, be driven to a point where we cannot
find any further reason, and where it becomes almost certain that no further reason is even theoretically
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE 37
Page No 40
discoverable. Starting with the common beliefs of daily life, we can be driven back from point to point, until
we come to some general principle, or some instance of a general principle, which seems luminously evident,
and is not itself capable of being deduced from anything more evident. In most questions of daily life, such as
whether our food is likely to be nourishing and not poisonous, we shall be driven back to the inductive
principle, which we discussed in Chapter VI. But beyond that, there seems to be no further regress. The
principle itself is constantly used in our reasoning, sometimes consciously, sometimes unconsciously; but
there is no reasoning which, starting from some simpler selfevident principle, leads us to the principle of
induction as its conclusion. And the same holds for other logical principles. Their truth is evident to us, and
we employ them in constructing demonstrations; but they themselves, or at least some of them, are incapable
of demonstration.
Selfevidence, however, is not confined to those among general principles which are incapable of proof.
When a certain number of logical principles have been admitted, the rest can be deduced from them; but the
propositions deduced are often just as selfevident as those that were assumed without proof. All arithmetic,
moreover, can be deduced from the general principles of logic, yet the simple propositions of arithmetic, such
as 'two and two are four', are just as selfevident as the principles of logic.
It would seem, also, though this is more disputable, that there are some selfevident ethical principles, such
as 'we ought to pursue what is good'.
It should be observed that, in all cases of general principles, particular instances, dealing with familiar things,
are more evident than the general principle. For example, the law of contradiction states that nothing can both
have a certain property and not have it. This is evident as soon as it is understood, but it is not so evident as
that a particular rose which we see cannot be both red and not red. (It is of course possible that parts of the
rose may be red and parts not red, or that the rose may be of a shade of pink which we hardly know whether
to call red or not; but in the former case it is plain that the rose as a whole is not red, while in the latter case
the answer is theoretically definite as soon as we have decided on a precise definition of 'red'.) It is usually
through particular instances that we come to be able to see the general principle. Only those who are practised
in dealing with abstractions can readily grasp a general principle without the help of instances.
In addition to general principles, the other kind of selfevident truths are those immediately derived from
sensation. We will call such truths 'truths of perception', and the judgements expressing them we will call
'judgements of perception'. But here a certain amount of care is required in getting at the precise nature of the
truths that are selfevident. The actual sensedata are neither true nor false. A particular patch of colour
which I see, for example, simply exists: it is not the sort of thing that is true or false. It is true that there is
such a patch, true that it has a certain shape and degree of brightness, true that it is surrounded by certain
other colours. But the patch itself, like everything else in the world of sense, is of a radically different kind
from the things that are true or false, and therefore cannot properly be said to be true. Thus whatever
selfevident truths may be obtained from our senses must be different from the sensedata from which they
are obtained.
It would seem that there are two kinds of selfevident truths of perception, though perhaps in the last analysis
the two kinds may coalesce. First, there is the kind which simply asserts the existence of the sensedatum,
without in any way analysing it. We see a patch of red, and we judge 'there is suchandsuch a patch of red',
or more strictly 'there is that'; this is one kind of intuitive judgement of perception. The other kind arises
when the object of sense is complex, and we subject it to some degree of analysis. If, for instance, we see a
round patch of red, we may judge 'that patch of red is round'. This is again a judgement of perception, but it
differs from our previous kind. In our present kind we have a single sensedatum which has both colour and
shape: the colour is red and the shape is round. Our judgement analyses the datum into colour and shape, and
then recombines them by stating that the red colour is round in shape. Another example of this kind of
judgement is 'this is to the right of that', where 'this' and 'that' are seen simultaneously. In this kind of
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE 38
Page No 41
judgement the sensedatum contains constituents which have some relation to each other, and the judgement
asserts that these constituents have this relation.
Another class of intuitive judgements, analogous to those of sense and yet quite distinct from them, are
judgements of memory. There is some danger of confusion as to the nature of memory, owing to the fact that
memory of an object is apt to be accompanied by an image of the object, and yet the image cannot be what
constitutes memory. This is easily seen by merely noticing that the image is in the present, whereas what is
remembered is known to be in the past. Moreover, we are certainly able to some extent to compare our image
with the object remembered, so that we often know, within somewhat wide limits, how far our image is
accurate; but this would be impossible, unless the object, as opposed to the image, were in some way before
the mind. Thus the essence of memory is not constituted by the image, but by having immediately before the
mind an object which is recognized as past. But for the fact of memory in this sense, we should not know that
there ever was a past at all, nor should we be able to understand the word 'past', any more than a man born
blind can understand the word 'light'. Thus there must be intuitive judgements of memory, and it is upon
them, ultimately, that all our knowledge of the past depends.
The case of memory, however, raises a difficulty, for it is notoriously fallacious, and thus throws doubt on the
trustworthiness of intuitive judgements in general. This difficulty is no light one. But let us first narrow its
scope as far as possible. Broadly speaking, memory is trustworthy in proportion to the vividness of the
experience and to its nearness in time. If the house next door was struck by lightning half a minute ago, my
memory of what I saw and heard will be so reliable that it would be preposterous to doubt whether there had
been a flash at all. And the same applies to less vivid experiences, so long as they are recent. I am absolutely
certain that half a minute ago I was sitting in the same chair in which I am sitting now. Going backward over
the day, I find things of which I am quite certain, other things of which I am almost certain, other things of
which I can become certain by thought and by calling up attendant circumstances, and some things of which I
am by no means certain. I am quite certain that I ate my breakfast this morning, but if I were as indifferent to
my breakfast as a philosopher should be, I should be doubtful. As to the conversation at breakfast, I can recall
some of it easily, some with an effort, some only with a large element of doubt, and some not at all. Thus
there is a continual gradation in the degree of selfevidence of what I remember, and a corresponding
gradation in the trustworthiness of my memory.
Thus the first answer to the difficulty of fallacious memory is to say that memory has degrees of
selfevidence, and that these correspond to the degrees of its trustworthiness, reaching a limit of perfect
selfevidence and perfect trustworthiness in our memory of events which are recent and vivid.
It would seem, however, that there are cases of very firm belief in a memory which is wholly false. It is
probable that, in these cases, what is really remembered, in the sense of being immediately before the mind,
is something other than what is falsely believed in, though something generally associated with it. George IV
is said to have at last believed that he was at the battle of Waterloo, because he had so often said that he was.
In this case, what was immediately remembered was his repeated assertion; the belief in what he was
asserting (if it existed) would be produced by association with the remembered assertion, and would therefore
not be a genuine case of memory. It would seem that cases of fallacious memory can probably all be dealt
with in this way, i.e. they can be shown to be not cases of memory in the strict sense at all.
One important point about selfevidence is made clear by the case of memory, and that is, that selfevidence
has degrees: it is not a quality which is simply present or absent, but a quality which may be more or less
present, in gradations ranging from absolute certainty down to an almost imperceptible faintness. Truths of
perception and some of the principles of logic have the very highest degree of selfevidence; truths of
immediate memory have an almost equally high degree. The inductive principle has less selfevidence than
some of the other principles of logic, such as 'what follows from a true premiss must be true'. Memories have
a diminishing selfevidence as they become remoter and fainter; the truths of logic and mathematics have
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE 39
Page No 42
(broadly speaking) less selfevidence as they become more complicated. Judgements of intrinsic ethical or
aesthetic value are apt to have some selfevidence, but not much.
