Title:   The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

Subject:  

Author:   Jean Jacques Rousseau

Keywords:  

Creator:  

PDF Version:   1.2



Contents:

Page No 1

Page No 2

Page No 3

Page No 4

Page No 5

Page No 6

Page No 7

Page No 8

Page No 9

Page No 10

Page No 11

Page No 12

Page No 13

Page No 14

Page No 15

Page No 16

Page No 17

Page No 18

Page No 19

Page No 20

Page No 21

Page No 22

Page No 23

Page No 24

Page No 25

Page No 26

Page No 27

Page No 28

Page No 29

Page No 30

Page No 31

Page No 32

Page No 33

Page No 34

Page No 35

Page No 36

Page No 37

Page No 38

Page No 39

Page No 40

Page No 41

Page No 42

Page No 43

Page No 44

Page No 45

Page No 46

Page No 47

Page No 48

Page No 49

Page No 50

Page No 51

Page No 52

Page No 53

Page No 54

Page No 55

Page No 56

Page No 57

Page No 58

Page No 59

Page No 60

Page No 61

Page No 62

Page No 63

Page No 64

Page No 65

Bookmarks





Page No 1


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

Jean Jacques Rousseau



Top




Page No 2


Table of Contents

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right.....................................................................................1


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

i



Top




Page No 3


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

Jean Jacques Rousseau

Translated by G. D. H. Cole

 Foreward

 Book I

 Book II

 Book III

 Book IV

Foederis aequas Dicamus leges.

Virgil, Aeneid xi.

FOREWARD

This little treatise is part of a longer work which I began years ago without realising my limitations, and long

since abandoned. Of the various fragments that might have been extracted from what I wrote, this is the most

considerable, and, I think, the least unworthy of being offered to the public. The rest no longer exists.

BOOK I

I MEAN to inquire if, in the civil order, there can be any sure and legitimate rule of administration, men

being taken as they are and laws as they might be. In this inquiry I shall endeavour always to unite what right

sanctions with what is prescribed by interest, in order that justice and utility may in no case be divided.

I enter upon my task without proving the importance of the subject. I shall be asked if I am a prince or a

legislator, to write on politics. I answer that I am neither, and that is why I do so. If I were a prince or a

legislator, I should not waste time in saying what wants doing; I should do it, or hold my peace.

As I was born a citizen of a free State, and a member of the Sovereign, I feel that, however feeble the

influence my voice can have on public affairs, the right of voting on them makes it my duty to study them:

and I am happy, when I reflect upon governments, to find my inquiries always furnish me with new reasons

for loving that of my own country.

1. SUBJECT OF THE FIRST BOOK

MAN is born free; and everywhere he is in chains. One thinks himself the master of others, and still remains

a greater slave than they. How did this change come about? I do not know. What can make it legitimate? That

question I think I can answer.

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 1



Top




Page No 4


If I took into account only force, and the effects derived from it, I should say: "As long as a people is

compelled to obey, and obeys, it does well; as soon as it can shake off the yoke, and shakes it off, it does still

better; for, regaining its liberty by the same right as took it away, either it is justified in resuming it, or there

was no justification for those who took it away." But the social order is a sacred right which is the basis of all

other rights. Nevertheless, this right does not come from nature, and must therefore be founded on

conventions. Before coming to that, I have to prove what I have just asserted.

2. THE FIRST SOCIETIES

THE most ancient of all societies, and the only one that is natural, is the family: and even so the children

remain attached to the father only so long as they need him for their preservation. As soon as this need

ceases, the natural bond is dissolved. The children, released from the obedience they owed to the father, and

the father, released from the care he owed his children, return equally to independence. If they remain united,

they continue so no longer naturally, but voluntarily; and the family itself is then maintained only by

convention.

This common liberty results from the nature of man. His first law is to provide for his own preservation, his

first cares are those which he owes to himself; and, as soon as he reaches years of discretion, he is the sole

judge of the proper means of preserving himself, and consequently becomes his own master.

The family then may be called the first model of political societies: the ruler corresponds to the father, and

the people to the children; and all, being born free and equal, alienate their liberty only for their own

advantage. The whole difference is that, in the family, the love of the father for his children repays him for

the care he takes of them, while, in the State, the pleasure of commanding takes the place of the love which

the chief cannot have for the peoples under him.

Grotius denies that all human power is established in favour of the governed, and quotes slavery as an

example. His usual method of reasoning is constantly to establish right by fact.[1] It would be possible to

employ a more logical method, but none could be more favourable to tyrants.

It is then, according to Grotius, doubtful whether the human race belongs to a hundred men, or that hundred

men to the human race: and, throughout his book, he seems to incline to the former alternative, which is also

the view of Hobbes. On this showing, the human species is divided into so many herds of cattle, each with its

ruler, who keeps guard over them for the purpose of devouring them.

As a shepherd is of a nature superior to that of his flock, the shepherds of men, i.e., their rulers, are of a

nature superior to that of the peoples under them. Thus, Philo tells us, the Emperor Caligula reasoned,

concluding equally well either that kings were gods, or that men were beasts.

The reasoning of Caligula agrees with that of Hobbes and Grotius. Aristotle, before any of them, had said that

men are by no means equal naturally, but that some are born for slavery, and others for dominion.

Aristotle was right; but he took the effect for the cause. Nothing can be more certain than that every man born

in slavery is born for slavery. Slaves lose everything in their chains, even the desire of escaping from them:

they love their servitude, as the comrades of Ulysses loved their brutish condition.[2] If then there are slaves

by nature, it is because there have been slaves against nature. Force made the first slaves, and their cowardice

perpetuated the condition.

I have said nothing of King Adam, or Emperor Noah, father of the three great monarchs who shared out the

universe, like the children of Saturn, whom some scholars have recognised in them. I trust to getting due

thanks for my moderation; for, being a direct descendant of one of these princes, perhaps of the eldest branch,


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 2



Top




Page No 5


how do I know that a verification of titles might not leave me the legitimate king of the human race? In any

case, there can be no doubt that Adam was sovereign of the world, as Robinson Crusoe was of his island, as

long as he was its only inhabitant; and this empire had the advantage that the monarch, safe on his throne, had

no rebellions, wars, or conspirators to fear.

3. THE RIGHT OF THE STRONGEST

THE strongest is never strong enough to be always the master, unless he transforms strength into right, and

obedience into duty. Hence the right of the strongest, which, though to all seeming meant ironically, is really

laid down as a fundamental principle. But are we never to have an explanation of this phrase? Force is a

physical power, and I fail to see what moral effect it can have. To yield to force is an act of necessity, not of

will  at the most, an act of prudence. In what sense can it be a duty?

Suppose for a moment that this socalled "right" exists. I maintain that the sole result is a mass of

inexplicable nonsense. For, if force creates right, the effect changes with the cause: every force that is greater

than the first succeeds to its right. As soon as it is possible to disobey with impunity, disobedience is

legitimate; and, the strongest being always in the right, the only thing that matters is to act so as to become

the strongest. But what kind of right is that which perishes when force fails? If we must obey perforce, there

is no need to obey because we ought; and if we are not forced to obey, we are under no obligation to do so.

Clearly, the word "right" adds nothing to force: in this connection, it means absolutely nothing.

Obey the powers that be. If this means yield to force, it is a good precept, but superfluous: I can answer for its

never being violated. All power comes from God, I admit; but so does all sickness: does that mean that we

are forbidden to call in the doctor? A brigand surprises me at the edge of a wood: must I not merely surrender

my purse on compulsion; but, even if I could withhold it, am I in conscience bound to give it up? For

certainly the pistol he holds is also a power.

Let us then admit that force does not create right, and that we are obliged to obey only legitimate powers. In

that case, my original question recurs.

4. SLAVERY

SINCE no man has a natural authority over his fellow, and force creates no right, we must conclude that

conventions form the basis of all legitimate authority among men.

If an individual, says Grotius, can alienate his liberty and make himself the slave of a master, why could not a

whole people do the same and make itself subject to a king? There are in this passage plenty of ambiguous

words which would need explaining; but let us confine ourselves to the word alienate. To alienate is to give

or to sell. Now, a man who becomes the slave of another does not give himself; he sells himself, at the least

for his subsistence: but for what does a people sell itself? A king is so far from furnishing his subjects with

their subsistence that he gets his own only from them; and, according to Rabelais, kings do not live on

nothing. Do subjects then give their persons on condition that the king takes their goods also? I fail to see

what they have left to preserve.

It will be said that the despot assures his subjects civil tranquillity. Granted; but what do they gain, if the wars

his ambition brings down upon them, his insatiable avidity, and the vexations conduct of his ministers press

harder on them than their own dissensions would have done? What do they gain, if the very tranquillity they

enjoy is one of their miseries? Tranquillity is found also in dungeons; but is that enough to make them

desirable places to live in? The Greeks imprisoned in the cave of the Cyclops lived there very tranquilly,

while they were awaiting their turn to be devoured.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 3



Top




Page No 6


To say that a man gives himself gratuitously, is to say what is absurd and inconceivable; such an act is null

and illegitimate, from the mere fact that he who does it is out of his mind. To say the same of a whole people

is to suppose a people of madmen; and madness creates no right.

Even if each man could alienate himself, he could not alienate his children: they are born men and free; their

liberty belongs to them, and no one but they has the right to dispose of it. Before they come to years of

discretion, the father can, in their name, lay down conditions for their preservation and wellbeing, but he

cannot give them irrevocably and without conditions: such a gift is contrary to the ends of nature, and

exceeds the rights of paternity. It would therefore be necessary, in order to legitimise an arbitrary

government, that in every generation the people should be in a position to accept or reject it; but, were this so,

the government would be no longer arbitrary.

To renounce liberty is to renounce being a man, to surrender the rights of humanity and even its duties. For

him who renounces everything no indemnity is possible. Such a renunciation is incompatible with man's

nature; to remove all liberty from his will is to remove all morality from his acts. Finally, it is an empty and

contradictory convention that sets up, on the one side, absolute authority, and, on the other, unlimited

obedience. Is it not clear that we can be under no obligation to a person from whom we have the right to exact

everything? Does not this condition alone, in the absence of equivalence or exchange, in itself involve the

nullity of the act? For what right can my slave have against me, when all that he has belongs to me, and, his

right being mine, this right of mine against myself is a phrase devoid of meaning?

Grotius and the rest find in war another origin for the socalled right of slavery. The victor having, as they

hold, the right of killing the vanquished, the latter can buy back his life at the price of his liberty; and this

convention is the more legitimate because it is to the advantage of both parties.

But it is clear that this supposed right to kill the conquered is by no means deducible from the state of war.

Men, from the mere fact that, while they are living in their primitive independence, they have no mutual

relations stable enough to constitute either the state of peace or the state of war, cannot be naturally enemies.

War is constituted by a relation between things, and not between persons; and, as the state of war cannot arise

out of simple personal relations, but only out of real relations, private war, or war of man with man, can exist

neither in the state of nature, where there is no constant property, nor in the social state, where everything is

under the authority of the laws.

Individual combats, duels and encounters, are acts which cannot constitute a state; while the private wars,

authorised by the Establishments of Louis IX, King of France, and suspended by the Peace of God, are abuses

of feudalism, in itself an absurd system if ever there was one, and contrary to the principles of natural right

and to all good polity.

War then is a relation, not between man and man, but between State and State, and individuals are enemies

only accidentally, not as men, nor even as citizens,[3] but as soldiers; not as members of their country, but as

its defenders. Finally, each State can have for enemies only other States, and not men; for between things

disparate in nature there can be no real relation.

Furthermore, this principle is in conformity with the established rules of all times and the constant practice of

all civilised peoples. Declarations of war are intimations less to powers than to their subjects. The foreigner,

whether king, individual, or people, who robs, kills or detains the subjects, without declaring war on the

prince, is not an enemy, but a brigand. Even in real war, a just prince, while laying hands, in the enemy's

country, on all that belongs to the public, respects the lives and goods of individuals: he respects rights on

which his own are founded. The object of the war being the destruction of the hostile State, the other side has

a right to kill its defenders, while they are bearing arms; but as soon as they lay them down and surrender,

they cease to be enemies or instruments of the enemy, and become once more merely men, whose life no one


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 4



Top




Page No 7


has any right to take. Sometimes it is possible to kill the State without killing a single one of its members; and

war gives no right which is not necessary to the gaining of its object. These principles are not those of

Grotius: they are not based on the authority of poets, but derived from the nature of reality and based on

reason.

The right of conquest has no foundation other than the right of the strongest. If war does not give the

conqueror the right to massacre the conquered peoples, the right to enslave them cannot be based upon a right

which does not exist. No one has a right to kill an enemy except when he cannot make him a slave, and the

right to enslave him cannot therefore be derived from the right to kill him. It is accordingly an unfair

exchange to make him buy at the price of his liberty his life, over which the victor holds no right. Is it not

clear that there is a vicious circle in founding the right of life and death on the right of slavery, and the right

of slavery on the right of life and death?

Even if we assume this terrible right to kill everybody, I maintain that a slave made in war, or a conquered

people, is under no obligation to a master, except to obey him as far as he is compelled to do so. By taking an

equivalent for his life, the victor has not done him a favour; instead of killing him without profit, he has killed

him usefully. So far then is he from acquiring over him any authority in addition to that of force, that the state

of war continues to subsist between them: their mutual relation is the effect of it, and the usage of the right of

war does not imply a treaty of peace. A convention has indeed been made; but this convention, so far from

destroying the state of war, presupposes its continuance.

So, from whatever aspect we regard the question, the right of slavery is null and void, not only as being

illegitimate, but also because it is absurd and meaningless. The words slave and right contradict each other,

and are mutually exclusive. It will always be equally foolish for a man to say to a man or to a people: "I make

with you a convention wholly at your expense and wholly to my advantage; I shall keep it as long as I like,

and you will keep it as long as I like."

5. THAT WE MUST ALWAYS GO BACK TO A FIRST CONVENTION

EVEN if I granted all that I have been refuting, the friends of despotism would be no better off. There will

always be a great difference between subduing a multitude and ruling a society. Even if scattered individuals

were successively enslaved by one man, however numerous they might be, I still see no more than a master

and his slaves, and certainly not a people and its ruler; I see what may be termed an aggregation, but not an

association; there is as yet neither public good nor body politic. The man in question, even if he has enslaved

half the world, is still only an individual; his interest, apart from that of others, is still a purely private

interest. If this same man comes to die, his empire, after him, remains scattered and without unity, as an oak

falls and dissolves into a heap of ashes when the fire has consumed it.

A people, says Grotius, can give itself to a king. Then, according to Grotius, a people is a people before it

gives itself. The gift is itself a civil act, and implies public deliberation. It would be better, before examining

the act by which a people gives itself to a king, to examine that by which it has become a people; for this act,

being necessarily prior to the other, is the true foundation of society.

Indeed, if there were no prior convention, where, unless the election were unanimous, would be the

obligation on the minority to submit to the choice of the majority? How have a hundred men who wish for a

master the right to vote on behalf of ten who do not? The law of majority voting is itself something

established by convention, and presupposes unanimity, on one occasion at least.

6. THE SOCIAL COMPACT

I SUPPOSE men to have reached the point at which the obstacles in the way of their preservation in the state


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 5



Top




Page No 8


of nature show their power of resistance to be greater than the resources at the disposal of each individual for

his maintenance in that state. That primitive condition can then subsist no longer; and the human race would

perish unless it changed its manner of existence.

But, as men cannot engender new forces, but only unite and direct existing ones, they have no other means of

preserving themselves than the formation, by aggregation, of a sum of forces great enough to overcome the

resistance. These they have to bring into play by means of a single motive power, and cause to act in concert.

This sum of forces can arise only where several persons come together: but, as the force and liberty of each

man are the chief instruments of his selfpreservation, how can he pledge them without harming his own

interests, and neglecting the care he owes to himself? This difficulty, in its bearing on my present subject,

may be stated in the following terms:

"The problem is to find a form of association which will defend and protect with the whole common force the

person and goods of each associate, and in which each, while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself

alone, and remain as free as before." This is the fundamental problem of which the Social Contract provides

the solution.

The clauses of this contract are so determined by the nature of the act that the slightest modification would

make them vain and ineffective; so that, although they have perhaps never been formally set forth, they are

everywhere the same and everywhere tacitly admitted and recognised, until, on the violation of the social

compact, each regains his original rights and resumes his natural liberty, while losing the conventional liberty

in favour of which he renounced it.

These clauses, properly understood, may be reduced to one  the total alienation of each associate, together

with all his rights, to the whole community; for, in the first place, as each gives himself absolutely, the

conditions are the same for all; and, this being so, no one has any interest in making them burdensome to

others.

Moreover, the alienation being without reserve, the union is as perfect as it can be, and no associate has

anything more to demand: for, if the individuals retained certain rights, as there would be no common

superior to decide between them and the public, each, being on one point his own judge, would ask to be so

on all; the state of nature would thus continue, and the association would necessarily become inoperative or

tyrannical.

Finally, each man, in giving himself to all, gives himself to nobody; and as there is no associate over whom

he does not acquire the same right as he yields others over himself, he gains an equivalent for everything he

loses, and an increase of force for the preservation of what he has.

If then we discard from the social compact what is not of its essence, we shall find that it reduces itself to the

following terms:

"Each of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction of the general will, and,

in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an indivisible part of the whole."

At once, in place of the individual personality of each contracting party, this act of association creates a moral

and collective body, composed of as many members as the assembly contains votes, and receiving from this

act its unity, its common identity, its life and its will. This public person, so formed by the union of all other

persons formerly took the name of city,[4] and now takes that of Republic or body politic; it is called by its

members State when passive. Sovereign when active, and Power when compared with others like itself.

Those who are associated in it take collectively the name of people, and severally are called citizens, as


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 6



Top




Page No 9


sharing in the sovereign power, and subjects, as being under the laws of the State. But these terms are often

confused and taken one for another: it is enough to know how to distinguish them when they are being used

with precision.

7. THE SOVEREIGN

THIS formula shows us that the act of association comprises a mutual undertaking between the public and the

individuals, and that each individual, in making a contract, as we may say, with himself, is bound in a double

capacity; as a member of the Sovereign he is bound to the individuals, and as a member of the State to the

Sovereign. But the maxim of civil right, that no one is bound by undertakings made to himself, does not

apply in this case; for there is a great difference between incurring an obligation to yourself and incurring one

to a whole of which you form a part.

Attention must further be called to the fact that public deliberation, while competent to bind all the subjects to

the Sovereign, because of the two different capacities in which each of them may be regarded, cannot, for the

opposite reason, bind the Sovereign to itself; and that it is consequently against the nature of the body politic

for the Sovereign to impose on itself a law which it cannot infringe. Being able to regard itself in only one

capacity, it is in the position of an individual who makes a contract with himself; and this makes it clear that

there neither is nor can be any kind of fundamental law binding on the body of the people  not even the

social contract itself. This does not mean that the body politic cannot enter into undertakings with others,

provided the contract is not infringed by them; for in relation to what is external to it, it becomes a simple

being, an individual.

But the body politic or the Sovereign, drawing its being wholly from the sanctity of the contract, can never

bind itself, even to an outsider, to do anything derogatory to the original act, for instance, to alienate any part

of itself, or to submit to another Sovereign. Violation of the act by which it exists would be selfannihilation;

and that which is itself nothing can create nothing.

As soon as this multitude is so united in one body, it is impossible to offend against one of the members

without attacking the body, and still more to offend against the body without the members resenting it. Duty

and interest therefore equally oblige the two contracting parties to give each other help; and the same men

should seek to combine, in their double capacity, all the advantages dependent upon that capacity.

Again, the Sovereign, being formed wholly of the individuals who compose it, neither has nor can have any

interest contrary to theirs; and consequently the sovereign power need give no guarantee to its subjects,

because it is impossible for the body to wish to hurt all its members. We shall also see later on that it cannot

hurt any in particular. The Sovereign, merely by virtue of what it is, is always what it should be.

This, however, is not the case with the relation of the subjects to the Sovereign, which, despite the common

interest, would have no security that they would fulfil their undertakings, unless it found means to assure

itself of their fidelity.

In fact, each individual, as a man, may have a particular will contrary or dissimilar to the general will which

he has as a citizen. His particular interest may speak to him quite differently from the common interest: his

absolute and naturally independent existence may make him look upon what he owes to the common cause as

a gratuitous contribution, the loss of which will do less harm to others than the payment of it is burdensome

to himself; and, regarding the moral person which constitutes the State as a persona ficta, because not a man,

he may wish to enjoy the rights of citizenship without being ready to fulfil the duties of a subject. The

continuance of such an injustice could not but prove the undoing of the body politic.

In order then that the social compact may not be an empty formula, it tacitly includes the undertaking, which


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 7



Top




Page No 10


alone can give force to the rest, that whoever refuses to obey the general will shall be compelled to do so by

the whole body. This means nothing less than that he will be forced to be free; for this is the condition which,

by giving each citizen to his country, secures him against all personal dependence. In this lies the key to the

working of the political machine; this alone legitimises civil undertakings, which, without it, would be

absurd, tyrannical, and liable to the most frightful abuses.

8. THE CIVIL STATE

THE passage from the state of nature to the civil state produces a very remarkable change in man, by

substituting justice for instinct in his conduct, and giving his actions the morality they had formerly lacked.

Then only, when the voice of duty takes the place of physical impulses and right of appetite, does man, who

so far had considered only himself, find that he is forced to act on different principles, and to consult his

reason before listening to his inclinations. Although, in this state, he deprives himself of some advantages

which he got from nature, he gains in return others so great, his faculties are so stimulated and developed, his

ideas so extended, his feelings so ennobled, and his whole soul so uplifted, that, did not the abuses of this

new condition often degrade him below that which he left, he would be bound to bless continually the happy

moment which took him from it for ever, and, instead of a stupid and unimaginative animal, made him an

intelligent being and a man.

Let us draw up the whole account in terms easily commensurable. What man loses by the social contract is

his natural liberty and an unlimited right to everything he tries to get and succeeds in getting; what he gains is

civil liberty and the proprietorship of all he possesses. If we are to avoid mistake in weighing one against the

other, we must clearly distinguish natural liberty, which is bounded only by the strength of the individual,

from civil liberty, which is limited by the general will; and possession, which is merely the effect of force or

the right of the first occupier, from property, which can be founded only on a positive title.

We might, over and above all this, add, to what man acquires in the civil state, moral liberty, which alone

makes him truly master of himself; for the mere impulse of appetite is slavery, while obedience to a law

which we prescribe to ourselves is liberty. But I have already said too much on this head, and the

philosophical meaning of the word liberty does not now concern us.

9. REAL PROPERTY

EACH member of the community gives himself to it, at the moment of its foundation, just as he is, with all

the resources at his command, including the goods he possesses. This act does not make possession, in

changing hands, change its nature, and become property in the hands of the Sovereign; but, as the forces of

the city are incomparably greater than those of an individual, public possession is also, in fact, stronger and

more irrevocable, without being any more legitimate, at any rate from the point of view of foreigners. For the

State, in relation to its members, is master of all their goods by the social contract, which, within the State, is

the basis of all rights; but, in relation to other powers, it is so only by the right of the first occupier, which it

holds from its members.

The right of the first occupier, though more real than the right of the strongest, becomes a real right only

when the right of property has already been established. Every man has naturally a right to everything he

needs; but the positive act which makes him proprietor of one thing excludes him from everything else.

Having his share, he ought to keep to it, and can have no further right against the community. This is why the

right of the first occupier, which in the state of nature is so weak, claims the respect of every man in civil

society. In this right we are respecting not so much what belongs to another as what does not belong to

ourselves.

In general, to establish the right of the first occupier over a plot of ground, the following conditions are


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 8



Top




Page No 11


necessary: first, the land must not yet be inhabited; secondly, a man must occupy only the amount he needs

for his subsistence; and, in the third place, possession must be taken, not by an empty ceremony, but by

labour and cultivation, the only sign of proprietorship that should be respected by others, in default of a legal

title.