Degrees of selfevidence are important in the theory of knowledge, since, if propositions may (as seems
likely) have some degree of selfevidence without being true, it will not be necessary to abandon all
connexion between selfevidence and truth, but merely to say that, where there is a conflict, the more
selfevident proposition is to be retained and the less selfevident rejected.
It seems, however, highly probable that two different notions are combined in 'selfevidence' as above
explained; that one of them, which corresponds to the highest degree of selfevidence, is really an infallible
guarantee of truth, while the other, which corresponds to all the other degrees, does not give an infallible
guarantee, but only a greater or less presumption. This, however, is only a suggestion, which we cannot as yet
develop further. After we have dealt with the nature of truth, we shall return to the subject of selfevidence,
in connexion with the distinction between knowledge and error.
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD
OUR knowledge of truths, unlike our knowledge of things, has an opposite, namely error. So far as things are
concerned, we may know them or not know them, but there is no positive state of mind which can be
described as erroneous knowledge of things, so long, at any rate, as we confine ourselves to knowledge by
acquaintance. Whatever we are acquainted with must be something; we may draw wrong inferences from our
acquaintance, but the acquaintance itself cannot be deceptive. Thus there is no dualism as regards
acquaintance. But as regards knowledge of truths, there is a dualism. We may believe what is false as well as
what is true. We know that on very many subjects different people hold different and incompatible opinions:
hence some beliefs must be erroneous. Since erroneous beliefs are often held just as strongly as true beliefs, it
becomes a difficult question how they are to be distinguished from true beliefs. How are we to know, in a
given case, that our belief is not erroneous? This is a question of the very greatest difficulty, to which no
completely satisfactory answer is possible. There is, however, a preliminary question which is rather less
difficult, and that is: What do we mean by truth and falsehood? It is this preliminary question which is to be
considered in this chapter.
In this chapter we are not asking how we can know whether a belief is true or false: we are asking what is
meant by the question whether a belief is true or false. It is to be hoped that a clear answer to this question
may help us to obtain an answer to the question what beliefs are true, but for the present we ask only 'What is
truth?' and 'What is falsehood?' not 'What beliefs are true?' and 'What beliefs are false?' It is very important to
keep these different questions entirely separate, since any confusion between them is sure to produce an
answer which is not really applicable to either.
There are three points to observe in the attempt to discover the nature of truth, three requisites which any
theory must fulfil.
(1) Our theory of truth must be such as to admit of its opposite, falsehood. A good many philosophers have
failed adequately to satisfy this condition: they have constructed theories according to which all our thinking
ought to have been true, and have then had the greatest difficulty in finding a place for falsehood. In this
respect our theory of belief must differ from our theory of acquaintance, since in the case of acquaintance it
was not necessary to take account of any opposite.
(2) It seems fairly evident that if there were no beliefs there could be no falsehood, and no truth either, in the
sense in which truth is correlative to falsehood. If we imagine a world of mere matter, there would be no
room for falsehood in such a world, and although it would contain what may be called 'facts', it would not
contain any truths, in the sense in which truths are thins of the same kind as falsehoods. In fact, truth and
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD 40
Page No 43
falsehood are properties of beliefs and statements: hence a world of mere matter, since it would contain no
beliefs or statements, would also contain no truth or falsehood.
(3) But, as against what we have just said, it is to be observed that the truth or falsehood of a belief always
depends upon something which lies outside the belief itself. If I believe that Charles I died on the scaffold, I
believe truly, not because of any intrinsic quality of my belief, which could be discovered by merely
examining the belief, but because of an historical event which happened two and a half centuries ago. If I
believe that Charles I died in his bed, I believe falsely: no degree of vividness in my belief, or of care in
arriving at it, prevents it from being false, again because of what happened long ago, and not because of any
intrinsic property of my belief. Hence, although truth and falsehood are properties of beliefs, they are
properties dependent upon the relations of the beliefs to other things, not upon any internal quality of the
beliefs.
The third of the above requisites leads us to adopt the view which has on the whole been commonest
among philosophers that truth consists in some form of correspondence between belief and fact. It is,
however, by no means an easy matter to discover a form of correspondence to which there are no irrefutable
objections. By this partly and partly by the feeling that, if truth consists in a correspondence of thought
with something outside thought, thought can never know when truth has been attained many philosophers
have been led to try to find some definition of truth which shall not consist in relation to something wholly
outside belief. The most important attempt at a definition of this sort is the theory that truth consists in
coherence. It is said that the mark of falsehood is failure to cohere in the body of our beliefs, and that it is the
essence of a truth to form part of the completely rounded system which is The Truth.
There is, however, a great difficulty in this view, or rather two great difficulties. The first is that there is no
reason to suppose that only one coherent body of beliefs is possible. It may be that, with sufficient
imagination, a novelist might invent a past for the world that would perfectly fit on to what we know, and yet
be quite different from the real past. In more scientific matters, it is certain that there are often two or more
hypotheses which account for all the known facts on some subject, and although, in such cases, men of
science endeavour to find facts which will rule out all the hypotheses except one, there is no reason why they
should always succeed.
In philosophy, again, it seems not uncommon for two rival hypotheses to be both able to account for all the
facts. Thus, for example, it is possible that life is one long dream, and that the outer world has only that
degree of reality that the objects of dreams have; but although such a view does not seem inconsistent with
known facts, there is no reason to prefer it to the commonsense view, according to which other people and
things do really exist. Thus coherence as the definition of truth fails because there is no proof that there can
be only one coherent system.
The other objection to this definition of truth is that it assumes the meaning of 'coherence' known, whereas, in
fact, 'coherence' presupposes the truth of the laws of logic. Two propositions are coherent when both may be
true, and are incoherent when one at least must be false. Now in order to know whether two propositions can
both be true, we must know such truths as the law of contradiction. For example, the two propositions, 'this
tree is a beech' and 'this tree is not a beech', are not coherent, because of the law of contradiction. But if the
law of contradiction itself were subjected to the test of coherence, we should find that, if we choose to
suppose it false, nothing will any longer be incoherent with anything else. Thus the laws of logic supply the
skeleton or framework within which the test of coherence applies, and they themselves cannot be established
by this test.
For the above two reasons, coherence cannot be accepted as giving the meaning of truth, though it is often a
most important test of truth after a certain amount of truth has become known.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD 41
Page No 44
Hence we are driven back to correspondence with fact as constituting the nature of truth. It remains to define
precisely what we mean by 'fact', and what is the nature of the correspondence which must subsist between
belief and fact, in order that belief may be true.
In accordance with our three requisites, we have to seek a theory of truth which (1) allows truth to have an
opposite, namely falsehood, (2) makes truth a property of beliefs, but (3) makes it a property wholly
dependent upon the relation of the beliefs to outside things.
The necessity of allowing for falsehood makes it impossible to regard belief as a relation of the mind to a
single object, which could be said to be what is believed. If belief were so regarded, we should find that, like
acquaintance, it would not admit of the opposition of truth and falsehood, but would have to be always true.
This may be made clear by examples. Othello believes falsely that Desdemona loves Cassio. We cannot say
that this belief consists in a relation to a single object, 'Desdemona's love for Cassio', for if there were such an
object, the belief would be true. There is in fact no such object, and therefore Othello cannot have any
relation to such an object. Hence his belief cannot possibly consist in a relation to this object.
It might be said that his belief is a relation to a different object, namely 'that Desdemona loves Cassio'; but it
is almost as difficult to suppose that there is such an object as this, when Desdemona does not love Cassio, as
it was to suppose that there is 'Desdemona's love for Cassio'. Hence it will be better to seek for a theory of
belief which does not make it consist in a relation of the mind to a single object.