In granting the right of first occupancy to necessity and labour, are we not really stretching it as far as it can

go? Is it possible to leave such a right unlimited? Is it to be enough to set foot on a plot of common ground, in

order to be able to call yourself at once the master of it? Is it to be enough that a man has the strength to expel

others for a moment, in order to establish his right to prevent them from ever returning? How can a man or a

people seize an immense territory and keep it from the rest of the world except by a punishable usurpation,

since all others are being robbed, by such an act, of the place of habitation and the means of subsistence

which nature gave them in common? When Nunez Balboa, standing on the seashore, took possession of the

South Seas and the whole of South America in the name of the crown of Castile, was that enough to

dispossess all their actual inhabitants, and to shut out from them all the princes of the world? On such a

showing, these ceremonies are idly multiplied, and the Catholic King need only take possession all at once,

from his apartment, of the whole universe, merely making a subsequent reservation about what was already

in the possession of other princes.

We can imagine how the lands of individuals, where they were contiguous and came to be united, became the

public territory, and how the right of Sovereignty, extending from the subjects over the lands they held,

became at once real and personal. The possessors were thus made more dependent, and the forces at their

command used to guarantee their fidelity. The advantage of this does not seem to have been felt by ancient

monarchs, who called themselves Kings of the Persians, Scythians, or Macedonians, and seemed to regard

themselves more as rulers of men than as masters of a country. Those of the present day more cleverly call

themselves Kings of France, Spain, England, etc.: thus holding the land, they are quite confident of holding

the inhabitants.

The peculiar fact about this alienation is that, in taking over the goods of individuals, the community, so far

from despoiling them, only assures them legitimate possession, and changes usurpation into a true right and

enjoyment into proprietorship. Thus the possessors, being regarded as depositaries of the public good, and

having their rights respected by all the members of the State and maintained against foreign aggression by all

its forces, have, by a cession which benefits both the public and still more themselves, acquired, so to speak,

all that they gave up. This paradox may easily be explained by the distinction between the rights which the

Sovereign and the proprietor have over the same estate, as we shall see later on.

It may also happen that men begin to unite one with another before they possess anything, and that,

subsequently occupying a tract of country which is enough for all, they enjoy it in common, or share it out

among themselves, either equally or according to a scale fixed by the Sovereign. However the acquisition be

made, the right which each individual has to his own estate is always subordinate to the right which the

community has over all: without this, there would be neither stability in the social tie, nor real force in the

exercise of Sovereignty.

I shall end this chapter and this book by remarking on a fact on which the whole social system should rest:

i.e., that, instead of destroying natural inequality, the fundamental compact substitutes, for such physical

inequality as nature may have set up between men, an equality that is moral and legitimate, and that men,

who may be unequal in strength or intelligence, become every one equal by convention and legal right.[5]


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 9



Top




Page No 12


BOOK II

1. THAT SOVEREIGNTY IS INALIENABLE

THE first and most important deduction from the principles we have so far laid down is that the general will

alone can direct the State according to the object for which it was instituted, i.e., the common good: for if the

clashing of particular interests made the establishment of societies necessary, the agreement of these very

interests made it possible. The common element in these different interests is what forms the social tie; and,

were there no point of agreement between them all, no society could exist. It is solely on the basis of this

common interest that every society should be governed.

I hold then that Sovereignty, being nothing less than the exercise of the general will, can never be alienated,

and that the Sovereign, who is no less than a collective being, cannot be represented except by himself: the

power indeed may be transmitted, but not the will.

In reality, if it is not impossible for a particular will to agree on some point with the general will, it is at least

impossible for the agreement to be lasting and constant; for the particular will tends, by its very nature, to

partiality, while the general will tends to equality. It is even more impossible to have any guarantee of this

agreement; for even if it should always exist, it would be the effect not of art, but of chance. The Sovereign

may indeed say: "I now will actually what this man wills, or at least what he says he wills"; but it cannot say:

"What he wills tomorrow, I too shall will" because it is absurd for the will to bind itself for the future, nor is it

incumbent on any will to consent to anything that is not for the good of the being who wills. If then the

people promises simply to obey, by that very act it dissolves itself and loses what makes it a people; the

moment a master exists, there is no longer a Sovereign, and from that moment the body politic has ceased to

exist.

This does not mean that the commands of the rulers cannot pass for general wills, so long as the Sovereign,

being free to oppose them, offers no opposition. In such a case, universal silence is taken to imply the consent

of the people. This will be explained later on.

2. THAT SOVEREIGNTY IS INDIVISIBLE

SOVEREIGNTY, for the same reason as makes it inalienable, is indivisible; for will either is, or is not,

general;[6] it is the will either of the body of the people, or only of a part of it. In the first case, the will, when

declared, is an act of Sovereignty and constitutes law: in the second, it is merely a particular will, or act of

magistracy  at the most a decree.

But our political theorists, unable to divide Sovereignty in principle, divide it according to its object: into

force and will; into legislative power and executive power; into rights of taxation, justice and war; into

internal administration and power of foreign treaty. Sometimes they confuse all these sections, and

sometimes they distinguish them; they turn the Sovereign into a fantastic being composed of several

connected pieces: it is as if they were making man of several bodies, one with eyes, one with arms, another

with feet, and each with nothing besides. We are told that the jugglers of Japan dismember a child before the

eyes of the spectators; then they throw all the members into the air one after another, and the child falls down

alive and whole. The conjuring tricks of our political theorists are very like that; they first dismember the

Body politic by an illusion worthy of a fair, and then join it together again we know not how.

This error is due to a lack of exact notions concerning the Sovereign authority, and to taking for parts of it

what are only emanations from it. Thus, for example, the acts of declaring war and making peace have been

regarded as acts of Sovereignty; but this is not the case, as these acts do not constitute law, but merely the

application of a law, a particular act which decides how the law applies, as we shall see clearly when the idea


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 10



Top




Page No 13


attached to the word law has been defined.

If we examined the other divisions in the same manner, we should find that, whenever Sovereignty seems to

be divided, there is an illusion: the rights which are taken as being part of Sovereignty are really all

subordinate, and always imply supreme wills of which they only sanction the execution.

It would be impossible to estimate the obscurity this lack of exactness has thrown over the decisions of

writers who have dealt with political right, when they have used the principles laid down by them to pass

judgment on the respective rights of kings and peoples. Every one can see, in Chapters III and IV of the First

Book of Grotius, how the learned man and his translator, Barbeyrac, entangle and tie themselves up in their

own sophistries, for fear of saying too little or too much of what they think, and so offending the interests

they have to conciliate. Grotius, a refugee in France, illcontent with his own country, and desirous of paying

his court to Louis XIII, to whom his book is dedicated, spares no pains to rob the peoples of all their rights

and invest kings with them by every conceivable artifice. This would also have been much to the taste of

Barbeyrac, who dedicated his translation to George I of England. But unfortunately the expulsion of James II,

which he called his "abdication," compelled him to use all reserve, to shuffle and to tergiversate, in order to

avoid making William out a usurper. If these two writers had adopted the true principles, all difficulties

would have been removed, and they would have been always consistent; but it would have been a sad truth

for them to tell, and would have paid court for them to no one save the people. Moreover, truth is no road to

fortune, and the people dispenses neither ambassadorships, nor professorships, nor pensions.

3. WHETHER THE GENERAL WILL IS FALLIBLE

IT follows from what has gone before that the general will is always right and tends to the public advantage;

but it does not follow that the deliberations of the people are always equally correct. Our will is always for

our own good, but we do not always see what that is; the people is never corrupted, but it is often deceived,

and on such occasions only does it seem to will what is bad.

There is often a great deal of difference between the will of all and the general will; the latter considers only

the common interest, while the former takes private interest into account, and is no more than a sum of

particular wills: but take away from these same wills the pluses and minuses that cancel one another,[7] and

the general will remains as the sum of the differences.

If, when the people, being furnished with adequate information, held its deliberations, the citizens had no

communication one with another, the grand total of the small differences would always give the general will,

and the decision would always be good. But when factions arise, and partial associations are formed at the

expense of the great association, the will of each of these associations becomes general in relation to its

members, while it remains particular in relation to the State: it may then be said that there are no longer as

many votes as there are men, but only as many as there are associations. The differences become less

numerous and give a less general result. Lastly, when one of these associations is so great as to prevail over

all the rest, the result is no longer a sum of small differences, but a single difference; in this case there is no

longer a general will, and the opinion which prevails is purely particular.

It is therefore essential, if the general will is to be able to express itself, that there should be no partial society

within the State, and that each citizen should think only his own thoughts:[8] which was indeed the sublime

and unique system established by the great Lycurgus. But if there are partial societies, it is best to have as

many as possible and to prevent them from being unequal, as was done by Solon, Numa and Servius. These

precautions are the only ones that can guarantee that the general will shall be always enlightened, and that the

people shall in no way deceive itself.

4. THE LIMITS OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 11



Top




Page No 14


IF the State is a moral person whose life is in the union of its members, and if the most important of its cares

is the care for its own preservation, it must have a universal and compelling force, in order to move and

dispose each part as may be most advantageous to the whole. As nature gives each man absolute power over

all his members, the social compact gives the body politic absolute power over all its members also; and it is

this power which, under the direction of the general will, bears, as I have said, the name of Sovereignty.

But, besides the public person, we have to consider the private persons composing it, whose life and liberty

are naturally independent of it. We are bound then to distinguish clearly between the respective rights of the

citizens and the Sovereign,[9] and between the duties the former have to fulfil as subjects, and the natural

rights they should enjoy as men.

Each man alienates, I admit, by the social compact, only such part of his powers, goods and liberty as it is

important for the community to control; but it must also be granted that the Sovereign is sole judge of what is

important.

Every service a citizen can render the State he ought to render as soon as the Sovereign demands it; but the

Sovereign, for its part, cannot impose upon its subjects any fetters that are useless to the community, nor can

it even wish to do so; for no more by the law of reason than by the law of nature can anything occur without a

cause.

The undertakings which bind us to the social body are obligatory only because they are mutual; and their

nature is such that in fulfilling them we cannot work for others without working for ourselves. Why is it that

the general will is always in the right, and that all continually will the happiness of each one, unless it is

because there is not a man who does not think of "each" as meaning him, and consider himself in voting for

all? This proves that equality of rights and the idea of justice which such equality creates originate in the

preference each man gives to himself, and accordingly in the very nature of man. It proves that the general

will, to be really such, must be general in its object as well as its essence; that it must both come from all and

apply to all; and that it loses its natural rectitude when it is directed to some particular and determinate object,

because in such a case we are judging of something foreign to us, and have no true principle of equity to

guide us.

Indeed, as soon as a question of particular fact or right arises on a point not previously regulated by a general

convention, the matter becomes contentious. It is a case in which the individuals concerned are one party, and

the public the other, but in which I can see neither the law that ought to be followed nor the judge who ought

to give the decision. In such a case, it would be absurd to propose to refer the question to an express decision

of the general will, which can be only the conclusion reached by one of the parties and in consequence will

be, for the other party, merely an external and particular will, inclined on this occasion to injustice and

subject to error. Thus, just as a particular will cannot stand for the general will, the general will, in turn,

changes its nature, when its object is particular, and, as general, cannot pronounce on a man or a fact. When,

for instance, the people of Athens nominated or displaced its rulers, decreed honours to one, and imposed

penalties on another, and, by a multitude of particular decrees, exercised all the functions of government

indiscriminately, it had in such cases no longer a general will in the strict sense; it was acting no longer as

Sovereign, but as magistrate. This will seem contrary to current views; but I must be given time to expound

my own.

It should be seen from the foregoing that what makes the will general is less the number of voters than the

common interest uniting them; for, under this system, each necessarily submits to the conditions he imposes

on others: and this admirable agreement between interest and justice gives to the common deliberations an

equitable character which at once vanishes when any particular question is discussed, in the absence of a

common interest to unite and identify the ruling of the judge with that of the party.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 12



Top




Page No 15


From whatever side we approach our principle, we reach the same conclusion, that the social compact sets up

among the citizens an equality of such a kind, that they all bind themselves to observe the same conditions

and should therefore all enjoy the same rights. Thus, from the very nature of the compact, every act of

Sovereignty, i.e., every authentic act of the general will, binds or favours all the citizens equally; so that the

Sovereign recognises only the body of the nation, and draws no distinctions between those of whom it is

made up. What, then, strictly speaking, is an act of Sovereignty? It is not a convention between a superior and

an inferior, but a convention between the body and each of its members. It is legitimate, because based on the

social contract, and equitable, because common to all; useful, because it can have no other object than the

general good, and stable, because guaranteed by the public force and the supreme power. So long as the

subjects have to submit only to conventions of this sort, they obey noone but their own will; and to ask how

far the respective rights of the Sovereign and the citizens extend, is to ask up to what point the latter can enter

into undertakings with themselves, each with all, and all with each.

We can see from this that the sovereign power, absolute, sacred and inviolable as it is, does not and cannot

exceed the limits of general conventions, and that every man may dispose at will of such goods and liberty as

these conventions leave him; so that the Sovereign never has a right to lay more charges on one subject than

on another, because, in that case, the question becomes particular, and ceases to be within its competency.

When these distinctions have once been admitted, it is seen to be so untrue that there is, in the social contract,

any real renunciation on the part of the individuals, that the position in which they find themselves as a result

of the contract is really preferable to that in which they were before. Instead of a renunciation, they have

made an advantageous exchange: instead of an uncertain and precarious way of living they have got one that

is better and more secure; instead of natural independence they have got liberty, instead of the power to harm

others security for themselves, and instead of their strength, which others might overcome, a right which

social union makes invincible. Their very life, which they have devoted to the State, is by it constantly

protected; and when they risk it in the State's defence, what more are they doing than giving back what they

have received from it? What are they doing that they would not do more often and with greater danger in the

state of nature, in which they would inevitably have to fight battles at the peril of their lives in defence of that

which is the means of their preservation? All have indeed to fight when their country needs them; but then no

one has ever to fight for himself. Do we not gain something by running, on behalf of what gives us our

security, only some of the risks we should have to run for ourselves, as soon as we lost it?

5. THE RIGHT OF LIFE AND DEATH

THE question is often asked how individuals, having no right to dispose of their own lives, can transfer to the

Sovereign a right which they do not possess. The difficulty of answering this question seems to me to lie in

its being wrongly stated. Every man has a right to risk his own life in order to preserve it. Has it ever been

said that a man who throws himself out of the window to escape from a fire is guilty of suicide? Has such a

crime ever been laid to the charge of him who perishes in a storm because, when he went on board, he knew

of the danger?

The social treaty has for its end the preservation of the contracting parties. He who wills the end wills the

means also, and the means must involve some risks, and even some losses. He who wishes to preserve his life

at others' expense should also, when it is necessary, be ready to give it up for their sake. Furthermore, the

citizen is no longer the judge of the dangers to which the lawdesires him to expose himself; and when the

prince says to him: "It is expedient for the State that you should die," he ought to die, because it is only on

that condition that he has been living in security up to the present, and because his life is no longer a mere

bounty of nature, but a gift made conditionally by the State.

The deathpenalty inflicted upon criminals may be looked on in much the same light: it is in order that we

may not fall victims to an assassin that we consent to die if we ourselves turn assassins. In this treaty, so far


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 13



Top




Page No 16


from disposing of our own lives, we think only of securing them, and it is not to be assumed that any of the

parties then expects to get hanged.

Again, every malefactor, by attacking social rights, becomes on forfeit a rebel and a traitor to his country; by

violating its laws be ceases to be a member of it; he even makes war upon it. In such a case the preservation

of the State is inconsistent with his own, and one or the other must perish; in putting the guilty to death, we

slay not so much the citizen as an enemy. The trial and the judgment are the proofs that he has broken the

social treaty, and is in consequence no longer a member of the State. Since, then, he has recognised himself to

be such by living there, he must be removed by exile as a violator of the compact, or by death as a public

enemy; for such an enemy is not a moral person, but merely a man; and in such a case the right of war is to

kill the vanquished.

But, it will be said, the condemnation of a criminal is a particular act. I admit it: but such condemnation is not

a function of the Sovereign; it is a right the Sovereign can confer without being able itself to exert it. All my

ideas are consistent, but I cannot expound them all at once.

We may add that frequent punishments are always a sign of weakness or remissness on the part of the

government. There is not a single illdoer who could not be turned to some good. The State has no right to

put to death, even for the sake of making an example, any one whom it can leave alive without danger.

The right of pardoning or exempting the guilty from a penalty imposed by the law and pronounced by the

judge belongs only to the authority which is superior to both judge and law, i.e., the Sovereign; each its right

in this matter is far from clear, and the cases for exercising it are extremely rare. In a wellgoverned State,

there are few punishments, not because there are many pardons, but because criminals are rare; it is when a

State is in decay that the multitude of crimes is a guarantee of impunity. Under the Roman Republic, neither

the Senate nor the Consuls ever attempted to pardon; even the people never did so, though it sometimes

revoked its own decision. Frequent pardons mean that crime will soon need them no longer, and no one can

help seeing whither that leads. But I feel my heart protesting and restraining my pen; let us leave these

questions to the just man who has never offended, and would himself stand in no need of pardon.

6. LAW

BY the social compact we have given the body politic existence and life; we have now by legislation to give

it movement and will. For the original act by which the body is formed and united still in no respect

determines what it ought to do for its preservation.

What is well and in conformity with order is so by the nature of things and independently of human

conventions. All justice comes from God, who is its sole source; but if we knew how to receive so high an

inspiration, we should need neither government nor laws. Doubtless, there is a universal justice emanating

from reason alone; but this justice, to be admitted among us, must be mutual. Humanly speaking, in default of

natural sanctions, the laws of justice are ineffective among men: they merely make for the good of the wicked

and the undoing of the just, when the just man observes them towards everybody and nobody observes them

towards him. Conventions and laws are therefore needed to join rights to duties and refer justice to its object.

In the state of nature, where everything is common, I owe nothing to him whom I have promised nothing; I

recognise as belonging to others only what is of no use to me. In the state of society all rights are fixed by

law, and the case becomes different.

But what, after all, is a law? As long as we remain satisfied with attaching purely metaphysical ideas to the

word, we shall go on arguing without arriving at an understanding; and when we have defined a law of

nature, we shall be no nearer the definition of a law of the State.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 14



Top




Page No 17


I have already said that there can be no general will directed to a particular object. Such an object must be

either within or outside the State. If outside, a will which is alien to it cannot be, in relation to it, general; if

within, it is part of the State, and in that case there arises a relation between whole and part which makes

them two separate beings, of which the part is one, and the whole minus the part the other. But the whole

minus a part cannot be the whole; and while this relation persists, there can be no whole, but only two

unequal parts; and it follows that the will of one is no longer in any respect general in relation to the other.

But when the whole people decrees for the whole people, it is considering only itself; and if a relation is then

formed, it is between two aspects of the entire object, without there being any division of the whole. In that

case the matter about which the decree is made is, like the decreeing will, general. This act is what I call a

law.

When I say that the object of laws is always general, I mean that law considers subjects en masse and actions

in the abstract, and never a particular person or action. Thus the law may indeed decree that there shall be

privileges, but cannot confer them on anybody by name. It may set up several classes of citizens, and even

lay down the qualifications for membership of these classes, but it cannot nominate such and such persons as

belonging to them; it may establish a monarchical government and hereditary succession, but it cannot

choose a king, or nominate a royal family. In a word, no function which has a particular object belongs to the

legislative power.

On this view, we at once see that it can no longer be asked whose business it is to make laws, since they are

acts of the general will; nor whether the prince is above the law, since he is a member of the State; nor

whether the law can be unjust, since no one is unjust to himself; nor how we can be both free and subject to

the laws, since they are but registers of our wills.

We see further that, as the law unites universality of will with universality of object, what a man, whoever he

be, commands of his own motion cannot be a law; and even what the Sovereign commands with regard to a

particular matter is no nearer being a law, but is a decree, an act, not of sovereignty, but of magistracy.

I therefore give the name "Republic" to every State that is governed by laws, no matter what the form of its

administration may be: for only in such a case does the public interest govern, and the res publica rank as a

reality. Every legitimate government is republican;[10] what government is I will explain later on.

Laws are, properly speaking, only the conditions of civil association. The people, being subject to the laws,

ought to be their author: the conditions of the society ought to be regulated solely by those who come

together to form it. But how are they to regulate them? Is it to be by common agreement, by a sudden

inspiration? Has the body politic an organ to declare its will? Who can give it the foresight to formulate and

announce its acts in advance? Or how is it to announce them in the hour of need? How can a blind multitude,

which often does not know what it wills, because it rarely knows what is good for it, carry out for itself so

great and difficult an enterprise as a system of legislation? Of itself the people wills always the good, but of

itself it by no means always sees it. The general will is always in the right, but the judgment which guides it

is not always enlightened. It must be got to see objects as they are, and sometimes as they ought to appear to

it; it must be shown the good road it is in search of, secured from the seductive influences of individual wills,

taught to see times and spaces as a series, and made to weigh the attractions of present and sensible

advantages against the danger of distant and hidden evils. The individuals see the good they reject; the public

wills the good it does not see. All stand equally in need of guidance. The former must be compelled to bring

their wills into conformity with their reason; the latter must be taught to know what it wills. If that is done,

public enlightenment leads to the union of understanding and will in the social body: the parts are made to

work exactly together, and the whole is raised to its highest power. This makes a legislator necessary.

7. THE LEGISLATOR


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 15



Top




Page No 18


IN order to discover the rules of society best suited to nations, a superior intelligence beholding all the

passions of men without experiencing any of them would be needed. This intelligence would have to be

wholly unrelated to our nature, while knowing it through and through; its happiness would have to be

independent of us, and yet ready to occupy itself with ours; and lastly, it would have, in the march of time, to

look forward to a distant glory, and, working in one century, to be able to enjoy in the next.[11] It would take

gods to give men laws.

What Caligula argued from the facts, Plato, in the dialogue called the Politicus, argued in defining the civil or

kingly man, on the basis of right. But if great princes are rare, how much more so are great legislators? The

former have only to follow the pattern which the latter have to lay down. The legislator is the engineer who

invents the machine, the prince merely the mechanic who sets it up and makes it go. "At the birth of

societies," says Montesquieu, "the rulers of Republics establish institutions, and afterwards the institutions

mould the rulers."[12]

He who dares to undertake the making of a people's institutions ought to feel himself capable, so to speak, of

changing human nature, of transforming each individual, who is by himself a complete and solitary whole,

into part of a greater whole from which he in a manner receives his life and being; of altering man's

constitution for the purpose of strengthening it; and of substituting a partial and moral existence for the

physical and independent existence nature has conferred on us all. He must, in a word, take away from man

his own resources and give him instead new ones alien to him, and incapable of being made use of without

the help of other men. The more completely these natural resources are annihilated, the greater and the more

lasting are those which he acquires, and the more stable and perfect the new institutions; so that if each

citizen is nothing and can do nothing without the rest, and the resources acquired by the whole are equal or

superior to the aggregate of the resources of all the individuals, it may be said that legislation is at the highest

possible point of perfection.

The legislator occupies in every respect an extraordinary position in the State. If he should do so by reason of

his genius, he does so no less by reason of his office, which is neither magistracy, nor Sovereignty. This

office, which sets up the Republic, nowhere enters into its constitution; it is an individual and superior

function, which has nothing in common with human empire; for if he who holds command over men ought

not to have command over the laws, he who has command over the laws ought not any more to have it over

men; or else his laws would be the ministers of his passions and would often merely serve to perpetuate his

injustices: his private aims would inevitably mar the sanctity of his work.

When Lycurgus gave laws to his country, he began by resigning the throne. It was the custom of most Greek

towns to entrust the establishment of their laws to foreigners. The Republics of modern Italy in many cases

followed this example; Geneva did the same and profited by it.[13] Rome, when it was most prosperous,

suffered a revival of all the crimes of tyranny, and was brought to the verge of destruction, because it put the

legislative authority and the sovereign power into the same hands.