It is common to think of relations as though they always held between two terms, but in fact this is not always
the case. Some relations demand three terms, some four, and so on. Take, for instance, the relation 'between'.
So long as only two terms come in, the relation 'between' is impossible: three terms are the smallest number
that render it possible. York is between London and Edinburgh; but if London and Edinburgh were the only
places in the world, there could be nothing which was between one place and another. Similarly jealousy
requires three people: there can be no such relation that does not involve three at least. Such a proposition as
'A wishes B to promote C's marriage with D' involves a relation of four terms; that is to say, A and B and C
and D all come in, and the relation involved cannot be expressed otherwise than in a form involving all four.
Instances might be multiplied indefinitely, but enough has been said to show that there are relations which
require more than two terms before they can occur.
The relation involved in judging or believing must, if falsehood is to be duly allowed for, be taken to be a
relation between several terms, not between two. When Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio, he
must not have before his mind a single object, 'Desdemona's love for Cassio', or 'that Desdemona loves
Cassio', for that would require that there should be objective falsehoods, which subsist independently of any
minds; and this, though not logically refutable, is a theory to be avoided if possible. Thus it is easier to
account for falsehood if we take judgement to be a relation in which the mind and the various objects
concerned all occur severally; that is to say, Desdemona and loving and Cassio must all be terms in the
relation which subsists when Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio. This relation, therefore, is a
relation of four terms, since Othello also is one of the terms of the relation. When we say that it is a relation
of four terms, we do not mean that Othello has a certain relation to Desdemona, and has the same relation to
loving and also to Cassio. This may be true of some other relation than believing; but believing, plainly, is
not a relation which Othello has to each of the three terms concerned, but to all of them together: there is only
one example of the relation of believing involved, but this one example knits together four terms. Thus the
actual occurrence, at the moment when Othello is entertaining his belief, is that the relation called 'believing'
is knitting together into one complex whole the four terms Othello, Desdemona, loving, and Cassio. What is
called belief or judgement is nothing but this relation of believing or judging, which relates a mind to several
things other than itself. An act of belief or of judgement is the occurrence between certain terms at some
particular time, of the relation of believing or judging.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD 42
Page No 45
We are now in a position to understand what it is that distinguishes a true judgement from a false one. For
this purpose we will adopt certain definitions. In every act of judgement there is a mind which judges, and
there are terms concerning which it judges. We will call the mind the subject in the judgement, and the
remaining terms the objects. Thus, when Othello judges that Desdemona loves Cassio, Othello is the subject,
while the objects are Desdemona and loving and Cassio. The subject and the objects together are called the
constituents of the judgement. It will be observed that the elation of judging has what is called a 'sense' or
'direction'. We may say, metaphorically, that it puts its objects in a certain order, which we may indicate by
means of the order of the words in the sentence. (In an inflected language, the same thing will be indicated by
inflections, e.g. by the difference between nominative and accusative.) Othello's judgement that Cassio loves
Desdemona differs from his judgement that Desdemona loves Cassio, in spite of the fact that it consists of the
same constituents, because the relation of judging places the constituents in a different order in the two cases.
Similarly, if Cassio judges that Desdemona loves Othello, the constituents of the judgement are still the same,
but their order is different. This property of having a 'sense' or 'direction' is one which the relation of judging
shares with all other relations. The 'sense' of relations is the ultimate source of order and series and a host of
mathematical concepts; but we need not concern ourselves further with this aspect.
We spoke of the relation called 'judging' or 'believing' as knitting together into one complex whole the subject
and the objects. In this respect, judging is exactly like every other relation. Whenever a relation holds
between two or more terms, it unites the terms into a complex whole. If Othello loves Desdemona, there is
such a complex whole as 'Othello's love for Desdemona'. The terms united by the relation may be themselves
complex, or may be simple, but the whole which results from their being united must be complex. Wherever
there is a relation which relates certain terms, there is a complex object formed of the union of those terms;
and conversely, wherever there is a complex object, there is a relation which relates its constituents. When an
act of believing occurs, there is a complex, in which 'believing' is the uniting relation, and subject and objects
are arranged in a certain order by the 'sense' of the relation of believing. Among the objects, as we saw in
considering 'Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio', one must be a relation in this instance, the
relation 'loving'. But this relation, as it occurs in the act of believing, is not the relation which creates the
unity of the complex whole consisting of the subject and the objects. The relation 'loving', as it occurs in the
act of believing, is one of the objects it is a brick in the structure, not the cement. The cement is the
relation 'believing'. When the belief is true, there is another complex unity, in which the relation which was
one of the objects of the belief relates the other objects. Thus, e.g., if Othello believes truly that Desdemona
loves Cassio, then there is a complex unity, 'Desdemona's love for Cassio', which is composed exclusively of
the objects of the belief, in the same order as they had in the belief, with the relation which was one of the
objects occurring now as the cement that binds together the other objects of the belief. On the other hand,
when a belief is false, there is no such complex unity composed only of the objects of the belief. If Othello
believes falsely that Desdemona loves Cassio, then there is no such complex unity as 'Desdemona's love for
Cassio'.
Thus a belief is true when it corresponds to a certain associated complex, and false when it does not.
Assuming, for the sake of definiteness, that the objects of the belief are two terms and a relation, the terms
being put in a certain order by the 'sense' of the believing, then if the two terms in that order are united by the
relation into a complex, the belief is true; if not, it is false. This constitutes the definition of truth and
falsehood that we were in search of. Judging or believing is a certain complex unity of which a mind is a
constituent; if the remaining constituents, taken in the order which they have in the belief, form a complex
unity, then the belief is true; if not, it is false.
Thus although truth and falsehood are properties of beliefs, yet they are in a sense extrinsic properties, for the
condition of the truth of a belief is something not involving beliefs, or (in general) any mind at all, but only
the objects of the belief. A mind, which believes, believes truly when there is a corresponding complex not
involving the mind, but only its objects. This correspondence ensures truth, and its absence entails falsehood.
Hence we account simultaneously for the two facts that beliefs (a) depend on minds for their existence, (b) do
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD 43
Page No 46
not depend on minds for their truth.
We may restate our theory as follows: If we take such a belief as 'Othello believes that Desdemona loves
Cassio', we will call Desdemona and Cassio the objectterms, and loving the objectrelation. If there is a
complex unity 'Desdemona's love for Cassio', consisting of the objectterms related by the objectrelation in
the same order as they have in the belief, then this complex unity is called the fact corresponding to the
belief. Thus a belief is true when there is a corresponding fact, and is false when there is no corresponding
fact.
It will be seen that minds do not create truth or falsehood. They create beliefs, but when once the beliefs are
created, the mind cannot make them true or false, except in the special case where they concern future things
which are within the power of the person believing, such as catching trains. What makes a belief true is a fact,
and this fact does not (except in exceptional cases) in any way involve the mind of the person who has the
belief.
Having now decided what we mean by truth and falsehood, we have next to consider what ways there are of
knowing whether this or that belief is true or false. This consideration will occupy the next chapter.
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION
THE question as to what we mean by truth and falsehood, which we considered in the preceding chapter, is of
much less interest than the question as to how we can know what is true and what is false. This question will
occupy us in the present chapter. There can be no doubt that some of our beliefs are erroneous; thus we are
led to inquire what certainty we can ever have that such and such a belief is not erroneous. In other words,
can we ever know anything at all, or do we merely sometimes by good luck believe what is true? Before we
can attack this question, we must, however, first decide what we mean by 'knowing', and this question is not
so easy as might be supposed.