Nevertheless, the decemvirs themselves never claimed the right to pass any law merely on their own

authority. "Nothing we propose to you," they said to the people, "can pass into law without your consent.

Romans, be yourselves the authors of the laws which are to make you happy."

He, therefore, who draws up the laws has, or should have, no right of legislation, and the people cannot, even

if it wishes, deprive itself of this incommunicable right, because, according to the fundamental compact, only

the general will can bind the individuals, and there can be no assurance that a particular will is in conformity

with the general will, until it has been put to the free vote of the people. This I have said already; but it is

worth while to repeat it.

Thus in the task of legislation we find together two things which appear to be incompatible: an enterprise too


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 16



Top




Page No 19


difficult for human powers, and, for its execution, an authority that is no authority.

There is a further difficulty that deserves attention. Wise men, if they try to speak their language to the

common herd instead of its own, cannot possibly make themselves understood. There are a thousand kinds of

ideas which it is impossible to translate into popular language. Conceptions that are too general and objects

that are too remote are equally out of its range: each individual, having no taste for any other plan of

government than that which suits his particular interest, finds it difficult to realise the advantages he might

hope to draw from the continual privations good laws impose. For a young people to be able to relish sound

principles of political theory and follow the fundamental rules of statecraft, the effect would have to become

the cause; the social spirit, which should be created by these institutions, would have to preside over their

very foundation; and men would have to be before law what they should become by means of law. The

legislator therefore, being unable to appeal to either force or reason, must have recourse to an authority of a

different order, capable of constraining without violence and persuading without convincing.

This is what has, in all ages, compelled the fathers of nations to have recourse to divine intervention and

credit the gods with their own wisdom, in order that the peoples, submitting to the laws of the State as to

those of nature, and recognising the same power in the formation of the city as in that of man, might obey

freely, and bear with docility the yoke of the public happiness.

This sublime reason, far above the range of the common herd, is that whose decisions the legislator puts into

the mouth of the immortals, in order to constrain by divine authority those whom human prudence could not

move.[14] But it is not anybody who can make the gods speak, or get himself believed when he proclaims

himself their interpreter. The great soul of the legislator is the only miracle that can prove his mission. Any

man may grave tablets of stone, or buy an oracle, or feign secret intercourse with some divinity, or train a

bird to whisper in his ear, or find other vulgar ways of imposing on the people. He whose knowledge goes no

further may perhaps gather round him a band of fools; but he will never found an empire, and his

extravagances will quickly perish with him. Idle tricks form a passing tie; only wisdom can make it lasting.

The Judaic law, which still subsists, and that of the child of Ishmael, which, for ten centuries, has ruled half

the world, still proclaim the great men who laid them down; and, while the pride of philosophy or the blind

spirit of faction sees in them no more than lucky impostures, the true political theorist admires, in the

institutions they set up, the great and powerful genius which presides over things made to endure.

We should not, with Warburton, conclude from this that politics and religion have among us a common

object, but that, in the first periods of nations, the one is used as an instrument for the other.

8. THE PEOPLE

AS, before putting up a large building, the architect surveys and sounds the site to see if it will bear the

weight, the wise legislator does not begin by laying down laws good in themselves, but by investigating the

fitness of the people, for which they are destined, to receive them. Plato refused to legislate for the Arcadians

and the Cyrenaeans, because he knew that both peoples were rich and could not put up with equality; and

good laws and bad men were found together in Crete, because Minos had inflicted discipline on a people

already burdened with vice.

A thousand nations have achieved earthly greatness, that could never have endured good laws; even such as

could have endured them could have done so only for a very brief period of their long history. Most peoples,

like most men, are docile only in youth; as they grow old they become incorrigible. When once customs have

become established and prejudices inveterate, it is dangerous and useless to attempt their reformation; the

people, like the foolish and cowardly patients who rave at sight of the doctor, can no longer bear that any one

should lay hands on its faults to remedy them.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 17



Top




Page No 20


There are indeed times in the history of States when, just as some kinds of illness turn men's heads and make

them forget the past, periods of violence and revolutions do to peoples what these crises do to individuals:

horror of the past takes the place of forgetfulness, and the State, set on fire by civil wars, is born again, so to

speak, from its ashes, and takes on anew, fresh from the jaws of death, the vigour of youth. Such were Sparta

at the time of Lycurgus, Rome after the Tarquins, and, in modern times, Holland and Switzerland after the

expulsion of the tyrants.

But such events are rare; they are exceptions, the cause of which is always to be found in the particular

constitution of the State concerned. They cannot even happen twice to the same people, for it can make itself

free as long as it remains barbarous, but not when the civic impulse has lost its vigour. Then disturbances

may destroy it, but revolutions cannot mend it: it needs a master, and not a liberator. Free peoples, be mindful

of this maxim: "Liberty may be gained, but can never be recovered."

Youth is not infancy. There is for nations, as for men, a period of youth, or, shall we say, maturity, before

which they should not be made subject to laws; but the maturity of a people is not always easily recognisable,

and, if it is anticipated, the work is spoilt. One people is amenable to discipline from the beginning; another,

not after ten centuries. Russia will never be really civilised, because it was civilised too soon. Peter had a

genius for imitation; but he lacked true genius, which is creative and makes all from nothing. He did some

good things, but most of what he did was out of place. He saw that his people was barbarous, but did not see

that it was not ripe for civilisation: he wanted to civilise it when it needed only hardening. His first wish was

to make Germans or Englishmen, when he ought to have been making Russians; and he prevented his

subjects from ever becoming what they might have been by persuading them that they were what they are

not. In this fashion too a French teacher turns out his pupil to be an infant prodigy, and for the rest of his life

to be nothing whatsoever. The empire of Russia will aspire to conquer Europe, and will itself be conquered.

The Tartars, its subjects or neighbours, will become its masters and ours, by a revolution which I regard as

inevitable. Indeed, all the kings of Europe are working in concert to hasten its coming.

9. THE PEOPLE (continued)

As nature has set bounds to the stature of a wellmade man, and, outside those limits, makes nothing but

giants or dwarfs, similarly, for the constitution of a State to be at its best, it is possible to fix limits that will

make it neither too large for good government, nor too small for selfmaintenance. In every body politic

there is a maximum strength which it cannot exceed and which it only loses by increasing in size. Every

extension of the social tie means its relaxation; and, generally speaking, a small State is stronger in

proportion than a great one.

A thousand arguments could be advanced in favour of this principle. First, long distances make

administration more difficult, just as a weight becomes heavier at the end of a longer lever. Administration

therefore becomes more and more burdensome as the distance grows greater; for, in the first place, each city

has its own, which is paid for by the people: each district its own, still paid for by the people: then comes

each province, and then the great governments, satrapies, and viceroyalties, always costing more the higher

you go, and always at the expense of the unfortunate people. Last of all comes the supreme administration,

which eclipses all the rest. All these over charges are a continual drain upon the subjects; so far from being

better governed by all these different orders, they are worse governed than if there were only a single

authority over them. In the meantime, there scarce remain resources enough to meet emergencies; and, when

recourse must be had to these, the State is always on the eve of destruction.

This is not all; not only has the government less vigour and promptitude for securing the observance of the

laws, preventing nuisances, correcting abuses, and guarding against seditious undertakings begun in distant

places; the people has less affection for its rulers, whom it never sees, for its country, which, to its eyes,

seems like the world, and for its fellowcitizens, most of whom are unknown to it. The same laws cannot suit


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 18



Top




Page No 21


so many diverse provinces with different customs, situated in the most various climates, and incapable of

enduring a uniform government. Different laws lead only to trouble and confusion among peoples which,

living under the same rulers and in constant communication one with another, intermingle and intermarry,

and, coming under the sway of new customs, never know if they can call their very patrimony their own.

Talent is buried, virtue unknown and vice unpunished, among such a multitude of men who do not know one

another, gathered together in one place at the seat of the central administration. The leaders, overwhelmed

with business, see nothing for themselves; the State is governed by clerks. Finally, the measures which have

to be taken to maintain the general authority, which all these distant officials wish to escape or to impose

upon, absorb all the energy of the public, so that there is none left for the happiness of the people. There is

hardly enough to defend it when need arises, and thus a body which is too big for its constitution gives way

and falls crushed under its own weight.

Again, the State must assure itself a safe foundation, if it is to have stability, and to be able to resist the

shocks it cannot help experiencing, as well as the efforts it will be forced to make for its maintenance; for all

peoples have a kind of centrifugal force that makes them continually act one against another, and tend to

aggrandise themselves at their neighbours' expense, like the vortices of Descartes. Thus the weak run the risk

of being soon swallowed up; and it is almost impossible for any one to preserve itself except by putting itself

in a state of equilibrium with all, so that the pressure is on all sides practically equal.

It may therefore be seen that there are reasons for expansion and reasons for contraction; and it is no small

part of the statesman's skill to hit between them the mean that is most favourable to the preservation of the

State. It may be said that the reason for expansion, being merely external and relative, ought to be subordinate

to the reasons for contraction, which are internal and absolute. A strong and healthy constitution is the first

thing to look for; and it is better to count on the vigour which comes of good government than on the

resources a great territory furnishes.

It may be added that there have been known States so constituted that the necessity of making conquests

entered into their very constitution, and that, in order to maintain themselves, they were forced to expand

ceaselessly. It may be that they congratulated themselves greatly on this fortunate necessity, which none the

less indicated to them, along with the limits of their greatness, the inevitable moment of their fall.

10. THE PEOPLE (continued)

A BODY politic may be measured in two ways  either by the extent of its territory, or by the number of its

people; and there is, between these two measurements, a right relation which makes the State really great.

The men make the State, and the territory sustains the men; the right relation therefore is that the land should

suffice for the maintenance of the inhabitants, and that there should be as many inhabitants as the land can

maintain. In this proportion lies the maximum strength of a given number of people; for, if there is too much

land, it is troublesome to guard and inadequately cultivated, produces more than is needed, and soon gives

rise to wars of defence; if there is not enough, the State depends on its neighbours for what it needs over and

above, and this soon gives rise to wars of offence. Every people, to which its situation gives no choice save

that between commerce and war, is weak in itself: it depends on its neighbours, and on circumstances; its

existence can never be more than short and uncertain. It either conquers others, and changes its situation, or it

is conquered and becomes nothing. Only insignificance or greatness can keep it free.

No fixed relation can be stated between the extent of territory and the population that are adequate one to the

other, both because of the differences in the quality of land, in its fertility, in the nature of its products, and in

the influence of climate, and because of the different tempers of those who inhabit it; for some in a fertile

country consume little, and others on an ungrateful soil much. The greater or less fecundity of women, the

conditions that are more or less favourable in each country to the growth of population, and the influence the

legislator can hope to exercise by his institutions, must also be taken into account. The legislator therefore


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 19



Top




Page No 22


should not go by what he sees, but by what he foresees; he should stop not so much at the state in which he

actually finds the population, as at that to which it ought naturally to attain. Lastly, there are countless cases

in which the particular local circumstances demand or allow the acquisition of a greater territory than seems

necessary. Thus, expansion will be great in a mountainous country, where the natural products, i.e., woods

and pastures, need less labour, where we know from experience that women are more fertile than in the

plains, and where a great expanse of slope affords only a small level tract that can be counted on for

vegetation. On the other hand, contraction is possible on the coast, even in lands of rocks and nearly barren

sands, because there fishing makes up to a great extent for the lack of landproduce, because the inhabitants

have to congregate together more in order to repel pirates, and further because it is easier to unburden the

country of its superfluous inhabitants by means of colonies.

To these conditions of lawgiving must be added one other which, though it cannot take the place of the rest,

renders them all useless when it is absent. This is the enjoyment of peace and plenty; for the moment at which

a State sets its house in order is, like the moment when a battalion is forming up, that when its body is least

capable of offering resistance and easiest to destroy. A better resistance could be made at a time of absolute

disorganisation than at a moment of fermentation, when each is occupied with his own position and not with

the danger. If war, famine, or sedition arises at this time of crisis, the State will inevitably be overthrown.

Not that many governments have not been set up during such storms; but in such cases these governments are

themselves the State's destroyers. Usurpers always bring about or select troublous times to get passed, under

cover of the public terror, destructive laws, which the people would never adopt in cold blood. The moment

chosen is one of the surest means of distinguishing the work of the legislator from that of the tyrant.

What people, then, is a fit subject for legislation? One which, already bound by some unity of origin, interest,

or convention, has never yet felt the real yoke of law; one that has neither customs nor superstitions deeply

ingrained, one which stands in no fear of being overwhelmed by sudden invasion; one which, without

entering into its neighbours' quarrels, can resist each of them singlehanded, or get the help of one to repel

another; one in which every member may be known by every other, and there is no need to lay on any man

burdens too heavy for a man to bear; one which can do without other peoples, and without which all others

can do;[15] one which is neither rich nor poor, but selfsufficient; and, lastly, one which unites the

consistency of an ancient people with the docility of a new one. Legislation is made difficult less by what it is

necessary to build up than by what has to be destroyed; and what makes success so rare is the impossibility of

finding natural simplicity together with social requirements. All these conditions are indeed rarely found

united, and therefore few States have good constitutions.

There is still in Europe one country capable of being given laws  Corsica. The valour and persistency with

which that brave people has regained and defended its liberty well deserves that some wise man should teach

it how to preserve what it has won. I have a feeling that some day that little island will astonish Europe.

11. THE VARIOUS SYSTEMS OF LEGISLATION

IF we ask in what precisely consists the greatest good of all, which should be the end of every system of

legislation, we shall find it reduce itself to two main objects, liberty and equality  liberty, because all

particular dependence means so much force taken from the body of the State and equality, because liberty

cannot exist without it.

I have already defined civil liberty; by equality, we should understand, not that the degrees of power and

riches are to be absolutely identical for everybody; but that power shall never be great enough for violence,

and shall always be exercised by virtue of rank and law; and that, in respect of riches, no citizen shall ever be

wealthy enough to buy another, and none poor enough to be forced to sell himself:[16] which implies, on the

part of the great, moderation in goods and position, and, on the side of the common sort, moderation in


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 20



Top




Page No 23


avarice and covetousness.

Such equality, we are told, is an unpractical ideal that cannot actually exist. But if its abuse is inevitable, does

it follow that we should not at least make regulations concerning it? It is precisely because the force of

circumstances tends continually to destroy equality that the force of legislation should always tend to its

maintenance.

But these general objects of every good legislative system need modifying in every country in accordance

with the local situation and the temper of the inhabitants; and these circumstances should determine, in each

case, the particular system of institutions which is best, not perhaps in itself, but for the State for which it is

destined. If, for instance, the soil is barren and unproductive, or the land too crowded for its inhabitants, the

people should turn to industry and the crafts, and exchange what they produce for the commodities they lack.

If, on the other hand, a people dwells in rich plains and fertile slopes, or, in a good land, lacks inhabitants, it

should give all its attention to agriculture, which causes men to multiply, and should drive out the crafts,

which would only result in depopulation, by grouping in a few localities the few inhabitants there are.[17] If a

nation dwells on an extensive and convenient coastline, let it cover the sea with ships and foster commerce

and navigation. It will have a life that will be short and glorious. If, on its coasts, the sea washes nothing but

almost inaccessible rocks, let it remain barbarous and ichthyophagous: it will have a quieter, perhaps a better,

and certainly a happier life. In a word, besides the principles that are common to all, every nation has in itself

something that gives them a particular application, and makes its legislation peculiarly its own. Thus, among

the Jews long ago and more recently among the Arabs, the chief object was religion, among the Athenians

letters, at Carthage and Tyre commerce, at Rhodes shipping, at Sparta war, at Rome virtue. The author of The

Spirit of the Laws has shown with many examples by what art the legislator directs the constitution towards

each of these objects. What makes the constitution of a State really solid and lasting is the due observance of

what is proper, so that the natural relations are always in agreement with the laws on every point, and law

only serves, so to speak, to assure, accompany and rectify them. But if the legislator mistakes his object and

adopts a principle other than circumstances naturally direct; if his principle makes for servitude while they

make for liberty, or if it makes for riches, while they make for populousness, or if it makes for peace, while

they make for conquest  the laws will insensibly lose their influence, the constitution will alter, and the

State will have no rest from trouble till it is either destroyed or changed, and nature has resumed her

invincible sway.

12. THE DIVISION OF THE LAWS

IF the whole is to be set in order, and the commonwealth put into the best possible shape, there are various

relations to be considered. First, there is the action of the complete body upon itself, the relation of the whole

to the whole, of the Sovereign to the State; and this relation, as we shall see, is made up of the relations of the

intermediate terms.

The laws which regulate this relation bear the name of political laws, and are also called fundamental laws,

not without reason if they are wise. For, if there is, in each State, only one good system, the people that is in

possession of it should hold fast to this; but if the established order is bad, why should laws that prevent men

from being good be regarded as fundamental? Besides, in any case, a people is always in a position to change

its laws, however good; for, if it choose to do itself harm, who can have a right to stop it?

The second relation is that of the members one to another, or to the body as a whole; and this relation should

be in the first respect as unimportant, and in the second as important, as possible. Each citizen would then be

perfectly independent of all the rest, and at the same time very dependent on the city; which is brought about

always by the same means, as the strength of the State can alone secure the liberty of its members. From this

second relation arise civil laws.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 21



Top




Page No 24


We may consider also a third kind of relation between the individual and the law, a relation of disobedience

to its penalty. This gives rise to the setting up of criminal laws, which, at bottom, are less a particular class of

law than the sanction behind all the rest.

Along with these three kinds of law goes a fourth, most important of all, which is not graven on tablets of

marble or brass, but on the hearts of the citizens. This forms the real constitution of the State, takes on every

day new powers, when other laws decay or die out, restores them or takes their place, keeps a people in the

ways in which it was meant to go, and insensibly replaces authority by the force of habit. I am speaking of

morality, of custom, above all of public opinion; a power unknown to political thinkers, on which none the

less success in everything else depends. With this the great legislator concerns himself in secret, though he

seems to confine himself to particular regulations; for these are only the arc of the arch, while manners and

morals, slower to arise, form in the end its immovable keystone.

Among the different classes of laws, the political, which determine the forms of the government, are alone

relevant to my subject.

BOOK III

BEFORE speaking of the different forms of government, let us try to fix the exact sense of the word, which

has not yet been very clearly explained.

1. GOVERNMENT IN GENERAL

I WARN the reader that this chapter requires careful reading, and that I am unable to make myself clear to

those who refuse to be attentive. Every free action is produced by the concurrence of two causes; one moral,

i.e., the will which determines the act; the other physical, i.e., the power which executes it. When I walk

towards an object, it is necessary first that I should will to go there, and, in the second place, that my feet

should carry me. If a paralytic wills to run and an active man wills not to, they will both stay where they are.

The body politic has the same motive powers; here too force and will are distinguished, will under the name

of legislative power and force under that of executive power. Without their concurrence, nothing is, or should

be, done.

We have seen that the legislative power belongs to the people, and can belong to it alone. It may, on the other

hand, readily be seen, from the principles laid down above, that the executive power cannot belong to the

generality as legislature or Sovereign, because it consists wholly of particular acts which fall outside the

competency of the law, and consequently of the Sovereign, whose acts must always be laws.

The public force therefore needs an agent of its own to bind it together and set it to work under the direction

of the general will, to serve as a means of communication between the State and the Sovereign, and to do for

the collective person more or less what the union of soul and body does for man. Here we have what is, in the

State, the basis of government, often wrongly confused with the Sovereign, whose minister it is.

What then is government? An intermediate body set up between the subjects and the Sovereign, to secure

their mutual correspondence, charged with the execution of the laws and the maintenance of liberty, both

civil and political.

The members of this body are called magistrates or kings, that is to say governors, and the whole body bears

the name prince.[18] Thus those who hold that the act, by which a people puts itself under a prince, is not a


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 22



Top




Page No 25


contract, are certainly right. It is simply and solely a commission, an employment, in which the rulers, mere

officials of the Sovereign, exercise in their own name the power of which it makes them depositaries. This

power it can limit, modify or recover at pleasure; for the alienation of such a right is incompatible with the

nature of the social body, and contrary to the end of association.

I call then government, or supreme administration, the legitimate exercise of the executive power, and prince

or magistrate the man or the body entrusted with that administration.

In government reside the intermediate forces whose relations make up that of the whole to the whole, or of

the Sovereign to the State. This last relation may be represented as that between the extreme terms of a

continuous proportion, which has government as its mean proportional. The government gets from the

Sovereign the orders it gives the people, and, for the State to be properly balanced, there must, when

everything is reckoned in, be equality between the product or power of the government taken in itself, and the

product or power of the citizens, who are on the one hand sovereign and on the other subject.

Furthermore, none of these three terms can be altered without the equality being instantly destroyed. If the

Sovereign desires to govern, or the magistrate to give laws, or if the subjects refuse to obey, disorder takes

the place of regularity, force and will no longer act together, and the State is dissolved and falls into

despotism or anarchy. Lastly, as there is only one mean proportional between each relation, there is also only

one good government possible for a State. But, as countless events may change the relations of a people, not

only may different governments be good for different peoples, but also for the same people at different times.

In attempting to give some idea of the various relations that may hold between these two extreme terms, I

shall take as an example the number of a people, which is the most easily expressible.

Suppose the State is composed of ten thousand citizens. The Sovereign can only be considered collectively

and as a body; but each member, as being a subject, is regarded as an individual: thus the Sovereign is to the

subject as ten thousand to one, i.e., each member of the State has as his share only a tenthousandth part of

the sovereign authority, although he is wholly under its control. If the people numbers a hundred thousand,

the condition of the subject undergoes no change, and each equally is under the whole authority of the laws,

while his vote, being reduced to a hundredthousandth part, has ten times less influence in drawing them up.

The subject therefore remaining always a unit, the relation between him and the Sovereign increases with the

number of the citizens. From this it follows that, the larger the State, the less the liberty.

When I say the relation increases, I mean that it grows more unequal. Thus the greater it is in the geometrical

sense, the less relation there is in the ordinary sense of the word. In the former sense, the relation, considered

according to quantity, is expressed by the quotient; in the latter, considered according to identity, it is

reckoned by similarity.

Now, the less relation the particular wills have to the general will, that is, morals and manners to laws, the

more should the repressive force be increased. The government, then, to be good, should be proportionately

stronger as the people is more numerous.

On the other hand, as the growth of the State gives the depositaries of the public authority more temptations

and chances of abusing their power, the greater the force with which the government ought to be endowed for

keeping the people in hand, the greater too should be the force at the disposal of the Sovereign for keeping

the government in hand. I am speaking, not of absolute force, but of the relative force of the different parts of

the State.

It follows from this double relation that the continuous proportion between the Sovereign, the prince and the

people, is by no means an arbitrary idea, but a necessary consequence of the nature of the body politic. It


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 23



Top




Page No 26


follows further that, one of the extreme terms, viz., the people, as subject, being fixed and represented by

unity, whenever the duplicate ratio increases or diminishes, the simple ratio does the same, and is changed

accordingly. From this we see that there is not a single unique and absolute form of government, but as many

governments differing in nature as there are States differing in size.

If, ridiculing this system, any one were to say that, in order to find the mean proportional and give form to the

body of the government, it is only necessary, according to me, to find the square root of the number of the

people, I should answer that I am here taking this number only as an instance; that the relations of which I am

speaking are not measured by the number of men alone, but generally by the amount of action, which is a

combination of a multitude of causes; and that, further, if, to save words, I borrow for a moment the terms of

geometry, I am none the less well aware that moral quantities do not allow of geometrical accuracy.

The government is on a small scale what the body politic which includes it is on a great one. It is a moral

person endowed with certain faculties, active like the Sovereign and passive like the State, and capable of

being resolved into other similar relations. This accordingly gives rise to a new proportion, within which

there is yet another, according to the arrangement of the magistracies, till an indivisible middle term is

reached, i.e., a single ruler or supreme magistrate, who may be represented, in the midst of this progression,

as the unity between the fractional and the ordinal series.

Without encumbering ourselves with this multiplication of terms, let us rest content with regarding

government as a new body within the State, distinct from the people and the Sovereign, and intermediate

between them.

There is between these two bodies this essential difference, that the State exists by itself, and the government

only through the Sovereign. Thus the dominant will of the prince is, or should be, nothing but the general will

or the law; his force is only the public force concentrated in his hands, and, as soon as he tries to base any

absolute and independent act on his own authority, the tie that binds the whole together begins to be

loosened. If finally the prince should come to have a particular will more active than the will of the

Sovereign, and should employ the public force in his hands in obedience to this particular will, there would

be, so to speak, two Sovereigns, one rightful and the other actual, the social union would evaporate instantly,

and the body politic would be dissolved.

However, in order that the government may have a true existence and a real life distinguishing it from the

body of the State, and in order that all its members may be able to act in concert and fulfil the end for which it

was set up, it must have a particular personality, a sensibility common to its members, and a force and will of

its own making for its preservation. This particular existence implies assemblies, councils, power and

deliberation and decision, rights, titles, and privileges belonging exclusively to the prince and making the

office of magistrate more honourable in proportion as it is more troublesome. The difficulties lie in the

manner of so ordering this subordinate whole within the whole, that it in no way alters the general

constitution by affirmation of its own, and always distinguishes the particular force it possesses, which is

destined to aid in its preservation, from the public force, which is destined to the preservation of the State;

and, in a word, is always ready to sacrifice the government to the people, and never to sacrifice the people to

the government.

Furthermore, although the artificial body of the government is the work of another artificial body, and has,

we may say, only a borrowed and subordinate life, this does not prevent it from being able to act with more or

less vigour or promptitude, or from being, so to speak, in more or less robust health. Finally, without

departing directly from the end for which it was instituted, it may deviate more or less from it, according to

the manner of its constitution.

From all these differences arise the various relations which the government ought to bear to the body of the


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 24



Top




Page No 27


State, according to the accidental and particular relations by which the State itself is modified, for often the

government that is best in itself will become the most pernicious, if the relations in which it stands have

altered according to the defects of the body politic to which it belongs.

2. THE CONSTITUENT PRINCIPLE IN THE VARIOUS FORMS OF GOVERNMENT

TO set forth the general cause of the above differences, we must here distinguish between government and its

principle, as we did before between the State and the Sovereign.

The body of the magistrate may be composed of a greater or a less number of members. We said that the

relation of the Sovereign to the subjects was greater in proportion as the people was more numerous, and, by

a clear analogy, we may say the same of the relation of the government to the magistrates.

But the total force of the government, being always that of the State, is invariable; so that, the more of this

force it expends on its own members, the less it has left to employ on the whole people.

The more numerous the magistrates, therefore, the weaker the government. This principle being fundamental,

we must do our best to make it clear.

In the person of the magistrate we can distinguish three essentially different wills: first, the private will of the

individual, tending only to his personal advantage; secondly, the common will of the magistrates, which is

relative solely to the advantage of the prince, and may be called corporate will, being general in relation to

the government, and particular in relation to the State, of which the government forms part; and, in the third

place, the will of the people or the sovereign will, which is general both in relation to the State regarded as

the whole, and to the government regarded as a part of the whole.

In a perfect act of legislation, the individual or particular will should be at zero; the corporate will belonging

to the government should occupy a very subordinate position; and, consequently, the general or sovereign

will should always predominate and should be the sole guide of all the rest.

According to the natural order, on the other hand, these different wills become more active in proportion as

they are concentrated. Thus, the general will is always the weakest, the corporate will second, and the

individual will strongest of all: so that, in the government, each member is first of all himself, then a

magistrate, and then a citizen  in an order exactly the reverse of what the social system requires.

This granted, if the whole government is in the hands of one man, the particular and the corporate will are

wholly united, and consequently the latter is at its highest possible degree of intensity. But, as the use to

which the force is put depends on the degree reached by the will, and as the absolute force of the government

is invariable, it follows that the most active government is that of one man.

Suppose, on the other hand, we unite the government with the legislative authority, and make the Sovereign

prince also, and all the citizens so many magistrates: then the corporate will, being confounded with the

general will, can possess no greater activity than that will, and must leave the particular will as strong as it

can possibly be. Thus, the government, having always the same absolute force, will be at the lowest point of

its relative force or activity.

These relations are incontestable, and there are other considerations which still further confirm them. We can

see, for instance, that each magistrate is more active in the body to which he belongs than each citizen in that

to which he belongs, and that consequently the particular will has much more influence on the acts of the

government than on those of the Sovereign; for each magistrate is almost always charged with some

governmental function, while each citizen, taken singly, exercises no function of Sovereignty. Furthermore,


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 25



Top




Page No 28


the bigger the State grows, the more its real force increases, though not in direct proportion to its growth; but,

the State remaining the same, the number of magistrates may increase to any extent, without the government

gaining any greater real force; for its force is that of the State, the dimension of which remains equal. Thus

the relative force or activity of the government decreases, while its absolute or real force cannot increase.

Moreover, it is a certainty that promptitude in execution diminishes as more people are put in charge of it:

where prudence is made too much of, not enough is made of fortune; opportunity is let slip, and deliberation

results in the loss of its object.

I have just proved that the government grows remiss in proportion as the number of the magistrates increases;

and I previously proved that, the more numerous the people, the greater should be the repressive force. From

this it follows that the relation of the magistrates to the government should vary inversely to the relation of

the subjects to the Sovereign; that is to say, the larger the State, the more should the government be tightened,

so that the number of the rulers diminish in proportion to the increase of that of the people.

It should be added that I am here speaking of the relative strength of the government, and not of its rectitude:

for, on the other hand, the more numerous the magistracy, the nearer the corporate will comes to the general

will; while, under a single magistrate, the corporate will is, as I said, merely a particular will. Thus, what may

be gained on one side is lost on the other, and the art of the legislator is to know how to fix the point at which

the force and the will of the government, which are always in inverse proportion, meet in the relation that is

most to the advantage of the State.

3. THE DIVISION OF GOVERNMENTS

WE saw in the last chapter what causes the various kinds or forms of government to be distinguished

according to the number of the members composing them: it remains in this to discover how the division is

made.

In the first place, the Sovereign may commit the charge of the government to the whole people or to the

majority of the people, so that more citizens are magistrates than are mere private individuals. This form of

government is called democracy.

Or it may restrict the government to a small number, so that there are more private citizens than magistrates;

and this is named aristocracy.

Lastly, it may concentrate the whole government in the hands of a single magistrate from whom all others

hold their power. This third form is the most usual, and is called monarchy, or royal government.

It should be remarked that all these forms, or at least the first two, admit of degree, and even of very wide

differences; for democracy may include the whole people, or may be restricted to half. Aristocracy, in its

turn, may be restricted indefinitely from half the people down to the smallest possible number. Even royalty

is susceptible of a measure of distribution. Sparta always had two kings, as its constitution provided; and the

Roman Empire saw as many as eight emperors at once, without it being possible to say that the Empire was

split up. Thus there is a point at which each form of government passes into the next, and it becomes clear

that, under three comprehensive denominations, government is really susceptible of as many diverse forms as

the State has citizens.

There are even more: for, as the government may also, in certain aspects, be subdivided into other parts, one

administered in one fashion and one in another, the combination of the three forms may result in a multitude

of mixed forms, each of which admits of multiplication by all the simple forms.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 26



Top




Page No 29


There has been at all times much dispute concerning the best form of government, without consideration of

the fact that each is in some cases the best, and in others the worst.

If, in the different States, the number of supreme magistrates should be in inverse ratio to the number of

citizens, it follows that, generally, democratic government suits small States, aristocratic government those of

middle size, and monarchy great ones. This rule is immediately deducible from the principle laid down. But it

is impossible to count the innumerable circumstances which may furnish exceptions.

4. DEMOCRACY

HE who makes the law knows better than any one else how it should be executed and interpreted. It seems

then impossible to have a better constitution than that in which the executive and legislative powers are

united; but this very fact renders the government in certain respects inadequate, because things which should

be distinguished are confounded, and the prince and the Sovereign, being the same person, form, so to speak,

no more than a government without government.

It is not good for him who makes the laws to execute them, or for the body of the people to turn its attention

away from a general standpoint and devote it to particular objects. Nothing is more dangerous than the

influence of private interests in public affairs, and the abuse of the laws by the government is a less evil than

the corruption of the legislator, which is the inevitable sequel to a particular standpoint. In such a case, the

State being altered in substance, all reformation becomes impossible, A people that would never misuse

governmental powers would never misuse independence; a people that would always govern well would not

need to be governed.

If we take the term in the strict sense, there never has been a real democracy, and there never will be. It is

against the natural order for the many to govern and the few to be governed. It is unimaginable that the

people should remain continually assembled to devote their time to public affairs, and it is clear that they

cannot set up commissions for that purpose without the form of administration being changed.

In fact, I can confidently lay down as a principle that, when the functions of government are shared by several

tribunals, the less numerous sooner or later acquire the greatest authority, if only because they are in a

position to expedite affairs, and power thus naturally comes into their hands.

Besides, how many conditions that are difficult to unite does such a government presuppose! First, a very

small State, where the people can readily be got together and where each citizen can with ease know all the

rest; secondly, great simplicity of manners, to prevent business from multiplying and raising thorny

problems; next, a large measure of equality in rank and fortune, without which equality of rights and

authority cannot long subsist; lastly, little or no luxury  for luxury either comes of riches or makes them

necessary; it corrupts at once rich and poor, the rich by possession and the poor by covetousness; it sells the

country to softness and vanity, and takes away from the State all its citizens, to make them slaves one to

another, and one and all to public opinion.

This is why a famous writer has made virtue the fundamental principle of Republics;[E1] for all these

conditions could not exist without virtue. But, for want of the necessary distinctions, that great thinker was

often inexact, and sometimes obscure, and did not see that, the sovereign authority being everywhere the

same, the same principle should be found in every wellconstituted State, in a greater or less degree, it is

true, according to the form of the government.

It may be added that there is no government so subject to civil wars and intestine agitations as democratic or

popular government, because there is none which has so strong and continual a tendency to change to another

form, or which demands more vigilance and courage for its maintenance as it is. Under such a constitution


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 27



Top




Page No 30


above all, the citizen should arm himself with strength and constancy, and say, every day of his life, what a

virtuous Count Palatine[19] said in the Diet of Poland: Malo periculosam libertatem quam quietum

servitium.[20]

Were there a people of gods, their government would be democratic. So perfect a government is not for men.

5. ARISTOCRACY

WE have here two quite distinct moral persons, the government and the Sovereign, and in consequence two

general wills, one general in relation to all the citizens, the other only for the members of the administration.

Thus, although the government may regulate its internal policy as it pleases, it can never speak to the people

save in the name of the Sovereign, that is, of the people itself, a fact which must not be forgotten.

The first societies governed themselves aristocratically. The heads of families took counsel together on public

affairs. The young bowed without question to the authority of experience. Hence such names as priests,

elders, senate, and gerontes. The savages of North America govern themselves in this way even now, and

their government is admirable.

But, in proportion as artificial inequality produced by institutions became predominant over natural

inequality, riches or power[21] were put before age, and aristocracy became elective. Finally, the

transmission of the father's power along with his goods to his children, by creating patrician families, made

government hereditary, and there came to be senators of twenty.

There are then three sorts of aristocracy  natural, elective and hereditary. The first is only for simple

peoples; the third is the worst of all governments; the second is the best, and is aristocracy properly so called.

Besides the advantage that lies in the distinction between the two powers, it presents that of its members

being chosen; for, in popular government, all the citizens are born magistrates; but here magistracy is

confined to a few, who become such only by election.[22] By this means uprightness, understanding,

experience and all other claims to preeminence and public esteem become so many further guarantees of

wise government.

Moreover, assemblies are more easily held, affairs better discussed and carried out with more order and

diligence, and the credit of the State is better sustained abroad by venerable senators than by a multitude that

is unknown or despised.

In a word, it is the best and most natural arrangement that the wisest should govern the many, when it is

assured that they will govern for its profit, and not for their own. There is no need to multiply instruments, or

get twenty thousand men to do what a hundred picked men can do even better. But it must not be forgotten

that corporate interest here begins to direct the public power less under the regulation of the general will, and

that a further inevitable propensity takes away from the laws part of the executive power.

If we are to speak of what is individually desirable, neither should the State be so small, nor a people so

simple and upright, that the execution of the laws follows immediately from the public will, as it does in a

good democracy. Nor should the nation be so great that the rulers have to scatter in order to govern it and are

able to play the Sovereign each in his own department, and, beginning by making themselves independent,

end by becoming masters.

But if aristocracy does not demand all the virtues needed by popular government, it demands others which

are peculiar to itself; for instance, moderation on the side of the rich and contentment on that of the poor; for

it seems that thoroughgoing equality would be out of place, as it was not found even at Sparta.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 28



Top




Page No 31


Furthermore, if this form of government carries with it a certain inequality of fortune, this is justifiable in

order that as a rule the administration of public affairs may be entrusted to those who are most able to give

them their whole time, but not, as Aristotle maintains, in order that the rich may always be put first. On the

contrary, it is of importance that an opposite choice should occasionally teach the people that the deserts of

men offer claims to preeminence more important than those of riches.

6. MONARCHY

So far, we have considered the prince as a moral and collective person, unified by the force of the laws, and

the depositary in the State of the executive power. We have now to consider this power when it is gathered

together into the hands of a natural person, a real man, who alone has the right to dispose of it in accordance

with the laws. Such a person is called a monarch or king.

In contrast with other forms of administration, in which a collective being stands for an individual, in this

form an individual stands for a collective being; so that the moral unity that constitutes the prince is at the

same time a physical unity, and all the qualities, which in the other case are only with difficulty brought

together by the law, are found naturally united.

Thus the will of the people, the will of the prince, the public force of the State, and the particular force of the

government, all answer to a single motive power; all the springs of the machine are in the same hands, the

whole moves towards the same end; there are no conflicting movements to cancel one another, and no kind of

constitution can be imagined in which a less amount of effort produces a more considerable amount of action.

Archimedes, seated quietly on the bank and easily drawing a great vessel afloat, stands to my mind for a

skilful monarch, governing vast states from his study, and moving everything while he seems himself

unmoved.

But if no government is more vigorous than this, there is also none in which the particular will holds more

sway and rules the rest more easily. Everything moves towards the same end indeed, but this end is by no

means that of the public happiness, and even the force of the administration constantly shows itself

prejudicial to the State.

Kings desire to be absolute, and men are always crying out to them from afar that the best means of being so

is to get themselves loved by their people. This precept is all very well, and even in some respects very true.

Unfortunately, it will always be derided at court. The power which comes of a people's love is no doubt the

greatest; but it is precarious and conditional, and princes will never rest content with it. The best kings desire

to be in a position to be wicked, if they please, without forfeiting their mastery: political sermonisers may tell

them to their hearts' content that, the people's strength being their own, their first interest is that the people

should be prosperous, numerous and formidable; they are well aware that this is untrue. Their first personal

interest is that the people should be weak, wretched, and unable to resist them. I admit that, provided the

subjects remained always in submission, the prince's interest would indeed be that it should be powerful, in

order that its power, being his own, might make him formidable to his neighbours; but, this interest being

merely secondary and subordinate, and strength being incompatible with submission, princes naturally give

the preference always to the principle that is more to their immediate advantage. This is what Samuel put

strongly before the Hebrews, and what Machiavelli has clearly shown. He professed to teach kings; but it was

the people he really taught. His Prince is the book of Republicans.[23]

We found, on general grounds, that monarchy is suitable only for great States, and this is confirmed when we

examine it in itself. The more numerous the public administration, the smaller becomes the relation between

the prince and the subjects, and the nearer it comes to equality, so that in democracy the ratio is unity, or

absolute equality. Again, as the government is restricted in numbers the ratio increases and reaches its

maximum when the government is in the hands of a single person. There is then too great a distance between


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 29



Top




Page No 32


prince and people, and the State lacks a bond of union. To form such a bond, there must be intermediate

orders, and princes, personages and nobility to compose them. But no such things suit a small State, to which

all class differences mean ruin.

If, however, it is hard for a great State to be well governed, it is much harder for it to be so by a single man;

and every one knows what happens when kings substitute others for themselves.

An essential and inevitable defect, which will always rank monarchical below the republican government, is

that in a republic the public voice hardly ever raises to the highest positions men who are not enlightened and

capable, and such as to fill them with honour; while in monarchies those who rise to the top are most often

merely petty blunderers, petty swindlers, and petty intriguers, whose petty talents cause them to get into the

highest positions at Court, but, as soon as they have got there, serve only to make their ineptitude clear to the

public. The people is far less often mistaken in its choice than the prince; and a man of real worth among the

king's ministers is almost as rare as a fool at the head of a republican government. Thus, when, by some

fortunate chance, one of these born governors takes the helm of State in some monarchy that has been nearly

overwhelmed by swarms of "gentlemanly" administrators, there is nothing but amazement at the resources he

discovers, and his coming marks an era in his country's history.

For a monarchical State to have a chance of being well governed, its population and extent must be

proportionate to the abilities of its governor. It is easier to conquer than to rule. With a long enough lever, the

world could be moved with a single finger; to sustain it needs the shoulders of Hercules. However small a

State may be, the prince is hardly ever big enough for it. When, on the other hand, it happens that the State is

too small for its ruler, in these rare cases too it is ill governed, because the ruler, constantly pursuing his great

designs, forgets the interests of the people, and makes it no less wretched by misusing the talents he has, than

a ruler of less capacity would make it for want of those he had not. A kingdom should, so to speak, expand or

contract with each reign, according to the prince's capabilities; but, the abilities of a senate being more

constant in quantity, the State can then have permanent frontiers without the administration suffering.

The disadvantage that is most felt in monarchical government is the want of the continuous succession which,

in both the other forms, provides an unbroken bond of union. When one king dies, another is needed;

elections leave dangerous intervals and are full of storms; and unless the citizens are disinterested and upright

to a degree which very seldom goes with this kind of government, intrigue and corruption abound. He to

whom the State has sold itself can hardly help selling it in his turn and repaying himself, at the expense of the

weak, the money the powerful have wrung from him. Under such an administration, venality sooner or later

spreads through every part, and peace so enjoyed under a king is worse than the disorders of an interregnum.

What has been done to prevent these evils? Crowns have been made hereditary in certain families, and an

order of succession has been set up, to prevent disputes from arising on the death of kings. That is to say, the

disadvantages of regency have been put in place of those of election, apparent tranquillity has been preferred

to wise administration, and men have chosen rather to risk having children, monstrosities, or imbeciles as

rulers to having disputes over the choice of good kings. It has not been taken into account that, in so exposing

ourselves to the risks this possibility entails, we are setting almost all the chances against us. There was sound

sense in what the younger Dionysius said to his father, who reproached him for doing some shameful deed by

asking, "Did I set you the example?" "No," answered his son, "but your father was not king."

Everything conspires to take away from a man who is set in authority over others the sense of justice and

reason. Much trouble, we are told, is taken to teach young princes the art of reigning; but their education

seems to do them no good. It would be better to begin by teaching them the art of obeying. The greatest kings

whose praises history tells were not brought up to reign: reigning is a science we are never so far from

possessing as when we have learnt too much of it, and one we acquire better by obeying than by

commanding. "Nam utilissimus idem ac brevissimus bonarum malarumque rerum delectus cogitare quid aut


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 30



Top




Page No 33


nolueris sub alio principe, aut volueris."[24]

One result of this lack of coherence is the inconstancy of royal government, which, regulated now on one

scheme and now on another, according to the character of the reigning prince or those who reign for him,

cannot for long have a fixed object or a consistent policy  and this variability, not found in the other forms

of government, where the prince is always the same, causes the State to be always shifting from principle to

principle and from project to project. Thus we may say that generally, if a court is more subtle in intrigue,

there is more wisdom in a senate, and Republics advance towards their ends by more consistent and better

considered policies; while every revolution in a royal ministry creates a revolution in the State; for the

principle common to all ministers and nearly all kings is to do in every respect the reverse of what was done

by their predecessors.

This incoherence further clears up a sophism that is very familiar to royalist political writers; not only is civil

government likened to domestic government, and the prince to the father of a family  this error has already

been refuted  but the prince is also freely credited with all the virtues he ought to possess, and is supposed

to be always what he should be. This supposition once made, royal government is clearly preferable to all

others, because it is incontestably the strongest, and, to be the best also, wants only a corporate will more in

conformity with the general will.

But if, according to Plato,[25] the "king by nature" is such a rarity, how often will nature and fortune conspire

to give him a crown? And, if royal education necessarily corrupts those who receive it, what is to be hoped

from a series of men brought up to reign? It is, then, wanton selfdeception to confuse royal government with

government by a good king. To see such government as it is in itself, we must consider it as it is under

princes who are incompetent or wicked: for either they will come to the throne wicked or incompetent, or the

throne will make them so.

These difficulties have not escaped our writers, who, all the same, are not troubled by them. The remedy, they

say, is to obey without a murmur: God sends bad kings in His wrath, and they must be borne as the scourges

of Heaven. Such talk is doubtless edifying; but it would be more in place in a pulpit than in a political book.

What are we to think of a doctor who promises miracles, and whose whole art is to exhort the sufferer to

patience? We know for ourselves that we must put up with a bad government when it is there; the question is

how to find a good one.

7. MIXED GOVERNMENTS

STRICTLY speaking, there is no such thing as a simple government. An isolated ruler must have subordinate

magistrates; a popular government must have a head. There is therefore, in the distribution of the executive

power, always a gradation from the greater to the lesser number, with the difference that sometimes the

greater number is dependent on the smaller, and sometimes the smaller on the greater.

Sometimes the distribution is equal, when either the constituent parts are in mutual dependence, as in the

government of England, or the authority of each section is independent, but imperfect, as in Poland. This last

form is bad; for it secures no unity in the government, and the State is left without a bond of union.

Is a simple or a mixed government the better? Political writers are always debating the question, which must

be answered as we have already answered a question about all forms of government.

Simple government is better in itself, just because it is simple. But when the executive power is not

sufficiently dependent upon the legislative power, i.e., when the prince is more closely related to the

Sovereign than the people to the prince, this lack of proportion must be cured by the division of the

government; for all the parts have then no less authority over the subjects, while their division makes them all


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 31



Top




Page No 34


together less strong against the Sovereign.

The same disadvantage is also prevented by the appointment of intermediate magistrates, who leave the

government entire, and have the effect only of balancing the two powers and maintaining their respective

rights. Government is then not mixed, but moderated.

The opposite disadvantages may be similarly cured, and, when the government is too lax, tribunals may be

set up to concentrate it. This is done in all democracies. In the first case, the government is divided to make it

weak; in the second, to make it strong: for the maxima of both strength and weakness are found in simple

governments, while the mixed forms result in a mean strength.

8. THAT ALL FORMS OF GOVERNMENT DO NOT SUIT ALL COUNTRIES

LIBERTY, not being a fruit of all climates, is not within the reach of all peoples. The more this principle, laid

down by Montesquieu,[E2] is considered, the more its truth is felt; the more it is combated, the more chance

is given to confirm it by new proofs.

In all the governments that there are, the public person consumes without producing. Whence then does it get

what it consumes? From the labour of its members. The necessities of the public are supplied out of the

superfluities of individuals. It follows that the civil State can subsist only so long as men's labour brings them

a return greater than their needs.

The amount of this excess is not the same in all countries. In some it is considerable, in others middling, in

yet others nil, in some even negative. The relation of product to subsistence depends on the fertility of the

climate, on the sort of labour the land demands, on the nature of its products, on the strength of its

inhabitants, on the greater or less consumption they find necessary, and on several further considerations of

which the whole relation is made up.

On the other side, all governments are not of the same nature: some are less voracious than others, and the

differences between them are based on this second principle, that the further from their source the public

contributions are removed, the more burdensome they become. The charge should be measured not by the

amount of the impositions, but by the path they have to travel in order to get back to those from whom they

came. When the circulation is prompt and wellestablished, it does not matter whether much or little is paid;

the people is always rich and, financially speaking, all is well. On the contrary, however little the people

gives, if that little does not return to it, it is soon exhausted by giving continually: the State is then never rich,

and the people is always a people of beggars.