At first sight we might imagine that knowledge could be defined as 'true belief'. When what we believe is
true, it might be supposed that we had achieved a knowledge of what we believe. But this would not accord
with the way in which the word is commonly used. To take a very trivial instance: If a man believes that the
late Prime Minister's last name began with a B, he believes what is true, since the late Prime Minister was Sir
Henry Campbell Bannerman. But if he believes that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime Minister, he will still
believe that the late Prime Minister's last name began with a B, yet this belief, though true, would not be
thought to constitute knowledge. If a newspaper, by an intelligent anticipation, announces the result of a
battle before any telegram giving the result has been received, it may by good fortune announce what
afterwards turns out to be the right result, and it may produce belief in some of its less experienced readers.
But in spite of the truth of their belief, they cannot be said to have knowledge. Thus it is clear that a true
belief is not knowledge when it is deduced from a false belief.
In like manner, a true belief cannot be called knowledge when it is deduced by a fallacious process of
reasoning, even if the premisses from which it is deduced are true. If I know that all Greeks are men and that
Socrates was a man, and I infer that Socrates was a Greek, I cannot be said to know that Socrates was a
Greek, because, although my premisses and my conclusion are true, the conclusion does not follow from the
premisses.
But are we to say that nothing is knowledge except what is validly deduced from true premisses? Obviously
we cannot say this. Such a definition is at once too wide and too narrow. In the first place, it is too wide,
because it is not enough that our premisses should be true, they must also be known. The man who believes
that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime Minister may proceed to draw valid deductions from the true premiss that
the late Prime Minister's name began with a B, but he cannot be said to know the conclusions reached by
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION 44
Page No 47
these deductions. Thus we shall have to amend our definition by saying that knowledge is what is validly
deduced from known premisses. This, however, is a circular definition: it assumes that we already know what
is meant by 'known premisses'. It can, therefore, at best define one sort of knowledge, the sort we call
derivative, as opposed to intuitive knowledge. We may say: 'Derivative knowledge is what is validly deduced
from premisses known intuitively'. In this statement there is no formal defect, but it leaves the definition of
intuitive knowledge still to seek.
Leaving on one side, for the moment, the question of intuitive knowledge, let us consider the above suggested
definition of derivative knowledge. The chief objection to it is that it unduly limits knowledge. It constantly
happens that people entertain a true belief, which has grown up in them because of some piece of intuitive
knowledge from which it is capable of being validly inferred, but from which it has not, as a matter of fact,
been inferred by any logical process.
Take, for example, the beliefs produced by reading. If the newspapers announce the death of the King, we are
fairly well justified in believing that the King is dead, since this is the sort of announcement which would not
be made if it were false. And we are quite amply justified in believing that the newspaper asserts that the
King is dead. But here the intuitive knowledge upon which our belief is based is knowledge of the existence
of sensedata derived from looking at the print which gives the news. This knowledge scarcely rises into
consciousness, except in a person who cannot read easily. A child may be aware of the shapes of the letters,
and pass gradually and painfully to a realization of their meaning. But anybody accustomed to reading passes
at once to what the letters mean, and is not aware, except on reflection, that he has derived this knowledge
from the sensedata called seeing the printed letters. Thus although a valid inference from the letters to their
meaning is possible, and could be performed by the reader, it s not in fact performed, since he does not in fact
perform any operation which can be called logical inference. Yet it would be absurd to say that the reader
does not know that the newspaper announces the King's death.
We must, therefore, admit as derivative knowledge whatever is the result of intuitive knowledge even if by
mere association, provided there is a valid logical connexion, and the person in question could become aware
of this connexion by reflection. There are in fact many ways, besides logical inference, by which we pass
from one belief to another: the passage from the print to its meaning illustrates these ways. These ways may
be called 'psychological inference'. We shall, then, admit such psychological inference as a means of
obtaining derivative knowledge, provided there is a discoverable logical inference which runs parallel to the
psychological inference. This renders our definition of derivative knowledge less precise than we could wish,
since the word 'discoverable' is vague: it does not tell us how much reflection may be needed in order to make
the discovery. But in fact 'knowledge' is not a precise conception: it merges into 'probable opinion', as we
shall see more fully in the course of the present chapter. A very precise definition, therefore, should not be
sought, since any such definition must be more or less misleading.
The chief difficulty in regard to knowledge, however, does not arise over derivative knowledge, but over
intuitive knowledge. So long as we are dealing with derivative knowledge, we have the test of intuitive
knowledge to fall back upon. But in regard to intuitive beliefs, it is by no means easy to discover any criterion
by which to distinguish some as true and others as erroneous. In this question it is scarcely possible to reach
any very precise result: all our knowledge of truths is infected with some degree of doubt, and a theory which
ignored this fact would be plainly wrong. Something may be done, however, to mitigate the difficulties of the
question.
Our theory of truth, to begin with, supplies the possibility of distinguishing certain truths as selfevident in a
sense which ensures infallibility. When a belief is true, we said, there is a corresponding fact, in which the
several objects of the belief form a single complex. The belief is said to constitute knowledge of this fact,
provided it fulfils those further somewhat vague conditions which we have been considering in the present
chapter. But in regard to any fact, besides the knowledge constituted by belief, we may also have the kind of
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION 45
Page No 48
knowledge constituted by perception (taking this word in its widest possible sense). For example, if you
know the hour of the sunset, you can at that hour know the fact that the sun is setting: this is knowledge of the
fact by way of knowledge of truths; but you can also, if the weather is fine, look to the west and actually see
the setting sun: you then know the same fact by the way of knowledge of things.
Thus in regard to any complex fact, there are, theoretically, two ways in which it may be known: (1) by
means of a judgement, in which its several parts are judged to be related as they are in fact related; (2) by
means of acquaintance with the complex fact itself, which may (in a large sense) be called perception, though
it is by no means confined to objects of the senses. Now it will be observed that the second way of knowing a
complex fact, the way of acquaintance, is only possible when there really is such a fact, while the first way,
like all judgement, is liable to error. The second way gives us the complex whole, and is therefore only
possible when its parts do actually have that relation which makes them combine to form such a complex.
The first way, on the contrary, gives us the parts and the relation severally, and demands only the reality of
the parts and the relation: the relation may not relate those parts in that way, and yet the judgement may
occur.
It will be remembered that at the end of Chapter XI we suggested that there might be two kinds of
selfevidence, one giving an absolute guarantee of truth, the other only a partial guarantee. These two kinds
can now be distinguished.
We may say that a truth is selfevident, in the first and most absolute sense, when we have acquaintance with
the fact which corresponds to the truth. When Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio, the
corresponding fact, if his belief were true, would be 'Desdemona's love for Cassio'. This would be a fact with
which no one could have acquaintance except Desdemona; hence in the sense of selfevidence that we are
considering, the truth that Desdemona loves Cassio (if it were a truth) could only be selfevident to
Desdemona. All mental facts, and all facts concerning sensedata, have this same privacy: there is only one
person to whom they can be selfevident in our present sense, since there is only one person who can be
acquainted with the mental things or the sensedata concerned. Thus no fact about any particular existing
thing can be selfevident to more than one person. On the other hand, facts about universals do not have this
privacy. Many minds may be acquainted with the same universals; hence a relation between universals may
be known by acquaintance to many different people. In all cases where we know by acquaintance a complex
fact consisting of certain terms in a certain relation, we say that the truth that these terms are so related has
the first or absolute kind of selfevidence, and in these cases the judgement that the terms are so related must
be true. Thus this sort of selfevidence is an absolute guarantee of truth.