It follows that, the more the distance between people and government increases, the more burdensome tribute

becomes: thus, in a democracy, the people bears the least charge; in an aristocracy, a greater charge; and, in

monarchy, the weight becomes heaviest. Monarchy therefore suits only wealthy nations; aristocracy, States of

middling size and wealth; and democracy, States that are small and poor.

In fact, the more we reflect, the more we find the difference between free and monarchical States to be this:

in the former, everything is used for the public advantage; in the latter, the public forces and those of

individuals are affected by each other, and either increases as the other grows weak; finally, instead of

governing subjects to make them happy, despotism makes them wretched in order to govern them.

We find then, in every climate, natural causes according to which the form of government which it requires

can be assigned, and we can even say what sort of inhabitants it should have.

Unfriendly and barren lands, where the product does not repay the labour, should remain desert and


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 32



Top




Page No 35


uncultivated, or peopled only by savages; lands where men's labour brings in no more than the exact

minimum necessary to subsistence should be inhabited by barbarous peoples: in such places all polity is

impossible. Lands where the surplus of product over labour is only middling are suitable for free peoples;

those in which the soil is abundant and fertile and gives a great product for a little labour call for monarchical

government, in order that the surplus of superfluities among the subjects may be consumed by the luxury of

the prince: for it is better for this excess to be absorbed by the government than dissipated among the

individuals. I am aware that there are exceptions; but these exceptions themselves confirm the rule, in that

sooner or later they produce revolutions which restore things to the natural order.

General laws should always be distinguished from individual causes that may modify their effects. If all the

South were covered with Republics and all the North with despotic States, it would be none the less true that,

in point of climate, despotism is suitable to hot countries, barbarism to cold countries, and good polity to

temperate regions. I see also that, the principle being granted, there may be disputes on its application; it may

be said that there are cold countries that are very fertile, and tropical countries that are very unproductive. But

this difficulty exists only for those who do not consider the question in all its aspects. We must, as I have

already said, take labour, strength, consumption, etc., into account.

Take two tracts of equal extent, one of which brings in five and the other ten. If the inhabitants of the first

consume four and those of the second nine, the surplus of the first product will be a fifth and that of the

second a tenth. The ratio of these two surpluses will then be inverse to that of the products, and the tract

which produces only five will give a surplus double that of the tract which produces ten.

But there is no question of a double product, and I think no one would put the fertility of cold countries, as a

general rule, on an equality with that of hot ones. Let us, however, suppose this equality to exist: let us, if you

will, regard England as on the same level as Sicily, and Poland as Egypt  further south, we shall have

Africa and the Indies; further north, nothing at all. To get this equality of product, what a difference there

must be in tillage: in Sicily, there is only need to scratch the ground; in England, how men must toil! But,

where more hands are needed to get the same product, the superfluity must necessarily be less.

Consider, besides, that the same number of men consume much less in hot countries. The climate requires

sobriety for the sake of health; and Europeans who try to live there as they would at home all perish of

dysentery and indigestion. "We are," says Chardin, "carnivorous animals, wolves, in comparison with the

Asiatics. Some attribute the sobriety of the Persians to the fact that their country is less cultivated; but it is my

belief that their country abounds less in commodities because the inhabitants need less. If their frugality," he

goes on, "were the effect of the nakedness of the land, only the poor would eat little; but everybody does so.

Again, less or more would be eaten in various provinces, according to the land's fertility; but the same

sobriety is found throughout the kingdom. They are very proud of their manner of life, saying that you have

only to look at their hue to recognise how far it excels that of the Christians. In fact, the Persians are of an

even hue; their skins are fair, fine and smooth; while the hue of their subjects, the Armenians, who live after

the European fashion, is rough and blotchy, and their bodies are gross and unwieldy."

The nearer you get to the equator, the less people live on. Meat they hardly touch; rice, maize, curcur, millet

and cassava are their ordinary food. There are in the Indies millions of men whose subsistence does not cost a

halfpenny a day. Even in Europe we find considerable differences of appetite between Northern and Southern

peoples. A Spaniard will live for a week on a German's dinner. In the countries in which men are more

voracious, luxury therefore turns in the direction of consumption. In England, luxury appears in a wellfilled

table; in Italy, you feast on sugar and flowers.

Luxury in clothes shows similar differences. In climates in which the changes of season are prompt and

violent, men have better and simpler clothes; where they clothe themselves only for adornment, what is

striking is more thought of than what is useful; clothes themselves are then a luxury. At Naples, you may see


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 33



Top




Page No 36


daily walking in the Pausilippeum men in goldembroidered upper garments and nothing else. It is the same

with buildings; magnificence is the sole consideration where there is nothing to fear from the air. In Paris and

London, you desire to be lodged warmly and comfortably; in Madrid, you have superb salons, but not a

window that closes, and you go to bed in a mere hole.

In hot countries foods are much more substantial and succulent; and the third difference cannot but have an

influence on the second. Why are so many vegetables eaten in Italy? Because there they are good, nutritious

and excellent in taste. In France, where they are nourished only on water, they are far from nutritious and are

thought nothing of at table. They take up all the same no less ground, and cost at least as much pains to

cultivate. It is a proved fact that the wheat of Barbary, in other respects inferior to that of France, yields much

more flour, and that the wheat of France in turn yields more than that of northern countries; from which it

may be inferred that a like gradation in the same direction, from equator to pole, is found generally. But is it

not an obvious disadvantage for an equal product to contain less nourishment?

To all these points may be added another, which at once depends on and strengthens them. Hot countries

need inhabitants less than cold countries, and can support more of them. There is thus a double surplus, which

is all to the advantage of despotism. The greater the territory occupied by a fixed number of inhabitants, the

more difficult revolt becomes, because rapid or secret concerted action is impossible, and the government can

easily unmask projects and cut communications; but the more a numerous people is gathered together, the

less can the government usurp the Sovereign's place: the people's leaders can deliberate as safely in their

houses as the prince in council, and the crowd gathers as rapidly in the squares as the prince's troops in their

quarters. The advantage of tyrannical government therefore lies in acting at great distances. With the help of

the rallyingpoints it establishes, its strength, like that of the lever,[26] grows with distance. The strength of

the people, on the other hand, acts only when concentrated: when spread abroad, it evaporates and is lost, like

powder scattered on the ground, which catches fire only grain by grain. The least populous countries are thus

the fittest for tyranny: fierce animals reign only in deserts.

9. THE MARKS OF A GOOD GOVERNMENT

THE question "What absolutely is the best government?" is unanswerable as well as indeterminate; or rather,

there are as many good answers as there are possible combinations in the absolute and relative situations of

all nations.

But if it is asked by what sign we may know that a given people is well or ill governed, that is another matter,

and the question, being one of fact, admits of an answer.

It is not, however, answered, because everyone wants to answer it in his own way. Subjects extol public

tranquillity, citizens individual liberty; the one class prefers security of possessions, the other that of person;

the one regards as the best government that which is most severe, the other maintains that the mildest is the

best; the one wants crimes punished, the other wants them prevented; the one wants the State to be feared by

its neighbours, the other prefers that it should be ignored; the one is content if money circulates, the other

demands that the people shall have bread. Even if an agreement were come to on these and similar points,

should we have got any further? As moral qualities do not admit of exact measurement, agreement about the

mark does not mean agreement about the valuation.

For my part, I am continually astonished that a mark so simple is not recognised, or that men are of so bad

faith as not to admit it. What is the end of political association? The preservation and prosperity of its

members. And what is the surest mark of their preservation and prosperity? Their numbers and population.

Seek then nowhere else this mark that is in dispute. The rest being equal, the government under which,

without external aids, without naturalisation or colonies, the citizens increase and multiply most, is beyond

question the best. The government under which a people wanes and diminishes is the worst. Calculators, it is


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 34



Top




Page No 37


left for you to count, to measure, to compare.[27]

10. THE ABUSE OF GOVERNMENT AND ITS TENDENCY TO DEGENERATE

AS the particular will acts constantly in opposition to the general will, the government continually exerts

itself against the Sovereignty. The greater this exertion becomes, the more the constitution changes; and, as

there is in this case no other corporate will to create an equilibrium by resisting the will of the prince, sooner

or later the prince must inevitably suppress the Sovereign and break the social treaty. This is the unavoidable

and inherent defect which, from the very birth of the body politic, tends ceaselessly to destroy it, as age and

death end by destroying the human body.

There are two general courses by which government degenerates: i.e., when it undergoes contraction, or when

the State is dissolved.

Government undergoes contraction when it passes from the many to the few, that is, from democracy to

aristocracy, and from aristocracy to royalty. To do so is its natural propensity.[28] If it took the backward

course from the few to the many, it could be said that it was relaxed; but this inverse sequence is impossible.

Indeed, governments never change their form except when their energy is exhausted and leaves them too

weak to keep what they have. If a government at once extended its sphere and relaxed its stringency, its force

would become absolutely nil, and it would persist still less. It is therefore necessary to wind up the spring and

tighten the hold as it gives way: or else the State it sustains will come to grief.

The dissolution of the State may come about in either of two ways.

First, when the prince ceases to administer the State in accordance with the laws, and usurps the Sovereign

power. A remarkable change then occurs: not the government, but the State, undergoes contraction; I mean

that the great State is dissolved, and another is formed within it, composed solely of the members of the

government, which becomes for the rest of the people merely master and tyrant. So that the moment the

government usurps the Sovereignty, the social compact is broken, and all private citizens recover by right

their natural liberty, and are forced, but not bound, to obey.

The same thing happens when the members of the government severally usurp the power they should

exercise only as a body; this is as great an infraction of the laws, and results in even greater disorders. There

are then, so to speak, as many princes as there are magistrates, and the State, no less divided than the

government, either perishes or changes its form.

When the State is dissolved, the abuse of government, whatever it is, bears the common name of anarchy. To

distinguish, democracy degenerates into ochlocracy, and aristocracy into oligarchy; and I would add that

royalty degenerates into tyranny; but this last word is ambiguous and needs explanation.

In vulgar usage, a tyrant is a king who governs violently and without regard for justice and law. In the exact

sense, a tyrant is an individual who arrogates to himself the royal authority without having a right to it. This

is how the Greeks understood the word "tyrant": they applied it indifferently to good and bad princes whose

authority was not legitimate.[29] Tyrant and usurper are thus perfectly synonymous terms.

In order that I may give different things different names, I call him who usurps the royal authority a tyrant,

and him who usurps the sovereign power a despot. The tyrant is he who thrusts himself in contrary to the

laws to govern in accordance with the laws; the despot is he who sets himself above the laws themselves.

Thus the tyrant cannot be a despot, but the despot is always a tyrant.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 35



Top




Page No 38


11. THE DEATH OF THE BODY POLITIC

SUCH is the natural and inevitable tendency of the best constituted governments. If Sparta and Rome

perished, what State can hope to endure for ever? If we would set up a longlived form of government, let us

not even dream of making it eternal. If we are to succeed, we must not attempt the impossible, or flatter

ourselves that we are endowing the work of man with a stability of which human conditions do not permit.

The body politic, as well as the human body, begins to die as soon as it is born, and carries in itself the causes

of its destruction. But both may have a constitution that is more or less robust and suited to preserve them a

longer or a shorter time. The constitution of man is the work of nature; that of the State the work of art. It is

not in men's power to prolong their own lives; but it is for them to prolong as much as possible the life of the

State, by giving it the best possible constitution. The best constituted State will have an end; but it will end

later than any other, unless some unforeseen accident brings about its untimely destruction.

The lifeprinciple of the body politic lies in the sovereign authority. The legislative power is the heart of the

State; the executive power is its brain, which causes the movement of all the parts. The brain may become

paralysed and the individual still live. A man may remain an imbecile and live; but as soon as the heart ceases

to perform its functions, the animal is dead.

The State subsists by means not of the laws, but of the legislative power. Yesterday's law is not binding

today; but silence is taken for tacit consent, and the Sovereign is held to confirm incessantly the laws it does

not abrogate as it might. All that it has once declared itself to will it wills always, unless it revokes its

declaration.

Why then is so much respect paid to old laws? For this very reason. We must believe that nothing but the

excellence of old acts of will can have preserved them so long: if the Sovereign had not recognised them as

throughout salutary, it would have revoked them a thousand times. This is why, so far from growing weak,

the laws continually gain new strength in any well constituted State; the precedent of antiquity makes them

daily more venerable: while wherever the laws grow weak as they become old, this proves that there is no

longer a legislative power, and that the State is dead.

12. HOW THE SOVEREIGN AUTHORITY MAINTAINS ITSELF

THE Sovereign, having no force other than the legislative power, acts only by means of the laws; and the

laws being solely the authentic acts of the general will, the Sovereign cannot act save when the people is

assembled. The people in assembly, I shall be told, is a mere chimera. It is so today, but two thousand years

ago it was not so. Has man's nature changed?

The bounds of possibility, in moral matters, are less narrow than we imagine: it is our weaknesses, our vices

and our prejudices that confine them. Base souls have no belief in great men; vile slaves smile in mockery at

the name of liberty.

Let us judge of what can be done by what has been done. I shall say nothing of the Republics of ancient

Greece; but the Roman Republic was, to my mind, a great State, and the town of Rome a great town. The last

census showed that there were in Rome four hundred thousand citizens capable of bearing arms, and the last

computation of the population of the Empire showed over four million citizens, excluding subjects,

foreigners, women, children and slaves.

What difficulties might not be supposed to stand in the way of the frequent assemblage of the vast population

of this capital and its neighbourhood. Yet few weeks passed without the Roman people being in assembly,

and even being so several times. It exercised not only the rights of Sovereignty, but also a part of those of


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 36



Top




Page No 39


government. It dealt with certain matters, and judged certain cases, and this whole people was found in the

public meetingplace hardly less often as magistrates than as citizens.

If we went back to the earliest history of nations, we should find that most ancient governments, even those

of monarchical form, such as the Macedonian and the Frankish, had similar councils. In any case, the one

incontestable fact I have given is an answer to all difficulties; it is good logic to reason from the actual to the

possible.

13. THE SAME (continued)

IT is not enough for the assembled people to have once fixed the constitution of the State by giving its

sanction to a body of law; it is not enough for it to have set up a perpetual government, or provided once for

all for the election of magistrates. Besides the extraordinary assemblies unforeseen circumstances may

demand, there must be fixed periodical assemblies which cannot be abrogated or prorogued, so that on the

proper day the people is legitimately called together by law, without need of any formal summoning.

But, apart from these assemblies authorised by their date alone, every assembly of the people not summoned

by the magistrates appointed for that purpose, and in accordance with the prescribed forms, should be

regarded as unlawful, and all its acts as null and void, because the command to assemble should itself

proceed from the law.

The greater or less frequency with which lawful assemblies should occur depends on so many considerations

that no exact rules about them can be given. It can only be said generally that the stronger the government the

more often should the Sovereign show itself.

This, I shall be told, may do for a single town; but what is to be done when the State includes several? Is the

sovereign authority to be divided? Or is it to be concentrated in a single town to which all the rest are made

subject?

Neither the one nor the other, I reply. First, the sovereign authority is one and simple, and cannot be divided

without being destroyed. In the second place, one town cannot, any more than one nation, legitimately be

made subject to another, because the essence of the body politic lies in the reconciliation of obedience and

liberty, and the words subject and Sovereign are identical correlatives the idea of which meets in the single

word "citizen."

I answer further that the union of several towns in a single city is always bad, and that, if we wish to make

such a union, we should not expect to avoid its natural disadvantages. It is useless to bring up abuses that

belong to great States against one who desires to see only small ones; but how can small States be given the

strength to resist great ones, as formerly the Greek towns resisted the Great King, and more recently Holland

and Switzerland have resisted the House of Austria?

Nevertheless, if the State cannot be reduced to the right limits, there remains still one resource; this is, to

allow no capital, to make the seat of government move from town to town, and to assemble by turn in each

the Provincial Estates of the country.

People the territory evenly, extend everywhere the same rights, bear to every place in it abundance and life:

by these means will the State become at once as strong and as well governed as possible. Remember that the

walls of towns are built of the ruins of the houses of the countryside. For every palace I see raised in the

capital, my mind's eye sees a whole country made desolate.

14. THE SAME (continued)


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 37



Top




Page No 40


THE moment the people is legitimately assembled as a sovereign body, the jurisdiction of the government

wholly lapses, the executive power is suspended, and the person of the meanest citizen is as sacred and

inviolable as that of the first magistrate; for in the presence of the person represented, representatives no

longer exist. Most of the tumults that arose in the comitia at Rome were due to ignorance or neglect of this

rule. The consuls were in them merely the presidents of the people; the tribunes were mere speakers;[30] the

senate was nothing at all.

These intervals of suspension, during which the prince recognises or ought to recognise an actual superior,

have always been viewed by him with alarm; and these assemblies of the people, which are the aegis of the

body politic and the curb on the government, have at all times been the horror of rulers: who therefore never

spare pains, objections, difficulties, and promises, to stop the citizens from having them. When the citizens

are greedy, cowardly, and pusillanimous, and love ease more than liberty, they do not long hold out against

the redoubled efforts of the government; and thus, as the resisting force incessantly grows, the sovereign

authority ends by disappearing, and most cities fall and perish before their time.

But between the sovereign authority and arbitrary government there sometimes intervenes a mean power of

which something must be said.

15. DEPUTIES OR REPRESENTATIVES

AS soon as public service ceases to be the chief business of the citizens, and they would rather serve with

their money than with their persons, the State is not far from its fall. When it is necessary to march out to war,

they pay troops and stay at home: when it is necessary to meet in council, they name deputies and stay at

home. By reason of idleness and money, they end by having soldiers to enslave their country and

representatives to sell it.

It is through the hustle of commerce and the arts, through the greedy selfinterest of profit, and through

softness and love of amenities that personal services are replaced by money payments. Men surrender a part

of their profits in order to have time to increase them at leisure. Make gifts of money, and you will not be

long without chains. The word finance is a slavish word, unknown in the citystate. In a country that is truly

free, the citizens do everything with their own arms and nothing by means of money; so far from paying to be

exempted from their duties, they would even pay for the privilege of fulfilling them themselves. I am far from

taking the common view: I hold enforced labour to be less opposed to liberty than taxes.

The better the constitution of a State is, the more do public affairs encroach on private in the minds of the

citizens. Private affairs are even of much less importance, because the aggregate of the common happiness

furnishes a greater proportion of that of each individual, so that there is less for him to seek in particular

cares. In a wellordered city every man flies to the assemblies: under a bad government no one cares to stir a

step to get to them, because no one is interested in what happens there, because it is foreseen that the general

will will not prevail, and lastly because domestic cares are allabsorbing. Good laws lead to the making of

better ones; bad ones bring about worse. As soon as any man says of the affairs of the State What does it

matter to me? the State may be given up for lost.

The lukewarmness of patriotism, the activity of private interest, the vastness of States, conquest and the abuse

of government suggested the method of having deputies or representatives of the people in the national

assemblies. These are what, in some countries, men have presumed to call the Third Estate. Thus the

individual interest of two orders is put first and second; the public interest occupies only the third place.

Sovereignty, for the same reason as makes it inalienable, cannot be represented; it lies essentially in the

general will, and will does not admit of representation: it is either the same, or other; there is no intermediate

possibility. The deputies of the people, therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives: they are merely its


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 38



Top




Page No 41


stewards, and can carry through no definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is null and

void  is, in fact, not a law. The people of England regards itself as free; but it is grossly mistaken; it is free

only during the election of members of parliament. As soon as they are elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is

nothing. The use it makes of the short moments of liberty it enjoys shows indeed that it deserves to lose them.

The idea of representation is modern; it comes to us from feudal government, from that iniquitous and absurd

system which degrades humanity and dishonours the name of man. In ancient republics and even in

monarchies, the people never had representatives; the word itself was unknown. It is very singular that in

Rome, where the tribunes were so sacrosanct, it was never even imagined that they could usurp the functions

of the people, and that in the midst of so great a multitude they never attempted to pass on their own authority

a single plebiscitum. We can, however, form an idea of the difficulties caused sometimes by the people being

so numerous, from what happened in the time of the Gracchi, when some of the citizens had to cast their

votes from the roofs of buildings.

Where right and liberty are everything, disadvantages count for nothing. Among this wise people everything

was given its just value, its lictors were allowed to do what its tribunes would never have dared to attempt;

for it had no fear that its lictors would try to represent it.

To explain, however, in what way the tribunes did sometimes represent it, it is enough to conceive how the

government represents the Sovereign. Law being purely the declaration of the general will, it is clear that, in

the exercise of the legislative power, the people cannot be represented; but in that of the executive power,

which is only the force that is applied to give the law effect, it both can and should be represented. We thus

see that if we looked closely into the matter we should find that very few nations have any laws. However

that may be, it is certain that the tribunes, possessing no executive power, could never represent the Roman

people by right of the powers entrusted to them, but only by usurping those of the senate.

In Greece, all that the people had to do, it did for itself; it was constantly assembled in the public square. The

Greeks lived in a mild climate; they had no natural greed; slaves did their work for them; their great concern

was with liberty. Lacking the same advantages, how can you preserve the same rights? Your severer climates

add to your needs;[31] for half the year your public squares are uninhabitable; the flatness of your languages

unfits them for being heard in the open air; you sacrifice more for profit than for liberty, and fear slavery less

than poverty.

What then? Is liberty maintained only by the help of slavery? It may be so. Extremes meet. Everything that is

not in the course of nature has its disadvantages, civil society most of all. There are some unhappy

circumstances in which we can only keep our liberty at others' expense, and where the citizen can be

perfectly free only when the slave is most a slave. Such was the case with Sparta. As for you, modern

peoples, you have no slaves, but you are slaves yourselves; you pay for their liberty with your own. It is in

vain that you boast of this preference; I find in it more cowardice than humanity.

I do not mean by all this that it is necessary to have slaves, or that the right of slavery is legitimate: I am

merely giving the reasons why modern peoples, believing themselves to be free, have representatives, while

ancient peoples had none. In any case, the moment a people allows itself to be represented, it is no long free:

it no longer exists.

All things considered, I do not see that it is possible henceforth for the Sovereign to preserve among us the

exercise of its rights, unless the city is very small. But if it is very small, it will be conquered? No. I will

show later on how the external strength of a great people[32] may be combined with the convenient polity

and good order of a small State.

16. THAT THE INSTITUTION OF GOVERNMENT IS NOT A CONTRACT


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 39



Top




Page No 42


THE legislative power once well established, the next thing is to establish similarly the executive power; for

this latter, which operates only by particular acts, not being of the essence of the former, is naturally separate

from it. Were it possible for the Sovereign, as such, to possess the executive power, right and fact would be

so confounded that no one could tell what was law and what was not; and the body politic, thus disfigured,

would soon fall a prey to the violence it was instituted to prevent.

As the citizens, by the social contract, are all equal, all can prescribe what all should do, but no one has a

right to demand that another shall do what he does not do himself. It is strictly this right, which is

indispensable for giving the body politic life and movement, that the Sovereign, in instituting the

government, confers upon the prince.

It has been held that this act of establishment was a contract between the people and the rulers it sets over

itself,  a contract in which conditions were laid down between the two parties binding the one to command

and the other to obey. It will be admitted, I am sure, that this is an odd kind of contract to enter into. But let

us see if this view can be upheld.

First, the supreme authority can no more be modified than it can be alienated; to limit it is to destroy it. It is

absurd and contradictory for the Sovereign to set a superior over itself; to bind itself to obey a master would

be to return to absolute liberty.

Moreover, it is clear that this contract between the people and such and such persons would be a particular

act; and from this is follows that it can be neither a law nor an act of Sovereignty, and that consequently it

would be illegitimate.