But although this sort of selfevidence is an absolute guarantee of truth, it does not enable us to be absolutely
certain, in the case of any given judgement, that the judgement in question is true. Suppose we first perceive
the sun shining, which is a complex fact, and thence proceed to make the judgement 'the sun is shining'. In
passing from the perception to the judgement, it is necessary to analyse the given complex fact: we have to
separate out 'the sun' and 'shining' as constituents of the fact. In this process it is possible to commit an error;
hence even where a fact has the first or absolute kind of selfevidence, a judgement believed to correspond to
the fact is not absolutely infallible, because it may not really correspond to the fact. But if it does correspond
(in the sense explained in the preceding chapter), then it must be true.
The second sort of selfevidence will be that which belongs to judgements in the first instance, and is not
derived from direct perception of a fact as a single complex whole. This second kind of selfevidence will
have degrees, from the very highest degree down to a bare inclination in favour of the belief. Take, for
example, the case of a horse trotting away from us along a hard road. At first our certainty that we hear the
hoofs is complete; gradually, if we listen intently, there comes a moment when we think perhaps it was
imagination or the blind upstairs or our own heartbeats; at last we become doubtful whether there was any
noise at all; then we think we no longer hear anything, and at last we know we no longer hear anything. In
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION 46
Page No 49
this process, there is a continual gradation of selfevidence, from the highest degree to the least, not in the
sensedata themselves, but in the judgements based on them.
Or again: Suppose we are comparing two shades of colour, one blue and one green. We can be quite sure they
are different shades of colour; but if the green colour is gradually altered to be more and more like the blue,
becoming first a bluegreen, then a greenyblue, then blue, there will come a moment when we are doubtful
whether we can see any difference, and then a moment when we know that we cannot see any difference. The
same thing happens in tuning a musical instrument, or in any other case where there is a continuous
gradation. Thus selfevidence of this sort is a matter of degree; and it seems plain that the higher degrees are
more to be trusted than the lower degrees.
In derivative knowledge our ultimate premisses must have some degree of selfevidence, and so must their
connexion with the conclusions deduced from them. Take for example a piece of reasoning in geometry. It is
not enough that the axioms from which we start should be selfevident: it is necessary also that, at each step
in the reasoning, the connexion of premiss and conclusion should be selfevident. In difficult reasoning, this
connexion has often only a very small degree of selfevidence; hence errors of reasoning are not improbable
where the difficulty is great.
From what has been said it is evident that, both as regards intuitive knowledge and as regards derivative
knowledge, if we assume that intuitive knowledge is trustworthy in proportion to the degree of its
selfevidence, there will be a gradation in trustworthiness, from the existence of noteworthy sensedata and
the simpler truths of logic and arithmetic, which may be taken as quite certain, down to judgements which
seem only just more probable than their opposites. What we firmly believe, if it is true, is called knowledge,
provided it is either intuitive or inferred (logically or psychologically) from intuitive knowledge from which
it follows logically. What we firmly believe, if it is not true, is called error. What we firmly believe, if it is
neither knowledge nor error, and also what we believe hesitatingly, because it is, or is derived from,
something which has not the highest degree of selfevidence, may be called probable opinion. Thus the
greater part of what would commonly pass as knowledge is more or less probable opinion.
In regard to probable opinion, we can derive great assistance from coherence, which we rejected as the
definition of truth, but may often use as a criterion. A body of individually probable opinions, if they are
mutually coherent, become more probable than any one of them would be individually. It is in this way that
many scientific hypotheses acquire their probability. They fit into a coherent system of probable opinions,
and thus become more probable than they would be in isolation. The same thing applies to general
philosophical hypotheses. Often in a single case such hypotheses may seem highly doubtful, while yet, when
we consider the order and coherence which they introduce into a mass of probable opinion, they become
pretty nearly certain. This applies, in particular, to such matters as the distinction between dreams and waking
life. If our dreams, night after night, were as coherent one with another as our days, we should hardly know
whether to believe the dreams or the waking life. As it is, the test of coherence condemns the dreams and
confirms the waking life. But this test, though it increases probability where it is successful, never gives
absolute certainty, unless there is certainty already at some point in the coherent system. Thus the mere
organization of probable opinion will never, by itself, transform it into indubitable knowledge.
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE
IN all that we have said hitherto concerning philosophy, we have scarcely touched on many matters that
occupy a great space in the writings of most philosophers. Most philosophers or, at any rate, very many
profess to be able to prove, by a priori metaphysical reasoning, such things as the fundamental dogmas of
religion, the essential rationality of the universe, the illusoriness of matter, the unreality of all evil, and so on.
There can be no doubt that the hope of finding reason to believe such theses as these has been the chief
inspiration of many lifelong students of philosophy. This hope, I believe, is vain. It would seem that
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE 47
Page No 50
knowledge concerning the universe as a whole is not to be obtained by metaphysics, and that the proposed
proofs that, in virtue of the laws of logic such and such things must exist and such and such others cannot, are
not capable of surviving a critical scrutiny. In this chapter we shall briefly consider the kind of way in which
such reasoning is attempted, with a view to discovering whether we can hope that it may be valid.
The great representative, in modern times, of the kind of view which we wish to examine, was Hegel
(17701831). Hegel's philosophy is very difficult, and commentators differ as to the true interpretation of it.
According to the interpretation I shall adopt, which is that of many, if not most, of the commentators and has
the merit of giving an interesting and important type of philosophy, his main thesis is that everything short of
the Whole is obviously fragmentary, and obviously incapable of existing without the complement supplied by
the rest of the world. Just as a comparative anatomist, from a single bone, sees what kind of animal the whole
must have been, so the metaphysician, according to Hegel, sees, from any one piece of reality, what the
whole of reality must be at least in its large outlines. Every apparently separate piece of reality has, as it
were, hooks which grapple it to the next piece; the next piece, in turn, has fresh hooks, and so on, until the
whole universe is reconstructed. This essential incompleteness appears, according to Hegel, equally in the
world of thought and in the world of things. In the world of thought, if we take any idea which is abstract or
incomplete, we find, on examination, that if we forget its incompleteness, we become involved in
contradictions; these contradictions turn the idea in question into its opposite, or antithesis; and in order to
escape, we have to find a new, less incomplete idea, which is the synthesis of our original idea and its
antithesis. This new idea, though less incomplete than the idea we started with, will be found, nevertheless, to
be still not wholly complete, but to pass into its antithesis, with which it must be combined in a new
synthesis. In this way Hegel advances until he reaches the 'Absolute Idea', which, according to him, has no
incompleteness, no opposite, and no need of further development. The Absolute Idea, therefore, is adequate
to describe Absolute Reality; but all lower ideas only describe ality as it appears to a partial view, not as it is
to one who simultaneously surveys the Whole. Thus Hegel reaches the conclusion that Absolute Reality
forms one single harmonious system, not in space or time, not in any degree evil, wholly rational, and wholly
spiritual. Any appearance to the contrary, in the world we know, can be proved logically so he believes
to be entirely due to our fragmentary piecemeal view of the universe. If we saw the universe whole, as we
may suppose God sees it, space and time and matter and evil and all striving and struggling would disappear,
and we should see instead an eternal perfect unchanging spiritual unity.
In this conception, there is undeniably something sublime, something to which we could wish to yield assent.
Nevertheless, when the arguments in support of it are carefully examined, they appear to involve much
confusion and many unwarrantable assumptions. The fundamental tenet upon which the system is built up is
that what is incomplete must be not selfsubsistent, but must need the support of other things before it can
exist. It is held that whatever has relations to things outside itself must contain some reference to those
outside things in its own nature, and could not, therefore, be what it is if those outside things did not exist. A
man's nature, for example, is constituted by his memories and the rest of his knowledge, by his loves and
hatreds, and so on; thus, but for the objects which he knows or loves or hates, he could not be what he is. He
is essentially and obviously a fragment: taken as the sumtotal of reality he would be selfcontradictory.