It is plain too that the contracting parties in relation to each other would be under the law of nature alone and

wholly without guarantees of their mutual undertakings, a position wholly at variance with the civil state. He

who has force at his command being always in a position to control execution, it would come to the same

thing if the name "contract" were given to the act of one man who said to another: "I give you all my goods,

on condition that you give me back as much of them as you please."

There is only one contract in the State, and that is the act of association, which in itself excludes the existence

of a second. It is impossible to conceive of any public contract that would not be a violation of the first.

17. THE INSTITUTION OF GOVERNMENT

UNDER what general idea then should the act by which government is instituted be conceived as falling? I

will begin by stating that the act is complex, as being composed of two others  the establishment of the law

and its execution.

By the former, the Sovereign decrees that there shall be a governing body established in this or that form; this

act is clearly a law.

By the latter, the people nominates the rulers who are to be entrusted with the government that has been

established. This nomination, being a particular act, is clearly not a second law, but merely a consequence of

the first and a function of government.

The difficulty is to understand how there can be a governmental act before government exists, and how the

people, which is only Sovereign or subject, can, under certain circumstances, become a prince or magistrate.

It is at this point that there is revealed one of the astonishing properties of the body politic, by means of

which it reconciles apparently contradictory operations; for this is accomplished by a sudden conversion of


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 40



Top




Page No 43


Sovereignty into democracy, so that, without sensible change, and merely by virtue of a new relation of all to

all, the citizens become magistrates and pass from general to particular acts, from legislation to the execution

of the law.

This changed relation is no speculative subtlety without instances in practice: it happens every day in the

English Parliament, where, on certain occasions, the Lower House resolves itself into Grand Committee, for

the better discussion of affairs, and thus, from being at one moment a sovereign court, becomes at the next a

mere commission; so that subsequently it reports to itself, as House of Commons, the result of its proceedings

in Grand Committee, and debates over again under one name what it has already settled under another.

It is, indeed, the peculiar advantage of democratic government that it can be established in actuality by a

simple act of the general will. Subsequently, this provisional government remains in power, if this form is

adopted, or else establishes in the name of the Sovereign the government that is prescribed by law; and thus

the whole proceeding is regular. It is impossible to set up government in any other manner legitimately and in

accordance with the principles so far laid down.

18. HOW TO CHECK THE USURPATIONS OF GOVERNMENT

WHAT we have just said confirms Chapter 16, and makes it clear that the institution of government is not a

contract, but a law; that the depositaries of the executive power are not the people's masters, but its officers;

that it can set them up and pull them down when it likes; that for them there is no question of contract, but of

obedience and that in taking charge of the functions the State imposes on them they are doing no more than

fulfilling their duty as citizens, without having the remotest right to argue about the conditions.

When therefore the people sets up an hereditary government, whether it be monarchical and confined to one

family, or aristocratic and confined to a class, what it enters into is not an undertaking; the administration is

given a provisional form, until the people chooses to order it otherwise.

It is true that such changes are always dangerous, and that the established government should never be

touched except when it comes to be incompatible with the public good; but the circumspection this involves

is a maxim of policy and not a rule of right, and the State is no more bound to leave civil authority in the

hands of its rulers than military authority in the hands of its generals.

It is also true that it is impossible to be too careful to observe, in such cases, all the formalities necessary to

distinguish a regular and legitimate act from a seditious tumult, and the will of a whole people from the

clamour of a faction. Here above all no further concession should be made to the untoward possibility than

cannot, in the strictest logic, be refused it. From this obligation the prince derives a great advantage in

preserving his power despite the people, without it being possible to say he has usurped it; for, seeming to

avail himself only of his rights, he finds it very easy to extend them, and to prevent, under the pretext of

keeping the peace, assemblies that are destined to the reestablishment of order; with the result that he takes

advantage of a silence he does not allow to be broken, or of irregularities he causes to be committed, to

assume that he has the support of those whom fear prevents from speaking, and to punish those who dare to

speak. Thus it was that the decemvirs, first elected for one year and then kept on in office for a second, tried

to perpetuate their power by forbidding the comitia to assemble; and by this easy method every government

in the world, once clothed with the public power, sooner or later usurps the sovereign authority.

The periodical assemblies of which I have already spoken are designed to prevent or postpone this calamity,

above all when they need no formal summoning; for in that case, the prince cannot stop them without openly

declaring himself a lawbreaker and an enemy of the State.

The opening of these assemblies, whose sole object is the maintenance of the social treaty, should always


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 41



Top




Page No 44


take the form of putting two propositions that may not be suppressed, which should be voted on separately.

The first is: "Does it please the Sovereign to preserve the present form of government?"

The second is: "Does it please the people to leave its administration in the hands of those who are actually in

charge of it?"

I am here assuming what I think I have shown; that there is in the State no fundamental law that cannot be

revoked, not excluding the social compact itself; for if all the citizens assembled of one accord to break the

compact, it is impossible to doubt that it would be very legitimately broken. Grotius even thinks that each

man can renounce his membership of his own State, and recover his natural liberty and his goods on leaving

the country.[33] It would be indeed absurd if all the citizens in assembly could not do what each can do by

himself.

BOOK IV

1. THAT THE GENERAL WILL IS INDESTRUCTIBLE

AS long as several men in assembly regard themselves as a single body, they have only a single will which is

concerned with their common preservation and general wellbeing. In this case, all the springs of the State

are vigorous and simple and its rules clear and luminous; there are no embroilments or conflicts of interests;

the common good is everywhere clearly apparent, and only good sense is needed to perceive it. Peace, unity

and equality are the enemies of political subtleties. Men who are upright and simple are difficult to deceive

because of their simplicity; lures and ingenious pretexts fail to impose upon them, and they are not even

subtle enough to be dupes. When, among the happiest people in the world, bands of peasants are seen

regulating affairs of State under an oak, and always acting wisely, can we help scorning the ingenious

methods of other nations, which make themselves illustrious and wretched with so much art and mystery?

A State so governed needs very few laws; and, as it becomes necessary to issue new ones, the necessity is

universally seen. The first man to propose them merely says what all have already felt, and there is no

question of factions or intrigues or eloquence in order to secure the passage into law of what every one has

already decided to do, as soon as he is sure that the rest will act with him.

Theorists are led into error because, seeing only States that have been from the beginning wrongly

constituted, they are struck by the impossibility of applying such a policy to them. They make great game of

all the absurdities a clever rascal or an insinuating speaker might get the people of Paris or London to believe.

They do not know that Cromwell would have been put to "the bells" by the people of Berne, and the Duc de

Beaufort on the treadmill by the Genevese.

But when the social bond begins to be relaxed and the State to grow weak, when particular interests begin to

make themselves felt and the smaller societies to exercise an influence over the larger, the common interest

changes and finds opponents: opinion is no longer unanimous; the general will ceases to be the will of all;

contradictory views and debates arise; and the best advice is not taken without question.

Finally, when the State, on the eve of ruin, maintains only a vain, illusory and formal existence, when in

every heart the social bond is broken, and the meanest interest brazenly lays hold of the sacred name of

"public good," the general will becomes mute: all men, guided by secret motives, no more give their views as

citizens than if the State had never been; and iniquitous decrees directed solely to private interest get passed


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 42



Top




Page No 45


under the name of laws.

Does it follow from this that the general will is exterminated or corrupted? Not at all: it is always constant,

unalterable and pure; but it is subordinated to other wills which encroach upon its sphere. Each man, in

detaching his interest from the common interest, sees clearly that he cannot entirely separate them; but his

share in the public mishaps seems to him negligible beside the exclusive good he aims at making his own.

Apart from this particular good, he wills the general good in his own interest, as strongly as any one else.

Even in selling his vote for money, he does not extinguish in himself the general will, but only eludes it. The

fault he commits is that of changing the state of the question, and answering something different from what

he is asked. Instead of saying, by his vote, "It is to the advantage of the State," he says, "It is of advantage to

this or that man or party that this or that view should prevail." Thus the law of public order in assemblies is

not so much to maintain in them the general will as to secure that the question be always put to it, and the

answer always given by it.

I could here set down many reflections on the simple right of voting in every act of Sovereignty  a right

which no one can take from the citizens  and also on the right of stating views, making proposals, dividing

and discussing, which the government is always most careful to leave solely to its members, but this

important subject would need a treatise to itself, and it is impossible to say everything in a single work.

2. VOTING

IT may be seen, from the last chapter, that the way in which general business is managed may give a clear

enough indication of the actual state of morals and the health of the body politic. The more concert reigns in

the assemblies, that is, the nearer opinion approaches unanimity, the greater is the dominance of the general

will. On the other hand, long debates, dissensions and tumult proclaim the ascendancy of particular interests

and the decline of the State.

This seems less clear when two or more orders enter into the constitution, as patricians and plebeians did at

Rome; for quarrels between these two orders often disturbed the comitia, even in the best days of the

Republic. But the exception is rather apparent than real; for then, through the defect that is inherent in the

body politic, there were, so to speak, two States in one, and what is not true of the two together is true of

either separately. Indeed, even in the most stormy times, the plebiscita of the people, when the Senate did not

interfere with them, always went through quietly and by large majorities. The citizens having but one interest,

the people had but a single will.

At the other extremity of the circle, unanimity recurs; this is the case when the citizens, having fallen into

servitude, have lost both liberty and will. Fear and flattery then change votes into acclamation; deliberation

ceases, and only worship or malediction is left. Such was the vile manner in which the senate expressed its

views under the Emperors. It did so sometimes with absurd precautions. Tacitus observes that, under Otho,

the senators, while they heaped curses on Vitellius, contrived at the same time to make a deafening noise, in

order that, should he ever become their master, he might not know what each of them had said.

On these various considerations depend the rules by which the methods of counting votes and comparing

opinions should be regulated, according as the general will is more or less easy to discover, and the State

more or less in its decline.

There is but one law which, from its nature, needs unanimous consent. This is the social compact; for civil

association is the most voluntary of all acts. Every man being born free and his own master, no one, under

any pretext whatsoever, can make any man subject without his consent. To decide that the son of a slave is

born a slave is to decide that he is not born a man.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 43



Top




Page No 46


If then there are opponents when the social compact is made, their opposition does not invalidate the contract,

but merely prevents them from being included in it. They are foreigners among citizens. When the State is

instituted, residence constitutes consent; to dwell within its territory is to submit to the Sovereign.[34]

Apart from this primitive contract, the vote of the majority always binds all the rest. This follows from the

contract itself. But it is asked how a man can be both free and forced to conform to wills that are not his own.

How are the opponents at once free and subject to laws they have not agreed to?

I retort that the question is wrongly put. The citizen gives his consent to all the laws, including those which

are passed in spite of his opposition, and even those which punish him when he dares to break any of them.

The constant will of all the members of the State is the general will; by virtue of it they are citizens and

free.[35] When in the popular assembly a law is proposed, what the people is asked is not exactly whether it

approves or rejects the proposal, but whether it is in conformity with the general will, which is their will.

Each man, in giving his vote, states his opinion on that point; and the general will is found by counting votes.

When therefore the opinion that is contrary to my own prevails, this proves neither more nor less than that I

was mistaken, and that what I thought to be the general will was not so. If my particular opinion had carried

the day I should have achieved the opposite of what was my will; and it is in that case that I should not have

been free.

This presupposes, indeed, that all the qualities of the general will still reside in the majority: when they cease

to do so, whatever side a man may take, liberty is no longer possible.

In my earlier demonstration of how particular wills are substituted for the general will in public deliberation,

I have adequately pointed out the practicable methods of avoiding this abuse; and I shall have more to say of

them later on. I have also given the principles for determining the proportional number of votes for declaring

that will. A difference of one vote destroys equality; a single opponent destroys unanimity; but between

equality and unanimity, there are several grades of unequal division, at each of which this proportion may be

fixed in accordance with the condition and the needs of the body politic.

There are two general rules that may serve to regulate this relation. First, the more grave and important the

questions discussed, the nearer should the opinion that is to prevail approach unanimity. Secondly, the more

the matter in hand calls for speed, the smaller the prescribed difference in the numbers of votes may be

allowed to become: where an instant decision has to be reached, a majority of one vote should be enough.

The first of these two rules seems more in harmony with the laws, and the second with practical affairs. In

any case, it is the combination of them that gives the best proportions for determining the majority necessary.

3. ELECTIONS

IN the elections of the prince and the magistrates, which are, as I have said, complex acts, there are two

possible methods of procedure, choice and lot. Both have been employed in various republics, and a highly

complicated mixture of the two still survives in the election of the Doge at Venice.

"Election by lot," says Montesquieu, "is democratic in nature."[E3] I agree that it is so; but in what sense?

"The lot," he goes on, "is a way of making choice that is unfair to nobody; it leaves each citizen a reasonable

hope of serving his country." These are not reasons.

If we bear in mind that the election of rulers is a function of government, and not of Sovereignty, we shall see

why the lot is the method more natural to democracy, in which the administration is better in proportion as

the number of its acts is small.

In every real democracy, magistracy is not an advantage, but a burdensome charge which cannot justly be


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 44



Top




Page No 47


imposed on one individual rather than another. The law alone can lay the charge on him on whom the lot

falls. For, the conditions being then the same for all, and the choice not depending on any human will, there is

no particular application to alter the universality of the law.

In an aristocracy, the prince chooses the prince, the government is preserved by itself, and voting is rightly

ordered.

The instance of the election of the Doge of Venice confirms, instead of destroying, this distinction; the mixed

form suits a mixed government. For it is an error to take the government of Venice for a real aristocracy. If

the people has no share in the government, the nobility is itself the people. A host of poor Barnabotes never

gets near any magistracy, and its nobility consists merely in the empty title of Excellency, and in the right to

sit in the Great Council. As this Great Council is as numerous as our General Council at Geneva, its

illustrious members have no more privileges than our plain citizens. It is indisputable that, apart from the

extreme disparity between the two republics, the bourgeoisie of Geneva is exactly equivalent to the patriciate

of Venice; our natives and inhabitants correspond to the townsmen and the people of Venice; our peasants

correspond to the subjects on the mainland; and, however that republic be regarded, if its size be left out of

account, its government is no more aristocratic than our own. The whole difference is that, having no

liferuler, we do not, like Venice, need to use the lot.

Election by lot would have few disadvantages in a real democracy, in which, as equality would everywhere

exist in morals and talents as well as in principles and fortunes, it would become almost a matter of

indifference who was chosen. But I have already said that a real democracy is only an ideal.

When choice and lot are combined, positions that require special talents, such as military posts, should be

filled by the former; the latter does for cases, such as judicial offices, in which good sense, justice, and

integrity are enough, because in a State that is well constituted, these qualities are common to all the citizens.

Neither lot nor vote has any place in monarchical government. The monarch being by right sole prince and

only magistrate, the choice of his lieutenants belongs to none but him. When the Abbé de SaintPierre

proposed that the Councils of the King of France should be multiplied, and their members elected by ballot,

he did not see that he was proposing to change the form of government.

I should now speak of the methods of giving and counting opinions in the assembly of the people; but

perhaps an account of this aspect of the Roman constitution will more forcibly illustrate all the rules I could

lay down. It is worth the while of a judicious reader to follow in some detail the working of public and

private affairs in a Council consisting of two hundred thousand men.

4. THE ROMAN COMITIA

WE are without wellcertified records of the first period of Rome's existence; it even appears very probable

that most of the stories told about it are fables; indeed, generally speaking, the most instructive part of the

history of peoples, that which deals with their foundation, is what we have least of. Experience teaches us

every day what causes lead to the revolutions of empires; but, as no new peoples are now formed, we have

almost nothing beyond conjecture to go upon in explaining how they were created.

The customs we find established show at least that these customs had an origin. The traditions that go back to

those origins, that have the greatest authorities behind them, and that are confirmed by the strongest proofs,

should pass for the most certain. These are the rules I have tried to follow in inquiring how the freest and

most powerful people on earth exercised its supreme power.

After the foundation of Rome, the newborn republic, that is, the army of its founder, composed of Albans,


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 45



Top




Page No 48


Sabines and foreigners, was divided into three classes, which, from this division, took the name of tribes.

Each of these tribes was subdivided into ten curiae, and each curia into decuriae, headed by leaders called

curiones and decuriones.

Besides this, out of each tribe was taken a body of one hundred Equites or Knights, called a century, which

shows that these divisions, being unnecessary in a town, were at first merely military. But an instinct for

greatness seems to have led the little township of Rome to provide itself in advance with a political system

suitable for the capital of the world.

Out of this original division an awkward situation soon arose. The tribes of the Albans (Ramnenses) and the

Sabines (Tatienses) remained always in the same condition, while that of the foreigners (Luceres) continually

grew as more and more foreigners came to live at Rome, so that it soon surpassed the others in strength.

Servius remedied this dangerous fault by changing the principle of cleavage, and substituting for the racial

division, which he abolished, a new one based on the quarter of the town inhabited by each tribe. Instead of

three tribes he created four, each occupying and named after one of the hills of Rome. Thus, while redressing

the inequality of the moment, he also provided for the future; and in order that the division might be one of

persons as well as localities, he forbade the inhabitants of one quarter to migrate to another, and so prevented

the mingling of the races.

He also doubled the three old centuries of Knights and added twelve more, still keeping the old names, and

by this simple and prudent method, succeeded in making a distinction between the body of Knights, and the

people, without a murmur from the latter.

To the four urban tribes Servius added fifteen others called rural tribes, because they consisted of those who

lived in the country, divided into fifteen cantons. Subsequently, fifteen more were created, and the Roman

people finally found itself divided into thirtyfive tribes, as it remained down to the end of the Republic.

The distinction between urban and rural tribes had one effect which is worth mention, both because it is

without parallel elsewhere, and because to it Rome owed the preservation of her morality and the

enlargement of her empire. We should have expected that the urban tribes would soon monopolise power and

honours, and lose no time in bringing the rural tribes into disrepute; but what happened was exactly the

reverse. The taste of the early Romans for country life is well known. This taste they owed to their wise

founder, who made rural and military labours go along with liberty, and, so to speak, relegated to the town

arts, crafts, intrigue, fortune and slavery.

Since therefore all Rome's most illustrious citizens lived in the fields and tilled the earth, men grew used to

seeking there alone the mainstays of the republic. This condition, being that of the best patricians, was

honoured by all men; the simple and laborious life of the villager was preferred to the slothful and idle life of

the bourgeoisie of Rome; and he who, in the town, would have been but a wretched proletarian, became, as a

labourer in the fields, a respected citizen. Not without reason, says Varro, did our greatsouled ancestors

establish in the village the nursery of the sturdy and valiant men who defended them in time of war and

provided for their sustenance in time of peace. Pliny states positively that the country tribes were honoured

because of the men of whom they were composed; while cowards men wished to dishonour were transferred,

as a public disgrace, to the town tribes. The Sabine Appius Claudius, when he had come to settle in Rome,

was loaded with honours and enrolled in a rural tribe, which subsequently took his family name. Lastly,

freedmen always entered the urban, arid never the rural, tribes: nor is there a single example, throughout the

Republic, of a freedman, though he had become a citizen, reaching any magistracy.

This was an excellent rule; but it was carried so far that in the end it led to a change and certainly to an abuse

in the political system.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 46



Top




Page No 49


First the censors, after having for a long time claimed the right of transferring citizens arbitrarily from one

tribe to another, allowed most persons to enrol themselves in whatever tribe they pleased. This permission

certainly did no good, and further robbed the censorship of one of its greatest resources. Moreover, as the

great and powerful all got themselves enrolled in the country tribes, while the freedmen who had become

citizens remained with the populace in the town tribes, both soon ceased to have any local or territorial

meaning, and all were so confused that the members of one could not be told from those of another except by

the registers; so that the idea of the word tribe became personal instead of real, or rather came to be little

more than a chimera.

It happened in addition that the town tribes, being more on the spot, were often the stronger in the comitia

and sold the State to those who stooped to buy the votes of the rabble composing them.

As the founder had set up ten curiae in each tribe, the whole Roman people, which was then contained within

the walls, consisted of thirty curiae, each with its temples, its gods, its officers, its priests and its festivals,

which were called compitalia and corresponded to the paganalia, held in later times by the rural tribes.

When Servius made his new division, as the thirty curiae could not be shared equally between his four tribes,

and as he was unwilling to interfere with them, they became a further division of the inhabitants of Rome,

quite independent of the tribes: but in the case of the rural tribes and their members there was no question of

curiae, as the tribes had then become a purely civil institution, and, a new system of levying troops having

been introduced, the military divisions of Romulus were superfluous. Thus, although every citizen was

enrolled in a tribe, there were very many who were not members of a curia.

Servius made yet a third division, quite distinct from the two we have mentioned, which became, in its

effects, the most important of all. He distributed the whole Roman people into six classes, distinguished

neither by place nor by person, but by wealth; the first classes included the rich, the last the poor, and those

between persons of moderate means. These six classes were subdivided into one hundred and ninetythree

other bodies, called centuries, which were so divided that the first class alone comprised more than half of

them, while the last comprised only one. Thus the class that had the smallest number of members had the

largest number of centuries, and the whole of the last class only counted as a single subdivision, although it

alone included more than half the inhabitants of Rome.

In order that the people might have the less insight into the results of this arrangement, Servius tried to give it

a military tone: in the second class he inserted two centuries of armourers, and in the fourth two of makers of

instruments of war: in each class, except the last, he distinguished young and old, that is, those who were

under an obligation to bear arms and those whose age gave them legal exemption. It was this distinction,

rather than that of wealth, which required frequent repetition of the census or counting. Lastly, he ordered

that the assembly should be held in the Campus Martius, and that all who were of age to serve should come

there armed.

The reason for his not making in the last class also the division of young and old was that the populace, of

whom it was composed, was not given the right to bear arms for its country: a man had to possess a hearth to

acquire the right to defend it, and of all the troops of beggars who today lend lustre to the armies of kings,

there is perhaps not one who would not have been driven with scorn out of a Roman cohort, at a time when

soldiers were the defenders of liberty.

In this last class, however, proletarians were distinguished from capite censi. The former, not quite reduced to

nothing, at least gave the State citizens, and sometimes, when the need was pressing, even soldiers. Those

who had nothing at all, and could be numbered only by counting heads, were regarded as of absolutely no

account, and Marius was the first who stooped to enrol them.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 47



Top




Page No 50


Without deciding now whether this third arrangement was good or bad in itself, I think I may assert that it

could have been made practicable only by the simple morals, the disinterestedness, the liking for agriculture

and the scorn for commerce and for love of gain which characterised the early Romans. Where is the modern

people among whom consuming greed, unrest, intrigue, continual removals, and perpetual changes of

fortune, could let such a system last for twenty years without turning the State upside down? We must indeed

observe that morality and the censorship, being stronger than this institution, corrected its defects at Rome,

and that the rich man found himself degraded to the class of the poor for making too much display of his

riches.

From all this it is easy to understand why only five classes are almost always mentioned, though there were

really six. The sixth, as it furnished neither soldiers to the army nor votes in the Campus Martius,[36] and

was almost without function in the State, was seldom regarded as of any account.

These were the various ways in which the Roman people was divided. Let us now see the effect on the

assemblies. When lawfully summoned, these were called comitia: they were usually held in the public square

at Rome or in the Campus Martius, and were distinguished as comitia curiata, comitia centuriata, and comitia

tributa, according to the form under which they were convoked. The comitia curiata were founded by

Romulus; the centuriata by Servius; and the tributa by the tribunes of the people. No law received its sanction

and no magistrate was elected, save in the comitia; and as every citizen was enrolled in a curia, a century, or a

tribe, it follows that no citizen was excluded from the right of voting, and that the Roman people was truly

sovereign both de jure and de facto.

For the comitia to be lawfully assembled, and for their acts to have the force of law, three conditions were

necessary. First, the body or magistrate convoking them had to possess the necessary authority; secondly, the

assembly had to be held on a day allowed by law; and thirdly, the auguries had to be favourable.

The reason for the first regulation needs no explanation; the second is a matter of policy. Thus, the comitia

might not be held on festivals or marketdays, when the countryfolk, coming to Rome on business, had not

time to spend the day in the public square. By means of the third, the senate held in check the proud and

restive people, and meetly restrained the ardour of seditious tribunes, who, however, found more than one

way of escaping this hindrance.

Laws and the election of rulers were not the only questions submitted to the judgment of the comitia: as the

Roman people had taken on itself the most important functions of government, it may be said that the lot of

Europe was regulated in its assemblies. The variety of their objects gave rise to the various forms these took,

according to the matters on which they had to pronounce.

In order to judge of these various forms, it is enough to compare them. Romulus, when he set up curia, had in

view the checking of the senate by the people, and of the people by the senate, while maintaining his

ascendancy over both alike. He therefore gave the people, by means of this assembly, all the authority of

numbers to balance that of power and riches, which he left to the patricians. But, after the spirit of monarchy,

he left all the same a greater advantage to the patricians in the influence of their clients on the majority of

votes. This excellent institution of patron and client was a masterpiece of statesmanship and humanity

without which the patriciate, being flagrantly in contradiction to the republican spirit, could not have

survived. Rome alone has the honour of having given to the world this great example, which never led to any

abuse, and yet has never been followed.

As the assemblies by curiae persisted under the kings till the time of Servius, and the reign of the later

Tarquin was not regarded as legitimate, royal laws were called generally leges curiatae.

Under the Republic, the curiae, still confined to the four urban tribes, and including only the populace of


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 48



Top




Page No 51


Rome, suited neither the senate, which led the patricians, nor the tribunes, who, though plebeians, were at the

head of the welltodo citizens. They therefore fell into disrepute, and their degradation was such, that thirty

lictors used to assemble and do what the comitia curiata should have done.

The division by centuries was so favourable to the aristocracy that it is hard to see at first how the senate ever

failed to carry the day in the comitia bearing their name, by which the consuls, the censors and the other

curule magistrates were elected. Indeed, of the hundred and ninetythree centuries into which the six classes

of the whole Roman people were divided, the first class contained ninetyeight; and, as voting went solely by

centuries, this class alone had a majority over all the rest. When all these centuries were in agreement, the rest

of the votes were not even taken; the decision of the smallest number passed for that of the multitude, and it

may be said that, in the comitia centuriata, decisions were regulated far more by depth of purses than by the

number of votes.

But this extreme authority was modified in two ways. First, the tribunes as a rule, and always a great number

of plebeians, belonged to the class of the rich, and so counterbalanced the influence of the patricians in the

first class.

The second way was this. Instead of causing the centuries to vote throughout in order, which would have

meant beginning always with the first, the Romans always chose one by lot which proceeded alone to the

election; after this all the centuries were summoned another day according to their rank, and the same

election was repeated, and as a rule confirmed. Thus the authority of example was taken away from rank, and

given to the lot on a democratic principle.

From this custom resulted a further advantage. The citizens from the country had time, between the two

elections, to inform themselves of the merits of the candidate who had been provisionally nominated, and did

not have to vote without knowledge of the case. But, under the pretext of hastening matters, the abolition of

this custom was achieved, and both elections were held on the same day.

The comitia tributa were properly the council of the Roman people. They were convoked by the tribunes

alone; at them the tribunes were elected and passed their plebiscita. The senate not only had no standing in

them, but even no right to be present; and the senators, being forced to obey laws on which they could not

vote, were in this respect less free than the meanest citizens. This injustice was altogether illconceived, and

was alone enough to invalidate the decrees of a body to which all its members were not admitted. Had all the

patricians attended the comitia by virtue of the right they had as citizens, they would not, as mere private

individuals, have had any considerable influence on a vote reckoned by counting heads, where the meanest

proletarian was as good as the princeps senatus.

It may be seen, therefore, that besides the order which was achieved by these various ways of distributing so

great a people and taking its votes, the various methods were not reducible to forms indifferent in themselves,

but the results of each were relative to the objects which caused it to be preferred.

Without going here into further details, we may gather from what has been said above that the comitia tributa

were the most favourable to popular government, and the comitia centuriata to aristocracy. The comitia

curiata, in which the populace of Rome formed the majority, being fitted only to further tyranny and evil

designs, naturally fell into disrepute, and even seditious persons abstained from using a method which too

clearly revealed their projects. It is indisputable that the whole majesty of the Roman people lay solely in the

comitia centuriata, which alone included all; for the comitia curiata excluded the rural tribes, and the comitia

tributa the senate and the patricians.

As for the method of taking the vote, it was among the ancient Romans as simple as their morals, although

not so simple as at Sparta. Each man declared his vote aloud, and a clerk duly wrote it down; the majority in


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 49



Top




Page No 52


each tribe determined the vote of the tribe, the majority of the tribes that of the people, and so with curiae and

centuries. This custom was good as long as honesty was triumphant among the citizens, and each man was

ashamed to vote publicly in favour of an unjust proposal or an unworthy subject; but, when the people grew

corrupt and votes were bought, it was fitting that voting should be secret in order that purchasers might be

restrained by mistrust, and rogues be given the means of not being traitors.

I know that Cicero attacks this change, and attributes partly to it the ruin of the Republic. But though I feel

the weight Cicero's authority must carry on such a point, I cannot agree with him; I hold, on the contrary,

that, for want of enough such changes, the destruction of the State must be hastened. Just as the regimen of

health does not suit the sick, we should not wish to govern a people that has been corrupted by the laws that a

good people requires. There is no better proof of this rule than the long life of the Republic of Venice, of

which the shadow still exists, solely because its laws are suitable only for men who are wicked.

The citizens were provided, therefore, with tablets by means of which each man could vote without any one

knowing how he voted: new methods were also introduced for collecting the tablets, for counting voices, for

comparing numbers, etc.; but all these precautions did not prevent the good faith of the officers charged with

these functions[37] from being often suspect. Finally, to prevent intrigues and trafficking in votes, edicts

were issued; but their very number proves how useless they were.

Towards the close of the Republic, it was often necessary to have recourse to extraordinary expedients in

order to supplement the inadequacy of the laws. Sometimes miracles were supposed; but this method, while it

might impose on the people, could not impose on those who governed. Sometimes an assembly was hastily

called together, before the candidates had time to form their factions: sometimes a whole sitting was occupied

with talk, when it was seen that the people had been won over and was on the point of taking up a wrong

position. But in the end ambition eluded all attempts to check it; and the most incredible fact of all is that, in

the midst of all these abuses, the vast people, thanks to its ancient regulations, never ceased to elect

magistrates, to pass laws, to judge cases, and to carry through business both public and private, almost as

easily as the senate itself could have done.

5. THE TRIBUNATE

WHEN an exact proportion cannot be established between the constituent parts of the State, or when causes

that cannot be removed continually alter the relation of one part to another, recourse is had to the institution

of a peculiar magistracy that enters into no corporate unity with the rest. This restores to each term its right

relation to the others, and provides a link or middle term between either prince and people, or prince and

Sovereign, or, if necessary, both at once.

This body, which I shall call the tribunate, is the preserver of the laws and of the legislative power. It serves

sometimes to protect the Sovereign against the government, as the tribunes of the people did at Rome;

sometimes to uphold the government against the people, as the Council of Ten now does at Venice; and

sometimes to maintain the balance between the two, as the Ephors did at Sparta.

The tribunate is not a constituent part of the city, and should have no share in either legislative or executive

power; but this very fact makes its own power the greater: for, while it can do nothing, it can prevent

anything from being done. It is more sacred and more revered, as the defender of the laws, than the prince

who executes them, or than the Sovereign which ordains them. This was seen very clearly at Rome, when the

proud patricians, for all their scorn of the people, were forced to bow before one of its officers, who had

neither auspices nor jurisdiction.

The tribunate, wisely tempered, is the strongest support a good constitution can have; but if its strength is

ever so little excessive, it upsets the whole State. Weakness, on the other hand, is not natural to it: provided it


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 50



Top




Page No 53


is something, it is never less than it should be.

It degenerates into tyranny when it usurps the executive power, which it should confine itself to restraining,

and when it tries to dispense with the laws, which it should confine itself to protecting. The immense power

of the Ephors, harmless as long as Sparta preserved its morality, hastened corruption when once it had begun.

The blood of Agis, slaughtered by these tyrants, was avenged by his successor; the crime and the punishment

of the Ephors alike hastened the destruction of the republic, and after Cleomenes Sparta ceased to be of any

account. Rome perished in the same way: the excessive power of the tribunes, which they had usurped by

degrees, finally served, with the help of laws made to secure liberty, as a safeguard for the emperors who

destroyed it. As for the Venetian Council of Ten, it is a tribunal of blood, an object of horror to patricians and

people alike; and, so far from giving a lofty protection to the laws, it does nothing, now they have become

degraded, but strike in the darkness blows of which no one dare take note.

The tribunate, like the government, grows weak as the number of its members increases. When the tribunes

of the Roman people, who first numbered only two, and then five, wished to double that number, the senate

let them do so, in the confidence that it could use one to check another, as indeed it afterwards freely did.

The best method of preventing usurpations by so formidable a body, though no government has yet made use

of it, would be not to make it permanent, but to regulate the periods during which it should remain in

abeyance. These intervals, which should not be long enough to give abuses time to grow strong, may be so

fixed by law that they can easily be shortened at need by extraordinary commissions.

This method seems to me to have no disadvantages, because, as I have said, the tribunate, which forms no

part of the constitution, can be removed without the constitution being affected. It seems to be also

efficacious, because a newly restored magistrate starts not with the power his predecessor exercised, but with

that which the law allows him.

6. THE DICTATORSHIP

THE inflexibility of the laws, which prevents them from adapting themselves to circumstances, may, in

certain cases, render them disastrous, and make them bring about, at a time of crisis, the ruin of the State. The

order and slowness of the forms they enjoin require a space of time which circumstances sometimes

withhold. A thousand cases against which the legislator has made no provision may present themselves, and

it is a highly necessary part of foresight to be conscious that everything cannot be foreseen.

It is wrong therefore to wish to make political institutions so strong as to render it impossible to suspend their

operation. Even Sparta allowed its laws to lapse.

However, none but the greatest dangers can counterbalance that of changing the public order, and the sacred

power of the laws should never be arrested save when the existence of the country is at stake. In these rare

and obvious cases, provision is made for the public security by a particular act entrusting it to him who is

most worthy. This commitment may be carried out in either of two ways, according to the nature of the

danger.

If increasing the activity of the government is a sufficient remedy, power is concentrated in the hands of one

or two of its members: in this case the change is not in the authority of the laws, but only in the form of

administering them. If, on the other hand, the peril is of such a kind that the paraphernalia of the laws are an

obstacle to their preservation, the method is to nominate a supreme ruler, who shall silence all the laws and

suspend for a moment the sovereign authority. In such a case, there is no doubt about the general will, and it

is clear that the people's first intention is that the State shall not perish. Thus the suspension of the legislative

authority is in no sense its abolition; the magistrate who silences it cannot make it speak; he dominates it, but


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 51



Top




Page No 54


cannot represent it. He can do anything, except make laws.

The first method was used by the Roman senate when, in a consecrated formula, it charged the consuls to

provide for the safety of the Republic. The second was employed when one of the two consuls nominated a

dictator:[38] a custom Rome borrowed from Alba.

During the first period of the Republic, recourse was very often had to the dictatorship, because the State had

not yet a firm enough basis to be able to maintain itself by the strength of its constitution alone. As the state

of morality then made superfluous many of the precautions which would have been necessary at other times,

there was no fear that a dictator would abuse his authority, or try to keep it beyond his term of office. On the

contrary, so much power appeared to be burdensome to him who was clothed with it, and he made all speed

to lay it down, as if taking the place of the laws had been too troublesome and too perilous a position to

retain.

It is therefore the danger not of its abuse, but of its cheapening, that makes me attack the indiscreet use of this

supreme magistracy in the earliest times. For as long as it was freely employed at elections, dedications and

purely formal functions, there was danger of its becoming less formidable in time of need, and of men

growing accustomed to regarding as empty a title that was used only on occasions of empty ceremonial.

Towards the end of the Republic, the Romans, having grown more circumspect, were as unreasonably

sparing in the use of the dictatorship as they had formerly been lavish. It is easy to see that their fears were

without foundation, that the weakness of the capital secured it against the magistrates who were in its midst;

that a dictator might, in certain cases, defend the public liberty, but could never endanger it; and that the

chains of Rome would be forged, not in Rome itself, but in her armies. The weak resistance offered by

Marius to Sulla, and by Pompey to Caesar, clearly showed what was to be expected from authority at home

against force from abroad.

This misconception led the Romans to make great mistakes; such, for example, as the failure to nominate a

dictator in the Catilinarian conspiracy. For, as only the city itself, with at most some province in Italy, was

concerned, the unlimited authority the laws gave to the dictator would have enabled him to make short work

of the conspiracy, which was, in fact, stifled only by a combination of lucky chances human prudence had no

right to expect.

Instead, the senate contented itself with entrusting its whole power to the consuls, so that Cicero, in order to

take effective action, was compelled on a capital point to exceed his powers; and if, in the first transports of

joy, his conduct was approved, he was justly called, later on, to account for the blood of citizens spilt in

violation of the laws. Such a reproach could never have been levelled at a dictator. But the consul's eloquence

carried the day; and he himself, Roman though he was, loved his own glory better than his country, and

sought, not so much the most lawful and secure means of saving the State, as to get for himself the whole

honour of having done so.[39] He was therefore justly honoured as the liberator of Rome, and also justly

punished as a lawbreaker. However brilliant his recall may have been, it was undoubtedly an act of pardon.

However this important trust be conferred, it is important that its duration should be fixed at a very brief

period, incapable of being ever prolonged. In the crises which lead to its adoption, the State is either soon

lost, or soon saved; and, the present need passed, the dictatorship becomes either tyrannical or idle. At Rome,

where dictators held office for six months only, most of them abdicated before their time was up. If their term

had been longer, they might well have tried to prolong it still further, as the decemvirs did when chosen for a

year. The dictator had only time to provide against the need that had caused him to be chosen; he had none to

think of further projects.

7. THE CENSORSHIP


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 52



Top




Page No 55


AS the law is the declaration of the general will, the censorship is the declaration of the public judgment:

public opinion is the form of law which the censor administers, and, like the prince, only applies to particular

cases.

The censorial tribunal, so far from being the arbiter of the people's opinion, only declares it, and, as soon as

the two part company, its decisions are null and void.

It is useless to distinguish the morality of a nation from the objects of its esteem; both depend on the same

principle and are necessarily indistinguishable. There is no people on earth the choice of whose pleasures is

not decided by opinion rather than nature. Right men's opinions, and their morality will purge itself. Men

always love what is good or what they find good; it is in judging what is good that they go wrong. This

judgment, therefore, is what must be regulated. He who judges of morality judges of honour; and he who

judges of honour finds his law in opinion.

The opinions of a people are derived from its constitution; although the law does not regulate morality, it is

legislation that gives it birth. When legislation grows weak, morality degenerates; but in such cases the

judgment of the censors will not do what the force of the laws has failed to effect.

From this it follows that the censorship may be useful for the preservation of morality, but can never be so for

its restoration. Set up censors while the laws are vigorous; as soon as they have lost their vigour, all hope is

gone; no legitimate power can retain force when the laws have lost it.

The censorship upholds morality by preventing opinion from growing corrupt, by preserving its rectitude by

means of wise applications, and sometimes even by fixing it when it is still uncertain. The employment of

seconds in duels, which had been carried to wild extremes in the kingdom of France, was done away with

merely by these words in a royal edict: "As for those who are cowards enough to call upon seconds." This

judgment, in anticipating that of the public, suddenly decided it. But when edicts from the same source tried

to pronounce duelling itself an act of cowardice, as indeed it is, then, since common opinion does not regard

it as such, the public took no notice of a decision on a point on which its mind was already made up.

I have stated elsewhere[40] that as public opinion is not subject to any constraint, there need be no trace of it

in the tribunal set up to represent it. It is impossible to admire too much the art with which this resource,

which we moderns have wholly lost, was employed by the Romans, and still more by the Lacedaemonians.

A man of bad morals having made a good proposal in the Spartan Council, the Ephors neglected it, and

caused the same proposal to be made by a virtuous citizen. What an honour for the one, and what a disgrace

for the other, without praise or blame of either! Certain drunkards from Samos[41] polluted the tribunal of the

Ephors: the next day, a public edict gave Samians permission to be filthy. An actual punishment would not

have been so severe as such an impunity. When Sparta has pronounced on what is or is not right, Greece

makes no appeal from her judgments.

8. CIVIL RELIGION

AT first men had no kings save the gods, and no government save theocracy. They reasoned like Caligula,

and, at that period, reasoned aright. It takes a long time for feeling so to change that men can make up their

minds to take their equals as masters, in the hope that they will profit by doing so.

From the mere fact that God was set over every political society, it followed that there were as many gods as

peoples. Two peoples that were strangers the one to the other, and almost always enemies, could not long

recognise the same master: two armies giving battle could not obey the same leader. National divisions thus

led to polytheism, and this in turn gave rise to theological and civil intolerance, which, as we shall see


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 53



Top




Page No 56


hereafter, are by nature the same.

The fancy the Greeks had for rediscovering their gods among the barbarians arose from the way they had of

regarding themselves as the natural Sovereigns of such peoples. But there is nothing so absurd as the

erudition which in our days identifies and confuses gods of different nations. As if Moloch, Saturn, and

Chronos could be the same god! As if the Phoenician Baal, the Greek Zeus, and the Latin Jupiter could be the

same! As if there could still be anything common to imaginary beings with different names!

If it is asked how in pagan times, where each State had its cult and its gods, there were no wars of religion, I

answer that it was precisely because each State, having its own cult as well as its own government, made no

distinction between its gods and its laws. Political war was also theological; the provinces of the gods were,

so to speak, fixed by the boundaries of nations. The god of one people had no right over another. The gods of

the pagans were not jealous gods; they shared among themselves the empire of the world: even Moses and

the Hebrews sometimes lent themselves to this view by speaking of the God of Israel. It is true, they regarded

as powerless the gods of the Canaanites, a proscribed people condemned to destruction, whose place they

were to take; but remember how they spoke of the divisions of the neighbouring peoples they were forbidden

to attack! "Is not the possession of what belongs to your god Chamos lawfully your due?" said Jephthah to

the Ammonites. "We have the same title to the lands our conquering God has made his own."[42] Here, I

think, there is a recognition that the rights of Chamos and those of the God of Israel are of the same nature.

But when the Jews, being subject to the Kings of Babylon, and, subsequently, to those of Syria, still

obstinately refused to recognise any god save their own, their refusal was regarded as rebellion against their

conqueror, and drew down on them the persecutions we read of in their history, which are without parallel till

the coming of Christianity.[43]

Every religion, therefore, being attached solely to the laws of the State which prescribed it, there was no way

of converting a people except by enslaving it, and there could be no missionaries save conquerors. The

obligation to change cults being the law to which the vanquished yielded, it was necessary to be victorious

before suggesting such a change. So far from men fighting for the gods, the gods, as in Homer, fought for

men; each asked his god for victory, and repayed him with new altars. The Romans, before taking a city,

summoned its gods to quit it; and, in leaving the Tarentines their outraged gods, they regarded them as

subject to their own and compelled to do them homage. They left the vanquished their gods as they left them

their laws. A wreath to the Jupiter of the Capitol was often the only tribute they imposed.

Finally, when, along with their empire, the Romans had spread their cult and their gods, and had themselves

often adopted those of the vanquished, by granting to both alike the rights of the city, the peoples of that vast

empire insensibly found themselves with multitudes of gods and cults, everywhere almost the same; and thus

paganism throughout the known world finally came to be one and the same religion.

It was in these circumstances that Jesus came to set up on earth a spiritual kingdom, which, by separating the

theological from the political system, made the State no longer one, and brought about the internal divisions

which have never ceased to trouble Christian peoples. As the new idea of a kingdom of the other world could

never have occurred to pagans, they always looked on the Christians as really rebels, who, while feigning to

submit, were only waiting for the chance to make themselves independent and their masters, and to usurp by

guile the authority they pretended in their weakness to respect. This was the cause of the persecutions.

What the pagans had feared took place. Then everything changed its aspect: the humble Christians changed

their language, and soon this socalled kingdom of the other world turned, under a visible leader, into the

most violent of earthly despotisms.

However, as there have always been a prince and civil laws, this double power and conflict of jurisdiction


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 54



Top




Page No 57


have made all good polity impossible in Christian States; and men have never succeeded in finding out

whether they were bound to obey the master or the priest.

Several peoples, however, even in Europe and its neighbourhood, have desired without success to preserve or

restore the old system: but the spirit of Christianity has everywhere prevailed. The sacred cult has always

remained or again become independent of the Sovereign, and there has been no necessary link between it and

the body of the State. Mahomet held very sane views, and linked his political system well together; and, as

long as the form of his government continued under the caliphs who succeeded him, that government was

indeed one, and so far good. But the Arabs, having grown prosperous, lettered, civilised, slack and cowardly,

were conquered by barbarians: the division between the two powers began again; and, although it is less

apparent among the Mahometans than among the Christians, it none the less exists, especially in the sect of

Ali, and there are States, such as Persia, where it is continually making itself felt.

Among us, the Kings of England have made themselves heads of the Church, and the Czars have done the

same: but this title has made them less its masters than its ministers; they have gained not so much the right

to change it, as the power to maintain it: they are not its legislators, but only its princes. Wherever the clergy

is a corporate body,[44] it is master and legislator in its own country. There are thus two powers, two

Sovereigns, in England and in Russia, as well as elsewhere.

Of all Christian writers, the philosopher Hobbes alone has seen the evil and how to remedy it, and has dared

to propose the reunion of the two heads of the eagle, and the restoration throughout of political unity, without

which no State or government will ever be rightly constituted. But he should have seen that the masterful

spirit of Christianity is incompatible with his system, and that the priestly interest would always be stronger

than that of the State. It is not so much what is false and terrible in his political theory, as what is just and

true, that has drawn down hatred on it.[45]

I believe that if the study of history were developed from this point of view, it would be easy to refute the

contrary opinions of Bayle and Warburton, one of whom holds that religion can be of no use to the body

politic, while the other, on the contrary, maintains that Christianity is its strongest support. We should

demonstrate to the former that no State has ever been founded without a religious basis, and to the latter, that

the law of Christianity at bottom does more harm by weakening than good by strengthening the constitution

of the State. To make myself understood, I have only to make a little more exact the too vague ideas of

religion as relating to this subject.

Religion, considered in relation to society, which is either general or particular, may also be divided into two

kinds: the religion of man, and that of the citizen. The first, which has neither temples, nor altars, nor rites,

and is confined to the purely internal cult of the supreme God and the eternal obligations of morality, is the

religion of the Gospel pure and simple, the true theism, what may be called natural divine right or law. The

other, which is codified in a single country, gives it its gods, its own tutelary patrons; it has its dogmas, its

rites, and its external cult prescribed by law; outside the single nation that follows it, all the world is in its

sight infidel, foreign and barbarous; the duties and rights of man extend for it only as far as its own altars. Of

this kind were all the religions of early peoples, which we may define as civil or positive divine right or law.

There is a third sort of religion of a more singular kind, which gives men two codes of legislation, two rulers,

and two countries, renders them subject to contradictory duties, and makes it impossible for them to be

faithful both to religion and to citizenship. Such are the religions of the Lamas and of the Japanese, and such

is Roman Christianity, which may be called the religion of the priest. It leads to a sort of mixed and

antisocial code which has no name.

In their political aspect, all these three kinds of religion have their defects. The third is so clearly bad, that it

is waste of time to stop to prove it such. All that destroys social unity is worthless; all institutions that set man


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 55



Top




Page No 58


in contradiction to himself are worthless.

The second is good in that it unites the divine cult with love of the laws, and, making country the object of

the citizens' adoration, teaches them that service done to the State is service done to its tutelary god. It is a

form of theocracy, in which there can be no pontiff save the prince, and no priests save the magistrates. To

die for one's country then becomes martyrdom; violation of its laws, impiety; and to subject one who is guilty

to public execration is to condemn him to the anger of the gods: Sacer estod.