This whole point of view, however, turns upon the notion of the 'nature' of a thing, which seems to mean 'all
the truths about the thing'. It is of course the case that a truth which connects one thing with another thing
could not subsist if the other thing did not subsist. But a truth about a thing is not part of the thing itself,
although it must, according to the above usage, be part of the 'nature' of the thing. If we mean by a thing's
'nature' all the truths about the thing, then plainly we cannot know a thing's 'nature' unless we know all the
thing's relations to all the other things in the universe. But if the word 'nature' is used in this sense, we shall
have to hold that the thing may be known when its 'nature' is not known, or at any rate is not known
completely. There is a confusion, when this use of the word 'nature' is employed, between knowledge of
things and knowledge of truths. We may have knowledge of a thing by acquaintance even if we know very
few propositions about it theoretically we need not know any propositions about it. Thus, acquaintance
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE 48
Page No 51
with a thing does not involve knowledge of its 'nature' in the above sense. And although acquaintance with a
thing is involved in our knowing any one proposition about a thing, knowledge of its 'nature', in the above
sense, is not involved. Hence, (1) acquaintance with a thing does not logically involve a knowledge of its
relations, and (2) a knowledge of some of its relations does not involve a knowledge of all of its relations nor
a knowledge of its 'nature' in the above sense. I may be acquainted, for example, with my toothache, and this
knowledge may be as complete as knowledge by acquaintance ever can be, without knowing all that the
dentist (who is not acquainted with it) can tell me about its cause, and without therefore knowing its 'nature'
in the above sense. Thus the fact that a thing has relations does not prove that its relations are logically
necessary. That is to say, from the mere fact that it is the thing it is we cannot deduce that it must have the
various relations which in fact it has. This only seems to follow because we know it already.
It follows that we cannot prove that the universe as a whole forms a single harmonious system such as Hegel
believes that it forms. And if we cannot prove this, we also cannot prove the unreality of space and time and
matter and evil, for this is deduced by Hegel from the fragmentary and relational character of these things.
Thus we are left to the piecemeal investigation of the world, and are unable to know the characters of those
parts of the universe that are remote from our experience. This result, disappointing as it is to those whose
hopes have been raised by the systems of philosophers, is in harmony with the inductive and scientific temper
of our age, and is borne out by the whole examination of human knowledge which has occupied our previous
chapters.
Most of the great ambitious attempts of metaphysicians have proceeded by the attempt to prove that such and
such apparent features of the actual world were selfcontradictory, and therefore could not be real. The whole
tendency of modern thought, however, is more and more in the direction of showing that the supposed
contradictions were illusory, and that very little can be proved a priori from considerations of what must be.
A good illustration of this is afforded by space and time. Space and time appear to be infinite in extent, and
infinitely divisible. If we travel along a straight line in either direction, it is difficult to believe that we shall
finally reach a last point, beyond which there is nothing, not even empty space. Similarly, if in imagination
we travel backwards or forwards in time, it is difficult to believe that we shall reach a first or last time, with
not even empty time beyond it. Thus space and time appear to be infinite in extent.
Again, if we take any two points on a line, it seems evident that there must be other points between them,
however small the distance between them may be: every distance can be halved, and the halves can be halved
again, and so on ad infinitum. In time, similarly, however little time may elapse between two moments, it
seems evident that there will be other moments between them. Thus space and time appear to be infinitely
divisible. But as against these apparent facts infinite extent and infinite divisibility philosophers have
advanced arguments tending to show that there could be no infinite collections of things, and that therefore
the number of points in space, or of instants in time, must be finite. Thus a contradiction emerged between
the apparent nature of space and time and the supposed impossibility of infinite collections.
Kant, who first emphasized this contradiction, deduced the impossibility of space and time, which he
declared to be merely subjective; and since his time very many philosophers have believed that space and
time are mere appearance, not characteristic of the world as it really is. Now, however, owing to the labours
of the mathematicians, notably Georg Cantor, it has appeared that the impossibility of infinite collections was
a mistake. They are not in fact selfcontradictory, but only contradictory of certain rather obstinate mental
prejudices. Hence the reasons for regarding space and time as unreal have become inoperative, and one of the
great sources of metaphysical constructions is dried up.
The mathematicians, however, have not been content with showing that space as it is commonly supposed to
be is possible; they have shown also that many other forms of space are equally possible, so far as logic can
show. Some of Euclid's axioms, which appear to common sense to be necessary, and were formerly supposed
to be necessary by philosophers, are now known to derive their appearance of necessity from our mere
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE 49
Page No 52
familiarity with actual space, and not from any a priori logical foundation. By imagining worlds in which
these axioms are false, the mathematicians have used logic to loosen the prejudices of common sense, and to
show the possibility of spaces differing some more, some less from that in which we live. And some of
these spaces differ so little from Euclidean space, where distances such as we can measure are concerned, that
it is impossible to discover by observation whether our actual space is strictly Euclidean or of one of these
other kinds. Thus the position is completely reversed. Formerly it appeared that experience left only one kind
of space to logic, and logic showed this one kind to be impossible. Now logic presents many kinds of space
as possible apart from experience, and experience only partially decides between them. Thus, while our
knowledge of what is has become less than it was formerly supposed to be, our knowledge of what may be is
enormously increased. Instead of being shut in within narrow walls, of which every nook and cranny could be
explored, we find ourselves in an open world of free possibilities, where much remains unknown because
there is so much to know.
What has happened in the case of space and time has happened, to some extent, in other directions as well.
The attempt to prescribe to the universe by means of a priori principles has broken down; logic instead of
being, as formerly, the bar to possibilities, has become the great liberator of the imagination, presenting
innumerable alternatives which are closed to unreflective common sense, and leaving to experience the task
of deciding, where decision is possible, between the many worlds which logic offers for our choice. Thus
knowledge as to what exists becomes limited to what we can learn from experience not to what we can
actually experience, for, as we have seen, there is much knowledge by description concerning things of which
we have no direct experience. But in all cases of knowledge by description, we need some connexion of
universals, enabling us, from such and such a datum, to infer an object of a certain sort as implied by our
datum. Thus in regard to physical objects, for example, the principle that sensedata are signs of physical
objects is itself a connexion of universals; and it is only in virtue of this principle that experience enables us
to acquire knowledge concerning physical objects. The same applies to the law of causality, or, to descend to
what is less general, to such principles as the law of gravitation.
Principles such as the law of gravitation are proved, or rather are rendered highly probable, by a combination
of experience with some wholly a priori principle, such as the principle of induction. Thus our intuitive
knowledge, which is the source of all our other knowledge of truths, is of two sorts: pure empirical
knowledge, which tells us of the existence and some of the properties of particular things with which we are
acquainted, and pure a priori knowledge, which gives us connexions between universals, and enables us to
draw inferences from the particular facts given in empirical knowledge. Our derivative knowledge always
depends upon some pure a priori knowledge and usually also depends upon some pure empirical knowledge.