On the other hand, it is bad in that, being founded on lies and error, it deceives men, makes them credulous

and superstitious, and drowns the true cult of the Divinity in empty ceremonial. It is bad, again, when it

becomes tyrannous and exclusive, and makes a people bloodthirsty and intolerant, so that it breathes fire and

slaughter, and regards as a sacred act the killing of every one who does not believe in its gods. The result is to

place such a people in a natural state of war with all others, so that its security is deeply endangered.

There remains therefore the religion of man or Christianity  not the Christianity of today, but that of the

Gospel, which is entirely different. By means of this holy, sublime, and real religion all men, being children

of one God, recognise one another as brothers, and the society that unites them is not dissolved even at death.

But this religion, having no particular relation to the body politic, leaves the laws in possession of the force

they have in themselves without making any addition to it; and thus one of the great bonds that unite society

considered in severally fails to operate. Nay, more, so far from binding the hearts of the citizens to the State,

it has the effect of taking them away from all earthly things. I know of nothing more contrary to the social

spirit.

We are told that a people of true Christians would form the most perfect society imaginable. I see in this

supposition only one great difficulty: that a society of true Christians would not be a society of men.

I say further that such a society, with all its perfection, would be neither the strongest nor the most lasting: the

very fact that it was perfect would rob it of its bond of union; the flaw that would destroy it would lie in its

very perfection.

Every one would do his duty; the people would be lawabiding, the rulers just and temperate; the magistrates

upright and incorruptible; the soldiers would scorn death; there would be neither vanity nor luxury. So far, so

good; but let us hear more.

Christianity as a religion is entirely spiritual, occupied solely with heavenly things; the country of the

Christian is not of this world. He does his duty, indeed, but does it with profound indifference to the good or

ill success of his cares. Provided he has nothing to reproach himself with, it matters little to him whether

things go well or ill here on earth. If the State is prosperous, he hardly dares to share in the public happiness,

for fear he may grow proud of his country's glory; if the State is languishing, he blesses the hand of God that

is hard upon His people.

For the State to be peaceable and for harmony to be maintained, all the citizens without exception would have

to be good Christians; if by ill hap there should be a single selfseeker or hypocrite, a Catiline or a Cromwell,

for instance, he would certainly get the better of his pious compatriots. Christian charity does not readily

allow a man to think hardly of his neighbours. As soon as, by some trick, he has discovered the art of

imposing on them and getting hold of a share in the public authority, you have a man established in dignity; it

is the will of God that he be respected: very soon you have a power; it is God's will that it be obeyed: and if

the power is abused by him who wields it, it is the scourge wherewith God punishes His children. There

would be scruples about driving out the usurper: public tranquillity would have to be disturbed, violence

would have to be employed, and blood spilt; all this accords ill with Christian meekness; and after all, in this


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 56



Top




Page No 59


vale of sorrows, what does it matter whether we are free men or serfs? The essential thing is to get to heaven,

and resignation is only an additional means of doing so.

If war breaks out with another State, the citizens march readily out to battle; not one of them thinks of flight;

they do their duty, but they have no passion for victory; they know better how to die than how to conquer.

What does it matter whether they win or lose? Does not Providence know better than they what is meet for

them? Only think to what account a proud, impetuous and passionate enemy could turn their stoicism! Set

over against them those generous peoples who were devoured by ardent love of glory and of their country,

imagine your Christian republic face to face with Sparta or Rome: the pious Christians will be beaten,

crushed and destroyed, before they know where they are, or will owe their safety only to the contempt their

enemy will conceive for them. It was to my mind a fine oath that was taken by the soldiers of Fabius, who

swore, not to conquer or die, but to come back victorious  and kept their oath. Christians would never have

taken such an oath; they would have looked on it as tempting God.

But I am mistaken in speaking of a Christian republic; the terms are mutually exclusive. Christianity preaches

only servitude and dependence. Its spirit is so favourable to tyranny that it always profits by such a régime.

True Christians are made to be slaves, and they know it and do not much mind: this short life counts for too

little in their eyes.

I shall be told that Christian troops are excellent. I deny it. Show me an instance. For my part, I know of no

Christian troops. I shall be told of the Crusades. Without disputing the valour of the Crusaders, I answer that,

so far from being Christians, they were the priests' soldiery, citizens of the Church. They fought for their

spiritual country, which the Church had, somehow or other, made temporal. Well understood, this goes back

to paganism: as the Gospel sets up no national religion, a holy war is impossible among Christians.

Under the pagan emperors, the Christian soldiers were brave; every Christian writer affirms it, and I believe

it: it was a case of honourable emulation of the pagan troops. As soon as the emperors were Christian, this

emulation no longer existed, and, when the Cross had driven out the eagle, Roman valour wholly

disappeared.

But, setting aside political considerations, let us come back to what is right, and settle our principles on this

important point. The right which the social compact gives the Sovereign over the subjects does not, we have

seen, exceed the limits of public expediency.[46] The subjects then owe the Sovereign an account of their

opinions only to such an extent as they matter to the community. Now, it matters very much to the

community that each citizen should have a religion. That will make him love his duty; but the dogmas of that

religion concern the State and its members only so far as they have reference to morality and to the duties

which he who professes them is bound to do to others. Each man may have, over and above, what opinions he

pleases, without it being the Sovereign's business to take cognisance of them; for, as the Sovereign has no

authority in the other world, whatever the lot of its subjects may be in the life to come, that is not its business,

provided they are good citizens in this life.

There is therefore a purely civil profession of faith of which the Sovereign should fix the articles, not exactly

as religious dogmas, but as social sentiments without which a man cannot be a good citizen or a faithful

subject.[47] While it can compel no one to believe them, it can banish from the State whoever does not

believe them  it can banish him, not for impiety, but as an antisocial being, incapable of truly loving the

laws and justice, and of sacrificing, at need, his life to his duty. If any one, after publicly recognising these

dogmas, behaves as if he does not believe them, let him be punished by death: he has committed the worst of

all crimes, that of lying before the law.

The dogmas of civil religion ought to be few, simple, and exactly worded, without explanation or

commentary. The existence of a mighty, intelligent and beneficent Divinity, possessed of foresight and


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 57



Top




Page No 60


providence, the life to come, the happiness of the just, the punishment of the wicked, the sanctity of the social

contract and the laws: these are its positive dogmas. Its negative dogmas I confine to one, intolerance, which

is a part of the cults we have rejected.

Those who distinguish civil from theological intolerance are, to my mind, mistaken. The two forms are

inseparable. It is impossible to live at peace with those we regard as damned; to love them would be to hate

God who punishes them: we positively must either reclaim or torment them. Wherever theological

intolerance is admitted, it must inevitably have some civil effect;[48] and as soon as it has such an effect, the

Sovereign is no longer Sovereign even in the temporal sphere: thenceforce priests are the real masters, and

kings only their ministers.

Now that there is and can be no longer an exclusive national religion, tolerance should be given to all

religions that tolerate others, so long as their dogmas contain nothing contrary to the duties of citizenship. But

whoever dares to say: Outside the Church is no salvation, ought to be driven from the State, unless the State

is the Church, and the prince the pontiff. Such a dogma is good only in a theocratic government; in any other,

it is fatal. The reason for which Henry IV is said to have embraced the Roman religion ought to make every

honest man leave it, and still more any prince who knows how to reason.

9. CONCLUSION

Now that I have laid down the true principles of political right, and tried to give the State a basis of its own to

rest on, I ought next to strengthen it by its external relations, which would include the law of nations,

commerce, the right of war and conquest, public right, leagues, negotiations, treaties, etc. But all this forms a

new subject that is far too vast for my narrow scope. I ought throughout to have kept to a more limited

sphere.

______

1. "Learned inquiries into public right are often only the history of past abuses; and troubling to study them

too deeply is a profitless infatuation" (Essay on the Interests of France in Relation to its Neighbours, by the

Marquis d'Argenson). This is exactly what Grotius has done.

2. See a short treatise of Plutarch's entitled That Animals Reason.

3. The Romans, who understood and respected the right of war more than any other nation on earth, carried

their scruples on this head so far that a citizen was not allowed to serve as a volunteer without engaging

himself expressly against the enemy, and against such and such an enemy by name. A legion in which the

younger Cato was seeing his first service under Popilius having been reconstructed, the elder Cato wrote to

Popilius that, if he wished his son to continue serving under him, he must administer to him a new military

oath, because, the first having been annulled, he was no longer able to bear arms against the enemy. The same

Cato wrote to his son telling him to take great care not to go into battle before taking this new oath. I know

that the siege of Clusium and other isolated events can be quoted against me; but I am citing laws and

customs. The Romans are the people that least often transgressed its laws; and no other people has had such

good ones.

4. The real meaning of this word has been almost wholly lost in modern times; most people mistake a town

for a city, and a townsman for a citizen. They do not know that houses make a town, but citizens a city. The

same mistake long ago cost the Carthaginians dear. I have never read of the title of citizens being given to the

subjects of any prince, not even the ancient Macedonians or the English of today, though they are nearer

liberty than any one else. The French alone everywhere familiarly adopt the name of citizens, because, as can

be seen from their dictionaries, they have no idea of its meaning; otherwise they would be guilty in usurping


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 58



Top




Page No 61


it, of the crime of lèsemajesté: among them, the name expresses a virtue, and not a right. When Bodin spoke

of our citizens and townsmen, he fell into a bad blunder in taking the one class for the other. M. d'Alembert

has avoided the error, and, in his article on Geneva, has clearly distinguished the four orders of men (or even

five, counting mere foreigners) who dwell in our town, of which two only compose the Republic. No other

French writer, to my knowledge, has understood the real meaning of the word citizen.

5. Under bad governments, this equality is only apparent and illusory: it serves only tokeep the pauper in his

poverty and the rich man in the position he has usurped. In fact, laws are always of use to those who possess

and harmful to those who have nothing: from which it follows that the social state is advantageous to men

only when all have something and none too much.

6. To be general, a will need not always be unanimous; but every vote must be counted: any exclusion is a

breach of generality.

7. "Every interest," says the Marquis d'Argenson, "has different principles. The agreement of two particular

interests is formed by opposition to a third." He might have added that the agreement of all interests is formed

by opposition to that of each. If there were no different interests, the common interest would be barely felt, as

it would encounter no obstacle; all would go on of its own accord, and politics would cease to be an art.

8. "In fact," says Machiavelli, "there are some divisions that are harmful to a Republic and some that are

advantageous. Those which stir up sects and parties are harmful; those attended by neither are advantageous.

Since, then, the founder of a Republic cannot help enmities arising, he ought at least to prevent them from

growing into sects" (History of Florence, Book vii).

9. Attentive readers, do not, I pray, be in a hurry to charge me with contradicting myself. The terminology

made it unavoidable, considering the poverty of the language; but wait and see.

10. I understand by this word, not merely an aristocracy or a democracy, but generally any government

directed by the general will, which is the law. To be legitimate, the government must be, not one with the

Sovereign, but its minister. In such a case even a monarchy is a Republic. This will be made clearer in the

following book.

11. A people becomes famous only when its legislation begins to decline. We do not know for how many

centuries the system of Lycurgus made the Spartans happy before the rest of Greece took any notice of it.

12. Montesquieu, The Greatness and Decadence of the Romans, ch. i.

13. Those who know Calvin only as a theologian much underestimate the extent of his genius. The

codification of our wise edicts, in which he played a large part, does him no less honour than his Institute.

Whatever revolution time may bring in our religion, so long as the spirit of patriotism and liberty still lives

among us, the memory of this great man will be for ever blessed.

14. "In truth," says Machiavelli, "there has never been, in any country, an extraordinary legislator who has

not had recourse to God; for otherwise his laws would not have been accepted: there are, in fact, many useful

truths of which a wise man may have knowledge without their having in themselves such clear reasons for

their being so as to be able to convince others" (Discourses on Livy, Bk. v, ch. xi).

15. If there were two neighbouring peoples, one of which could not do without the other, it would be very

hard on the former, and very dangerous for the latter. Every wise nation, in such a case, would make haste to

free the other from dependence. The Republic of Thiascala, enclosed by the Mexican Empire, preferred doing

without salt to buying from the Mexicans, or even getting it from them as a gift. The Thiascalans were wise


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 59



Top




Page No 62


enough to see the snare hidden under such liberality. They kept their freedom, and that little State, shut up in

that great Empire, was finally the instrument of its ruin.

16. If the object is to give the State consistency, bring the two extremes as near to each other as possible;

allow neither rich men nor beggars. These two estates, which are naturally inseparable, are equally fatal to the

common good; from the one come the friends of tyranny, and from the other tyrants. It is always between

them that public liberty is put up to auction; the one buys, and the other sells.

17. "Any branch of foreign commerce," says M. d'Argenson, "creates on the whole only apparent advantage

for the kingdom in general; it may enrich some individuals, or even some towns; but the nation as a whole

gains nothing by it, and the people is no better off."

18. Thus at Venice the College, even in the absence of the Doge, is called "Most Serene Prince."

19. The Palatine of Posen, father of the King of Poland, Duke of Lorraine.

20. I prefer liberty with danger to peace with slavery.

21. It is clear that the word optimales meant, among the ancients, not the best, but the most powerful.

22. It is of great importance that the form of the election of magistrates should be regulated by law; for if it is

left at the discretion of the prince, it is impossible to avoid falling into hereditary aristocracy, as the Republics

of Venice and Berne actually did. The first of these has therefore long been a State dissolved; the second,

however, is maintained by the extreme wisdom of the senate, and forms an honourable and highly dangerous

exception.

23. Machiavelli was a proper man and a good citizen; but, being attached to the court of the Medici, he could

not help veiling his love of liberty in the midst of his country's oppression. The choice of his detestable hero,

Caesar Borgia, clearly enough shows his hidden aim; and the contradiction between the teaching of the Prince

and that of the Discourses on Livy and the History of Florence shows that this profound political thinker has

so far been studied only by superficial or corrupt readers. The Court of Rome sternly prohibited his book. I

can well believe it; for it is that Court it most clearly portrays.

24. Tacitus, Histories, i. 16. "For the best, and also the shortest way of finding out what is good and what is

bad is to consider what you would have wished to happen or not to happen, had another than you been

Emperor."

25. In the Statesman.

26. This does not contradict what I said before (Book II, ch. 9) about the disadvantages of great States; for we

were then dealing with the authority of the government over the members, while here we are dealing with its

force against the subjects. Its scattered members serve it as rallyingpoints for action against the people at a

distance, but it has no rallyingpoint for direct action on its members themselves. Thus the length of the lever

is its weakness in the one case, and its strength in the other.

27. On the same principle it should be judged what centuries deserve the preference for human prosperity.

Those in which letters and arts have flourished have been too much admired, because the hidden object of

their culture has not been fathomed, and their fatal effects not taken into account. "ldque apud imperitos

humanitas vocabatur, cum pars servitutis esset." (Fools called "humanity" what was a part of slavery, Tacitus,

Agricola, 31.) Shall we never see in the maxims books lay down the vulgar interest that makes their writers

speak? No, whatever they may say, when, despite its renown, a country is depopulated, it is not true that all is


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 60



Top




Page No 63


well, and it is not enough that a poet should have an income of 100,000 francs to make his age the best of all.

Less attention should be paid to the apparent repose and tranquillity of the rulers than to the wellbeing of

their nations as wholes, and above all of the most numerous States. A hailstorm lays several cantons waste,

but it rarely makes a famine. Outbreaks and civil wars give rulers rude shocks, but they are not the real ills of

peoples, who may even get a respite, while there is a dispute as to who shall tyrannise over them. Their true

prosperity and calamities come from their permanent condition: it is when the whole remains crushed beneath

the yoke, that decay sets in, and that the rulers destroy them at will, and "ubi solitudinem faciunt, pacem

appellant." (Where they create solitude, they call it peace, Tacitus, Agricola, 31.) When the bickerings of the

great disturbed the kingdom of France, and the Coadjutor of Paris took a dagger in his pocket to the

Parliament, these things did not prevent the people of France from prospering and multiplying in dignity, ease

and freedom. Long ago Greece flourished in the midst of the most savage wars; blood ran in torrents, and yet

the whole country was covered with inhabitants. It appeared, says Machiavelli, that in the midst of murder,

proscription and civil war, our republic only throve: the virtue, morality and independence of the citizens did

more to strengthen it than all their dissensions had done to enfeeble it. A little disturbance gives the soul

elasticity; what makes the race truly prosperous is not so much peace as liberty.

28. The slow formation and the progress of the Republic of Venice in its lagoons are a notable instance of this

sequence; and it is most astonishing that, after more than twelve hundred years' existence, the Venetians seem

to be still at the second stage, which they reached with the Serrar di Consiglio in 1198. As for the ancient

Dukes who are brought up against them, it is proved, whatever the Squittinio della libertà veneta may say of

them, that they were in no sense sovereigns.

A case certain to be cited against my view is that of the Roman Republic, which, it will be said, followed

exactly the opposite course, and passed from monarchy to aristocracy and from aristocracy to democracy. I

by no means take this view of it.

What Romulus first set up was a mixed government, which soon deteriorated into despotism. From special

causes, the State died an untimely death, as newborn children sometimes perish without reaching manhood.

The expulsion of the Tarquins was the real period of the birth of the Republic. But at first it took on no

constant form, because, by not abolishing the patriciate, it left half its work undone. For, by this means,

hereditary aristocracy, the worst of all legitimate forms of administration, remained in conflict with

democracy, and the form of the government, as Machiavelli has proved, was only fixed on the establishment

of the tribunate: only then was there a true government and a veritable democracy. In fact, the people was

then not only Sovereign, but also magistrate and judge; the senate was only a subordinate tribunal, to temper

and concentrate the government, and the consuls themselves, though they were patricians, first magistrates,

and absolute generals in war, were in Rome itself no more than presidents of the people.

From that point, the government followed its natural tendency, and inclined strongly to aristocracy. The

patriciate, we may say, abolished itself, and the aristocracy was found no longer in the body of patricians as

at Venice and Genoa, but in the body of the senate, which was composed of patricians and plebeians, and

even in the body of tribunes when they began to usurp an active function: for names do not affect facts, and,

when the people has rulers who govern for it, whatever name they bear, the government is an aristocracy.

The abuse of aristocracy led to the civil wars and the triumvirate. Sulla, Julius Caesar and Augustus became

in fact real monarchs; and finally, under the despotism of Tiberius, the State was dissolved. Roman history

then confirms, instead of invalidating, the principle I have laid down.

29. "Omnes enim et habentur et dicuntur tyranni, qui potestate utuntur perpetua in ea civitate quae libertate

usa est" (Cornelius Nepos, Life of Miltiades). (For all those are called and considered tyrants, who hold

perpetual power in a State that has known liberty.) It is true that Aristotle (Ethics, Book viii, chapter x)

distinguishes the tyrant from the king by the fact that the former governs in his own interest, and the latter


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 61



Top




Page No 64


only for the good of his subjects; but not only did all Greek authors in general use the word tyrant in a

different sense, as appears most clearly in Xenophon's Hiero, but also it would follow from Aristotle's

distinction that, from the very beginning of the world, there has not yet been a single king.

30. In nearly the same sense as this word has in the English Parliament. The similarity of these functions

would have brought the consuls and the tribunes into conflict, even had all jurisdiction been suspended.

31. To adopt in cold countries the luxury and effeminacy of the East is to desire to submit to its chains; it is

indeed to bow to them far more inevitably in our case than in theirs.

32. I had intended to do this in the sequel to this work, when in dealing with external relations I came to the

subject of confederations. The subject is quite new, and its principles have still to be laid down.

33. Provided, of course, he does not leave to escape his obligations and avoid having to serve his country in

the hour of need. Flight in such a case would be criminal and punishable, and would be, not withdrawal, but

desertion.

34. This should of course be understood as applying to a free State; for elsewhere family, goods, lack of a

refuge, necessity, or violence may detain a man in a country against his will; and then his dwelling there no

longer by itself implies his consent to the contract or to its violation.

35. At Genoa, the word Liberty may be read over the front of the prisons and on the chains of the

galleyslaves. This application of the device is good and just. It is indeed only malefactors of all estates who

prevent the citizen from being free. In the country in which all such men were in the galleys, the most perfect

liberty would be enjoyed.

36. I say "in the Campus Martius" because it was there that the comitia assembled by centuries; in its two

other forms the people assembled in the forum or elsewhere; and then the capite censi had as much influence

and authority as the foremost citizens.

37. Custodes, diribitores, rogatores suffragiorum.

38. The nomination was made secretly by night, as if there were something shameful in setting a man above

the laws.

39. That is what he could not be sure of, if he proposed a dictator; for he dared not nominate himself, and

could not be certain that his colleague would nominate him.

40. I merely call attention in this chapter to a subject with which I have dealt at greater length in my Letter to

M. d'Alembert.

41. They were from another island, which the delicacy of our language forbids me to name on this occasion.

42. Nonne ea quae possidet Chamos deus tuus, tibi jure debentur? (Judges, 11:24.) Such is the text in the

Vulgate. Father de Carrières translates: "Do you not regard yourselves as having a right to what your god

possesses?" I do not know the force of the Hebrew text: but I perceive that, in the Vulgate, Jephthah

positively recognises the right of the god Chamos, and that the French translator weakened this admission by

inserting an "according to you," which is not in the Latin.

43. It is quite clear that the Phocian War, which was called "the Sacred War," was not a war of religion. Its

object was the punishment of acts of sacrilege, and not the conquest of unbelievers.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 62



Top




Page No 65


44. It should be noted that the clergy find their bond of union not so much in formal assemblies, as in the

communion of Churches. Communion and excommunication are the social compact of the clergy, a compact

which will always make them masters of peoples and kings. All priests who communicate together are

fellowcitizens, even if they come from opposite ends of the earth. This invention is a masterpiece of

statesmanship: there is nothing like it among pagan priests; who have therefore never formed a clerical

corporate body.

45. See, for instance, in a letter from Grotius to his brother (April 11, 1643), what that learned man found to

praise and to blame in the De Cive. It is true that, with a bent for indulgence, he seems to pardon the writer

the good for the sake of the bad; but all men are not so forgiving.

46. "In the republic," says the Marquis d'Argenson, "each man is perfectly free in what does not harm others."

This is the invariable limitation, which it is impossible to define more exactly. I have not been able to deny

myself the pleasure of occasionally quoting from this manuscript, though it is unknown to the public, in order

to do honour to the memory of a good and illustrious man, who had kept even in the Ministry the heart of a

good citizen, and views on the government of his country that were sane and right.

47. Caesar, pleading for Catiline, tried to establish the dogma that the soul is mortal: Cato and Cicero, in

refutation, did not waste time in philosophising. They were content to show that Caesar spoke like a bad

citizen, and brought forward a doctrine that would have a bad effect on the State. This, in fact, and not a

problem of theology, was what the Roman senate had to judge.

48. Marriage, for instance, being a civil contract, has civil effects without which society cannot even subsist.

Suppose a body of clergy should claim the sole right of permitting this act, a right which every intolerant

religion must of necessity claim, is it not clear that in establishing the authority of the Church in this respect,

it will be destroying that of the prince, who will have thenceforth only as many subjects as the clergy choose

to allow him? Being in a position to marry or not to marry people according to their acceptance of such and

such a doctrine, their admission or rejection of such and such a formula, their greater or less piety, the Church

alone, by the exercise of prudence and firmness, will dispose of all inheritances, offices and citizens, and

even of the State itself, which could not subsist if it were composed entirely of bastards? But, I shall be told,

there will be appeals on the ground of abuse, summonses and decrees; the temporalities will be seized. How

sad! The clergy, however little, I will not say courage, but sense it has, will take no notice and go its way: it

will quietly allow appeals, summonses, decrees and seizures, and, in the end, will remain the master. It is not,

I think, a great sacrifice to give up a part, when one is sure of securing all.


The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right

The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right 63



Top





Bookmarks



1. Table of Contents, page = 3

2. The Social Contract, Or Principles of Political Right, page = 4