Philosophical knowledge, if what has been said above is true, does not differ essentially from scientific
knowledge; there is no special source of wisdom which is open to philosophy but not to science, and the
results obtained by philosophy are not radically different from those obtained from science. The essential
characteristic of philosophy which makes it a study distinct from science, is criticism. It examines critically
the principles employed in science and in daily life; it searches out any inconsistencies there may be in these
principles, and it only accepts them when, as the result of a critical inquiry, no reason for rejecting them has
appeared. If, as many philosophers have believed, the principles underlying the sciences were capable, when
disengaged from irrelevant detail, of giving us knowledge concerning the universe as a whole, such
knowledge would have the same claim on our belief as scientific knowledge has; but our inquiry has not
revealed any such knowledge, and therefore, as regards the special doctrines of the bolder metaphysicians,
has had a mainly negative result. But as regards what would be commonly accepted as knowledge, our result
is in the main positive: we have seldom found reason to reject such knowledge as the result of our criticism,
and we have seen no reason to suppose man incapable of the kind of knowledge which he is generally
believed to possess.
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE 50
Page No 53
When, however, we speak of philosophy as a criticism of knowledge, it is necessary to impose a certain
limitation. If we adopt the attitude of the complete sceptic, placing ourselves wholly outside all knowledge,
and asking, from this outside position, to be compelled to return within the circle of knowledge, we are
demanding what is impossible, and our scepticism can never be refuted. For all refutation must begin with
some piece of knowledge which the disputants share; from blank doubt, no argument can begin. Hence the
criticism of knowledge which philosophy employs must not be of this destructive kind, if any result is to be
achieved. Against this absolute scepticism, no logical argument can be advanced. But it is not difficult to see
that scepticism of this kind is unreasonable. Descartes' 'methodical doubt', with which modern philosophy
began, is not of this kind, but is rather the kind of criticism which we are asserting to be the essence of
philosophy. His 'methodical doubt' consisted in doubting whatever seemed doubtful; in pausing, with each
apparent piece of knowledge, to ask himself whether, on reflection, he could feel certain that he really knew
it. This is the kind of criticism which constitutes philosophy. Some knowledge, such as knowledge of the
existence of our sensedata, appears quite indubitable, however calmly and thoroughly we reflect upon it. In
regard to such knowledge, philosophical criticism does not require that we should abstain from belief. But
there are beliefs such, for example, as the belief that physical objects exactly resemble our sensedata
which are entertained until we begin to reflect, but are found to melt away when subjected to a close inquiry.
Such beliefs philosophy will bid us reject, unless some new line of argument is found to support them. But to
reject the beliefs which do not appear open to any objections, however closely we examine them, is not
reasonable, and is not what philosophy advocates.
The criticism aimed at, in a word, is not that which, without reason, determines to reject, but that which
considers each piece of apparent knowledge on its merits, and retains whatever still appears to be knowledge
when this consideration is completed. That some risk of error remains must be admitted, since human beings
are fallible. Philosophy may claim justly that it diminishes the risk of error, and that in some cases it renders
the risk so small as to be practically negligible. To do more than this is not possible in a world where
mistakes must occur; and more than this no prudent advocate of philosophy would claim to have performed.
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY
HAVING now come to the end of our brief and very incomplete review of the problems of philosophy, it will
be well to consider, in conclusion, what is the value of philosophy and why it ought to be studied. It is the
more necessary to consider this question, in view of the fact that many men, under the influence of science or
of practical affairs, are inclined to doubt whether philosophy is anything better than innocent but useless
trifling, hairsplitting distinctions, and controversies on matters concerning which knowledge is impossible.
This view of philosophy appears to result, partly from a wrong conception of the ends of life, partly from a
wrong conception of the kind of goods which philosophy strives to achieve. Physical science, through the
medium of inventions, is useful to innumerable people who are wholly ignorant of it; thus the study of
physical science is to be recommended, not only, or primarily, because of the effect on the student, but rather
because of the effect on mankind in general. Thus utility does not belong to philosophy. If the study of
philosophy has any value at all for others than students of philosophy, it must be only indirectly, through its
effects upon the lives of those who study it. It is in these effects, therefore, if anywhere, that the value of
philosophy must be primarily sought.
But further, if we are not to fail in our endeavour to determine the value of philosophy, we must first free our
minds from the prejudices of what are wrongly called 'practical' men. The 'practical' man, as this word is
often used, is one who recognizes only material needs, who realizes that men must have food for the body,
but is oblivious of the necessity of providing food for the mind. If all men were well off, if poverty and
disease had been reduced to their lowest possible point, there would still remain much to be done to produce
a valuable society; and even in the existing world the goods of the mind are at least as important as the goods
of the body. It is exclusively among the goods of the mind that the value of philosophy is to be found; and
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY 51
Page No 54
only those who are not indifferent to these goods can be persuaded that the study of philosophy is not a waste
of time.
Philosophy, like all other studies, aims primarily at knowledge. The knowledge it aims at is the kind of
knowledge which gives unity and system to the body of the sciences, and the kind which results from a
critical examination of the grounds of our convictions, prejudices, and beliefs. But it cannot be maintained
that philosophy has had any very great measure of success in its attempts to provide definite answers to its
questions. If you ask a mathematician, a mineralogist, a historian, or any other man of learning, what definite
body of truths has been ascertained by his science, his answer will last as long as you are willing to listen.
But if you put the same question to a philosopher, he will, if he is candid, have to confess that his study has
not achieved positive results such as have been achieved by other sciences. It is true that this is partly
accounted for by the fact that, as soon as definite knowledge concerning any subject becomes possible, this
subject ceases to be called philosophy, and becomes a separate science. The whole study of the heavens,
which now belongs to astronomy, was once included in philosophy; Newton's great work was called 'the
mathematical principles of natural philosophy'. Similarly, the study of the human mind, which was a part of
philosophy, has now been separated from philosophy and has become the science of psychology. Thus, to a
great extent, the uncertainty of philosophy is more apparent than real: those questions which are already
capable of definite answers are placed in the sciences, while those only to which, at present, no definite
answer can be given, remain to form the residue which is called philosophy.
This is, however, only a part of the truth concerning the uncertainty of philosophy. There are many questions
and among them those that are of the profoundest interest to our spiritual life which, so far as we can
see, must remain insoluble to the human intellect unless its powers become of quite a different order from
what they are now. Has the universe any unity of plan or purpose, or is it a fortuitous concourse of atoms? Is
consciousness a permanent part of the universe, giving hope of indefinite growth in wisdom, or is it a
transitory accident on a small planet on which life must ultimately become impossible? Are good and evil of
importance to the universe or only to man? Such questions are asked by philosophy, and variously answered
by various philosophers. But it would seem that, whether answers be otherwise discoverable or not, the
answers suggested by philosophy are none of them demonstrably true. Yet, however slight may be the hope
of discovering an answer, it is part of the business of philosophy to continue the consideration of such
questions, to make us aware of their importance, to examine all the approaches to them, and to keep alive that
speculative interest in the universe which is apt to be killed by confining ourselves to definitely ascertainable
knowledge.
Many philosophers, it is true, have held that philosophy could establish the truth of certain answers to such
fundamental questions. They have supposed that what is of most importance in religious beliefs could be
proved by strict demonstration to be true. In order to judge of such attempts, it is necessary to take a survey of
human knowledge, and to form an opinion as to its methods and its limitations. On such a subject it would be
unwise to pronounce dogmatically; but if the investigations of our previous chapters have not led us astray,
we shall be compelled to renounce the hope of finding philosophical proofs of religious beliefs. We cannot,
therefore, include as part of the value of philosophy any definite set of answers to such questions. Hence,
once more, the value of philosophy must not depend upon any supposed body of definitely ascertainable
knowledge to be acquired by those who study it.
The value of philosophy is, in fact, to be sought largely in its very uncertainty. The man who has no tincture
of philosophy goes through life imprisoned in the prejudices derived from common sense, from the habitual
beliefs of his age or his nation, and from convictions which have grown up in his mind without the
cooperation or consent of his deliberate reason. To such a man the world tends to become definite, finite,
obvious; common objects rouse no questions, and unfamiliar possibilities are contemptuously rejected. As
soon as we begin to philosophize, on the contrary, we find, as we saw in our opening chapters, that even the
most everyday things lead to problems to which only very incomplete answers can be given. Philosophy,
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY 52
Page No 55
though unable to tell us with certainty what is the true answer to the doubts which it raises, is able to suggest
many possibilities which enlarge our thoughts and free them from the tyranny of custom. Thus, while
diminishing our feeling of certainty as to what things are, it greatly increases our knowledge as to what they
may be; it removes the somewhat arrogant dogmatism of those who have never travelled into the region of
liberating doubt, and it keeps alive our sense of wonder by showing familiar things in an unfamiliar aspect.
Apart from its utility in showing unsuspected possibilities, philosophy has a value perhaps its chief value
through the greatness of the objects which it contemplates, and the freedom from narrow and personal
aims resulting from this contemplation. The life of the instinctive man is shut up within the circle of his
private interests: family and friends may be included, but the outer world is not regarded except as it may
help or hinder what comes within the circle of instinctive wishes. In such a life there is something feverish
and confined, in comparison with which the philosophic life is calm and free. The private world of instinctive
interests is a small one, set in the midst of a great and powerful world which must, sooner or later, lay our
private world in ruins. Unless we can so enlarge our interests as to include the whole outer world, we remain
like a garrison in a beleagured fortress, knowing that the enemy prevents escape and that ultimate surrender is
inevitable. In such a life there is no peace, but a constant strife between the insistence of desire and the
powerlessness of will. In one way or another, if our life is to be great and free, we must escape this prison and
this strife.
One way of escape is by philosophic contemplation. Philosophic contemplation does not, in its widest survey,
divide the universe into two hostile camps friends and foes, helpful and hostile, good and bad it views
the whole impartially. Philosophic contemplation, when it is unalloyed, does not aim at proving that the rest
of the universe is akin to man. All acquisition of knowledge is an enlargement of the Self, but this
enlargement is best attained when it is not directly sought. It is obtained when the desire for knowledge is
alone operative, by a study which does not wish in advance that its objects should have this or that character,
but adapts the Self to the characters which it finds in its objects. This enlargement of Self is not obtained
when, taking the Self as it is, we try to show that the world is so similar to this Self that knowledge of it is
possible without any admission of what seems alien. The desire to prove this is a form of selfassertion and,
like all selfassertion, it is an obstacle to the growth of Self which it desires, and of which the Self knows that
it is capable. Selfassertion, in philosophic speculation as elsewhere, views the world as a means to its own
ends; thus it makes the world of less account than Self, and the Self sets bounds to the greatness of its goods.
In contemplation, on the contrary, we start from the notSelf, and through its greatness the boundaries of Self
are enlarged; through the infinity of the universe the mind which contemplates it achieves some share in
infinity.
For this reason greatness of soul is not fostered by those philosophies which assimilate the universe to Man.
Knowledge is a form of union of Self and notSelf; like all union, it is impaired by dominion, and therefore
by any attempt to force the universe into conformity with what we find in ourselves. There is a widespread
philosophical tendency towards the view which tells us that Man is the measure of all things, that truth is
manmade, that space and time and the world of universals are properties of the mind, and that, if there be
anything not created by the mind, it is unknowable and of no account for us. This view, if our previous
discussions were correct, is untrue; but in addition to being untrue, it has the effect of robbing philosophic
contemplation of all that gives it value, since it fetters contemplation to Self. What it calls knowledge is not a
union with the notSelf, but a set of prejudices, habits, and desires, making an impenetrable veil between us
and the world beyond. The man who finds pleasure in such a theory of knowledge is like the man who never
leaves the domestic circle for fear his word might not be law.
The true philosophic contemplation, on the contrary, finds its satisfaction in every enlargement of the
notSelf, in everything that magnifies the objects contemplated, and thereby the subject contemplating.
Everything, in contemplation, that is personal or private, everything that depends upon habit, selfinterest, or
desire, distorts the object, and hence impairs the union which the intellect seeks. By thus making a barrier
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY 53
Page No 56
between subject and object, such personal and private things become a prison to the intellect. The free
intellect will see as God might see, without a here and now, without hopes and fears, without the trammels of
customary beliefs and traditional prejudices, calmly, dispassionately, in the sole and exclusive desire of
knowledge knowledge as impersonal, as purely contemplative, as it is possible for man to attain. Hence
also the free intellect will value more the abstract and universal knowledge into which the accidents of private
history do not enter, than the knowledge brought by the senses, and dependent, as such knowledge must be,
upon an exclusive and personal point of view and a body whose senseorgans distort as much as they reveal.
The mind which has become accustomed to the freedom and impartiality of philosophic contemplation will
preserve something of the same freedom and impartiality in the world of action and emotion. It will view its
purposes and desires as parts of the whole, with the absence of insistence that results from seeing them as
infinitesimal fragments in a world of which all the rest is unaffected by any one man's deeds. The impartiality
which, in contemplation, is the unalloyed desire for truth, is the very same quality of mind which, in action, is
justice, and in emotion is that universal love which can be given to all, and not only to those who are judged
useful or admirable. Thus contemplation enlarges not only the objects of our thoughts, but also the objects of
our actions and our affections: it makes us citizens of the universe, not only of one walled city at war with all
the rest. In this citizenship of the universe consists man's true freedom, and his liberation from the thraldom
of narrow hopes and fears.
Thus, to sum up our discussion of the value of philosophy; Philosophy is to be studied, not for the sake of any
definite answers to its questions since no definite answers can, as a rule, be known to be true, but rather for
the sake of the questions themselves; because these questions enlarge our conception of what is possible,
enrich our intellectual imagination and diminish the dogmatic assurance which closes the mind against
speculation; but above all because, through the greatness of the universe which philosophy contemplates, the
mind also is rendered great, and becomes capable of that union with the universe which constitutes its highest
good.
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE
The student who wishes to acquire an elementary knowledge of philosophy will find it both easier and more
profitable to read some of the works of the great philosophers than to attempt to derive an allround view
from handbooks. The following are specially recommended:
PLATO: Republic, especially Books VI and VII.
DESCARTES: Meditations.
SPINOZA: Ethics.
LEIBNIZ: The Monadology.
BERKELEY: Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.
HUME: Enquiry concerning Human Understanding.
KANT: Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysic.
The Problems of Philosophy
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE 54
Bookmarks
1. Table of Contents, page = 3
2. The Problems of Philosophy, page = 4
3. Bertrand Russell, page = 4
4. PREFACE, page = 4
5. CHAPTER I. APPEARANCE AND REALITY , page = 4
6. CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER , page = 8
7. CHAPTER III. THE NATURE OF MATTER , page = 11
8. CHAPTER IV. IDEALISM , page = 15
9. CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION , page = 18
10. CHAPTER VI. ON INDUCTION , page = 23
11. CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES, page = 26
12. CHAPTER VIII. HOW A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE IS POSSIBLE , page = 30
13. CHAPTER IX. THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS , page = 33
14. CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS , page = 37
15. CHAPTER XI. ON INTUITIVE KNOWLEDGE , page = 40
16. CHAPTER XII. TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD , page = 43
17. CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION , page = 47
18. CHAPTER XIV. THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE , page = 50
19. CHAPTER XV. THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY , page = 54
20. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE , page = 57